1 “’In the end, We have the Gatling Gun, And they have not’: Future Prospects of Indigenous Knowledges” James Maffie Department of Philosophy, Colorado State University Fort Collins, Colorado, USA 80523-1781 maffiej@lamar.colostate.edu Abstract: Charles Taylor argues the superiority of Western technology demonstrates the epistemological superiority of Western science over indigenous knowledges. I argue Taylor’s “might makes right” argument lacks deductive and inductive cogency, begs significant questions against indigenous knowledges, and confounds military subjugation with philosophical refutation. Polycentric global epistemology represents one possible future of indigenous knowledges. It consists of a variety of dialogues between mutual epistemological “others”. Participants ask, “how may this or that knowledge practice be brought into the service of human well-being?” It admits all varieties of knowledge practices ranging from rational argument and experimentation to dance, song, and ritual performance. It establishes a trading zone for mutual sharing, borrowing, and learning as well as collaborative projects. Keywords: Epistemology, indigenous knowledges, western science, western technology, “might makes right,” epistemological relativism, postcolonialism, feminism, polycentric global epistemology, alternative knowledges, trading zone. 1. Introduction The post-contact history as well as one likely future of indigenous knowledges is poignantly expressed by a ditty about 19th century British imperial forces in Africa cited 2 approvingly by Charles Taylor [1] in his 1982 article, “Rationality”: “In the end, We have the Gatling gun, And they have not.” The British employed the Gatling machine gun in their wars against the Zulu in 1871 and 1879, and against the Ashanti in 1874.1 The invention and deployment of Western technology such as the Gatling gun is philosophically significant, according to Taylor [1:104], since the undeniable superiority of Western technology “commands attention in a quite nontheoretical way.” As such it functions both as a theory-neutral foundation for rejecting epistemological relativism as well as a non-self-serving foundation for defending the epistemological superiority of modern Western science (MWS). By Taylor’s lights, Western technological might makes Western epistemological right.2 I begin my discussion of the futures of indigenous knowledges (IKs) with Taylor’s argument since I believe it poignantly expresses both popular and learned Western attitudes towards IKs. As Taylor’s unabashed use of the ditty shows, Western imperialism and Western confidence in its enduring ability to “shock and awe” the “other” serve as the backdrop and indeed bottom line for most Western discussions of IKs. Western hegemony is seen as evidence of Western epistemological (if not also moral, cultural, and biological) superiority.3 “The development of the machine gun”, writes historian of empire and technology Daniel Headrick [2:101], “ushered in an era of arms races and industrial slaughter.” The superiority of the Gatling gun consisted in its greater cost-effectiveness at killing. 2 Taylor speaks of Western science and technology in general terms and as a unified singularities. While I agree with those who defend the disunity of science and technology and thus the appropriate use of the plural, “sciences” and “technologies,” my discussion will follow Taylor’s usage for the sake of simplicity. The qualifications discussed in section 4.1 below must also be applied to the notions of science and technology. I also follow Taylor by expressing the relevant binary as “West vs. non-West” despite its many shortcomings and roots in European orientalism. Other binaries such as “North vs. South” and “1st world vs. 3rd world” have been proposed. None however is without its problems. As Harding [3:203, note #1] correctly observes, these terms refer to schools of thought and discursive traditions, not to the ethnicity, nationality or residence of their practitioners. For further discussion, see Harding, [3], Jaggar [4] and Shohat and Stam [5]. 3 Headrick [2:209], for example, writes, 1 3 Given its resonance with deeply held Western attitudes, it is not surprising Taylor’s argument has little drawn, if any, critical attention from Western philosophers. In fact, Taylor finds company with the likes of Ernest Gellner who writes: The cognitive and technological superiority of [the scientific-industrial] form of life is so manifest, and so loaded with implications for the satisfaction of human wants and needs … that it simply cannot be questioned. If a doctrine conflicts with the acceptance of the superiority of scientific-industrial societies over others, then it is really out (quoted in Salmond [10:259]).4 Taylor’s argument did, however, catch the eye of African philosopher Emevwo Biakolo. After rehearsing the repeated failure of Western philosophers to prove the epistemological superiority of MWS, Biakolo observes they appear to have one remaining argument left: the brute fact of Gatling guns. Biakolo [12:11] writes, "Indeed, confronted with a Gatling gun argument such as Taylor's, what hope of refutation have we?" Biakolo’s response seems to be one of exasperation, indignation, and outrage. How, as Enrique Dussel [13] puts it, can the colonial “other,” the “negated alterity” of European colonialism, respond to the “genocidal reason" of her imperial master? Is epistemology, like history, to be written by the victor? I argue in Section 2 below that Taylor’s argument lacks cogency. Section 3 surveys several indigenous responses to Taylor. Section 4 explores one possible future of indigenous knowledges: what I call “polycentric global epistemology.” The era of the new imperialism was also the age in which racism reached its zenith. Europeans, once respectful of some non-Western peoples – especially the Chinese – began to confuse levels of technology with levels of culture in general, and finally with biological capacity. Easy conquests had warped the judgment of even the scientific elites. While G. Gutierrez [6] writes, If in the first instance one could speak of the expansion and conquest as a result of the technological superiority of some peoples over others, in a second stage the technological superiority and the greater military capacity was made synonymous with rationality… (quoted in Levins and Lewontin, [7:226-27). See also Blaut [8], Harding [3] and Dussel [9]. 4 Laudan [11] advances a similar argument. 4 2. Critique of Taylor 2.1. Taylor’s Argument “Rationality” originally appeared in a highly respected collection of essays devoted to issues of epistemological relativism and the rationality of indigenous peoples. Taylor writes impatiently of the endless caviling over indigenous practices such as Azande chicken poisoning, and the seemingly endless conceptual acrobatics of epistemological relativists motivated by an “anti-imperialist liberal conscience” [1:99]. Cutting to the chase, he states what he sees an undeniable, brute fact: the more efficient killing power of European Gatling guns. [Technological] superiority commands attention in a quite non-theoretical way… We are reminded of the ditty about nineteenth-century British colonial forces in Africa: ‘Whatever happens, We have the Gatling gun and they have not.’ But … technological superiority also commands attention for good intellectual reasons [1:104]. The superior “technological spin-off” [1:97] of MWS is a theory-independent fact of that matter that cuts across incommensurable knowledge systems. Taylor writes, “once a spectacular degree of technological control is achieved, it commands attention and demands explanation" [1:103]. MWS “score[s] successes which command the attention of [IKs], and in fact have invariably done so when they met” [1:104]. "There is an inner connection between understanding the world and achieving technological control which rightly commands everyone's attention, and doesn't just justify our practice in our own eyes" [1:101]. In short, the greater technological might of MWS consequently entails its greater epistemological right. While we might feel queasy about “might makes right” arguments in the moral realm, we must find them compelling in the epistemological. 5 Western technological prowess has the additional virtue of trumping epistemological relativism and thus reassuring the West of its own epistemological superiority. The very existence of technological advance forces the issue. In this way, one set of practices can pose a challenge for an incommensurable interlocutor, not indeed in the language of this interlocutor, but in terms which the interlocutor cannot ignore. And out of this can arise valid transcultural judgments of superiority [1:103].5 Taylor then adduces additional evidence for science’s epistemological superiority. MWS can explain its technological superiority whereas IKs cannot: The superiority of modern science is that it has a very simple explanation for [its technological success]: that it has greatly advanced our understanding of the material world. It's not clear what traditional [IKs] could say about this phenomenon, or where [they] could go for an explanation [1:103]. Taylor thus challenges IKs to explain Western technological prowess. I call this “Taylor’s challenge.” One may respond to Taylor in several ways: (a) attack the cogency of his inference from might to right; (b) respond to “Taylor’s challenge”; or (c) refuse to respond to Taylor. I examine each below. 2.2. Criticizing the Cogency of Taylor’s Argument 2.2.1. Taylor’s Premises Let’s begin by granting Taylor the following three premises: modern Western technology (MWT) is successful; MWT is more successful than indigenous technologies; Gellner writes, “the philosophical significance of the scientific-industrial ‘form of life’ … is that for all practical purposes, it does provide us with a solution of the problem of relativism – though a highly asymmetrical one...” (quoted in Salmond [10:259]). See also Laudan [11]. Taylor cites the global diffusion of Western technology as additional evidence of the epistemological superiority of MWS for it shows a recognition of the superiority of Western science. Time does not allow me to address this argument. The fact of diffusionism as well as explanation of diffusionism in terms of epistemological superiority are criticized by Turnbull [14], Latour [15], Hess [16] and Harding [3] among others. 