Enjoyment and Beauty Beauty is powerful. It compels our attention and appreciation and unites us in shared visions. Our goal is to describe beauty in a way that illuminates its power. The description consists of arguments for three claims. First, one enjoys the items one judges to be beautiful. Second, the enjoyment is a special kind; one does not enjoy in that way items one does not find beautiful. Third, to believe that something is beautiful is to believe, on the basis of the special kind of enjoyment, that others will, other things being equal, enjoy the item in that special way. The arguments for the second and third claims characterize beauty’s power to compel attention and appreciation and address its power to unite. The first claim is an essential preliminary. The inspiration for this approach is Kant’s Critique of Judgment, where Kant (arguably) advances all three claims. Our concern, however, is with the truth of the claims, not with Kantian exegesis, and our arguments will not, for the most part, be the same as Kant’s. I. The First Claim Must one enjoy what one finds beautiful? The question arises because it seems possible to think something beautiful without enjoying it at any time. Imagine, for example, that you and Jones are looking that the Taj Mahal. Your enjoyment leads you to exclaim, “Beautiful, isn’t it?” Jones agrees, thereby expressing his own judgment that the Taj is beautiful. Jones is not, however, enjoying the Taj. He is not cognitively or affectively impaired; he attends to features that people generally regard as making the Taj beautiful, and he makes a good faith effort to enjoy looking at the building, but he simply does not enjoy it. He is indifferent. He agrees with you because he knows that it is the received opinion that the Taj is beautiful. His agreement acknowledges that the Taj belongs with that diverse collection of items that people generally take to be beautiful. Jones’s statement that the Taj is beautiful may be misleading since it is typically one’s enjoyment that convinces one that something is beautiful. But surely Jones can consistently say, “I believe the Taj is beautiful, although I do not, never have, and expect I never will enjoy it.” Even if Jones cannot base his judgment on his own enjoyment, he can base it on the reports of others. Compare believing that Beijing is densely populated. One can form that belief based in entirely on the reports of others, so why can’t one, on the basis of reports, judge that the Taj is beautiful? In response, we distinguish two types of judgments of beauty. Jones’ judgment of beauty illustrates the first; the defining feature is that the reasons for judgment consist entirely in the reports of others. The following conditions characterize the second type of judgment: (1) one forms the subjective conviction that the item has certain features; (2) one enjoys the item as having those features; and (3) that enjoyment is one’s reason for the judgment. By “a judgment of beauty” and similar expressions, we shall mean a judgment of this second sort unless we explicitly indicate otherwise. Section II discusses (2); Section III, (3). We devote the rest of this section to explaining and defending (1). In doing so, we assume that a judgment of beauty is something for which one typically has reasons. To see that one typically has reasons for a judgment of beauty, suppose that, in the Taj example, Jones asks you why you think the Taj is beautiful. Jones is not asking for an explanation of why you respond to the Taj as you do; he is asking you to identify what you regard as the features which are key to experiencing it as beautiful. You answer by citing the features you enjoy. We take this to be the typical pattern: one defends one’s judgment that a face, painting, statute, or poem, for example, is beautiful by citing the features one enjoys. It is a fundamental fact about beauty that the features are unified; the beauty items parts, qualities, internal and external relations present themselves to the enjoyer as an organized whole. The enjoyment reveals the item as having these features and his enjoyment-mediated revelation serves as the reason for the judgment of beauty. It is a fundamental fact about beauty that, as we will argue in Section IV, this revelation is articulated. Even apparently simple beauties, like the beauty of a particular shade of red, only stand out as beautiful because of the relation of that red to its surroundings (visual or conceptual) and our ability to compare it to many other closely similar shades. To avoid misunderstanding, we should emphasize that we are not claiming that, when one gives reasons for a judgment of beauty, one expects others to infer on the basis of these reasons that the item is beautiful. The role of reasons is not to compel agreement by providing evidentiary grounds. We assign a far different role to reasons in Sections II and III. Now we turn to the claim that, when one judges something beautiful, one forms the subjective conviction that the item has certain features. We begin by explaining what we mean by “subjective.” A subjective judgment is one that is not objective. Israel Scheffler captures the relevant sense of “objective”: A fundamental feature of science is its ideal of objectivity, an ideal that subjects all scientific statements to the test of independent and impartial criteria, recognizing no authority of persons in the realm of cognition. The claimant to scientific knowledge is responsible for what he says, acknowledging the relevance of considerations beyond his wish or advocacy to the judgment of his assertions. In assertion . . . he is trying to meet independent standards, to satisfy factual requirements whose fulfillment cannot be guaranteed in advance. In this case of judgments of beauty, one does recognize the “authority of persons in the realm of cognition,” as the following example illustrates. When Brian asks Brianna why she thinks the Mona Lisa is beautiful, Brianna describes an organized array of features she perceives the painting as having. Here we understand “perceives the painting as having” to mean that she is not, for example, merely repeating what she has read; she sees the painting as having the array of features for herself, through her own eyes. In response, Brian produces a painting—the faux Mona Lisa—having all of the specified features. Brianna denies it is beautiful. Brian complains that the two paintings are relevantly the same: both have the array of features Brianna specified. Brianna responds by pointing out relevant differences--e. g., “the background is different,” “the use of light is different,” “the eyebrows are different,” and so on. None of the features she mentions were included in her earlier specification of the array. She insists that the differences mean the faux Mona Lisa does not exhibit the same organized array of features as the true Mona Lisa. When Brianna denies the faux Mona Lisa lacks the relevant organized array, she is not—cannot be—making a mistake about a matter of objective fact. As Kant notes, If any one reads me his poem, or brings me a play, which all said and done, fails to commend itself to my taste, then let him adduce . . . critics of taste, with the host of rules laid down by them, as a proof of the beauty of his poem; let certain passages particularly displeasing to me accord completely with the rules of beauty (as . . . universally recognized) . . . I take my stand on the ground that my judgment is one of taste . . . This would appear to be one of the chief reasons why this faculty of aesthetic judgement