The Stumbling Blocks of Contextualism: Presentism and Antiquarianism EVGENY ROSHCHIN Introduction More than ten years ago David Runciman pointed to the triumphant victory of ‘contextualism’ in the history of political thought, which had been confirmed by the decades of research first stimulated by the great methodological disputes and controversies over linguistic action and the role of context in the 1960s-1970s. At that time the reputation of this approach was already so strong that, as Runciman noted, serious questions about its methods were no longer raised.1 The discipline of International Relations (IR) lagged behind political theory in debating the ways of accommodating intellectual history in its political and research agenda.2 Nevertheless, as David Armitage observes, we are now living through the renaissance in the studies of history of international political thought. 3 Most of the key contributions to this burgeoning literature, as well as on disciplinary history of IR, are faithful to the premises of contextualism, such as those by Armitage,4 Richard Tuck,5 Beate Jahn,6 Edward Keene7 and Duncan Bell.8 One of the key sources of methodological inspiration for David Runciman, ‘History of Political Thought: The State of the Discipline’, British Journal of Politics and International Relations, 3:1 (2001), pp. 84-7. 2 For an example of raising the problem of history and disciplinary history in IR see contributions to a Special forum on the role of history in IR in Millennium: Journal of International Studies 37: 2 (2008); and Geoffrey Roberts, ‘History, Theory and the Narrative Turn in IR’, Review of International Studies, 32:4 (2006), pp. 70314. 3 David Armitage, Foundations of Modern International Thought (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2013), p. 24. 4 In addition to Armitage 2013, see David Armitage, The Ideological Origins of the British Empire (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000). 5 Richard Tuck, The Rights of War and Peace: Political Thought and the International Order from Grotius to Kant (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999; repr. 2009). 6 Beate Jahn (ed.), Classical Theory in International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). 7 See his Beyond the Anarchical Society: Grotius, Colonialism and Order in World Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002); International Political Thought: A Historical Introduction (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2005); ‘The Development of the Concept of International Society: An Essay on Political Argument in International Relations Theory’, in Beverly Neufeld and Michi Ebata (eds.) Confronting the Political: International Relations at the Millennium (London: Macmillan Press, 2001), pp. 17-46. 8 Duncan Bell (ed.), Victorian Visions of Global Order: Empire and International Relations in Nineteenth Century Political Thought (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007). In addition to these monographs, there is a number of research articles in various IR journals that identify themselves as contextualist and rhetorical studies, e.g. Casper Sylvest, ‘Interwar Internationalism, the British Labour Party, and the 1 1 many of these works is the approach practiced by a number of scholars labelled collectively as a ‘Cambridge school’ and more specifically by Quentin Skinner.9 The exponents of contextualist approach in IR enthusiastically endorsed its original aims of fighting anachronistic, ‘presentist’ and, thus, distorted and mythological accounts of classical political thought necessitated by the needs of the present-day theory.10 Instead of prevailing tendency to build such teleological accounts of history and universal historical laws, they advocated historicist reading of past concepts and arguments in their own context, which reveals the degrees of contingency and particularity that not only undermine the legitimacy of mainstream canons (i.e. realism, liberalism and the English School), but possibly also their accounts of universal rules of social conduct.11 For this reason commentators noted the efficacy of Skinner’s approach for the reconstruction of the politics of disciplinary history highlighting the ways in which arguments are sidelined and concepts redescribed as a result of political choices made by the contributors to the debate.12 The growing popularity of contextualist approach to the study of history of international political thought contributes to concurrently growing anxiety about the problems that it presumably bears. Contextualist studies in IR seem to take for granted the overall orientation of Skinner’s approach and omit the problematic formulation of the tasks contained therein. Namely, what remains problematic is the relation of such research to the present. One part of the overall problem stems from the understanding of context as comprising numerous historically distant texts engaging in debate with each other according to certain rules and belonging to a specific social milieu.13 For some the turn to context as an exogenous factor explaining disciplinary history in itself might be distorting as it is likely to ‘participate in the Historiography of International Relations’, International Studies Quarterly, 48:2 (2004), p. 414; Christopher Hobson, ‘Beyond the End of History: The Need for a ‘Radical Historicisation’ of Democracy in International Relations’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies 37:3 (2009), pp. 637-9; Evgeny Roshchin, ‘(Un)Natural and Contractual International Society: A Conceptual Inquiry’, European Journal of International Relations 19:2 (2013), pp. 257-279; Ian Hall, ‘Power Politics and Appeasement: Political Realism in British International Thought, c.1935-1955’, The British Journal of Politics and International Relations 8 (2006), pp. 175-6. 9 See a collection of his essays on method in Quentin Skinner, Visions of Politics, Vol. 1: Regarding Method (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002). I shall not discuss in this article the project of Begriffsgeschichte because my argument will emphasize rhetorical contestation and genealogical orientation of the history of concepts. 10 Beate Jahn, ‘Classical Theory and International Relations in Context’, Beate Jahn (ed.), Classical Theory, pp. 6-16. 11 See Keene, International Political Thought, pp. 4-5. 12 See Duncan S.A. Bell, ‘Language, Legitimacy, and the Project of Critique’, Alternatives: Global, Local, Political, 27:3 (2002), p. 330; Duncan S.A. Bell, ‘Political Theory and the Functions of Intellectual History: A Response to Emmanuel Navon’, Review of International Studies, 29 (2003), pp. 157-8. 13 For this reason Kari Palonen defines Skinner’s approach as ‘pointilist’ history, see his Quentin Skinner: History, Politics, Rhetoric (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2003), p. 179. 2 presentist agenda of legitimation and critique and, in one way or another, reinforce the conventional image of the field’s history in terms of successive idealist, realist, and behavioral phases’.14 This is a common misunderstanding of contextualist interpretations. Skinner’s approach, for instance, explicitly rejects the possibility of explaining historical texts by reference to their social context and confines its analysis to speech-acts and their conventions.15 Nor does this approach prioritise meaning over action. As Skinner always emphasises, the task of the history of speech-acts is to place them within the broader debate in order to see what the authors might have been doing, instead of identifying what they thought they were doing.16 Any claims about the author’s intentions can only have the status of hypothesis, ‘for which we can hope to assemble a great deal of evidence’ 17 by contrasting it with the relevant context. Skinner admits that this task is accomplished by establishing intertextuality among the scrutinized works.18 Thus, by establishing the relations to other texts and arguments we can hypothesise about the intentions and actions of an author.19 However, for the sceptics the study of such context potentially bears little, if any, implications to ‘broader’ questions of social science and the present-day concerns that IR seeks to address, at the same time provoking fear of lapsing into historical relativism.20 Therefore, some critics in IR are tempted to present contextualist methods as one out of many tools that help to formulate ‘big’ questions for comparative studies or even to portray 14 Brian C. Schmidt, The Political Discourse of Anarchy: A Disciplinary History of International Relations (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1997), p. 33-7. This suggestion is not totally misplaced because even among contextualists arguments are made for the inclusion of relevant political contexts into analysis see James Farr, ‘Understanding Conceptual Change Politically’, in Terrence Ball et al. (eds) Political Innovation and Conceptual Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), p. 41. Moreover, such supporters of contextualism in IR as Duncan Bell argue that more inclusive approaches embracing institutions and networks fit better for the study of disciplinary history, see his ‘Writing the World: Disciplinary History and Beyond’, International Affairs 85 (2009): 10–12. 