Norm Descriptivism: From ‘Is’ to ‘Ought’ John Ku, University of Michigan Howard Nye, University of Michigan I. Introduction We constantly make judgments of what an agent should do, or what actions she has reason to perform (and probably other people do too). Some philosophers claim that what we are doing is judging whether or not these actions conform to certain standards that are in no way essentially tied to the agent’s own deliberations. Examples might include views that what an agent should do just is what is commanded by certain supernatural entities, what is customary in her society, what maximizes universal happiness, or what is congruent with certain objects in Plato’s heaven. Others claim that what we are doing is expressing something like our endorsement of the agent’s conduct, which is obviously in no way essentially connected to the standards that guide the agent’s deliberation. We think these approaches all go wrong from the start. In order to carry the kind of normative force they do, judgments of what reasons for action an agent has must be essentially connected to the standards that guide the agent’s own deliberations. This is what we take to be the most crucial intuition about normativity, and exploring, developing, and supporting this connection to deliberative standards drives the structure of this paper. Of course there will be standards guiding deliberation that agents can rationally scrutinize, but the very fact that agents can do this shows that their deliberative processes must involve built-in standards to which these less fundamental standards are being held. We will in fact argue that the only thing an agent can possibly be doing in deliberation is questioning whether she is conforming to these built-in standards. Since the normative question of what an agent should do just is this question the agent is asking in deliberation, that an agent should do something just is for these standards to prescribe her doing it. II. The Structure of Deliberation One might wonder, however, what exactly this talk of deliberative standards or standards guiding an agent’s deliberation amounts to. In this section we will attempt to give a more precise account of what it means. In doing so we intend to give an account of what any agent or entity acting for reasons must be doing in deliberation. To illustrate the distinctive character of agency and deliberation, let us start by contrasting it with the motivational systems of non-agents. Many non-human animals (e.g. mice) seem to have motivational states in accordance with certain patterns that we as observers could formulate. For instance, we might observe that when mice are hungry, they tend to be motivated to seek food. We might formulate a norm or imperative that the mouse seems to be following, like “when you are hungry, seek food!” In such cases it would also appear that there is a mechanism within the mouse that causes its behavior to follow this pattern, and in this sense we might say that the mouse internalizes the norm.1 It seems, however, that while human behavior sometimes merely follows patterns in the same ways as that of animals like mice, humans also often do something different. While creatures like mice have representations of the world that play a causal role in their behavior, they seem to lack representations of their own motivational states and behavior. Humans, on the other hand, do seem to have representations of their own motivational states and behavior. Furthermore, these representations do not seem to be merely epiphenomenal, but play an important causal role in human motivation and behavior. These representations seem to play a 1 This notion of norm internalization, while inspired by and broadly consistent with that of Gibbard (1990) is in fact somewhat broader, as it does not require that there is any “coordinative rationale” behind the attitude or behavior pattern in question (see Nye (2005b)). crucial role in the phenomena of human criticism and evaluation of their motivational states and actions, as well as many of their more “reflective” practices. When humans criticize or evaluate their attitudes, they must be holding these attitudes up against some standard that they have some kind of access to. Appearances of the conformance (or lack thereof) of their attitudes to the standard, moreover, seems to exert causal influence on the attitudes they actually come to have – which is just to say that these evaluations are not merely epiphenomenal. This kind of causal influence from internal representations of standards seems to be exactly what goes on when humans intuitively “endorse principles” or “accept norms.” To accept a norm in this way requires that the norm play the causal role of such a standard, but so far this standard could just be something like an intuitively “first-order” principle, like “don’t lie!” However, we certainly seem to be able to evaluate such first-order principles themselves. Yet, to evaluate these principles, it seems that we must be doing the same thing that we do in evaluating our attitudes – namely holding them up to some standard in a way that causes our acceptance (or rejection) of them to conform to it. Now, at some point, our psychologies will run out of standards against which to assess other standards.2 The standards at 2 Which will be the case, moreover, for any entity with finite psychological capacities. One can, however, certainly imagine entities (whether psychologically finite or infinite) who lack unified standards for assessing the standards that determine what norms they accept. These entities might accept various first-order norms, some of which might be supported by a chain of higher order norms terminating in one highest order norm, while others of which are supported by a chain of higher order norms terminating in a different highest order norm. There might, of course, be some causal mechanism within the entity that causes the prescriptions of one of the highest order norms to win out over the other on various occasions, but such agents would, ex hypothesi, lack any standard or