is has been given the name of taste. For a man may recount to me the ingredients of a dish, and observe that each and every one of them is just what I like . . . yet I am deaf to these arguments. I try the dish with my own tongue and palate, and I pass judgement according to their verdict. One recognizes the authority of persons in ascriptions of features to the items we judge beautiful, as illustrated by Brianna authority with regard to whether the two Mona Lisa’s share the same organize array of features. There are two dimensions to her authority: whether the paintings possess certain features, and whether those features are organized in a certain way. Her authority may extend to both; “may” because if one of Brianna’s organized features is simply “red there,” we do not claim she is authoritative about that; if however, the feature is “a certain interaction of light and dark in the background,” she may be authoritative in this regard (one may try to decompose all such features into arrays of features over which one is not authoritative; we will not pursue this possibility). As we argue in Section III, Brianna’s reason for her judgment that the Mona Lisa is beautiful is her enjoyment of the painting as having the organized array of features she subjectively ascribes to it. The Taj Mahal example illustrates the same point. Jones judges that the Taj is beautiful merely based on the reports of others. You—we may assume—form a firstperson authoritative belief that the Taj has a certain organized array of features, enjoy the Taj as having that array, and for that reason judge it beautiful. We should clarify what we mean by enjoying an item “as having an array of features.” Consider first that, whenever one enjoys something, one enjoys it as having one or more features. There is typically an answer to the question, “What do you enjoy about it?” If, for example, one enjoys chocolate, one enjoys it for its bitter-sweet taste, or as a rebellion against one’s strict diet, or whatever. The answer to, “What do you enjoy about it?” specifies the features one enjoys it as having. To see that there must always be some answer to that question, imagine Carol claims to enjoy dining out in restaurants, but sincerely denies that there is anything she enjoys about it. She insists she does not enjoy the food, the restaurant atmosphere, the experience of being waited on, the people watching, or anything else. She is completely indifferent to every feature of dining out. This is a paradigm case of not enjoying dining out; Carol just self-deceptively believes she enjoys it. The enjoyment of items we first-person-authoritatively believe to have a certain array of features is just a special case of the general truth that to enjoy is to enjoy an item as being some way. We conclude this section with a final comment on the Mona Lisa example. It is tempting, following Kant, describe Brianna’s subjective ascription of an array of features to the Mona Lisa as a product of the “free play of the Imagination.” Of course, the Imagination to which Kant appeals is a transcendental faculty, and we wish to avoid any such appeal. Even so, we can still non-transcendentally describe Brianna’s perception as a result of “free play of the imagination” in the following sense: the organized array of features Brianna ascribes to the Mona Lisa is her own first-personauthoritative construction. What Brianna does is akin to seeing shapes in clouds, an activity that one might well describe as a free play of the imagination. Unlike one’s typical attitude toward clouds, however, one typically repeatedly contemplates and investigates things one finds beautiful in ways that extend and enrich that array of features one apprehends it as having. Beauty creates opportunities for imaginative interaction, opportunities we value highly. The interaction is typically temporally structured in a way which involves attention to the various features in question as a sustained appreciation of the whole. Even with the simple beauties of flowers and geometrical designs, the eye ranges over the form, appreciates the variations in color, calls to mind perhaps other beautiful flowers. Beauty is typically discovered in a sustained and variegated experience of the object over time. The experience would not be the kind of experience it is without the features of the object in question; they are in that sense necessary to the experience of beauty, as is the object itself. But the beauty is the object's as a whole. This imaginative activity is associated, not just with enjoyment, but with enjoyment of a special kind. A further consideration of the Mona Lisa example motivates this claim. Imagine that, although Brianna does not find the faux Mona Lisa beautiful, she nonetheless enjoys it as having a certain organized array of features, just not the same array she believes the true Mona Lisa as having. Her enjoyment of the true Mona Lisa provides with her reasons to think it is beautiful, but her enjoyment of the faux Mona Lisa does not. What accounts for the difference? The relevant differences she points out between the two paintings do not constitute an answer to this question. They merely show that she is not guilty of failing to treat like things alike; they do not provide an explanation of how one enjoyment plays a reasonproviding role and the other does not. We suggest that what accounts for the difference is that the basis of a judgment of beauty is a special kind of enjoyment. II. The Second Claim: A Special Kind of Enjoyment The distinguishing feature of the relevant kind of enjoyment is the presence of a certain type of reason for that very enjoyment, a presence caused (or causally sustained) by the enjoyment itself. Section B characterizes the type of reason; section C addresses the causal claim. Section A explains what we mean by a reason to enjoy something. A. Reasons We treat a reason to enjoy as a special case of a reason for action. This may seem obviously wrong. Surely, unlike action, enjoyment is an experience which is not under our voluntary control; it just either happens or does not happen. In fact, enjoyment is typically under one’s voluntary control in two ways: one can often determine whether it occurs, and how long it endures. If Smith goes the museum, he knows he will enjoy various impressionist paintings, which he finds beautiful; if he does go, he can determine the duration of the enjoyment by how long he stays. This is, however, not sufficient to give a clear sense to a reason to enjoy. One may rightly object that all the example shows is that Smith’s expectation of enjoyment is a reason for him to go to the museum. The expectation of the experience is a reason for the action of going to the museum. Where is there a need to posit a reason for the enjoyment itself? The answer lies in a fundamental fact about beauty: it commands enjoyment. Everyday talk and thought about beauty reflect this fact. Imagine two painters, Marcia and Martin, discussing the facial features of a potential model; they both see her as having the same organized array of features; however, while Marcia finds her beautiful, Martin finds her completely unappealing. Marcia responds, “You don’t enjoy looking at her? What is wrong with you?” Similar examples abound. One who judges something beautiful one’s enjoyment reveals features the one is convinced are to be enjoyed, not just by oneself, but by anyone—at least anyone who apprehends the item in the same way. One is convinced that the command has it source entirely in the way the item is apprehended, and that—apart from whatever