Two rival views of the basis for the Christian religion Christianity is based on reason. Christianity is based on faith. Theological Problems with 1 If we can be saved merely by the use of reason, then the sacrifice on the cross was unnecessary for salvation. Theological Problems with 2 Since not everyone is a Christian, even today, the cross has been of no effect in a huge number of cases. This implies that the sacrifice was never intended to redeem all, but only some, arbitrarily selected for redemption. How Christianity is based on reason i) Causal inference from design in nature as an effect (leads us to infer the existence of a very wise, benevolent, and powerful intelligent designer as cause) But an intelligent, benevolent being would be concerned to tell us important things that we couldn’t know by unassisted reason (e.g., about an afterlife) So there must have been a revelation. And there must have been signs given to prove that the revelation is authentic. So miracles must have occurred How Christianity is based on reason, cont.’d ii) Historical experience, communicated by testimony (shows that the authentic miracles were performed to authenticate the revelation of Christ) So the Christian revelation must be the true one. And our faith in it can be based on reason and not merely on grace. Hume’s project in Enquiry XI and X Attack the view that the Christian religion (or any other) is based on reason. (Apparently, in the name of establishing that its proper and only foundation is a gracious gift of faith) In Enquiry X, the attack on rational belief in miracles is made in Hume’s own voice and is also presented as if it were merely an attack on “superstitious delusion of all kinds” (esp. Catholocism) leaving room for an attenuated, deistic religion based on reason and without any particular revelation In Enquiry XI, the attack on the design argument is presented by way of reporting on a discussion with a “friend” who reports the views of “Epicurus” the double framing establishes an apparent distance from Hume’s own commitments (and a real legal distance) moreover, “Epicurus” only attacks arguments for providence and an afterlife, not arguments for the existence of an intelligent creator Hume presents himself as objecting to the friend’s reasons for rejecting providence. But the response, though apparently offered in defence of providence, actually attacks the design argument as a reason for believing in the existence of God. Hume’s thesis in the essay on miracles A rational person (one who proportions belief to the evidence), could never believe that a miracle has occurred on the basis of human testimony. Limitations Irrational belief in miracles is not ruled out (on the contrary, it is explicitly allowed) Rational belief in miracles on the basis of divine testimony is explicitly allowed (Hume twice remarked that when the scriptures are taken as divine testimony there can be no doubt of the truth of their reports.) (though he did not say how one might go about establishing that the testimony is authentically divine) Rational belief in miracles on the basis of immediate personal experience is allowed. In particular, that a rational person should be able to sincerely believe that the scripture is the word of God, despite having no evidence for that belief is instanced as a miracle and one that the individual believer, elected for grace, experiences within themselves Marvel An entirely unprecedented event, but one not contrary to the established laws of nature. Miracle An event that occurs contrary to what the laws of nature say should happen and that is supposed to have been brought about by the will of an unseen, intelligent being Law of Nature A regularity in the succession of events that has never been known to be violated. Hume’s argument When reasoning from effect to cause, we must proportion our belief to the evidence. The more regular the succession, the stronger the belief; the greater the number of exceptions, the weaker the belief This applies to human testimony, considered as an effect of the actual occurrence of the events described. Our experience tells us that not all testimony is reliable. But it also shows us that testimony is accompanied by different “circumstances” In some of these circumstances it is more reliable than in others Circumstances shown by experience to affect the reliability of testimony The number of witnesses Their “independence” Their intelligence (are they easily duped?) Their interests (do they have something to gain or lose?) Their reputation (have they lied in the past) What they would stand to lose if shown to have told a lie How easy it would be to show that they told a lie A further factor affecting our judgments of the reliability of testimony The marvellousness or miraculousness of the event reported. Two ways in which this further factor influences our judgments Past experience has shown us that the more marvellous or miraculous an event report, the less likely it is to turn out to be true. Past experience has shown us that events of that sort do not occur. “Part i” of the essay on miracles entirely discounts the first of these factors. The thought experiment of Part i Suppose we have the best possible testimony to the occurrence of a miracle (Set aside all influence of any past experience of the unreliability of marvellous or miraculous tales) This means the testimony would have to be of a type that has never been observed to be false in any past experience So it is a law of nature that testimony of that type is never wrong The degree of conviction produced by that testimony