principle by which to genuinely adjudicate conflicts between the prescriptions of these norms. We would thus argue that such entities are in fact “fractured agents”; both of the psychological governance processes of the highest order norms would be “unified agents” that both in a sense inhabit the entity in question and war within it. Views according to which we humans are fractured agents may have been held by Henry Sidgwick (1874), thought modally possible by Francis Hutcheson (1725), and may be held today by people who hold particularly strong versions of the thesis of the incommensurability of reasons. Moreover, even if an entity were a unified agent (i.e. with a single highest order norm or something like it) at a point in time, it might be fractured across time – due to (merely causal) changes over time in what its fundamental norms are. Allan Gibbard in fact expresses the view that we humans fit exactly this description in Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (see especially chapters 9 and following). Our view can accurately accommodate the conceivability or even existence of statically or dynamically fractured agents. Our view explains what it is for the unified agents within the fractured agent to have reasons, and which our psychologies terminate – which are those used as standards for determining the acceptance of all other principles – we might call “fundamental norms.” We conclude from these facts about our practices of principle acceptance and evaluation that we have a dedicated psychological system – which we might call a normative governance system3 - that employs these fundamental norms to evaluate our acceptances, motivations, and actions with the following features: 1.) It exerts direct causal influence on our motivations and actions; appearances that our motivations conform (or fail to conform) to norms in the system tend to cause us to have (or refrain from having) them. 2.) It is unified by the direct causal influence that higher-order accepted norms exert on lowerorder accepted norms; appearances that a lower-order norm conforms to (or fails to conform to) a higher-order norm in the system tend to cause us to accept (or refrain from accepting) it. Note that the higher-order norms we accept, including our fundamental or “highest-order” norms, need not be (and usually are not) those we consciously reference in our deliberations or those we ordinarily think to be more or most fundamental. All that must be the case for us to accept these norms in this way is for our cognitive architecture to include representations of them in this psychological system and for these representations to cause our actual acceptances to conform to them in the way described above. simply insists that there are no further principles to which the fractured agent can appeal to, and thus no further reasons that apply to the fractured agent. 3 Allan Gibbard uses this phrase to refer to the psychological mechanism underlying the shaping of attitudes and actions in response to normative judgments. While Gibbard does himself think that this mechanism is essentially one for ensuring coordination-via-consensus formation (which view we argue against) and describes it in these terms, it seems that what he primarily intends the phrase ‘normative governance system’ to refer to is that of the truth-maker of attitude guidance via normative judgments, whether it is coordinative or not (which is consistent with our usage here). It seems, moreover, that deliberation on the part of any agent can be nothing other than the evaluation of attitudes and actions by reference to the standards of a dedicated psychological system with features 1.) and 2.). Intuitively, deliberation is a process of searching for authoritative grounds for endorsing actions and principles. This kind of search involves coming to be motivated to act or accept a principle when it appears to be prescribed by standards the agent trusts. But what could this kind of search amount to other than an attempt to determine the prescriptions of a system of this kind at work in the agent’s psychology? To question the authority of a principle ultimately involves nothing other than holding it up to a standard with the kind of causal influence we attributed to fundamental norms. To settle a deliberative question is to determine whether a principle does meet such a standard. III. Normativity With this account of deliberation in mind, we can now turn to the meaning of normative judgments that an agent has reason to perform an action. We will here further articulate and argue in support of our claim that the normative question of what an agent should do just is this question the agent is asking in deliberation. Having established this, we will explain how, given our account of what question the agent is asking in deliberation, we can arrive at an analysis of these normative judgments. We would like to articulate a more general intuition that normative judgments of what an agent should do are intimately connected to the endorsement of the agent whose reasons they are. To do this, let us begin by contrasting it with views that sharply conflict with it. As mentioned in the introduction, some philosophers have held the view that when a speaker makes a judgment of what an agent should do she is expressing something like her own endorsement of the agent’s conduct.4 Of course, when an agent makes judgments about her own reasons for action, the speaker and the agent are one and the same, which may lend an air of superficial plausibility to the view. But consider cases in which the speaker and the agent are different people. According to these views, the speaker’s judgment that the agent has certain reasons for action expresses (roughly) the speaker’s endorsement of the agent’s acting in that way. One might wonder how in these cases the mere expression of the speaker’s endorsement could look anything like a normative judgment of what reasons the agent has for action. If judgments about an agent’s reasons for action were simply something like expressions of what the speaker