15 Bell, ‘Language, Legitimacy’, p. 331; Gerard Holden, ‘Who Contextualizes the Contextualizers? Disciplinary History and the Discourse about IR Discourse’, Review of International Studies 28 (2002), p. 261; Skinner, Visions of Politics, Vol. 1: Regarding Method. 16 Quentin Skinner, ‘Is It Still Possible to Interpret Texts?’, International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 89 (2008), p. 654. 17 Ibid., p. 653. 18 Ibid., p. 652. Currently, establishing intertextuality seems to be an accepted solution. For instance, Holden seems to believe that context can be identified with sufficient accuracy (Holden, ‘Who Contextualizes the Contextualizers?’, p. 263), which however looks like a much too assured a conclusion as contexts always elude identification by multiplying. 19 Bell, ‘Language, Legitimacy’, p. 331 20 For the argument on the study of concepts as the province of political theory and the difference in scope with social science see Richard Ned Lebow, A Cultural Theory of International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), p. 40. 3 constructivist philosophy of history as ‘Skinnerian’.21 This is, however, to underappreciate the claim that language is not a neutral reservoir of information but in itself a tool of framing and making politics and, thus, the history of arguments and concepts can be an independent and legitimate field of study.22 The other part of the problem consists in the paradox of presentism permeating the contextualist studies and reflections upon them. As mentioned above, one of the key tasks of contextualism is to challenge ‘ahistoricist’ canons of established traditions of thought or historical mythologies tailored to legitimise present-day discourses.23 Paradoxically, the advocates of the Skinnerian contextualism are likely to commit the presentist fallacy themselves were they prepared to simply adopt Skinner’s linguistic and rhetorical approach. Armitage in a self-critical reflection over the development of ‘international intellectual history’ noted a possibility of ‘presentism’ in such studies,24 i.e. a bias in selecting the fragments of historical material under the pressure of the present-day concerns. I shall argue that the problem of presentism and the identity of the ‘concept’ may be recognised already in Skinner’s early works on the use of language and can be traced in his later rhetorical and genealogical investigation of concepts. I also argue that the solution to this problem may be found in reformulation of research tasks that have been presented in contextualist IR studies as well as in Skinner’s recent rhetorical and genealogical essays. Such contextualist challenging by means of historicisation leaves the epistemological status of the challenger unclear and may replace one sort of presentism with another. Moreover, it is unclear how discovered contingency of a certain argument or concept, which can only belong to a specific historical episode, can be utilised in contemporary debates. In fact, if contextualist research were only meant to destabilise traditions by showing contingency of their constitutive elements, it would certainly generate fear of having one’s research pigeonholed as only having an antiquarian value and with little relevance to current debates. Skinner himself contributes to the proliferation of this anxiety, when he famously proclaims in Liberty before Liberalism that he leaves the reader to ‘ruminate’ on the Christian Reus-Smit, ‘Reading History through Constructivist Eyes’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 37:2 (2008), p. 400; see also Christian Reus-Smit, ‘The Idea of History and History with Ideas’, in Stephen Hobden and John M. Hobson (eds) Historical Sociology of International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), pp. 120-40. For the critique of such labeling see Ben Holland, ‘Sovereignty as Dominium? Reconstructing the Constructivist Roman Law Thesis’, International Studies Quarterly, 54 (2010), p. 456, fn 18. 22 Kari Palonen, ‘The History of Concepts as a Style of Political Theorizing: Quentin Skinner’s and Reinhart Koselleck’s Subversion of Normative Theory’, European Journal of Political Theory, I:1 (2002), pp. 91-106. 23 Skinner, Visions, Vol. I, p. 59. See also Keene, International Political Thought, pp. 14-21 24 Armitage, Foundations of Modern International Thought, p.30-1. 21 4 perspective on liberty recovered in his research.25 I argue that the concern with relevance and the problem of presentism can be effectively addressed, if not sorted out entirely, by further elaboration of the functions of ‘contestation’ and ‘debunking’ that his turn to genealogy sought to perform. Skinner himself might not be prepared to accept the type of debunking expected from genealogical investigations, but without recognition of this function and the clarification of scholar’s role in constructing a genealogical narrative the contextualist IR studies remain a usual suspect. The paradox of presentism Critics took issue with Skinner’s conception of the concept and the position of subject who is to determine the identity of the concept. Melvin Richter pointed out that, despite the epistemological primacy of the historical context in the Skinnerian approach, his categories of analysis are ‘phrased in the terms of present-day analytical philosophy of language rather than those theories of language held by past thinkers’.26 This is a serious criticism for a type of research that attempts to understand concepts-in-use. Richter further develops this point by showing another potentially burdensome problem in taking-up the Wittgensteinian dictum that concepts are tools, for, as he observes, it is not obvious how one ‘could write the history of the uses of a concept in argument without having taken a position on the identity of the concept’. He continues by resolutely dismissing the disclaimer that the meaning is in the use for the simple reason that a scholar needs certain means to differentiate between similar concepts in the same linguistic context.27 Indeed, if the primary units of analysis in the Skinnerian type of contextualism are specific terms used in specific arguments, then, in order to draw any conclusions as to the trajectory of and changes in a concept, a researcher has to make an extra analytical effort to construct a concept out of the words used in a text. Skinner in a sense confirms this conclusion by arguing against equating words and concepts.28 However, such a distinction grants a detached position to the scholar who must construct concepts out of words-in-use. These second-order constructs are not the same as concepts-inuse, for even the authors under scrutiny do not always identify and delimit the concepts they use for the convenience of an interpreter. This ‘privileged’ position by virtue of its mere 25 Quentin Skinner, Liberty before Liberalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), p. 118. Melvin Richter, The History of Political and Social Concepts: A Critical Introduction (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), p. 132. 27 Ibid., p.134. 28 Skinner, Visions, Vol. I, p. 159. 26 5 existence creates a window of opportunity for smuggling a ‘presentist’ bias into historical interpretation.29 Jens Bartelson’s critique is based on similar premises. He specifically argues that Skinner’s approach entails a ‘suprahistorical vantage point’ in relation to truth in past texts. He illustrates this point by referring to Skinner’s statement about Jean Bodin’s belief in ‘witches in league with the devil’ as false,30 while a steadfast contextualist would insist on making an opposite claim – on the existence of mermaids and demons – insofar as corresponding terms are literally and rationally used in the discourse of the time. Skinner in this respect does not trust his sources and judges them from the contemporary perspective on being and criteria of real, thus in principle permitting a degree of presentist arbitrariness.31 This criticism, probably, is not entirely justified because, as Skinner later shows by picking again the example of beliefs in witches this time by the French peasantry, it is inadequate to dismiss these as delusory or as expressions of something else. Rather, it is worthwhile to discover the range of other beliefs that make such beliefs rational. 