individual traits condition the apprehension—that source is otherwise free of any idiosyncratic taint from one’s wants, aspirations, dreams, values, and the like. Compare enjoying bittersweet chocolate. If Sally enjoys bittersweet chocolate, and Ed does not, Sally does not think that Ed ought to. She just thinks they differ. We capture the idea of beauty commanding enjoyment in terms of reasons: One who judges an item beautiful, on the other hand, is convinced that there is a reason for anyone (everyone who apprehends the item in the same way) to enjoy the item. Smith’s visit to the museum illustrates the point. Smith finds some of the impressionist paintings beautiful, and his conviction that there is a reason to enjoy the paintings serves as a reason for him to do so by visiting the museum. Similarly, when Marcia responds to Martin, “You don’t enjoy looking at her? What is wrong with you?”, she expresses her puzzlement that he does not acknowledge and conform to the reason she is convinced there is to enjoy the model’s face. To characterize the special kind of enjoyment associated with judgments of beauty, we will distinguish two types of reason to enjoy. The distinction is a special case of a general distinction between two types of reason for action. To draw the distinction, we first ask, what is it for something to be a reason for a person to perform an action? We begin with the observation that reasons typically play a characteristic motivationaljustificatory role. An example: Smith devotes considerable time to chess; he studies the game, analyzes his past games, seeks out chess partners, browses in the chess section of bookstores, and so on. When asked why he engages in these activities, he explains that a well-played game displays the beauty of forces in dynamic tension and reveals creativity, courage, and practical judgment in an exercise of intuition and calculation akin to both mathematics and art. These considerations motivate him to engage in a variety of activities; and, they serve as his justification for performing the very actions they motivate. We take it to be clear that reasons play a distinctive motivational-justificatory role. We need not, however, offer any further characterization role that role in order to make it clear what we mean by a reason for action. The chess example, which involves the explicit articulation of reasons, may suggest the implausibly rationalistic view that a reason always plays its motivational-justificatory role through explicit reasoning prior to action. Worse yet in the context of our discussion of beauty, it may associate reasons for action with dispassionate reflection. Reasons may of course operate explicitly and dispassionately. For example, reflecting on his need to improve his ability to blend strategy and tactics, Smith may—explicitly and even dispassionately—reason his way to the conclusion that he should study former world champion Mikhail Tal’s games. The same reasons, however, could operate implicitly and in the presence of passion. Imagine that Smith, without prior reasoning, he accidentally happens on a collection of Tal’s games while wandering around a bookstore to kill time. The collection catches his eye; the conviction, “I need this!” takes hold of him and he straightaway decides to buy the book. The thought and the decision occur against the background of an emotion-laden memory of a recent bitter defeat caused by his lack of skill in blending strategy and tactics. Despite the passion and lack of explicit reasoning, the same reasons that figure in the explicit reasoning may also operate in this case. If Smith were later asked why he bought the book, it would hardly be odd for him to give a reason by saying, “I realized I need to study Tal’s games to improve his ability to blend strategy and tactics.” He doing so he would not only be justifying his choice, he would be citing the reason’s motivational power as an explanation of the action. While on occasion we treat such after the fact rationalizations skeptically as the likely products of self-deception or fabrication, on the whole they are part and parcel of the routine conduct of everyday life, and we, without specific grounds for doubt, we regard them as true. These observations suggest the following initial account of a reason for action: a psychological state (or complex of such states) is a reason for a person to perform an action if and only if the state (or states) plays, or would in appropriate circumstances play, the relevant motivational-justificatory role. We drop the “or complex of such states” qualification from now on. There is no need to take a position on the long-standing debate about what sort of psychological state is required to explain the motivational dimension of reasons. Some—crudely, “Humeans”—will insist that Smith’s beliefs about chess are never sufficient on their own to motivate; they must always be supplemented by a separate motivational state--a desire, hope, aspiration, an allegiance to an ideal, or some such thing. Others—crudely, “Kantians”— will insist that a separate motivational state is not always required; a belief may, in appropriate circumstances, motivate on its own. Each view tends in the direction of the other. Plausible Humeans interpret “desire” broadly to include such diverse sources of motivation as values, ideals, needs, commitments, personal loyalties, and patterns of emotional reaction; plausible Kantians refer to such sources of motivation to explain why the same belief may motivate one person but not another. There is, however, no need to opt for one view or the other; everything we say is consistent with either. We should, however, emphasize one merely terminological point: We will, for convenience, describe beliefs as reasons; one should read in whatever motivational factor one thinks is also required. The suggested initial account conceives of reasons for action as psychological states that do, or would, play a certain motivationaljustificatory role. The difficulty is that a state can be a reason even if it does not, and would not, play the relevant role. Thus: Robert is a prominent wine critic. His doctor informs him he has gout and must, on pain of destroying his health and ultimately his life, stop drinking the rich French wines in which he delights. Robert persists nonetheless; he thinks of himself as a badly injured warrior who, although doomed to defeat, defiantly refuses to cease fighting for his ideal—Robert’s ideal being the refinement of taste as a source of pleasure. When his friends try to change his mind, their arguments fall on deaf ears. Robert acknowledges that if others were in his situation, the health considerations would, for them, serve as a compelling internal reason choose good health over the delight of fine wine; but, as he emphasizes, those considerations play no such role for him. He takes pride in this, seeing it as a sign of the depth of his commitment. The friends think the health considerations are a reason for Robert to abandon his gourmet pursuits, a reason Robert ignores, and they are surely correct. The considerations are a reason in the sense that Robert’s beliefs about the effects of his gourmet pursuits on his health should play the motivational-justificatory role of a reason, even though they do not. This is not to say that the considerations should be decisive; playing a motivational- justificatory role does not mean playing a decisive role. In general, a belief can be a reason for a person even if it does not in fact play the motivationaljustificatory role of a reason for that