5 6 and MWT’s successes command people’s attention. Giving Taylor a “pass” on these is not uncontroversial, seeing as the success of MWT and the accounting practices that measure this success have both come under blistering attack. Alvares [17:83] writes: Much of science has passed under the slogan of the conquest of nature. We are given to believe that we are in control of nature today even though we are not even certain of our survival. This alleged control justifies the scientists’ authority.6 Alvares [17:78] then contradicts Taylor’s conclusion: If a correct picture of nature had emerged from science, there would have been no pollution or ecological imbalance on the application of such scientific knowledge. The negative consequences indicate that the picture itself does not fit with the demands of nature. Indeed, many argue that global warming represents an “attention commanding” brute fact that trumps Taylor’s (and Gellner’s) confidence in the epistemological superiority of MWS. According to Sachs [25: 36], for example, global warming represents a “civilizational impasse” that calls into question the very core assumptions of Western culture. Indeed, one wonders why a parallel, indigenous ditty, “We have a sustainable way of life, and they have not,” is not equally if not more damning of MWS and Gellner’s “scientific-industrial way of life”?7 Taylor readily concedes MWS and MWT may have “disastrous” [1:103] consequences in terms of our relationships with nature, but quickly adds that this does not gainsay the epistemological superiority of MWS. Environmental destruction is the result 6 See also Alvares [18, 19]. The success of Western technology has been called into question by (among others) Shiva [20, 21], Third World Network [22], and Escobar [23]. One might argue that the position statements of and hence disagreement between Taylor and Gellner, on the one hand, and Alvares, on the other, are formulated in overly general terms. Neither side offers a fine-grained analysis of the interrelationships between sciences, technologies, cultures, and capitalisms, and hence a fine-grained attribution of causal responsibility. Thanks to David Turnbull for pointing this out to me. See Harding [3,24] for further discussion and overview of these issues. 7 See Flannery [26]. While many indigenous ways of life are not and have not been sustainable, others appear to be equally or more sustainable than Gellner’s “scientific-industrial way of life.” 7 of Western scientific culture’s “estrangement from ourselves and our world” and thus epistemologically irrelevant [1:103]. Environmental destruction is a product of the valueladen application of our technology and knowledge, not our value-neutral technological capabilities or scientific knowledge per se. Very briefly, this response looks inadequate on three counts. First, it is not clear that the application of our technology and knowledge is distinguishable from our technological capabilities and scientific knowledge in the way Taylor needs. Second, it is not clear that the latter is any less value-laden than the former. And finally, even if we do assume along with Taylor that scientific knowledge is distinguishable from its technological applications, then it is not clear why technological success counts in favor of epistemological success but technological failure does not count against it.8 Let’s grant Taylor three further premises: MWS and MWT are separable enterprises (rather than a single enterprise, viz., technoscience); MWT is a “spin-off” of MWS; and the practical success of MWT is due to its “inner connection” with MWS. These premises are likewise controversial.9 The question now confronting us is: what exactly does the attention commanding success of MWT prove epistemologically speaking? How do we get from the practical superiority of MWT to the epistemological superiority of MWS? 2.2.2. Taylor’s Argument Lacks Cogency Taylor appears to conceive epistemological success in terms of “understanding … physical nature” [1:103], and he seems to conceive this in terms of apprehending truths 8 See Harding [3,24], Levins and Lewontin [7], Hess [16], Shiva [20,21], Alvares [17,18,19] and Turnbull [14] for further discussion. 9 For criticism, see Chambers and Gillespie [27], Shiva [20, 21] Hess [16], Turnbull [14], Harding [3,24], and Alvares [17,18,19]. 