32 Despite building his criticism on a possibly unfortunate example, Bartelson still detects a principle that determines the detached position of the scholar in relation to the language of sources. These criticisms should be taken seriously as they bear upon the basic ontological and methodological postulates of the contextualist research programme, and particularly to the formulation of research questions. At the stage of formulating a research question it is hard to find unequivocal safeguards against the presentist fallacy, because the object of study is conceived from the perspective of present and the researcher has a preconception of what she will be looking into. Furthermore, given that the current understanding of a concept is naturally expressed in the modern lexicon, a scholar has to be clear about whether the presentday words and terms are going to be the guiding lights in the search of this concept in the past. For such a light might easily obscure the connection between the terms in the past and 29 Jouni-Matti Kuukkonen also notes the contradiction related to the identity of the concept in the historical contexts. If it is not equal to word or term, then our analytical construction of concept might cause the same distortion that Skinner tries to avoid, even if we derive its name from a relevant historical context (Kuukkonen, ‘Making Sense of Conceptual Change’, History and Theory, 47 (2008), pp. 358-61). 30 Quentin Skinner, ‘A Reply to y Critics’, in James Tully (ed.) Meaning and Context. Quentin Skinner and His Critics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1988), p. 236. 31 Jens Bartelson, A Genealogy of Sovereignty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), pp. 66-67. For an overview of criticism of Skinner’s ‘ahistoricism’, mainly referring to The Foundations, see also Cary J. Nederman, ‘Quentin Skinner’s State: Historical Method and Traditions of Discourse’, Canadian Journal of Political Science, 18:2 (1985), p. 340, who nonetheless, argues that Skinner is fully consistent in his method. 32 Quentin Skinner, ‘Political Theory After Enlightenment’, in Joan W. Scott and Debra (eds) Schools of Thought. Twenty Years of Interpretative Social Science (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2001), p. 22. 6 eventually lapse into historical absurdity, of which Skinner himself warned. 33 A mere correspondence of vocabularies between historical epochs in itself does not mean we share the same conceptual apparatus. The same words might, in fact, express very different concepts, and this discrepancy must be controlled and mitigated by other means. In order to avoid such ‘presentism’ one would need to pretend that the language to be analysed is completely unknown, or considerably strange to a researcher, like a foreign language never learnt before, which nonetheless manifests a number of regularities even for non-native speakers. This would be an ideally, but also naively, historicized approach, similar to that of empiricist historians, which, however, raises doubts about the possibility of formulating research questions that can be understandable to contemporary audiences and reaching beyond ‘antiquarian interests.’ Kari Palonen recently suggested a remedy to this problem in the form of the necessary distinction that a research design should include: ‘analytical categories’ of the researcher’s narrative should be distinguished from the ‘historical concepts’ enshrined in the material; such categories should not be used if they are themselves part of the historical conceptual apparatus used in the sources.34 Such a distinction certainly helps to preclude unacceptable relativism and points to the construction of interpretative categories for a particular analytical account of the sources. These categories are not only different from the lexicon of sources, but they are also used in a different manner and for a different purpose. Nonetheless, unless the perspectivist nature of such research is constantly recognised, analytical categories cannot but uphold the status of historical concepts as ‘untouchable’ and immune from politicization, even if these categories are employed for the tactical reasons of research. Thus, what seems to remain unresolved in Skinnerian contextualism is the tension between philosophy and history, the meaning of the concept and its particular historical and terminological expressions. The necessity to construct a concept out of historical instances involves taking a position on its identity. In other words, it means stating what it is and, hence, stepping onto the turf of defining its meaning. Skinner’s refusal to fix meaning beyond the dimension of action, that is, outside the relationship between the speech-act and the criteria of application of a concept, thus, for some, contributes to the ambiguity of the 33 Skinner, Visions Vol. I, pp. 158-160. Kari Palonen, ‘Reinhart Koselleck on Translation, Anachronism and Conceptual Change’, in Martin J. Burke and Melvin Richter (eds) Why Concepts Matter: Translating Social and Political Thought (Leiden and Boston: Brill, 2012), pp. 83-5. 34 7 achieved results in writing the history of a concept.35 Certainly, part of this complicated relationship between the meaning and use of concepts is due to Skinner’s reliance in his early methodological work on speech-act theory as developed by Austin. And, in fact, most critics limit their analysis of Skinner’s contextualism to his powerful interventions into methodological debates of the 1960-1970s.36 However, as Palonen points out, this linguistic theory of speech-acts gave way to an emphasis on the instruments derived from classical rhetoric (e.g. of Aristotle, Cicero, Quintilian) and marked a rhetorical turn in Skinner’s writing. This did not mean only a change in emphases on various schemes of conceptual change, but also signalled Skinner’s dropping of the idea of ‘standard meaning’ or ‘accepted denotations’ of concepts that can either be followed or manipulated. 37 Instead, he adopts the assumption that there is ‘a degree of ‘neighbourliness’ […] between apparently conflicting evaluative terms’,38 which prevents any serious discussion of the correct understanding of the concept. Hence, the rhetorical redescription of concepts promised to do away with the ambiguous relation to meaning. However, as I argue in the next section, the problems with meaning, definition of concepts and, thus, ‘presentism’ remain part and parcel of Skinner’s recent ‘rhetorical’ studies. The rhetorical turn The role of rhetoric in political analysis is not entirely new to the field of international studies. Previous attempts to employ rhetorical analysis drew largely on the Habermasian approach to communicative action, persuasion, internalization of values and formation of mutual understanding.39 In contrast to the contextualism discussed above, these attempts employ very problematic notions of shared meaning and attribute a degree of causality to ideas. Even those sociological approaches in IR that conceive of ‘rhetorical action’ as central to their explanation of how social norms can be shaped by means of rhetoric (i.e. Frank One of the confusions might consist of what Bartelson calls a ‘reductionist’ position towards concepts, i.e. the reduction of concepts to utterances or statements, which loses sight of the concepts themselves. Thus, talking about concepts, while emphasizing the primacy of utterances, does not always help us to understand the concept. Thus, Bartelson proposes an alternative approach that derives from the idea of conceptual autonomy. See Jens Bartelson, The Critique of the State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), p. 21. 36 The same sometimes is true of his followers. See, for instance, Brett Bowden, The Empire of Civilization: The Evolution of an Imperial Idea (Chicago: The University of Chicago, 2009), pp.7-8. 37 Palonen, Quentin Skinner, p. 163. 38 Skinner, Visions Vol. I, p. 182. 39 Thomas Risse, ‘‘‘Let’s Argue!’’: Communicative Action in World Politics’, International Organization, 54:1 (2000), pp. 1–39. 