Section 4: Philosophy of Mind ON THE POSSIBILLITY OF INTROSPECTION Markus Werning Heinrich-Heine-Universität Düsseldorf LS Theoretische Philosophie Universitätsstraße 1 40225 Düsseldorf werning@phil-fak.uni-duesseldorf.de Introspective thoughts seem to be almost ubiquitous companions of ours. The capacity of introspection, moreover, is an indispensable component in the notion of ourselves as human subjects. Although the existence of introspective thoughts strikes us intuitively as indubitable, it is far from obvious how even their logical possibility can be defended against rather plausible background assumptions. The opinions that introspective thoughts are possible and that thought necessarily is productive and compositional (cf. Fodor 1998), the paper argues, can only be reconciled if we assume that introspective thoughts are formed in a symbolic (i.e. representational) structure that combines symbolic elements from sub-symbolic elements that can themselves be represented in the structure. The overall conclusion of the paper is that introspection requires the possession of a phonetic language. Not every second-order thought of one’s own (i.e., a thought of one’s own about a thought of one’s own) is already an introspective thought. Three additional conditions have to be fulfilled: First, an introspective thought is a report of a thought of one’s own (where the notion of a thought subsumes all sorts of propositional attitudes including perceptions, desires, beliefs and memories, cf. Fodor 1975). For this reason the wish that I believed in God does not count as an introspective thought because the wish does not report the belief, but merely aims at it. Second, the report of the thought is epistemically basic and in particular non-inferred. In this respect the notion of introspection is likened to that of perception (hence intro-SPECTION). This condition, e.g., rules out that an introspective thought be a thought that reports, say, an until then unconscious wish of the person and does so on no other epistemic ground than that a psychoanalyst (or some encephalograph) informed the person about her wish. Third, the epistemic basis of an introspective thought is internally accessible for the subject (hence ‘INTRO-spection’). According to a widely accepted view on mental representation, a representation is conceived of as a pair of an internal symbol (the bearer of the representation) and a (usually) external content (e.g. an actual or merely possible object or state of affairs). To become introspectively aware of a thought, thus, is to become aware of it by accessing its internal symbolic component, not by accessing its external content. Some authors, in contrast, have argued that one sometimes (or always) becomes aware of a perception of one’s own simply by perceiving the external content of the perception (cf. e.g. Harman 1990). Those cases of second-order thoughts would not count as introspective according to the third condition because they are not founded epistemically on anything internal to the subject. With these conditions for introspection at hand, the paper argues that, since an introspective thought reports another thought by accessing its internal component, it should be treated analogous to the direct report of a sentence by another sentence, i.e., as quotation. Four ways to analyze quotation (respectively, its analogue in general symbolic structures) can be distinguished. The first way, lexical quotation, assumes that every quotation is syntactically unanalyzable, i.e., lexical. Lexical quotation fails as an account of introspection because it violates the constraint that symbolic structures be productive. Since a productive structure builds infinitely many symbols from a finite set of lexical symbols, no productive structure allows lexical quotation. All of the infinitely many symbols would be quotable and would consequently contribute with more than finitely many quotations of them to the lexicon. The second view of quotation could be called holophrastic quotation because arbitrary (complex or primitive) symbols are taken as a whole and set in quotation marks (or syntactically transformed in a specific other way by a function Q). To accomplish this, the following syntactic rule is postulated: If t is a well-formed symbol of the language, then ‘t’ (or more generally, Q(t)) is a well-formed symbol of the language. This rule is accompanied by a semantic interpretation according to which the semantic value of ‘t’(generally speaking: of Q(t)) is t. Although holophrastic quotation is productive, it is shown, that it violates another constraint, the principle of compositionality, if the structure contains at least two symbols with the same semantic value. Compositionality requires that the semantic value of a syntactically complex symbol is syntaxdependently determined by the semantic values of its syntactic parts. Formally this means: Given the function of semantic evaluation M for a certain symbolic structure, this structure is compositional just in case, for each n-ary syntactic operation S of the structure, there is a semantic operation MS such that M(S(t1, ..., tn)) = MS(M(t1), ..., M(tn)), provided S is defined for the array of symbols (t1, ..., tn). In symbolic structures that (i) have the syntactic operation of holophrastic quotation Q with M(Q(t)) = t and (ii) in which some symbols t and t* have the same semantic value M(t) = M(t*), one can easily derive a contradiction to the principle of compositionality (The proof is provided in the paper). The third way, analytic quotation, unlike holophrastic quotation doesn’t apply a syntactic operation of quotation to whole symbols however complex, but to their lexical syntactic parts. Although slightly different, this method, too, violates the requirement of compositionality, for very similar reasons holophrastic quotation does. The failure of lexical, holophrastic and analytic quotation motivates an alternative, fourth way of analyzing quotation: phonetic or, more generally, sub-symbolic quotation. Here, the quotation of a symbol is constructed from representations of the subsymbolic parts of the symbol. The English expression ‘dog’, e.g., can unequivocally be referred to by a concatenation of the representations ‘d’, ‘o’, and ‘g’ each of which represents a specific voiced dental consonant, a particular lower tongue vowel or, respectively, a specific voiced velar consonant. Representations of the phonetic parts of an expression, thus, enable the quotation of the expression. This view on quotation allows for productivity and compositionality, but requires that sub-symbolic elements can themselves be represented in the symbolic structure. Unlike Mentalese, natural languages do build symbolic elements, i.e., morphemes, from in the language representable subsymbolic elements, i.e., phonemes. This justifies the conclusion that introspective thoughts are formed in an phonetic language whose phonetic parts are internally acces- sible by the subject. Introspective thoughts, understood in the above sense and reconstructed as quotations, we may conclude, are only possible if the thoughts introspected are formed in a phonetic language as instances of inner speech. Introspection thus requires the possession of a natural language. This a priori result is supplemented by a number of psychological data (Morin, 1993) and neurobiological experiments (Craik & al., 1999) indicating a correlation between introspection and inner speech. The possibility of becoming introspectively aware of other than phonetically structured thoughts, e.g., introspecting perceptive or proprioceptive thoughts remains dubitable. References Craik, F., Moroz, T., Moscovitch, M., Stuss, D., Winocur, G., Tulving, E., & Kapur, S. (1999). In search of the self: A positron emission tomography study. Psychological Science, 10(1). Fodor, J. (1975). The Language of Thought. New York: Crowell. Fodor, J. (1998). Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Harman, G (1990). The Intrinsic Quality of Experience. Philosophical Perspectives, 4. Morin, A. (1993). Self-talk and self-awareness: On the nature of the relation. The Journal of Mind and Behavior, 14(3).