8 about the deep structure of nature, or as Plato put it, “cutting nature at the joints”. Taylor thus appears to embrace a version of scientific realism, i.e. the thesis that MWS yields a true (or approximately true) account of the physical world.10 The epistemological status of scientific realism has long exercised 20th century Western philosophers of science. Scientific realists standardly defend their thesis by appealing to the predictive and manipulative success of MWS. Early scientific realists (led by J.J.C. Smart) defended their view using a traditional, a priori philosophical argument: the "no miracles" argument.11 They argue that if science did not deliver truth, it would be a miracle that it worked as well as it does. While perhaps intuitively compelling, this argument is deductively invalid and logically fallacious. One cannot exclude a priori the logical possibility of miracles any more than one can exclude Cartesian evil demons. Taylor’s inference from might to right is thus also deductively invalid. Technological success does not logically entail epistemological success since neither technological, practical or even predictive success logically entails truth (or even approximate truth). Later scientific realists (led by Boyd [30]) advance what they regard as a more plausible albeit openly a posteriori naturalistic philosophy-style argument: an abductive inference or argument from inference to the best explanation. While acknowledging the deductive invalidity of inferring truth (or approximate truth) from predictive and manipulative success, they claim truth (or approximate truth) offers the best scientific explanation of the latter.12 Unfortunately, critics such as Larry Laudan, Arthur Fine and Bas van Fraassen have successfully shown Boyd’s abductive inference to be fatally 10 11 For additional discussion, see Klee [28] and Godfrey-Smith [29]. See Klee [28] and Godfrey-Smith [29] for discussion. 9 flawed on scientific grounds. Furthermore, they have cast significant doubt upon the utility if not very intelligibility of the concept of approximate truth.13 At this time the inference from technological (and even predictive) success to truth (or truth-likeness) thus appears dead in the water. Pace Taylor, the epistemological superiority of MWS cannot rest on the fact “that [MWS] has a very simple explanation for [technological success]: that it has greatly advanced our understanding of the material world,” for science offers no such explanation.14 In sum, Taylor’s argument lacks deductive and inductive cogency. Greater technological control does not “justify our practice” even “in our own eyes" [1:101]. Whatever the “inner connection between understanding the world and achieving technological control” is, it is neither deductive nor inductive. Simply put, Taylor’s argument confounds subjugation with refutation. IKs have been defeated, not disproven, by Western technology. Before proceeding, let’s assume for the sake of argument that Taylor’s inference is cogent. Where does “might makes right” take us? As Cesaire [32] noted, after decades of faithful service in the killing fields of imperialism, Europe’s capacity for efficient, industrial slaughter was eventually turned upon itself, most notoriously by Nazi Germany. Is the attention commanding technological success of the death camps such as Auschwitz proof of Nazi epistemological superiority over Jews, Slavs, socialists, homosexuals, etc.? Many Europeans perceived the Third Reich’s stunning military 12 Abductive inference is a species of inductive inference. See the essays by Larry Laudan, Arthur Fine, and Bas van Fraassen in Leplin [31]. For further discussion, see Klee [28] and Godfrey-Smith [29]. 14 Even if truth did provide the “best” scientific explanation of the technological success, this argument would beg the question against IK’s, not because inductive logic is relative, but because comparative judgments of best are always context-relative. There is no absolute, context-free criterion of best. What 13 10 triumphs over France in 1940 as conclusive evidence of its superiority over French ideas of universal reason and modernity (Wolin [33]). Should we add to the list the epistemological superiority of “Nazi physics” over “Jewish” and “bourgeois physics”? One wonders, had Nazi Germany won WW II, or the Soviet Union, the Cold War, would Taylor still be invoking “technological might makes epistemological right”? Or would he find himself in Biakolo’s shoes, i.e. being required to explain the obvious technological superiority of his conquerors? 2.3 Taylor’s Metaphysical Assumptions Taylor’s argument rests upon several crucial, undefended metaphysical assumptions that beg the question against non-Western-science-style knowledges.15 Perhaps most significantly, Taylor assumes reality is structured and unified by a single set of timeless laws or essences: i.e. that the cosmos is a universe rather than a pluriverse. In the West this notion dates at least to Plato’s metaphysical realism (and arguably more distantly to the religious idea of a cosmos governed divine commandments). Reality is characterized by being, not becoming. That which is permanent, static, and timeless is real; that which is impermanent, mutable, and timed is not. Laws, structure, and essences do not change and are ontologically fundamental. All else is ontologically derivative and reducible to them. This picture also assumes an ontological