35 8 Schimmelfennig’s study of the EU’s expansion), thereby displaying a degree of affinity with Skinner’s approach and diverging from Habermasian communicative action, mysteriously provide little room for the analysis of rhetoric and the recognition of amenability of values to rhetorical redescription. For them, rhetoric appears simply as window dressing that furthers actors’ material gains.40 Skinner’s approach offers an alternative understanding of rhetoric and rhetorical action, which is central to the analysis of conceptual change and linguistic action and is more rigorously safeguarded from anachronistic and analytical fallacies. In this approach speech and action are not causally related, but are understood as the same phenomenon. Thus, as Bell notes, instead of accounting for the motives and rationale that particular agents may hold for their action, this approach directs our attention to the ways in which agents manipulate the application of concepts, simultaneously expanding or limiting the space for an intelligible and (il)legitimate action.41 Thus, such a linguistic perspective on disciplinary history is not only an effective means for a project of self-critique,42 but also a fruitful way to highlight the analysis of conceptual change as a primary task for case-studies in diplomatic history43 and as a mode of political theorising in general.44 As I intimated above, this type of rhetorical approach is not immune to the ‘presentist’ bias that smuggles the issue of meaning into the discussion, contrary to Skinner’s constant emphasis on the dimension of action. As Skinner explains, his approach to rhetorical analysis builds on the tools and figures of classical rhetoric and for him conceptual change is often synonymous with successful rhetorical redescription. In Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes, he discusses paradiastole as the key rhetorical figure that captures the essence of rhetorical redescription, that is, ‘a figure by means of which similar things are Frank Schimmelfennig, ‘The Community Trap: Liberal Norms, Rhetorical Action, and the Eastern Enlargement of the European Union’, International Organization, 55:1 (2001), pp. 63-66. The ‘rationalist’ critics of communicative and rhetorical action approaches similarly neglect this dimension of rhetoric, see Christian Grobe, ‘The Power of Words: Argumentative Persuasion in International Negotiations’, European Journal of International Relations, 16:1 (2010), pp. 5–29. 41 This understanding renders any action ideological and, as critics argue, implies a degree of essentialism while complicating the task of understanding a statement as an abstract philosophical statement (Robert Lamb, ‘Quentin Skinner’s Revised Historical Contextualism: A Critique’, History of the Human Sciences 22:3 (2009), pp. 66-68. 42 Bell, ‘Language, Legitimacy’, pp. 327–350. 43 Evgeny Roshchin, ‘Supplanting Love, Accepting Friendship: A History of Russian Diplomatic Concepts’, Redescriptions, 13 (2009), pp. 125-46. 44 Kari Palonen, ‘The History of Concepts as a Style of Political Theorizing: Quentin Skinner’s and Reinhart Koselleck’s Subversion of Normative Theory’, European Journal of Political Theory, I:1 (2002), pp. 91-106. 40 9 distinguished from each other’.45 Skinner further explicates this technique of rhetorical redescription: ‘Rather than speaking of substituting one word for another, verbum pro verbo, we ought therefore to speak of substituting one thing for another, res pro re.’ Thus, the task, or the political action, of the ‘innovating ideologist’ consists in replacing ‘whatever descriptions our opponents may have offered with a different set of terms that serve to describe the action with no less plausibility, but place it at the same time in a different moral light’.46 Skinner also expresses a commitment to the language of historical sources for the purpose of reconstructing an argument. While reflecting on his method in The Foundations, he concludes that ‘nowadays I would see it as a sacred duty, when attempting to reproduce the contents of an argument, to make use of the exact terminology employed by the protagonists themselves. To fail to do so is inevitably to supply them with distinctions they did not make’.47 The political action is thus expressed in the vocabulary protagonists use, and the style and circumstances in which they do so.48 The task of extracting a neutral definition of terms or a meaning independent from the context of debate would be an illusion.49 However, the analysis of rhetorical redescription as an explanation of conceptual change and commitment to nominalism do not always work hand in hand, because such research requires taking a detached stand and attempting analytical abstraction from the speech-acts of the sources. The requirement is dictated by the constantly recurring problem of a concept of the concept. Skinner’s understanding of the concept is primarily about the range of reference or circumstances in which the term can be applied. Thus, the concept captures a sort of empirical situation or a case that includes linguistic and social action. But this situation does not reveal itself to a researcher; instead, it is the researcher who has to isolate a situation by devising criteria for doing so. Admittedly, one can envisage ideal situations, such as the list of offences included in a criminal code. In this case, the terms are grouped into sets that constitute cases/concepts by authority of a law-giving institution. In the situation of debate such authority would be derived from the grammar of a specific language and the practiced 45 Quentin Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996, repr. 2004), pp.150-1. 46 Ibid., p. 145; see also Quentin Skinner, ‘Paradiastole: Redescribing the Vices as Virtues’, in Sylvia Adamson et al. (eds) Renaissance Figures of Speech (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), p. 163. 47 Quentin Skinner, ‘Surveying the Foundations’, in Annabel Brett et al. (eds) Rethinking the Foundations of Modern Political Thought (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006), p. 247. 48 Such commitment to context-bound vocabulary provides grounds to consider Skinner a ‘nominalist’, see Palonen, Quentin Skinner, pp. 36-7. 49 Quentin Skinner, ‘A Third Concept of Liberty’, Proceedings of the British Academy, 117 (2002), p. 265. 10 rhetorical conventions, which is much less unequivocal than in the case of law. In this situation there is an inherent ambiguity about the belonging of specific terms to a particular case/concept. This ambiguity is increased as a result of manipulation of terms by their users and the original overlap of the sets, which may include more than one term from the situation in question and thus results in similar, but not identical, concepts (the situation recognized by Skinner with the help of the concept of ‘neighbourliness’). This means a very fluid and dynamic linguistic situation, in which concepts intermingle and, thus, can be effectively changed and redescribed by the interested parties. Indeed, it is the condition for the deployment of the ‘rhetorical’ approach. However, such fluidity requires a procedure of double isolation or taking stand on the identity of the object of study. Firstly, as stated above, comes the need to isolate the situation historically and thematically, which implies that a researcher chooses a perspective on the object. Secondly, the researcher must identify the constitutive terms of the chosen situation, which includes at the minimum their explicit naming and also possibly their designation, and relevant family resemblances. Thus, if we are to undertake the analysis of conceptual change in res pro re style, then we cannot but establish the identity of particular ‘res’ involved in the redescription before continuing with a claim that it was replaced with something else. Therefore, the procedure of double isolation should be considered as a possibility for a ‘presentist’ bias and the fixation of meaning determined by a detached position of a researcher whose agenda is inevitably driven by presentist concerns. Hence, the choice of specific terms for scrutiny, i.e. ‘state’, would always remain questionable. In fact, despite the declared primacy in the turn to rhetoric of the sources and speechacts contained therein, Skinner steps onto this shaky turf by defining the meaning of the objects of his research. For instance, sometimes he tries to clarify for the readers that the terms he is discussing do or do not describe something: ‘this is not to say that the word state was the one most commonly employed to describe the form of union underlying civil government’50 or take another example from the same piece: ‘to speak of a city or state, in other words, is to refer to a community of people who are subject to sovereign power’.51 The function of describing and referring in these instances is not so different from defining. Neither is the idea of the meaning of concept totally absent from his writing, e.g. he may 50 51 Quentin Skinner, ‘A Genealogy of the Modern State’, Proceedings of the British Academy, 162 (2009), p. 327. Ibid., p. 328. 