Treatise 1.4.2 On the causes leading us to believe in the existence of “body” (bodies are objects that continue to exist independently of being perceived) (Hume considered the question of the justification for the belief in body to be beside the point — — since believing in the existence of body is not an option for us … … we are compelled to do so … and we need to do so) The causes leading us to believe in the existence of body could lead us to believe one or other (or both) of two different things: • that objects continue to exist when not being perceived • that objects are distinct from the mind and its perceptions meaning: • that they exist outside of us • that they exist and act independently of us There are three possible causes of the belief: • the senses • reason • the imagination Why the belief can’t be based on the senses The senses only give us impressions. And … … they obviously can’t produce a belief in continued existence of our impressions apart from being perceived. Were they to produce a belief in distinct existence, they would have to do so by leading us to believe either: • that our impressions are images of distinctly existing objects, or … • that our impressions just are distinctly existing objects They can’t do the first because they give us no idea of any objects other than our impressions. Neither can they do the second. • because they can’t lead us to think that our impressions are external to ourselves ◦ because we have no impression of self that they could be external to ◦ because our impressions of things outside our bodies are no different from our impressions of our bodies in all being impressions had by the mind, and so things within the mind (this is particularly evident of impressions of sound, taste, and smell, but recent theories of vision have recognized that it is even true of those of vision) ◦ because there is no fallacy in sensation, which always presents impressions as being what they are, … … and all our impressions (of primary qualities, of secondary qualities, and of pleasures and pains) originally appear to us as being “on the same footing” that is, as all being merely impressions in us and nothing else external to us. • because they can’t lead us to think that our impressions are independent of us ◦ since independence has to do with causes, and causal relations are only ascertained by the imagination Why the belief can’t be based on reason The belief has one or other of two forms: • that our impressions just are bodies • that our impressions are subjective effects and/or representations of bodies If the belief has the first form, then there is no role for reason to play, since there is no inference from impression to body. If the belief has the second form, then it is not accepted by the majority of people, who believe that all impressions, except for those of pain and pleasure, exist outside of themselves. So the belief must be based on the imagination. Moreover, the belief the imagination produces must be a belief in the continued or distinct existence of our very impressions themselves. More precisely, it must be a belief in the continued or distinct existence of some of our impressions … (those of sensation excluding pain & pleasure, visual after-images, etc.) … but not of others (passions, pains, visual after-images). What is the difference between these two groups of impressions that inspires the imagination to produce the belief? – not their superior force or vivacity – not their occurring independently of the will – rather, their constancy and coherence What is it about their constancy and coherence that leads the imagination to form the belief? 1. An inadequate explanation. We need to suppose that impressions continue to exist unperceived in order to preserve our belief in their coherence. [Some examples to illustrate why we might think this] The reason why this explanation is inadequate: It doesn’t account for how we get the belief in coherence in the first place. Our belief in the coherence of certain impressions attributes more regularity to those impressions than we discover by experience. Consequently, the belief cannot be grounded on experience. 2. Something else the belief might be grounded on: An inertial tendency of the imagination Having observed a certain degree of coherence in objects as they appear to the senses, we go on to suppose the unperceived existence of objects in order to be able to attribute a yet greater degree of coherence to them and so “render the uniformity as compleat as possible” The problem with 2 It is too weak to support such a grand conclusion as the unperceived existence of all objects. Hume’s solution Look for the cause of the belief in the constancy of the impressions, giving rise to the belief in their continued existence apart from being perceived. How this happens When the [1] same object (i.e., impression) is frequently present and absent to the senses, we are impelled to imagine [2] it to [3] continue to exist between the appearances, and [4] believe that this is really the case. (Note that the object under consideration here really is just an impression; not an object distinct from our impressions. This is because the belief just is a belief in the unperceived existence of our perceptions, at least in the form in which most of us have it.) 4 parts of this explanation that need to be discussed: 1. What we mean by “the same object.” 