appearance/reality distinction. That which changes is only apparently real; that which is static is really real. This metaphysical picture has traditionally shaped two epistemological assumptions: knowledge of reality consists of the correct theoretical apprehension of the fundamental, counts as “best” depends upon one’s context, and Taylor begs the question by assuming the relevant context to be MWS. 15 In addition to those discussed, Taylor assumes nature is inanimate and reality is characterized by an ontological fact/value distinction. Given spatial constraints, I can not explore these here. 11 timeless ontological order of reality, and; explanation consists of situating events or objects in terms of this order. A wide variety of world philosophies reject Taylor’s metaphysical picture including classical Confucianism and Daoism as well as indigenous North and Mesoamerican philosophies.16 They maintain that the cosmos is a pluriverse rather than a universe. Reality is plural, not single. It consists of a multiplicity of ontological and causal relationships that are neither unified or ordered into a single whole, nor reducible to some more basic single order. Rather than no one “true” order there are many “equally true” orders. Hence there is no single way the world is really, fundamentally or essentially; no way it is at bottom. In place of a single set of basic Platonic-style “joints,” there are many “joints” no one of which is more ontologically fundamental than the next. There are neither natural kinds nor essences ordering reality. Reality is processive, not static. Finally, there is no ontological distinction between appearance and reality. These philosophies conceive knowing and understanding in practical terms of knowing how to do things, not in theoretical terms of knowing that certain facts, truths, or laws obtain. Since there are many relations in nature no one (or specific group) of which is ontologically more fundamental, it follows that knowledge of no one (or specific group of) relationship(s) is epistemologically more fundamental (in the sense of understanding how nature “really works”). There are many different knowings of nature, all of which are on a par. Knowing how to build Gatling guns and gas chambers, for example, is no more epistemologically probative than knowing how to prepare food, cure susto (soul 16 For classical East Asian philosophy, see Hall [34] and Hall and Ames [35]. For indigenous North American philosophies, see Cajete [36], Deloria, et al. [37], Deloria, Jr., and Wildcat, [38] and Pratt [39]. For indigenous Mesoamerican philosophy, see Maffie [40,41]. For Afro-Caribbean philosophy, see Henry [42]. For general discussion, see Posey [43]. 12 loss), or live sustainably upon the earth. Thus, the fact that MWS has succeeded in mastering one particular set of natural relationships does not entail that it better understands reality per se or that it is epistemologically superior to non-western knowledge systems that focus on different relationships. Note, however, that these epistemologies do distinguish knowings in terms of the values they promote. Knowing how to use those natural relations that enable humans to flourish is more significant than knowing how to use those relations that enable humans to build Gatling guns. Significance is conceived in terms of a single integrated category of epistemology, ethics, social-political philosophy, and aesthetics.17 A host of unorthodox Western philosophers (including James [44], Dewey 45], Cartwright [46], Rorty [47], Dupre [48], Turnbull [14,49], and Harding [3,24] to name only a few) also reject Taylor’s metaphysical assumptions. They conceive the universe in pluralistic terms (see also Galison and Stump [50]). There are many regularities, processes, orders, and forces in nature, no one of which is ontologically more basic and hence epistemologically more fundamental than the other. Note, finally, that none of the aforementioned need deny Taylor’s premises that technological success “commands attention,” that technological success is based upon understanding natural relationships, or that MWS succeeds in cutting nature “at the joints.” What they do deny is that nature possesses just one set of joints and hence the validity of Taylor’s inference that MWS therefore knows nature in some more fundamental way. 17 For further discussion, see Hall and Ames [35,55], Deloria, et al [37], Deloria and Wildcat [38], Pratt [39] and Maffie [40,41, 54]. 