11 speak of ‘the same concept’52 or the fact of ‘possessing a concept’53 when discussing the range of application of this concept. The possibility of admitting ‘presentist’ anachronism, generated by the tension between meaning/identity and use, apparently demands more rigorous means of control than what has been practiced so far. I argue that the risks stemming from the problematic relation of the past to the present asserted in the turn to rhetoric can be effectively mitigated by means of the perspectivist and genealogical orientations in Skinner’s recent work. Firstly, the understanding of objectivity that Skinner borrows from Max Weber54 recognizes the inherent perspectivist nature of any conceptual reconstruction and the contingency of our ‘truth’ statements. This in a sense unveils the pretence of timeless metalanguage and ‘suprahistorical vantage point’ that critics, such as Bartelson, see in Skinner’s approach. Secondly, the relativism that can possibly be engendered by the albeit limited privilege of historical sources and the arbitrariness seemingly present in the selection of historical episodes can be rationalized after further elaboration of genealogical approach. The genealogical turn There are certainly many heterogeneous directions in which genealogical studies developed in recent decades in political theory and IR mainly under the influence of Michel Foucault. 55 My task here is to explore how Skinner’s stated goal of using genealogy fits into this field and can in fact profit by way of clarifying and specifying its methodological injunctions. Skinner’s use of the term ‘genealogy’ to identify his own research is a fairly recent phenomenon. Curiously, the term was still missing in the influential 1989 and 2002 essays on the state,56 in which Skinner formulated his task as ‘to sketch the historical circumstances out of which these linguistic and conceptual transformations arose’.57 Once the term entered into the Quentin Skinner, ‘Rhetoric and Conceptual Change’, Finnish Yearbook of Political Thought, 3 (1999), p. 71. Skinner, ‘A Third Concept of Liberty’, p. 261. 54 Skinner, ‘Rhetoric and Conceptual Change’, p. 62. 55 See, for instance, such classical works as David Campbell, Writing Security: US Foreign Policy and the Politics of Identity (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1998); James Der Derian, On Diplomacy: A Genealogy of Western Estrangement (Oxford: Blackwell, 1987); Richard Price, The Chemical Weapons Taboo (Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1997). For a recent overview of genealogy and genealogical research in IR see Srdjan Vucetic, ‘Genealogy as a Research Tool in International Relations’, Review of International Studies, 37:3 (2011), pp. 1295-1312. 56 Quentin Skinner, ‘The State’, in Terrence Ball et al. (eds) Political Innovation and Conceptual Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), pp. 90-131; Quentin Skinner, ‘From the State of Princes to the Person of the State’, in Visions of Politics Vol. 2: Renaissance Virtues (New York: Cambridge University Press 2002), pp. 368-413. 57 Skinner, ‘From the State of Princes’, p. 369. 52 53 12 formulation of his research agenda, it produced some confusion regarding the task of genealogy and the role of the meaning of concepts in this analysis. The way Skinner understands genealogy as a rhetorical redescription derives from the Nietzschean premise that concepts that have history are in principle undefinable. Their meaning is always contested and is nothing more than armour in the past and present-day battles.58 From this perspective, the historicity of concepts parallels the views of the classical rhetoricians on the contingency of normative concepts which excludes the possibility of any correct meaning of terms and emphasizes the ‘neighbourliness’ of the forms of social action that can be described by them.59 It is this insight that helps Skinner to identify the deployment of the rhetorical technique of paradiastole in Nietzsche’s The Genealogy of Morality: ‘it is Nietzsche’s contention, in short, that the slave morality of the Christians succeeded in overturning the moral world of antiquity by rhetorically redescribing a number of vices as their neighbouring virtues’.60 Thus, a genealogical investigation of rhetorical redescription by its nature should uncover neglected and sidelined concepts. And by virtue of contrasting the perspectives of losers and winners in historical battle it should stimulate critical reflection on the present state of the winners. As Skinner puts it, ‘intellectual historians can hope to provide their readers with information relevant to the making of judgements about their current values and beliefs, and then leave them to ruminate’. In this way, Skinner hopes to do away with the antiquarian image of the critical historical exercise.61 As Melissa Lane observed recently, these can be summarised as two central contributions of Skinner’s approach, namely ‘falsifiability’ and ‘fruits’ (freedom being the third contribution). In her interpretation, falsifiability in Skinner’s work stands for revealed contestations of our political arrangements and thus challenges the claim of necessity, while ‘fruits’ contribution consists in recovering ‘buried treasures’ and showing their relevance for our concerns.62 The question always is whether we can indeed prompt the reader to ruminate or, in other words, render genealogy effective. This question has an important implication. It is Skinner, ‘Surveying the Foundations’, p. 244. Skinner, ‘Rhetoric and Conceptual Change’, p. 67. 60 Ibid., p. 70. 61 Skinner, Liberty before Liberalism, pp. 118-9. 62 Melissa Lane, ‘Doing Our Own Thinking for Ourselves: On Quentin Skinner’s Genealogical Turn’, Journal of the History of Ideas 73:1 (2012), pp. 73-74. I disagree, however, with Lane’s claim that these two contributions are stronger than the establishment of contingency, because any credible attempt to show that things could have been otherwise, i.e. contingent, necessarily shows how they actually were or could have been so. From this perspective, establishing contingency in fact subsumes the two identified contributions. 58 59 13 about the chances of the audience hearing the message and connecting it to the problems that are of immediate relevance. Some observers indeed believe that Skinner’s studies have direct relevance to contemporary politics precisely by bringing his readers to ruminate.63 However, the expectation that one’s potential audience starts immediately to ruminate is often farfetched, because, firstly, when we uncover a neglected perspective on a concept, it is not always apparent who would be the addressee of the presented finding given the multiplicity and heterogeneity of disciplines and accompanying scholarly and political debates.64 Secondly, it is not evident how to engage the existing perspectives: if we admit the historicity and contested nature of the uncovered concepts, the same should hold true concerning the concepts of today. It is, perhaps, tempting to stabilize the meaning or conventionality of application of a concept in the present in order to mesmerize the audience by the radical difference of the recovered perspective from the past. But such coherence of the present is hardly achievable. Therefore, a fair strategy would consist in subjecting the present-day debate to the same rhetorical and conceptual scrutiny as the sources of the past and demonstrating in which way a particular neglected perspective from the seventeenth century should be more relevant to the current contestation than another from the late nineteenth century, and how exactly it can shape current modes of argumentation and competing interpretations of concepts. 