person. Indeed, the person need not have the belief. If Robert did not believe that his gourmet pursuits were threatening his health, it would still be true that he should form that belief and that it should play the motivational-justificatory role of a reason. One way to accommodate examples like Robert is to define a reason for action as follows: a psychological state is a reason for a person to perform an action if and only if it should be the case that the state plays, or would in appropriate circumstances play, the characteristic motivationaljustificatory role of a reason. This, however, has the uncomfortable consequence that one cannot describe a person’s belief as a reason when one thinks that belief should not play the relevant motivational-justificatory role. Consider the shaman who believes that sacrificing a chicken will help cure a disease that the observing anthropologist knows to be measles. The belief about the efficacy of the sacrifice plays the motivational-justificatory role of a reason for the shaman; the anthropologist, however, thinks the belief should not play that role (on the ground that the shaman’s goal is to provide an efficacious treatment). The anthropologist cannot, under the suggested definition, agree that there is a reason for the shaman to sacrifice the chicken. This seems quite odd as it is not obviously improper to answer, “Is there a reason the shaman is sacrificing the chicken?” with, “Yes, he believes that it will cure the disease.” The solution we adopt is to acknowledge that one uses “reason” ambiguously. One uses it to describe the “does play” cases whether or not the belief should play the motivational-justificatory role of a reason, and one uses it to describe the “should play” cases whether or not the belief does play the relevant role. We will call the belief in the “does play” cases an active reason. More fully, a belief is an active reason if and only if it does, or would in appropriate circumstances, play the motivational-justificatory role of a reason. We will call the belief in the “should play” cases a normative reason. More fully, a belief is a normative reason if and only if it should be an active reason. Thus, an active reason may, but need not be, a normative reason, and normative reason may, but need not be, an active reason. There are of course competing accounts of when normative reasons exist. Typically, views see the existence as depending on various factors— values, ideals, needs, commitments, and the like; to the extent the view holds that disagreements about the existence of normative reasons are not rationally resolvable disagreements, the view embraces a degree of relativism. On such views, Robert’s values (or whatever) may be sufficiently different than the friends’ values (or whatever) that there is a normative reason from their perspective but not from his. We will not address such relativistic claims here; while we do not subscribe to a complete relativism about reasons, everything we say will be consistent with any plausible relativism. One just needs to add to our claims whatever relativization one thinks is required. Now we can provide a provisional characterization of the type of enjoyment on which we base our judgments of beauty. One enjoys x as having an organized array of features F, where: (1) one first-person-authoritatively believes x has F; (2) that belief is a—certain type of—active reason for one’s enjoyment of x as having F; (3) that person regards this belief as a—certain type of—normative reason to enjoy x as having F; (4) one’s enjoyment of x causes or causally sustains (3). The next section motivates conditions (2) and (3) by characterizing the relevant types of reasons. B. The Special Type of Enjoyment An example is helpful. Suppose you and Jones have taken time out of your heavily scheduled business trip to travel from Delhi to Agra to see the Taj Mahal, which you are not both contemplating. Each of you enjoys it; however, you find it beautiful while Jones does not. After an hour, Jones has had enough. He decides it is time to return to the pressing demands of the business trip instead of lingering longer at the Taj. You, however, wish to continue to contemplate and investigate the building, which you feel is just beginning to yield up its treasures. When Jones asks you why, you respond, with surprise, “Why? Just look at the way the whole structure seems almost weightless!” You continue in this vein, articulating your active reason to enjoy the Taj by drawing Jones’ attention the features of the Taj you enjoy. The presence of this reason explains (in part) why you are motivated to continue to contemplate and investigate the features in question, and why you think you are justified in doing so. We take this to be characteristic of the enjoyment of the beautiful: the (first-person authoritative) belief that the item has an organized array of features is an active reason to enjoy the item as having those features. The continued contemplation and investigation may not occur if competing active reasons succeed in directing action along different lines, but, when contemplation and investigation do continue, they may increase the number and richness of the enjoyed features and increase the detail and complexity of the features organization. The result is a richer, more complex and detailed first-person authoritative belief that the item has an organized array of features and hence a more complex and detail active reason. But Jones is unmoved by all this and still wants to leave. Two differences in the reasons you have to enjoy the Taj explain the difference in attitude. The first difference is that Jones’s reasons are derived; yours are not. A reason is a derived active reason for a person to perform an action A if and only if it is a reason for the person to perform A only because there are other distinct reasons for the person to perform other actions, and performing A is a means to performing those other actions. An underived reason is a reason that is not derived. Jones’ active reasons to enjoy the Taj are derived from the principles to which he adheres. The first is that more enjoyment is better than less. Since he enjoys the Taj, he has a reason to make time for that enjoyment among is other pursuits. Jones’s second principle is that one should enjoy significant artistic achievements. He regards the Taj as a significant artistic achievement, so he has a second reason to make time to enjoy it. Were it not for his adherence to these principles, Jones would not—let us assume—have an active reason to enjoy the Taj. After an hour, however, he feels he has devoted enough time to enjoying the Taj and is ready to turn to other pursuits. Your active reason, in contrast, is underived. Your belief that the Taj has certain features is not an active reason only because there are other distinct active reasons for you to perform other actions, and enjoying the Taj is a means to performing those other actions. Enjoying the Taj is, for you, an end in its own right, and you feel that you have just begun to realize that end, that the Taj has much more to reveal. This is characteristic of the enjoyment of beauty: the first-person-authoritative belief that the item has an organized array of features is an underived active reason to enjoy the item has having those features. Typically, this active reason motivates and justifies a sustained interaction which reveals the beauty of the item in a variegated, temporally extended experience. The underived nature of your active reason does not, however, fully explain why you want to continue