endorsed and not conceptually connected to something about the agent’s endorsement, it would simply look as though the speaker is either failing to address the topic of the agent’s actions or simply browbeating or “spitting at” the agent. What this seems to suggest is that the conceptual connection of normative judgments to endorsement must be to the agent’s rather than the speaker’s endorsement. This view of the connection goes hand in hand with a picture according to which normative judgments play their primary role in guiding agents’ deliberations. But it also allows for a more accurate picture of what goes on in normative discussions and generally judgments of what reasons another agent has for action. On this view, normative discussion proceeds as a kind of public deliberation, in which discussants work together to determine what is prescribed by what an agent ultimately endorses. The agent whose reasons are in question may or may not be party to the discussion, but what normative discussants are doing is essentially “taking up the perspective” of this agent. For instance according to Allan Gibbard’s expressivist account (which may be the most prominent contemporary theory of normative judgments), the content of normative judgments – including judgments of what reasons for action an agent has – are to be explained as expressing mind states of norm acceptance (Or one’s “ruling out” of a set of systems of norms or factual-normative worlds (See Gibbard’s Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, Chapter 5)). Gibbard intends this mind state of norm acceptance to coincide with and help elucidate that of a judge’s endorsement. 4 Such a view of the dynamics of normative discussion obviously allows that there can be mere exchanges of normative judgments, i.e. ones more motivated by “brow-beating” or convincing by any means necessary than the objective of figuring out the prescriptions of what the agent ultimately endorses. It is merely a view according to which there is a genuine conceptual distinction to be made between normative discussion as public deliberation proper and the mere exchanges of normative judgments that are in fact parasitic on it. This review of the force of normative judgments seems to support a view of normative judgments according to which they are judgments about what an agent ultimately endorses. In explaining the structure of deliberation, we gave an account of what it could be for an agent to endorse a principle or treat it as authoritative, according to which this must amount to viewing it as prescribed by her normative governance system (or what her fundamental norms prescribe). Hence, it seems that normative judgments that an agent should do something amount to nothing other than judgements that her normative governance system prescribes doing it. Much the same conclusion can be drawn from our examination of the dynamics of normative judgments in discussion. The lesson we drew from this examination was that normative questions of what an agent has reason to do have the same content as the questions she asks herself in deliberation. The account of deliberative questioning we reached earlier was that it involved nothing other than holding up a principle or action to the standards of one’s normative governance system. Hence, it would seem that normative judgments would have the same content as those an agent reaches in settling deliberative questions, which content we argued is that of a judgment whether a principle or action is prescribed by her normative governance system. Thus, the understanding of the meaning of normative judgments to which we have come is the following: Norm Descriptivism:5 Agent A has reason to φ iff A’s normative governance system prescribes A’s φ-ing. Note that this view offers us a naturalistic, descriptivist analysis of normative concepts that reduces normative facts to facts about a dedicated psychological system guiding the agent’s attitudes and actions. Some have held that because ‘ought’ judgments have an essential connection to the guidance of agents’ attitudes that no descriptive or ‘is’ judgments could have, one can never infer an ‘ought’ judgment from any set of purely ‘is’ judgments. However, once one appreciates the structure of deliberation and the content of the ‘is’ judgments we have proposed normative judgments can be analysed into, one can see that some (very specific) ‘is’ judgments do indeed have the essential connection to the guidance of agents’ attitudes that normative judgment do. Judgments of what one’s normative governance prescribes simply are the descriptive judgments that cause one to endorse or reject attitudes and actions. ‘Ought’ judgments just are a particular, essentially attitude guiding kind of ‘is’ judgments. While we have for expository purposes focused on the case of reasons for action, the line of thought behind the norm descriptivist analysis actually allows us to give analyses of all normative concepts. Just like judgments of what an agent should do, normative judgments that an agent has reason to have any kind of attitude – including beliefs, emotions, and other motivational states (like desires) – are essentially connected to the endorsement of the agent whose reasons they are. Exactly analogous considerations to those we have discussed in the case Inspiration for the name of our view is drawn from Allan Gibbard’s naming his particular expressivist view “norm expressivism.” Just as he attempts to draw on features of normative governance to support a particular expressivist account of the meaning of normative judgments, considerations of normative governance shape and drive our particular descriptivist view. 5 of deliberation about action show that agents can have normative governance systems that prescribe what to believe, feel, and desire. Thus, analogous arguments would support the following general analysis of normative concepts, motivated by the relationships between normative judgment, deliberation, and endorsement: Generalized Norm Descriptivism: A has reason to , (where is any particular attitude - a