65 Thus, only by sharing in rumination with relevant audiences can we hope to overcome the antiquarian prejudice against the history of concepts as a perspectivist enterprise that still exists in political theory, and in IR in particular. Partly, these problems are due to Skinner’s ambivalence about the task and nature of genealogy per se. Genealogy is not the same as paradiastolic redescription, but at the same time Skinner does not seem to develop it as an alternative or supplementary method. As he admits in his reply to Lane, he found the concept helpful in tracing ‘contested uses of Holly Hamilton-Bleakly, ‘Linguistic Philosophy and The Foundations’, in Brett and Tully (eds), Rethinking the Foundations, p. 32; see also Skinner’s own interventions into contemporary debate as a way of helping his readers to ruminate in Skinner, ‘Political Theory’, pp. 15-24; Quentin Skinner, ‘States and the Freedom of Citizens’, in Quentin Skinner and Bo Stråth (eds) States and Citizens: History, Theory, Prospects (Cambridge: Cambridge Uiversity Press, 2003), pp. 11-27. 64 As Lane, following Mark Bevir, points out, genealogy will have no ‘debunking effect’ for those who do not uphold the beliefs in question as natural. Lane, ‘Doing Our Own Thinking for Ourselves’, p. 80; Mark Bevir, ‘What is Genealogy?’, Journal of the Philosophy of History 2 (2008), p. 272. 65 Roshchin, ‘(Un)Natural and Contractual International Society’, pp. 258-262; Skinner, ‘States and the Freedom of Citizens’, pp. 11-27. 63 14 evaluative terms’ and portray them as ‘a descending family tree’.66 The same conclusion about the nature of the employed concept follows from the vocabulary in which it is expressed. In Skinner’s own formulation we can ‘trace’, ‘investigate’, ‘unfold’ and ‘discover’ genealogy of concepts, while such verbs as ‘doing’ or ‘practicing’, which could facilitate the understanding of genealogy as a method or methodological tool, are avoided.67 The image of genealogical tree certainly prompts a researcher to build a narrative that shows the complex development of the concept from the bottom of the tree to the top (which, of course, is not the same as writing a ‘Whiggish’ history). But this picture remains rather a metaphor, which at best can only stimulate investigation. This is one of the reasons why the task of discovery in his genealogy remains confusing as to its epistemological status, for it is not clear whether such a finding is pre-programmed, as in the relation of a branch to a tree or an embranchment, or whether the result of research is held open-ended and contingent upon unexpected ruptures and discontinuities as Nietzschean thought would suggest. Despite the reservations about the image of genealogy, I argue that Skinner’s rhetorical genealogy remains Nietzschean. Pace Lane, who maintains that as opposed to mere contingency Nietzschean genealogy is about contestation and debunking, 68 I see these goals implemented in Skinner’s genealogical project, even if in a version different from what is expected by Lane. Skinner links the explanation of genealogy to Nietzsche: ‘we should proceed genealogically, that’s to say trying to see how the concept developed in our culture’.69 This development is never teleological or uniform. He emphasises that such genealogy is about contending uses of the concept and the belief that there has never been any agreed, natural or essential meaning of the concept under investigation.70 For him ‘to trace the genealogy of the state is to discover that the concept has been the subject of continuous contestation and debate’.71 Therefore, the concepts can only be understood as inalienable elements of endless rhetorical/scholarly/political contestation and in themselves are objects of contestation. The primary significance in this process is attached to the condition of battle. Quentin Skinner, ‘On the Liberty of the Ancients and the Moderns: A Reply to My Critics’, Journal of the History of Ideas 73:1 (2012), p. 129. 67 Skinner, ‘A Genealogy of the Modern State’, pp. 325-6; for similar uses see the 2010 revised version of the article see Quentin Skinner, ‘The Sovereign State: A Genealogy’, in Hent Kalmo, Quentin Skinner (eds) Sovereignty in Fragments. The Past, Present and Future of a Contested Concept (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), pp. 26-46. 68 Lane, ‘Doing Our Own Thinking for Ourselves’, p. 79. 69 Quentin Skinner, ‘A Genealogy of Liberty’, Una’s Lecture (2008-2009), available at the Doreen B. Townsend Center for the Humanities, UC Berkeley, website http://townsendcenter.berkeley.edu/media/quentin-skinnermodern-history-university-cambridge (last accessed on 17/07/13). 70 Skinner, ‘A Genealogy of the Modern State’, pp. 325-6. 71 Ibid., p. 360; italics mine. 66 15 Such understanding of contestation is crucial for the link to the concept ‘will to power’, which Skinner does not wish to endorse in his approach.72 The will to power might indeed be interpreted as a feature of a specific historical subject and social process and thus belong to an area outside of his research programme. However, for the purpose of this article it is sufficient to invoke a particular instance of this concept from The Genealogy of Morality, where Nietzsche argues against the idea of objective and ‘pure reason’, to show that it is compatible with Skinner’s approach: ‘the will to see things differently, is no small discipline and preparation of the intellect for its coming “objectivity”’. By this he means that ‘the only knowledge we have is knowledge from a perspective’ (3:12; italics original). From the perspective of this injunction the identified rhetorical battle over or contestation of ‘freedom’, for example, by Thomas Hobbes and his republican opponents, would be nothing other but contestation driven by wills to power. The ‘debunking’ function of Skinner’s rhetorical genealogy is less obvious and runs into a problem of the beginning and the ending of such research. Skinner recognizes that genealogies do not have any clear beginning, nor do they have a clear end. But then he chooses, so to say, a least arbitrary moment to start his analysis of liberty and that is the work of Hobbes, because he was first to provide a ‘systematic analysis’ of the ‘liberty of subjects’ and his account appeared to be extremely influential and familiar to modern readership. The choice of Hobbes’s work as an instance of remarkable discussion of the subject matter is certainly well grounded in and substantiated by Skinner’s own work on early modern political thought.73 Nonetheless, to informed audiences, such a choice might already seem preprogrammed in terms of timing and type of scrutinized sources, which in principle might be compromising the ideal of no clear beginning. The probability of a pre-determined ‘beginning’ of study in the past is supplemented with attempts to fix the meaning and the use at an ‘end’, that is in the present, which would help Skinner’s audience to see the watershed between allegedly prevailing and marginalized perspectives. Skinner does not provide us with present-day definitions himself; instead he delegates the job of fixing the meaning in the present to other authorities: ‘this is not to deny that one particular definition has come to predominate. As handbooks on political theory regularly point out, there has been a noticeable tendency in recent times to think of the state Skinner, ‘On the Liberty of the Ancients and the Moderns’, p. 129. See, for instance, Skinner, Liberty before Liberalism; and Quentin Skinner, Hobbes and Republican Liberty (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008). 