to contemplate the Taj. Why do the pressing demands of the business trip not take precedence for you over your underived active reason to enjoy the Taj? Because you recognize a second to enjoy the Taj, a reason Jones does not acknowledge. Your first-personauthoritative belief that the Taj has certain features not only serves as an underived active reason to enjoy the Taj, you also regard it as an underived normative reason to do so. Of course, this reason too could yield to the pressing demands of the business trip, but it nonetheless an additional hurdle those demands must overcome. To regard the belief as an underived normative reason to enjoy the Taj is to think that the belief should play the role of an underived active reason. If you were asked why you regard the in this way, you would identify the features you believe the Taj to have, the features you enjoy it as having. Your attitude is, “You can’t see that and not acknowledge that it is to be enjoyed!” The natural—but incorrect— characterization of this attitude is that you regard the fact that the Taj has the features you enjoy as sufficient in and of itself to establish the belief that it has those features should serve as an underived active reason. The problem is that the Taj’s having the organized array is not a matter of objective fact. There is just your first-person-authoritative belief that the Taj has those features; it is in your eyes that Taj reveals itself as possessing an array of features sufficient to establish an underived normative reason to enjoy it. But not only in your eyes. To say that would be to overlook the point emphasized earlier: when beauty commands enjoyment, the command is not personally addressed, but impersonally: not “You should enjoy this,” but “This is to be enjoyed.” We suggest capturing the impersonality of the command the following way. You think that anyone who formed the firstperson authoritative belief that the Taj had the features in question would also be convinced that there was an underived normative reason to enjoy the Taj as having those features. We will have many occasions to use this formula, and it proves convenient to shorten it. To this end, let us say that an underived normative reason is belief-universal when and only when anyone who forms the relevant first-person-authoritative belief will also believe that that underived normative reason exists. We can then simply say that you are convinced that your first-person-authoritative belief that the Taj has a certain array of features is a belief-universal underived normative reason to enjoy the Taj as having those features. We take the conviction that the relevant first-person-authoritative belief is a belief-universal underived normative reason to a defining feature of the special sort of enjoyment that is the ground of the judgment of beauty. In this regard, it is illuminating to compare Jones. When he looks at the Taj, he does not believe that there is a belief-universal underived normative reason to enjoy the Taj. His reasons to enjoy the Taj are entirely derived reasons. In this regard, Jones’ attitude toward the Taj is similar to his attitude toward bittersweet chocolate, which he also enjoys. He devotes some time and attention to enjoying the chocolate because he believes more enjoyment is, other things being equal, better than less, and because the thinks a full life should have some room for sensory pleasures. He does not, however, think that anyone who believes that the chocolate is bittersweet will also believe that there is an underived normative reason to enjoy the chocolate as bittersweet. We do not deny that a chocolate gourmet might have such a belief. Imagine the gourmet, aware of chocolate’s manifold possibilities, locates this realization of bitter sweetness in a complex of similar discriminations and thereby reveals this particular realization of the taste as something that should be highly prized. Jones, however, is no chocolate gourmet; he just tastes an undifferentiated bitter sweetness, and by no means believes that there is an underived normative reason to enjoy the chocolate as bittersweet. The enjoyment of beauty differs in precisely this way from the routine enjoyment of chocolate. One who finds an item beautiful sees it as making a claim on everyone that it should be enjoyed— everyone, that is, who forms the relevant first-person-authoritative belief. One of course sometimes also thinks that everyone should form the relevant belief. Many evidently take such a view of the Taj, one of the Seven Wonders of the World. Those who take this view regard those who fail to believe as they to as suffering from an impaired apprehension of the item: if they were just able to apprehend the item in an unimpaired way, they would form the relevant belief. We will consider such cases in more detail in Section IV. At the moment, however, the point to emphasize is that there are many examples in which it just reveals one’s lack of appreciation of the ways in which others may be different to insist that others should believe as one does. Consider Wallace Stevens’ poem, “Sunday Morning,” which offers Stevens’ reflections, from a distinctly non-Christian perspective, on the Christian story of the crucifixion of Christ, the sacrament of communion, and the Christian promise of an immortal afterlife. Vicki enjoys reading the poem and finds it beautiful. If asked why she thinks the poem beautiful, she would point out the features she enjoys—the elegance and precision of the language, the power of the metaphors, and so on. Vicki regards her firstperson authoritative belief that the poem has these features as an underived normative reason to enjoy the poem as having those features. Now imagine Guanglei, a Buddhist graduate student in Beijing reads “Sunday Morning” and finds it opaque and boring. He does not form the same first-personauthoritative belief that Vicki does. Should he? It is difficult to see how this could be true. Seeing in “Sunday Morning” what Vicki does requires some understanding—both cognitive and affective—of the Christian picture of purification through suffering, forgiveness through communion, and the reward of immortality to the faithful. Ought Guanglei immerse himself in Christian culture to better appreciate the poem? Perhaps, if one eliminates the constraints of time, the press of practical demands, the limits of memory, and understanding, and the like. But surely not if one imagines Guanglei in the midst of his pursuit of a life to which the Christian background of Sunday Morning is utterly foreign and completely irrelevant. To summarize, we restate the suggested characterization of the relevant type of enjoyment. One enjoys an item x as having an organized array of features, where: (1) one first-person-authoritatively believes x has F; (2) that belief is an underived active reason for one’s enjoyment of x as having F; (3) that person regards this belief as a belief-universal underived normative reason to enjoy x as having F; (4) one’s enjoyment of x causes or causally sustains (3). We turn to the causal claim. C. Causation The causal claim is that your enjoyment causes you to regard your belief that the Taj has a certain array of features as a belief-universal underived normative reason to enjoy the item as having that array. The claim resolves an otherwise awkward difficulty. To see the problem, suppose Ed has never seen Gauguin’s Riders On The Beach. The first time he lays eyes on it, he enjoys in the special way just characterized and judges it beautiful. It follows that he regards the relevant