Hobbes File

advertisement
Negative liberty is defined as freedom from interference by other
people, and is set in contrast to positive liberty, which is defined as an
individual's freedom from inhibitions of the social structure within the
society such as classism, sexism or racism and is primarily concerned with
the possession of sociological agency. According to Thomas Hobbes, "a
free man is he that in those things which by his strength and wit he is
able to do is not hindered to do what he hath the will to do" (Leviathan,
Ch. XXI, [2], thus alluding to liberty in its negative sense).
The distinction between negative and positive liberty was drawn originally
by Hegel[but most famous in the anglophone tradition by Isaiah Berlin in
his 1958 lecture "Two Concepts of Liberty." According to Berlin, the
distinction is deeply embedded in the political tradition. In Berlin's
words, "liberty in the negative sense involves an answer to the question:
'What is the area within which the subject — a person or group of
persons — is or should be left to do or be what he is able to do or be,
without interference by other persons'."[1] Restrictions on negative
liberty are imposed by a person, not by natural causes or incapacity.
Helvetius expresses the point clearly: "The free man is the man who is
not in irons, nor imprisoned in a gaol, nor terrorized like a slave by the
fear of punishment ... it is not lack of freedom, not to fly like an eagle or
swim like a whale."
Negative liberty and authority: Hobbes and Locke
Full
name
Thomas Hobbes
Born
5 April 1588
Westport near Malmesbury,
Wiltshire, England
Died
4 December 1679 (aged 91)
Derbyshire, England
Era
17th-century philosophy
(Modern Philosophy)
One might ask, "How is men's desire for liberty to be reconciled with the
assumed need for authority?" Its answer by various thinkers provides a
fault line for understanding their view on liberty but also a cluster of
intersecting concepts such as authority, equality, and justice.
Hobbes and Locke give two influential and representative solutions to this
question. As a starting point, both agree that a line must be drawn and a
space sharply delineated where each individual can act unhindered
according to their tastes, desires, and inclinations. This zone defines the
sacrosanct space of personal liberty. But, they believe no society is
possible without some authority, where the intended purpose of authority
is to prevent collisions among the different ends and, thereby, to
demarcate the boundaries where each person's zone of liberty begins and
ends. Where Hobbes and Locke differ is the extent of the zone. Hobbes,
who took a rather negative view of human nature, argued that a strong
authority was needed to curb men's intrinsically wild, savage, and corrupt
impulses. Only a powerful authority can keep at bay the permanent and
always looming threat of anarchy. Locke believed, on the other hand, that
men on the whole are more good than wicked and, accordingly, the area
for individual liberty can be left rather at large.
Locke is a slightly more ambiguous case than Hobbes because although his
conception of liberty was largely negative (in terms of non-interference),
he differed in that he courted the "republican" (classical) tradition of
liberty by rejecting the notion that an individual could be free if he was
under the arbitrary power of another:
"This freedom from absolute, arbitrary power, is so necessary to, and
closely joined with a man's preservation, that he cannot part with it, but
by what forfeits his preservation and life together: for a man, not having
the power of his own life, cannot, by compact, or his own consent, enslave
himself to any one, nor put himself under the absolute, arbitrary power of
another, to take away his life, when he pleases. No body can give more
power than he has himself; and he that cannot take away his own life,
cannot give another power over it. Indeed, having by his fault forfeited
his own life, by some act that deserves death; he, to whom he has
forfeited it, may (when he has him in his power) delay to take it, and
make use of him to his own service, and he does him no injury by it: for,
whenever he finds the hardship of his slavery outweigh the value of his
life, it is in his power, by resisting the will of his master, to draw on
himself the death he desires."[6]
Monarchy
Thomas Hobbes' Leviathan outlines a commonwealth based upon a
monarchy to whom citizens have ceded their rights. The basic reasoning
for Hobbes' assertion that this system was most ideal relates more to
Hobbes' value of order and simplicity in government. The monarchy
provides for its subjects, and its subjects go about their day-to-day lives
without interaction with the government:
The commonwealth is instituted when all agree in the following manner: I
authorise and give up my right of governing myself to this man, or to this
assembly of men, on this condition; that thou give up, thy right to him,
and authorise all his actions in like manner. The sovereign has twelve
principal rights:
1. because a successive covenant cannot override a prior one, the
subjects cannot (lawfully) change the form of government.
2. because the covenant forming the commonwealth is the subjects
giving to the sovereign the right to act for them, the sovereign
cannot possibly breach the covenant; and therefore the subjects
can never argue to be freed from the covenant because of the
actions of the sovereign.
3. the selection of sovereign is (in theory) by majority vote; the
minority have agreed to abide by this.
4. every subject is author of the acts of the sovereign: hence the
sovereign cannot injure any of his subjects, and cannot be accused
of injustice.
5. following this, the sovereign cannot justly be put to death by the
subjects.
6. because the purpose of the commonwealth is peace, and the
sovereign has the right to do whatever he thinks necessary for the
preserving of peace and security and prevention of discord,
therefore the sovereign may judge what opinions and doctrines are
averse; who shall be allowed to speak to multitudes; and who shall
examine the doctrines of all books before they are published.
7. to prescribe the rules of civil law and property.
8. to be judge in all cases.
9. to make war and peace as he sees fit; and to command the army.
10. to choose counsellors, ministers, magistrates and officers.
11. to reward with riches and honour; or to punish with corporal or
pecuniary punishment or ignominy.
12. to establish laws of honour and a scale of worth.
Hobbes explicitly rejects the idea of Separation of Powers, in particular
the form that would later become the separation of powers under the
United States Constitution. Part 6 is a perhaps under-emphasised feature
of Hobbes's argument: his is explicitly in favour of censorship of the
press and restrictions on the rights of free speech, should they be
considered desirable by the sovereign in order to promote order.
Upon closer inspection of Hobbes' Leviathan, it becomes clear that
Hobbes believed individual people in society must give up liberty to a
sovereign. Whether that sovereign is an absolute monarch or other form
was left open to debate, however Hobbes himself viewed the absolute
monarch as the best of all options. Hobbes himself said,
For as amongst masterless men, there is perpetual war, of every man
against his neighbour; no inheritance, to transmit to the son, nor to
expect from the father; no propriety of goods, or lands; no security; but
a full and absolute liberty in every particular man: so in states, and
commonwealths not dependent on one another, every commonwealth, not
every man, has an absolute liberty, to do what it shall judge, that is to
say, what that man, or assembly that representeth it, shall judge most
conducing to their benefit.[7]
From this quote it is clear that Hobbes contended that people in a state
of nature ceded their individual rights to create sovereignty, retained by
the state, in return for their protection and a more functional society. In
essence, a social contract between the sovereign and citizens evolves out
of pragmatic self-interest. Hobbes named the state Leviathan, thus
pointing to the artifice involved in the social contract.[8][9] In this vein,
Hobbes' concept of negative liberty was built upon the notion that the
state would not act upon its subjects because its subjects had willingly
relinquished their liberties.
Download