72 73 16 […] as nothing more than the name of an established apparatus of government’.74 Despite the proclaimed unwillingness to establish the meaning of the concepts he studies, it is evident that Skinner cannot resist the need to isolate the concepts under scrutiny thereby practically equating ‘the range of reference’ to the notion of meaning.75 Thus, the analysed terms refer to particular res, which have to be analytically constructed with the help of vocabulary of sources and a scholar himself. The same analytical technique is manifested in the isolation of particular ‘theories’ or agents in the period under study, such as ‘the absolutist theory’ and ‘the political anatomists’.76 A presupposition of some sort of meaning attached to the concept of the state in the present, i.e. at the start of the genealogical study, as the metaphor of genealogical tree suggests, seems to allow a privileged entry to the history of discourse through the exclusive focus on the term ‘state’. However, if we assume that the term ‘state’ answered to various concepts in the selected time span of the study, as Skinner himself admits, and continues to be a subject of heated contestation, as the Nietzschean genealogy indicates, it is not entirely clear why the term ‘state’ should be granted such privilege over a possible set of terms (especially, if words are not equal to concepts, while concepts can be expressed with a number of terms). Thus, the problems identified in the previous section on rhetorical analysis also translate into Skinner’s genealogical tracing of the history of concepts. These ambiguities could have been avoided, if Skinner stipulated his genealogical approach in greater detail. His primary example of genealogy is derived from Nietzsche and serves chiefly to formulate a general task of his research, albeit practically working as a metaphor of a genealogical tree. It is surprising that he largely ignores the methodological discussions of genealogy of the last two decades that originate from the same intellectual source – Nietzsche, but received a new powerful impetus from the work of Michel Foucault. Foucault’s name figures sometimes in Skinner’s discussion of his methodological orientations, but he seems to associate Foucault mainly with his early ‘structuralist’ works and overlooks his genealogical studies.77 However, the exclusive emphasis on Foucault’s archaeology does not give enough credit to the Skinner, ‘A Genealogy of the Modern State’, p. 326. See a similar statement in the same article: ‘Critics agreed that, when we talk about the state, we are referring to a type of civic union, a body or society of people united under government’, ibid., p. 332. 75 For the range of reference of the term ‘state’ see ibid., p. 332. 76 Ibid., pp. 330, 333. 77 See Skinner, Liberty before Liberalism (p. 112 fn.19.) for the reference to Foucault’s The Archaeology of Knowledge (1969). 74 17 genealogical injunctions that informed much of his ‘middle period’78 and raises questions about Skinner’s characterisation of his own work as ‘genealogical’. This is all the more puzzling given the apparent affinities between certain genealogical principles in the work of Foucault and Skinner. For instance, Skinner stresses the need for historians to focus on discontinuities instead of origins.79 Coupled with the idea of no clear beginning and end of any genealogy, however compromised, it is strikingly similar to Foucault’s resoluteness to prioritise in historical analysis episodes, ruptures, contingency and negation of the idea of origin and progress in history, rationality of change and the idea of history as a permanent battle. The same can be said about ‘pointillist’ history of the one and history viewed from perspective of localised events and episodes of the other. 80 These parallels invite one to inquire into the potential of genealogy as practiced by Foucault and his followers and to address the issues related to presentism and antiquarianism in the genealogical rhetorical approach adopted by Skinner, were he prepared to endorse the idea of genealogy fully. By no means does this speculation imply my attempt to reconcile the approaches of Foucault and Skinner, which would inevitably lapse into construction of strawmen out of both, producing only a superficial comparison inattentive to the changes in early and later writings of both thinkers.81 Their research agenda is certainly incongruent in too many aspects (particularly, in the roles of subject-as-agency and power) to contend that one could benefit from another. Nor do I believe that a debt to one source of intellectual inspiration – the Nietzschean interpretation of genealogy – should necessarily result in adopting similar genealogical strategies.82 See also Skinner, ‘Surveying the Foundations’, p. 243. Ibid., p. 237. 80 Michel Foucault, ‘Nietzsche, Genealogy, History’, in Paul Rabinow (ed.) The Foucault Reader: An Introduction to Foucault’s Thought (London: Penguin Books, 1991), pp. 76-100; Michel Foucault, ‘Truth and Power’, in James D. Faubion (ed.) Michel Foucault. Essential Works of Foucault 1954 -1984, Vol. 3 “Power,” (London: Penguin Books, 2002), p. 116; Hubert Dreyfus, Paul Rabinow, Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, Afterword by M. Foucault (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1983, 2 nd ed.); Michael Mahon, Foucault’s Nietzschean Genealogy: Truth, Power, and the Subject (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 1992), pp. 108-10; Richard Rorty, ‘Foucault and Epistemology’, in David C. Hoy (ed.) Foucault: A Critical Reader (Oxford UK & Cambridge USA: Blackwell Publishers, 1986, repr. 1994), pp. 41-49; Wendy Brown, ‘Genealogical Politics’, in Jeremy Moss (ed.) The Later Foucault. Politics and Philosophy (London and New Delhi: Sage, 1998), p. 42. 81 For an example of such ‘reconciliation’ see Ryan Walter, ‘Reconciling Foucault and Skinner on the State: The Primacy of Politics?’, History of the Human Sciences, 21 (2008), pp. 94-114. 82 As has been noted before, Foucault’s understanding of genealogy also diverged from that of Nietzsche. See, for instance, Jeremy Moss, ‘Introduction: The Later Foucault’, in Moss (ed.) The Later Foucault, pp. 6-8; and Bevir, ‘What is Genealogy?’, p. 274. 78 79 18 Nevertheless, Foucault’s practice of genealogy, especially in relation to the dimension of the ‘truth axis’83 and thus thematically close to Skinner’s project of history of concepts, seems to contain principles that can be employed as tools for rhetorical genealogies and help us reappraise Skinner’s contribution to the present-day thinking.84 Probably the central idea here is the vector of relation that genealogy establishes between history and the present. Perspectivism and the task of setting the audiences to ruminate that Skinner derives from the work of Nietzsche and Weber share much with the task of genealogy as an inquiry into the history of the present to produce ‘problematizations’. As such genealogy does not simply dig up past objects and put them on display; rather it proceeds from the identification of the problem in the present and traces the lines of its transformations in history. 85 The thrust of such an exercise is not to construct what intellectual historians would call a ‘Whiggish history’, but to demonstrate that history is written in a way as to render the present meaningful or problematic. This, in fact, is a way to stimulate critical reflection on our modern understanding that Skinner expects his genealogical research to achieve.86 Thus, the power struggle over the present and its polemical definition cannot but discriminate against past transformations and knowledge that can potentially destabilize it, the discovery of which is the key task of genealogy.87 In this sense, the tasks of Foucault’s and Skinner’s genealogies are similar, if not identical. However, in Foucault’s work genealogy preserves a more explicit and solid link to present-day social practice thereby offering a clear contribution to the ongoing debate. This genealogy takes a largely retrospective vector by unfolding problematic phenomena back in time through a series of often non-linear and disconnected transformations88 or, in Skinner’s terms, ‘pointillist’ changes that exclude the idea of charting long-term conceptual change and development. Looking from this perspective on Skinner’s use of genealogy and the correspondence between his goals with the Nietzschean and Foucauldian genealogical project, it is evident that the proclaimed aim of Mahon, Foucault’s Nietzschean Genealogy, p. 103. A laudable example of research building on a combination of Foucault’s and Skinner’s methodological orientations, although omitting the discussed issue of presentism, is Shane P. Mulligan, ‘The Uses of Legitimacy in International Relations’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies 34:2 (2005), pp.349-375. 85 David C. Hoy, ‘Introduction’, in Hoy (ed.) Foucault: A Critical Reader, pp. 6-7; David C. Hoy, ‘Foucault and Critical Theory’, in Moss (ed.) The Later Foucault, pp. 24-6; Moss, ‘Introduction: The Later Foucault’, pp. 7-8. 86 Skinner, ‘A Genealogy of the Modern State’, p. 325. 87 The critical effect of genealogy, which consists in its ability to change the conception of phenomenon it investigates, is what gives it a name of ‘effective history’, see Martin Saar, ‘Understanding Genealogy: History, Power and the Self’, Journal of the Philosophy of History 2 (2008), p. 298. 88 Michel Foucault, ‘Questions of Method’, in Faubion (ed.) Michel Foucault, p. 224. For a comprehensive methodological reading of the Foucauldian genealogy see Vucetic, ‘Genealogy as a Research Tool’, pp. 12981304. 