first-person-authoritative belief that the painting has a certain array of features as a belief-universal underived normative reason to enjoy the item as having that array. The difficulty is that it is far from routine to form the conviction that an underived normative reason exists as the result of a single experience of a particular item. Compare this example. A mugger threatens Victoria with a knife. She could safely retreat, but she does not consider that option; attitudes inculcated through years of self-defense classes take hold, and, confident that she can repel the attacker, she stands her ground. When he attacks, it is necessary for her to use deadly force to repel the danger, and she kills the would-be mugger. Was there a normative reason for Victoria to retreat? And, if so, should that reason have been a decisive one? Edwards, upon reading the report of the incident, immediately forms the belief that no normative reason existed for Victoria to retreat, and that, if it had, it should not have been decisive. Edwards does not, however, take the formation of his belief to be sufficient to establish that that it is true. He takes as a starting point for discussion and investigation; if he pursues the matter, he will see if others agree, if his view of Victoria is consistent with other particular and general judgments about normative reasons. So what explains your regarding the belief about the Taj as sufficient to establish the existence of a normative reason? Because your enjoyment causes you to regard the belief in that way. Through enjoyment, beauty takes hold of one and makes one believe that there is a normative reason for one—anyone who apprehends it as one does—to enjoy it. A further elaboration of the Taj example provides support. Disturbed by his failure to find the Taj beautiful, Jones returns the next day, having spent the prior evening studying expert discussions of the Taj. He looks at the Taj again—armed this time with a thorough knowledge of the features the experts regard as contributing to the Taj’s beauty. When he looks at the Taj, he sees that it does indeed have the organized array of features the experts identify. He sees this through his own eyes; that is, he forms the first-person authoritative belief that the Taj has the array. He enjoys the Taj as having that array, and the belief serves as an active reason to enjoy the Taj. He even regards the belief that the Taj has the array as an underived normative reason to enjoy the Taj as having that array. But he regards the belief in this way only because his reading of the experts has convinced him it is true. He finds no ground for the belief in his own experience. As he says, “The Taj does not speak to me in the way it evidently speaks to others,” and he still does not find the Taj beautiful. He thinks it is a nicely designed building, and he enjoys the harmony of the design, but, as far as he is concerned, the Taj belongs with the wide variety of other things— including bathrooms, HBO’s Sex and the City, and an immense variety of faces and bodies—that he enjoys it as harmoniously designed but that he does not regard as beautiful. He continues to regard the belief that the Taj has the array as an underived normative reason to enjoy the Taj as having that array, but this belief persists in spite of, not because of, his experiences. Now imagine that, in the midst of his disappointment about not finding the Taj beautiful, Jones notices the unexpected presence of a friend, who is also contemplating the Taj. They fall into conversation for some time, and, then, in a lull in the conversation, Jones happens, without thinking about it, to look back at the Taj. He looks without any expectations, without any explicit thought about the expert-identified features which he was scrutinizing earlier. Suddenly, the building speaks to him in a way it did not before: he enjoys it has having the expert-identified array of features, and, this time, the enjoyment causes him to regard his belief that it has the array as an underived normative reason to enjoy the Taj. The belief persists in spite of, not because of, his experiences. Jones thinks, “Now I see! It is beautiful!” In general, when one enjoys an item one finds beautiful, one’s enjoyment of the item as testifies to its own justification by causing (or causally sustaining) one’s regarding one’s belief that the item has an array of features is an underived normative reason to enjoy the item. The Jones example illustrates how our talk of “causes or causally sustains” is to be understood in the context of everyday causal explanations. The identification of causes in such explanations is highly pragmatic. When eight-year-old Sally asks her mother why the mill wheel turns, Catherine replies that the wheel turns because the water strikes it. When Sally, now an undergraduate, is working on a similar homework problem for her Physics course, her answer includes a calculation of the friction in the mill wheel system. Our only claim is that we can, and do, make distinctions of the sort illustrated by the Jones example—between convictions that persist in spite of, not because of one’s experiences, and convictions that persist because of, not in spite of, them. We propose a further causal condition: one’s enjoyment of the item as having an organized array of features is not only the cause of one’s regarding the belief as a belief-universal underived normative reason, the enjoyment is also the effect of one’s so regarding the belief. One enjoys an item x as having an organized array of features, where: (1) one first-person-authoritatively believes x has F; (2) that belief is an underived active reason for one’s enjoyment of x as having F; (3) that person regards this belief as a belief-universal underived normative reason to enjoy x as having F; (4) one’s enjoyment of x as having F causes or causally sustains (3), and (3) causally sustains one’s enjoyment of x as having F. III. The Third Claim The third claim is that to judge that something is beautiful is to judge that, other things being equal, others will enjoy the item in the way just characterized. To elaborate and defend this account, we need a name for the type of enjoyment characterized in the last section; thus, where one enjoys an item as having an organized array of features, and, in doing so, meets conditions (1) – (4), let us say that one b-enjoys the item as having those features. We claim: to judge that something is beautiful is to judge that others will, other things being equal, b-enjoy the item as having the organized array of features, provided that they form the relevant firstperson-authoritative belief that the item has the array. The reason for the judgment is one’s own b-enjoyment. That reason is required because to judge that something is beautiful is not merely to assert that others will enjoy as one does, it is to declare that one’s own enjoyment is an adequate reason for the assertion. The following example illustrates the account. Carol is looking at Michelangelo’s David. She b-enjoys the statute for the way the sensuous harmony of the naked form expresses composure, confidence, and readiness for action, and for this reason judges it beautiful. It follows that she regards her belief that the David exhibits those features as a belief-universal underived normative reason to enjoy the item as having those features. This attitude toward is built into the enjoyment itself; however, when Carol judges that the David is beautiful, she adds an additional claim about others: she asserts that those who form the same first-person-authoritative