2. Why we consider two objects interrupted by a gap to nonetheless be the same. 3. Why we are impelled to form the idea that the object continues to exist unperceived across the gap. 4. Why we believe this idea. 1. What we mean by “same” Hume’s view of time and identity: Where there is no change there is no passage of time. So a view of an unchanging object gives no idea of the passage of time. So such a view gives us just a single impression. Where there is any change, we receive multiple impressions. However, sometimes, while we are having a single impression, we also have other, changing impressions. Comparison of these two impression sets with one another leads us to imaginatively split the single impression into earlier and later appearances. When we think of the earlier and later appearances we think there are many things. When we think there is really just one impression we think there is just one thing. We run these two thoughts together to form the (really contradictory) notion of the oneness of the many things. This is the idea of identity or sameness of an object through an interval of time. (It is really a mish-mash of inconsistent thoughts.) 2. Why we consider two objects interrupted by a gap to nonetheless be the same object. When one impression ceases, something else happens, and then another impression starts, we are undeniably having two impressions and not one. But suppose the two impressions very closely resemble one another. Then the state the mind feels itself in when it contemplates them feels to it very much like the state it is in when it contemplates a strictly identical object (when it has a single impression over a supposed variation of time, with no gaps) So there are two resemblances: – between the two separated impressions – between the way it feels to contemplate two separated impressions and the way it feels to contemplate an “identical” object The effect of these resemblances is to lead us to confuse the two kinds of experience. As a consequence, we think that in this case as well we are contemplating just one object, rather than two. 3. Why we consider the object to exist unperceived across the gap Because we realize from just a bit of reflection that we really are having two impressions, not one. But this realization does not eliminate the influence of the resemblance relations, which continue to tempt us to think of the objects as being one. We try to eliminate the contrary evidence by inventing the fiction of the existence of the object when it is not being perceived. An objection But isn’t the object we are supposing to exist unperceived just an impression, and isn’t it a gross error to suppose that an impression can exist unperceived? No. A mind is just a bundle of perceptions, and there is no contradiction in supposing one of them to detach itself from the bundle and return to it later. On this account, for an object to be perceived just is for an impression to enter the bundle. 4. Why we believe the object continues to exist unperceived. Because of vivacity transmitted from our memories of the resembling impressions to the idea of an unperceived impression linking them In this case, the vivacity is transmitted from the memories by the “propensity” we have to consider the memories to be connected by the existence of something unperceived. So it is indirectly due to the resemblance relation, which is the ground of that propensity. A problem with this cause of belief in body The cause leads us to believe in the continued existence of our impressions. And thereby their distinct existence (because continued existence implies distinct existence and vice versa) But we have good reason to suppose that our impressions have no distinct existence. An “experiment” to confirm this: Press the side of an eyeball and you see everything double. Consider these doubled images. Causal reasoning shows that at least one of them is dependent on pressing the side of the eyeball. And so not distinct from us and what we do to ourselves. But the two images are alike in all respects but position. From like effects we ought to infer like causes. So the other image must be due to us as well. This same reasoning could be applied to any of a number of instances of perceptual relativity and variation. e.g., the changes in the size and shape of visible objects with changes in our position Upshot We are caught up in a contradiction: Imagination, under the influence of the resemblance relation and natural propensities leads us to believe in the continued existence of our impressions when not perceived and hence their distinct existence. But causal reasoning leads us to deny the distinct existence of our impressions and hence to deny that they could continue to exist when not perceived. What do we do about this? The vulgar: – do not think about the problem and simply continue to follow natural instinct & imagination Philosophers – try to have things both ways: • satisfy the imagination by continuing to believe that objects exist unperceived • satisfy reason by denying that these objects are our impressions This leads to a theory of “double existence” According to this theory, our impressions are caused by distinct, external objects that resemble them. So our impressions are transient images or copies of distinct, continued external objects. Problems with the vulgar theory It is patently false. Problems with the philosophical theory It makes a causal assertion that is unjustified and unjustifiable. Before we can say that x causes y, we need to have had experience of x’s regularly being followed by y’s. But we have no experience of distinct external objects resembling our impressions and causing them. We only ever experience our impressions. Philosophers invent the theory of double existence because they wanted to have things both ways. (Because the vulgar way of looking at things still holds enough sway over them that they want to reconcile it with reason.) But because there is no good reason for the theory, … … if they believe it, their belief is based on wishful thinking (and on the propensities of the imagination leading us to wish that way) not on the evidence. Hume’s sceptical conclusion After a thorough review of the causes of the belief in body, it is hard not to be sceptical of the soundness of that belief. All the same, none of us is capable of preserving in this scepticism for long and believing only what is legitimated by reason. Our nature forces us to believe in body whether we think the reasons for doing so are good or not.