83 84 19 critical reflection/rumination can also be the aim of ‘debunking’ certain beliefs and concepts, which are used as armour in contemporary political and rhetorical battles. If we remained committed to the principles of no definite beginning and no pre-determined findings, then neither Skinnerian nor any other version of Nietzschean genealogy should be concerned with identifying the necessarily converse evaluative narrative to those beliefs it aims to question or change. This is one of the possible outcomes on par with its other legitimate and productive effects, such as recovering lost perspectives on a subject that may not undermine its overall identity. Thus, the effects of genealogical research can, and will often be, limited in scope (i.e. only specific audiences, phenomena and concepts within a broader contestation are targeted) and scale (i.e. debunking might consist in complete reversal normative narrative or in a more ‘modest’ transformation or unsettling of a concept). Furthermore, as such a history of the present this genealogy remains ‘presentist’ insofar as it is sees history as a product of power struggle and polemical construction of the present, not as a teleological progression.89 In other words, the professed perspectivism should be applied more consistently in dealing with historical sources. It means the perspective of a historian/political theorist90 needs to be assigned epistemological primacy as long as we do not seek to recover a ‘real’ history91 and vindicate a radical relativism by assigning primacy to the language of our sources. It is a truism to maintain that sources do not speak for themselves, thus, it is our job to take a stand on the identity of the objects of analysis simultaneously resisting the idea of writing a teleological or ‘Whiggish’ history and trying to identify the points of change and rupture that may unveil the forsaken perspectives of the losers in power struggles.92 The voice of these latter perspectives will inevitably be mediated by the present and thrown into the heat of specific current theoretical/political debates.93 Thus, the recurring need to identify particular res in Skinner’s studies from this genealogical perspective would no longer look problematic, since it should start with identification of specific res in the present, their problematizations and contestations, and, thus, be consistent in adhering to this principle in the context of past sources. Such a genealogical perspective would also be Hoy, ‘Introduction’, in Hoy (ed.) Foucault: A Critical Reader, pp. 11-4. For the explication of objectivity in terms of perspectivism see Max Weber, ‘The ‘Objectivity’ of Knowledge in Social Science and Social Policy’, in Sam Whimster (ed.) The Essential Weber: A Reader (London and New York: Routledge, 2004), p. 374. 91 This is the aim of John G. Gunnell’s The Descent of Political Theory: The Genealogy of an American Vocation (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1993). 92 See Foucault, ‘Truth and Power’, pp. 116-9. 93 For a similar proposal see Palonen, ‘Reinhart Koselleck on Translation’, p. 80. 89 90 20 suspicious of any pre-determined choices of historical periods because the problematization of particular phenomena, concepts and practices cannot have a universal rationality and, hence, history. Conclusion Despite all the possible methodological traps and pitfalls that Skinner’s approach may contain, it can still offer useful and rigorous tools to analyse conceptual change in terms of rhetorical re-description and thus contribute to political theory and IR by explicating disciplinary history, as well as case studies of diplomatic and political rhetoric. 94 As no approach in social science should remain or, indeed, does remain immune to continuous questioning and further shaping as a result of its empirical application or theoretical reflection over its fundamental premises, so could the approach advocated by Skinner benefit from a firmer commitment to its pronounced genealogy. In many ways, Skinner’s epistemological injunctions and his understanding of history and commitment to perspectivism are already genealogical. However, further steps in this direction are needed in order to make this project matter for wider political theory and IR audiences. Such a step requires effective engagement with the current debates and the retrospective reorientation of genealogy. This would help in tackling the problems of presentism and the status of the mediated recovery of forsaken perspectives. In terms of research strategy, the ‘perspectivist’ link to the present can engage into current debates by the necessary mapping of the present-day contestation of a concept as its point of departure. It would then depart by unfolding contemporary debates back in history, thus contributing to a history of the present. Such unfolding through the system of explicit references to contemporaneous and past conventions and contexts may further help us in identifying the locations in which the link to the present loosens to the point of breakage, while elucidating the transformation of vocabularies involved in conceptual transformation. Thus, controlling the flow and identity of vocabulary (i.e. in the form of copying, borrowing and adapting the modes of application) would be a crucial element in such retrospective genealogical research. Of course, the flow is not an uninterrupted retrospective progression, See, for instance, Quentin Skinner, ‘Political Rhetoric and the Role of Ridicule’, in Kari Palonen et al. (eds) The Ashgate Research Companion to The Politics of Democratization in Europe: Concepts and Histories (Farnham: Ashgate, 2008), pp. 137-49. 94 21 but rather a pointillist trajectory, in which the changes in points are best understood through the lenses of rhetorical redescription and contextual analysis. Such reorientation of genealogical approach to rhetorical conceptual change also responds to those concerned with the presence of self-identified, or misidentified, intellectual traditions, which is one of the key issues with the Skinnerian approach in IR, i.e. the discipline that revolves largely around the idea of great debates, schools and traditions. The genealogical rhetorical approach can finally start accounting for IR traditions by establishing them as rhetorical constructs and practice. Indeed, presenting a case as a tradition, which arranges a history of thought on a specific issue in a linear and possibly intelligible order, can in itself qualify for being a rhetorical strategy.95 Such a strategy may consist in intentional or unintentional misinterpretation of texts, misrepresentation of authors, the omission of inconvenient facts and details and, necessarily, simplification. Not only this interpretation sheds new light on the construction of intellectual ‘origins’ of, let’s say, liberal or realist tradition of thought, it also helps us understand the presentation of alternative explanations and counterfactuals by the representatives of competing camps as necessarily a rhetorical and perspectivist exercise. The rhetorical genealogical reorientation would also have implications for the existing Skinnerian IR studies. For example, Keene’s International Political Thought as explicitly seeking to do the Skinnerian history of concepts,96 could have also dealt with a possibility of presentism more consistently. This could have been done by systematically recognizing the author’s role in constructing the identity of specific concepts in every chapter and the corresponding presentist constraints in such construction, instead of affirming an alternative/new perspective on the subject. The relation to the present in Keene’s work only deepens the impression of antiquarianism, as he mainly seeks to establish contrasts with contemporary views and achieve better understanding of the past.97 Apart from identifying aspects of classical thought that contemporary literature neglects,98 the approach advocated in this article would have expected such works to show how exactly a recovered perspective engages contemporary contested views and which arguments in the existing debate it debunks 95 Markus Kornprobst similarly suggested to interpret IR debates from the perspective of rhetoric, see his ‘International Relations as Rhetorical Discipline: Toward (Re-) Newing Horizons’, International Studies Review, 11 (2009), pp. 87–108; however, the genealogical rhetorical approach of this article cannot hope to produce synergetic knowledge by way of dialogue, which is the aim of Kornprobst’s contribution. 96 Keene (2005), p. 23. 97 Ibid., pp. 17-19. 98 Ibid., pp. 21-5. 22 by undermining the foundations of their legitimacy or by offering new factors/variables they cannot account for. 23