belief will b-enjoy the David as having the same array of features, and hence that their enjoyment will reveal to them that the relevant normative reason exists. These others will have the same reason Carol does to judge the David beautiful, and, since Carol regards that reason as adequate, she assumes they will judge accordingly. The key step in motivating this account is to explain why one would assume that relevant others will b-enjoy as one does. Carol’s b-enjoyment is ground for attributing a like enjoyment to others only if she assumes they are relevantly similar to her, and the question is what ground she has for such an assumption. One might appeal to a shared human nature: one can expect other to enjoy as one does because others share the same human nature. This is scarcely plausible given the considerable disagreement over judgments of beauty among different cultures as well as within the same culture, and, if shared-human-nature proponents respond that it is only certain key aspects that are shared, one is owed not only an explanation of what they are, but of how everyone who makes a judgment of beauty knows what they are. We think this demand cannot be met. This may seem to land us in a difficult position. We insist that, when one judges something beautiful, one takes one’s b-enjoyment to be an adequate reason for the judgment. But, without some assumption of a shared nature, how can it serve as adequate reason? To see the problem, consider that one who b-enjoys an item is convinced that the relevant the first-person-authoritative belief as a belief-universal underived normative reason to enjoy the item as having certain features. That is, one believes that anyone who forms the belief will recognize the reason. But this conviction simply arises in one as a causal product of one’s enjoyment. Absent some assumption of a shared nature, how can one have a reason for it? And, even if one did, having a reason to believe others will recognize the reason is not the same has having a reason to think that the will b-enjoy the item. They might acknowledge the reason in the absence of the enjoyment. So, absent some assumption of a share nature, how can one’s b-enjoyment possibly be an adequate reason to judge that others will b-enjoy as one does? It cannot. That is, it cannot be an adequate reason for the empirical prediction that others will b-enjoy as one does. It can, however, be an adequate reason for the hypothesis—advanced for future confirmation or disconfirmation—that others will so enjoy. To see the idea, recall a point we emphasize earlier: it is a fundamental fact about beauty that it commands enjoyment. We interpreted this command as the conviction, caused by the enjoyment itself, anyone who formed the relevant first-person-authoritative belief would recognize, as one does, the existence of an underived normative reason to enjoy the item. One sees forming the belief as sufficient in and of itself for the recognition of the reason and hence does not see the acknowledgment of the reason as depending in any other way on idiosyncratic wants, aspirations, dreams, values, and the like. To judge that something is beautiful is to advance the hypothesis that one is right about lack of dependency. It is to formulate, for confirmation or disconfirmation, the hypothesis that others will b-enjoy as one does and hence, through their own enjoyment, agree that the normative reason exists. One’s enjoyment is an adequate reason to formulate this hypothesis, as we will explain more fully shortly. A continuation of the David example is helpful. Suppose Carol expresses her view that the David is beautiful to her companion, Mason; Mason, who does not b-enjoy the statute, replies, “Sadly, not for me.” Carol first assumes that Mason simply fails to find in the statute the sensuous harmony expressive of composure, confidence, and readiness for action, but she is quickly corrected. Mason, an art historian, offers a description of the David that elaborates on the sensuous harmony theme in ways that Carol finds illuminating and that deepens her b-enjoyment; in offering the description, Mason is not merely reporting the views of other experts; he sees what he is describing with his own eyes and is articulating his own firstperson-authoritative belief. Carol is now even more puzzled. She cannot understand how Mason can see the statute as he does and not find it beautiful. She suggests to him that a homophobia-induced inability to enjoy looking at a naked male body prevents him from b-enjoying the statue and on that basis finding it beautiful. Mason, who is gay, responds that he is certain that homophobia is not the problem. He nonetheless does not benjoy the David, and never has; he does not know why. Mason acknowledges that many others agree with Carol, and he is more than willing on that basis to agree that the David is beautiful, but this agreement does not express his judgment that the statue is beautiful. He makes no such judgment; his agreement merely acknowledges the view of the majority of others. Mason is not a member of that community. As the example illustrates, there are two dimensions to Mason’s failure to b-enjoy the David: it falsifies Carol’s assumption that he would do so, and it excludes him from a community b-enjoyers. We focus on the latter dimension, for the moment. The assumption that others will b-enjoy as one does need not be seen as an ungrounded empirical prediction but as a step toward a community of like b-enjoyers, a beacon that may attract others who agree. We have any number of reasons to seek the agreement of others on any number of points, and, in the case of beauty, one is typically concerned to discover whether one’s unsupported conviction that there is a beliefuniversal normative reason to enjoy really is belief-universal; that is, is it really true that anyone who forms the relevant belief will also acknowledge the existence of the normative reason? The agreement of others confirms that, despite the subjectivity of one’s attribution of the relevant features to the item, one’s vision transcends the contingent limitations of one’s particular situation and reveals something valid for all other similar believers. We suggest that, given our many and varied reasons to seek the agreement of others, one’s b-enjoyment of an item is sufficient reason for one to judge it beautiful, to advance, for confirmation or disconfirmation, the claim that those who form the same first-person-authoritative belief will b-enjoy the item as one does, and hence will acknowledge that the relevant normative reason exists. Now let us turn to the other dimension of Mason’s failure to b-enjoy the David. The failure is a counter instance to Carol’s judgment that others will, other things being equal, b-enjoy the David as having the relevant organized array of features, provided that they form the first-person authoritative belief that the item has that array. How is Carol to revise her judgment? She has three options. First, she can leave her judgment unrevised. It is an “other things being equal” judgment, and, her position can be that other things are, for some unknown reason, not equal in Mason’s case. Some disagreements over beauty are plausibly disagreements over whether “other things” are “equal.” Consider feminists who deny the Taj Mahal is beautiful because they regard it as a monument to male domination. One who judged the Taj beautiful might dismiss the feminists’ denial on the ground that other things are not equal: their feminists’ views distort their judgment of the Taj in the way homophobia