cannot exceed proof. But because the testimony is testimony to a miracle, what it proves is the occurrence of an event that all our past experience tells us could not have occurred. i.e., an event that violates another law of nature. So in this case there is one law of nature (testimony of this sort cannot be false) contradicting another law of nature (an event of the sort testified to cannot occur) Hume’s conclusion The best that can happen in this case in the mind of a wise person (the minds of fools are another matter) is a “mutual destruction of evidence” (in accord with the theory of probability laid out in Treatise 1.3.11-12) Result: we at best end up not knowing what to believe whether the testimony is true or whether the event did not occur An objection: Why should a miracle have to be a violation of a law of nature? Ans. Nothing else will do the job of giving a sign of the presence of God. Another objection: This argument is too strong, because it rules out the possibility of scientific progress by discovering events contrary to what our current understanding of the laws of nature would predict. Ans. A miracle has to be a one time violation of a law of nature as the consequence of the will of an unseen intelligent being. If the event is something that will always occur in similar circumstances, then it is not a miracle. But (supposing determinism) when we don’t get the laws of nature right, the event merely looks miraculous and is in fact the sort of thing that always occurs in circumstances of a certain sort. So subsequent investigation ought to be able to correct the laws and explain the event. So the argument does not make scientific progress impossible; it merely describes some of the conditions under which it occurs. When an apparently miraculous event is reported by means of excellent testimony … … the wise ought to suspend all belief either way (this means suspending both the belief that the testimony is true and the belief that the event did not occur) Since this ignorance is intolerable we naturally seek to resolve it through further investigation of the case. If we can discover a hidden regularity in nature responsible for the event (a new law of nature) Then we have no more reason to doubt the testimony. But we also have no more reason to think the event was a miracle. As long as we fail to discover any such regularity, we must continue to suspend belief either way. The argument of Part ii In principle, no (human) testimony to the occurrence of a miracle … has ever been or could ever be of the sort that has been proven to be perfectly reliable by past experience. None has ever been good enough because as a matter of fact the witnesses have not been numerous enough, smart enough, or disinterested enough, nor have the opportunities for independent assessment been available. None could ever be good enough because: • the witnesses can never be disinterested. Thre are are special psychological factors that give people an interest in reporting and wanting to believe marvellous and miraculous stories: ◦ the pleasure of surprise & wonder ◦ religious sentiment inspiring: - enthusiasm - dishonesty in the service of the noble cause - dishonesty in one’s own self interest • past experience shows us that the more marvellous or miraculous the story, the less likely it is to be true • the miracle stories of different religious traditions contradict one another (and the best attested miracle stories are better attested than those in the New Testament, though they support the false religions of French Jansenist Catholicism and Roman Paganism) Concluding Remark on the “limitations” of the argument “… there may possibly be miracles, or violations of the usual course of nature, of such a kind as to admit of proof from human testimony …” This remark is illustrated with three increasingly radical case stories: • a story of 6 days of darkness (it becomes clear that Hume does not consider this to be a true case of testimony to a “miracle” as strictly defined: “It is evident, that our present philosophers, instead of doubting the fact, ought to receive it as certain, and ought to search for the causes whence it might be derived.” To think it is a consequence of discoverable natural causes is to deny it is a miraculous occurrence. So all we have here is a “violation of the usual course of nature” established by human testimony, not a miracle so established. • A story of the death and resurrection of Queen Elizabeth In this case, the strongest testimony is inadequate to prove the occurrence of the miraculous event and we will never allow that the death and resurrection was anything other than a hoax. What makes for the difference between the cases is that the one is not as clearly a violation of the laws of nature. What makes for the identity of the cases is that in both we look for some underlying law to explain the strange event that was reported. some corruption in the normal astronomical operations some political motive for perpetrating a hoax • A story of death and resurrection taken to serve as the basis for a religion In this case sensible people will reject the story without even bothering to look for an underlying law explaining the event (because it is too obvious from past experience that the only cause is the religious motive to perpetrate a hoax) The upshot of this discussion of cases is that there really are no limitations on the argument. The only way an extraordinary event can be justly believed on the basis of human testimony is if it is supposed to be not really miraculous but rather than consequence of hidden laws.