Abstracts Anton Markoc Title: The Cogency of the Levelling Down Objection Abstract: The most famous argument against telic egalitarianism and, indirectly, for prioritarianism is the so-called Levelling Down Objection. It is usually assumed that if this argument works and if there are no other equally strong objections to prioritarianism or more plausible competing views to it, we should accept it. My paper has two aims. First, I will show that the Levelling Down Objection, contrary to all accusations, rest on a solid principle and poses a genuine challenge to telic egalitarianism. Second, I will argue that the objection itself threatens prioritarianism to a no lesser degree than egalitarianism. Viktor Ilievski Title: Unity of the theory of unity of virtue in Plato's Laches and Protagoras Abstract The purpose of this paper is to examine the content of the Socratic theory of unity of virtues which has been a subject of lively debate in the last few decades. In striving to add to the debate, I will focus on the relevant passages of the two main sources of the theory, namely Plato's dialogues Laches and Protagoras. With this paper I attempt to establish, on the basis of textual evidence and reasoning, that a) there is no incongruity between the Laches' and the Protagoras' account of the status of virtues, and b) when Socrates in the Protagoras poses the question whether virtue is a single whole having justice etc., as his parts, or whether the latter are just synonyms referring to the same thing, the answer he expects is that they are all reducible to knowledge and thus simultaneously one and different. Zsuzsanna Balogh Title: Sense of self and the loss thereof Abstract: There are several notions of the self in philosophy but there is no consensus about what exactly it means to be a self. The concept is characterised in a variety of ways, including the uses of different terms, such as the core self (Damasio, 2000); the embodied self (Gallagher, 2005, Gallagher and Zahavi 2008); the autobiographical self; the extended self (Damasio, 2000); the narrative self (Schechtman, 2011) and the social self (James, 1890) to name but a few. Regardless of the metaphysical status of the self, our phenomenological self-experience gives rise to a vivid sense of self accompanying experience and action (Damasio 2000, Sartre 1957), which sense I take to be more fundamental than any kind of self. The analysis of this sense of self is the subject of my doctoral thesis, as in my view, a study of the sense of self as opposed to what the self is, gives us much finer-grained and more valuable insight into individuation and personal identity than a metaphysical account may do. On the one hand, the phenomenological characterisation of self-experience offers an account of the sense of self that involves pre-reflective and reflective levels of first-person experience and corresponding senses of the self (Zahavi, 2005), viz. the minimal sense of self and the narrative one. The minimal sense of self individuates in a basic way in my view, by providing the 'experiential boundaries' of the self. The narrative sense of self differentiates on more elaborate levels. On the other hand, empirically-informed characterisations of personality disorders and psychopathologies often make reference to the senses of self in their terminologies, thereby offering a way of connecting their insights to phenomenology. One such reference involves the loss of one's sense of self. I analyse what this amounts to in the case of schizophrenia in terms of phenomenology and explain the ways in which patients' self-reports of this aspect of the psychopathology may inform our understanding of the senses of self. I also revise the characteristics of the minimal sense of self offered by Nelson et al. (2009) from a philosophical standpoint. Işık Sarıhan Title: Mary’s Ignorance of Intentional Objects: A Physicalism-Friendly Representationalist Explanation for Why Having a Type of Experience is Necessary to Fully Understand that Experience-Type. Abstract: Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument is an argument to the effect that knowledge of phenomenal mental states cannot be acquired through what he calls “physical information”. In his paper where he presents us the thought experiment involving Mary the Color Scientist, he also presents us the simpler case of Fred, who can see more colors than the ordinary person. He does this to point to our intuition that one cannot have the knowledge of a phenomenal state type (such as experiencing a shade of red) without oneself undergoing that state. For instance, colorblind people do not know what color experiences are like. Like colorblind people, Mary in her black and white room doesn’t know what color experiences are like, even though she has all the physical knowledge one can acquire through linguistic media. This paper is an attempt to show how we can give a philosophical account of this correct intuition in a way compatible with physicalism. This will be done by using the resources of representationalism about phenomenal states. I will not argue for the truth of representationalism, I will just try to demonstrate that if representationalism is true, then we have a simple account of the lack of phenomenal knowledge, an account which is indifferent to the truth or falsity of physicalism. George-Florin Calian Title: Is Plato a Platonist regarding Numbers? Abstract: This paper deals with the relation between numbers and forms in Plato’s Parmenides, as an attempt to provide an answer to the question if numbers can be forms for Plato. In the Republic, the realm of mathematics is separated from the realm of forms. Why did Plato operate such a difference between the realm of forms and that of mathematics, despite the fact that he did not operate such a difference in other circumstances – on the contrary, he used mathematics as the example par excellence to prove that forms are real? In Meno, mathematical knowledge is treated undifferentiated from the knowledge of forms. Therefore, does the difference argued for in the Republic imply that numbers are not forms? And that numbers are intermediates between forms and things, as Aristotle testifies? A possible answer could be given by the reading of the second hypothesis from the second part of the Parmenides (142b-145a). I am discussing its analytical argument suggesting that Plato conceived numbers as generated, but not as forms, in order to avoid an infinite number of forms. Alina Asavei Title: Re-thinking Disinterestedness: Aesthetic Disinterestedness and Political-Critical Art Abstract: Political-critical art strives to arouse viewer’s awareness of the mechanism of domination, turning her in a conscious agent. Thus we can talk more about an active use of art, rather than a passive response to it. Is then possible to preserve an instance of aesthetic disinterestedness in attending politically concerned art? I will argue that we can shed a positive light on interestedness in attending art in general (and political-critical art in particular), without radically displacing the traditional, old-fashioned and contested aesthetic disinterestedness. One of the most important (if not the only one) contemporary attempts to find a middle ground between an interested and a disinterested apprehending of politically-charged art is undertaken by Peggy Zeglin Brand but, even though her endeavor is significant for contemporary aesthetics, it may still be questioned (especially because of the difficulties resting in the core of her argument – “the switch of attentions”). I argue that political art might be aesthetically experienced if we re-think some traditional concepts (like “disinterestedness”). Moreover, political-critical art’s appropriate attendance involves a disinterested interest and purpose but traditional aesthetic theories of disinterestedness, with their emphasis on disinterested perception and attention cannot accommodate them precisely because for these theories the “disinterested purpose” is oxymoronic. I argue that political art’s theory could (to some extent) better accommodate the theory of disinterestedness as envisaged by Lord Shaftsbury, its author, than the more contemporary theories (like Stolnitz’s in the 20th century).