might distort one’s judgment about the David. The feminists would hardly agree! And that is precisely our point: some controversies over beauty are plausibly represented as controversies over whether other things are equal. The claim that other things are not equal is, course, not a plausible defense if one encounters widespread disagreement with a judgment of beauty. This is not to deny that it is possible for “other things” not to be “equal” across the board; evil space aliens may have the responses of almost everyone. Such eventualities are extremely unlikely, however. So what could Carol do if, implausibly, almost everyone disagreed with her judgment that the David was beautiful. She might decide—and this is the second of the three options—that she had not identified the relevant organized array of features with sufficient precision and detail. Perhaps she could count on agreement from those who form the first-person-authoritative belief that the David has a certain richer, and more complex array of features. Consider another illustration. Suppose Mason finds beautiful the opening lines of the poem in Nabokov’s Pale Fire (a waxwing is a robin): I was the shadow of the waxwing slain By the false azure in the window pane; I was the smudge of ashen fluff—and I Lived on, flew on, in that reflected sky. Mason first-person-authoritatively believes that the lines capture the situation of a self-consciousness that identifies itself only with its own selfconscious thoughts and imaginings, not with any contingent circumstance in which that self-consciousness happens to be embodied. Carol forms the same first-person-authoritative belief, but she thinks any sufficiently mature adult should regard the lines as the adolescent and indefensible refusal to accept that the self is embodied in a particular contingent setting, and, far from regarding the lines as beautiful, she finds their adolescent indulgence unpleasant. Grant, for the sake of argument, that the vast majority of readers agree with Carol. Mason could respond by attempting to reformulate his first-person-authoritative assessment of the lines in a way that sidestepped the charge of adolescent indulgence. He might, for example, set the lines in the context of the rest of the poem and see the lines, not as the endorsement of a self-consciousness refusing to identify with anything beyond its own self-consciousness, but as introducing the plight of such a self-consciousness and laying the foundation for considering ways to escape its isolation (the first line, after all, reads “I was” not “I am”). We suggest that debates over beauty exhibit just this sort of criticism and redefinition. The third, and final, possibility is one is just wrong. If most who form the relevant belief do not b-enjoy the item, it is misleading to describe the item as beautiful. In such a case, one might say, “Well, I think it is beautiful!”, but one misleads if one invites someone home to view the item on the assurance that it is beautiful. We defer to the next section the question of the size of a b-enjoyment community needed to support a judgment of beauty that is not misleading. A final point: in the David example, we implicitly assumed that Carol’s judgment of beauty was cotemporaneous with her b-enjoyment. Similar remarks hold when one’s b-enjoyment is in the past or expected in the future. Past b-enjoyments raise no particular issues, but the expected benjoyment is worth an example. Imagine that, as you rush through the museum, a sculpture catches your eye, and I think “Beautiful; if I had time, I would enjoy it.” Your prediction of enjoyment is based on your first-person authoritative belief that the painting has a certain array of features. You know yourself well enough to reliably predict that you would enjoy the sculpture in a way that fulfills (1) – (5). So far we have focused heavily on why one would expect others to benjoy as one does, and we have emphasized the role of communities of similar b-enjoyers. In doing so, we emphasized that the agreement of others confirms that the way in which one apprehends the things one finds beautiful transcends particular situation and reveals something valid for all other similar believers. We conclude this section by noting that this aspect of the account of beauty provides a satisfying explanation of the claim, often made, that beauty involves the display of the “universal” in the “particular.” Our purpose is just to underscore the fact that to judge that something is beautiful is to claim that one’s subjective assessment of an item nonetheless provides a basis for a claim valid for others. We begin with Plato, who advances a version of the universal in the particular claim. For Plato, the Form of Beauty (the “universal”) shines through the particulars in which it is instantiated (or better, reflected) with such power that the enjoyment of beauty has a unique power to awaken in us a memory of our prior perception of, and love for, the eternal Form itself. The “universal in the particular” retains its appeal even when one abandons the metaphysics of the Forms. Wallace Stevens offers a distinctly non-Platonic formulation of the claim: Beauty is momentary in the mind— But the fitful tracing of a portal; But in the flesh it is immortal. The body dies, the body’s beauty lives. Stevens’ lines seem to express a deep truth about the display of universality in transient particulars. But what truth? When we try to articulate it, we seem to produce only disappointing banalities. This is especially true in the case of literary works. Novels, for example, contain a wealth of detail about particular characters in particular contingent circumstances. How is someone who judges one of the novels to be beautiful supposed to find “the universal” in the midst of the mass of contingencies? Of course, the novel will almost certainly contain “universal themes,” themes found throughout literature: for example, people may fall in love, or mistakenly think they fallen in love, but may or may not realize it until it is, or is not, too late. But surely the insight that beauty consists in the display of the universal in the particular does not reduce to the banality that literary works tend to contain common themes. The problem also arises with visual works. Michelangelo’s David is often offered as an example of masculine beauty, but what is the “universal” displayed in the particular statute? Surely it is not just that other exemplars of masculine beauty sometimes have similar features. There is more than that to the idea that beauty is immortal in the flesh. Those who assert the universal in the particular claim mean to offer a deep insight, not make an obvious empirical generalization. We suggest the following way to rescue the insight. In the case of items one deems beautiful, the “universal” in the particular consists in one’s regarding the first-person authoritative belief that the item has a certain array of features as an underived normative reason to enjoy the item has having those features. When one finds a statue or a novel beautiful, the features which figure in one’s belief may be unique to the statute or novel. One may cite the particular way in which Michelangelo’s David portrays both calm composure and immediate readiness for action, or the particular way in which characters interact in a novel. The claim to universality is the claim that, unique though the features may be, an underived normative reason to enjoy the statute or novel as having those features exists for anyone who forms the relevant belief. IV. Objections and Replies