belief, an emotion, another motivational state – or action) iff A’s normative governance system prescribes A’s -ing. IV. Replies to Objections One might worry that an analysis like ours could not capture the normative force of morality. However, our view can indeed capture an in fact vindicate the view that one necessarily has reason to fulfill one’s moral obligations. It seems impossible to understand what moral obligations are without analyzing them in terms of warrant or reasons to feel emotions like guilt, resentment, and impartial anger. If one considers all of the disparate kinds of things that people have intelligibly held to be morally obligatory (e.g. such things as not harming others, not defecting in collective action problems, but also doing all manor of apparently miscellaneous things like observing rules of etiquette, abstaining from random sexual practices, and obeying the de dicto will of alleged deities), it seems that one can find nothing common to their judgments other than the view that people should feel guilt towards doing such things, and others are justified in feeling resentment or impartial anger towards them if they do. Thus, as a conceptual matter, if one is genuinely morally obligated to do something, one should feel guilt towards not doing it.6 6 Note that the kind of guilt involved in feeling guilt towards doing something is a prospective version of the emotion we might more readily identify as guilt, which is often retrospective in character. However, this feeling of prospective guilt surely exists and plays a crucial role in our social and normative lives – it may be more often referred to in ordinary English as a “feeling of obligation.” Now, as Gibbard (1990) and Scanlon (1998) have argued, our assessments of the rationality of our actions proceeds via our assessments of the rationality of the motivational states that lead us to them. Thus, our actions are caused to conform to our assessments of the rationality of the motivational states that lead us to them. Hence, because our actions are normatively governed via the normative governance of our motivational states in this way, reasons to be in motivational states just constitute reasons for action (i.e. the actions motivated by those motivational states). Note that guilt is indeed a motivational state; part of what it is to feel guilty towards doing something is to be motivated not to do it. Thus, if one has reason to feel guilt towards doing something, one necessarily has (at least some) reason not to do it. Hence, since moral obligation is conceptually tied to warranted guilt in the way just described, if one is morally obligated not to do something, then one necessarily has reason not to do it.7 Understood on our account, what it is for an agent to have reason to feel emotions like guilt, and thus have reasons to be motivated and act out of it, just is for the agent’s normative governance system to prescribe her feeling guilt. Now, one might still wonder whether we have any genuine moral obligations, which conceived on our account amounts to wondering whether our normative governance systems ever prescribe our feeling guilt towards actions. However, it would seem just as implausible to suppose that our normative governance systems never prescribe our feeling guilt as it would to suppose that they never prescribe our being in any other motivational states (e.g. desire). We often feel guilt; sometimes we think it warranted and sometimes think it unwarranted, just as we often desire things and sometimes think these desires warranted or unwarranted. Since both motivational states, along with their normative This line of argument is proposed, discussed, and defended in some detail in Nye (2005a), and “Morality and the Bearing of Apt Feelings on Wise Choices.” 7 governance, are evolutionary adaptations, there is no reason to suppose that our normative governance systems would never prescribe either, and every reason to think that they often will. A final objection to our view might run as follows. One might agree that we have a normative governance system that prescribes attitudes, actions, and norms on our parts, and is responsible for our ability to criticize, evaluate, and endorse them, but still raise the question, “why should I endorse what my normative governance system prescribes? Why should I accord such authority to my normative governance system?” But given our account of deliberation and endorsement, questioning whether or not to endorse the prescriptions of one’s normative governance system just amounts to questioning whether or not our normative governance systems prescribe their own prescriptions. Such questioning is well within the scope of our view, as our view renders such questions intelligible.8 It is in fact conceptually possible for there to be agents whose normative governance systems simultaneously prescribe various things and also prescribe rejecting their own prescriptions. Such agents might be aptly referred to as ‘liar paradoxes’, and might not be guided very effectively by their normative governance systems, but this does not detract from the plausibility of our view. In short, these agents might be screwed, but our view would not. 8 We are grateful to Matthew Pugsley for very helpful discussion on this point and the suggestion that our view delivers this result. Works Cited Gibbard, Allan. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1990. Hutcheson, Francis. Treatise II: An Inquiry Concerning the Original of our Ideas of virtue or Moral Good. 1725. Nye, Howard L.M. “Emotion, Motivation, and Normativity: A Case Study of Francis Hutcheson and the Normativity of Benevolence and Moral Goodness” (manuscript), 2005a. Nye, Howard L.M. “Do Evolutionary Considerations Support Gibbard’s Theory of Normative Judgment?” (manuscript), 2005b. Nye, Howard L.M. “Morality and the Bearing of Apt Feelings on Wise Choices” (manuscript), 2005. Scanlon, T.M. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1998. Sidgwick, Henry. The Methods of Ethics. 1874. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1981.