13 2.4. Taylor’s Epistemological Assumptions Taylor also makes a host of question-begging epistemological assumptions. He assumes, e.g.: a conception of epistemology which defines evidence, understanding, explanation, and knowledge in terms of truth; the aim of cognition from the epistemological point of view is maximizing truth and minimizing falsehood; truth is a matter of correspondence between sentences, propositions, or representations and reality.18 This set of assumptions is rejected by those philosophies which Hall and Ames [35, 55] call “way-seeking” as opposed to “truth-seeking”. Hall and Ames [35, 55] along with Hansen [56] argue classical Taoist and Confucian epistemologies are concerned neither with truth, true belief nor truthful representation. Rather, they are concerned with identifying the proper path or appropriate model of conduct that will enable humans to live the kind of life suitable for human beings. For Confucians, e.g., this consists of living harmoniously with one's social surroundings. Correspondence truth plays no role in this endeavor. One aims for a life of authenticity, genuineness, rectitude and wholeness -- not knowledge defined as justified true belief. Confucian epistemology seeks to identify the kind practical of know-how needed for following this path. Deloria, Jr., (Deloria, et al [37]) and Hester and Cheney [57] contend indigenous North American philosophies treat cognitive states as maps rather than as beliefs. Native Americans adopt an agnostic attitude towards the correspondence-truth of their maps seeing as they are concerned only with the utility of maps as practical action-guides. Native American philosophy does not focus upon belief and thus worries not about the correspondence-truth of belief. Native Americans focus upon practices and adopt an 14 attitude of non-belief (i.e. neither belief nor disbelief) towards their practices. Knowing is likewise practical. It is not a species of belief or theoretical attitude towards some abstract proposition, justified or otherwise. Conquest-era indigenous Nahuatl-speaking philosophers in Central Mexico conceived knowing in terms of balance, well-groundedness, moral uprightness, authenticity and disclosingness (Gingerich [58], Leon-Portilla [59], Maffie [40,41,52]). Correspondence truth played no role in their notions of wisdom, knowledge, or right belief. Indigenous Amazonia philosophy similarly conceives knowledge in terms of the trustworthy, responsible, and careful ordering and arranging of things. It eschews broad, overarching, abstract conceptions of truth such as correspondence between propositions and world (Brotherston [60]). In sum, way-seeking epistemologies maintain there are many different ways of knowing, no one of which is more probative (in the truth-centered epistemological sense of apprehending the structure of nature) than the next. Secondly, Taylor begs the question by assuming that knowledge of reality is necessarily expressible in terms of technology, that technology exhausts human knowledge of reality, and that greater knowledge necessarily yields greater technological control. However, these assumptions are rejected by the foregoing way-seeking epistemologies as well as by the lion’s share of Western truth-seeking epistemologies (beginning with Plato and Aristotle) that standardly define knowledge in terms of theoretical contemplation rather than practical application. They maintain there are ways of knowing nature that are not expressible technologically. By their lights, greater technological success does not entail greater understanding.19 18 19 For additional discussion, see Verran [51], Hall [34] and Maffie [52,53,54]. Thanks to Paul Roth for helping me clarify this point. See Maffie [54] for further discussion. 15 Lastly, Taylor begs the question by assuming a fact/value distinction according to which knowledge of reality consists of knowing descriptive facts, regularities, or truths but not knowing normative or valuational (e.g. moral or aesthetic) facts, regularities, or truths. 3. Some Indigenous Responses to “Taylor’s Challenge” 3.1. Some Indigenous Explanations Indigenous explanations of Western technological success are readily available. Needless to say, Western scientists and philosophers do not consider them even remotely plausible. However I suggest this evaluation begs the question against indigenous styles of explanation (such as narrative and intentional explanations) by assuming the correctness of both Western metaphysics and the Western scientific styles of explanation (e.g. subsumption under general laws) such metaphysics underwrites.20 I sketched one such explanation above. Western technological success is a consequence of MWS successfully mastering certain natural relationships. Indigenous knowledges master others. A similar explanation subsumes MWS and MWT within a broader distinction between two kinds of knowing that is grounded upon a distinction between two kinds of forces: “evil” or “dark” vs. “good” or “light.” “Sorcerers” possess the former kind of knowing; “shamans,” the latter. Yet neither sorcery nor shamanism are epistemologically more probative.21 The Kogi of the Colombian Sierra Nevada apparently explain the Conquest and Western technological success as follows. Kogi and Europeans are long separated 20 For discussion of the contrasting styles of western scientific vs. indigenous explanation, see Frankfurt and Frankfurt [61], Lindberg, [62] and Posey [43]. 21 The distinction between what Western anthropologists call “sorcery” and “shamanism” is widespread. See, for example, Hallen [63], Middleton [64] and Ortiz de Montellano [65]. 16 brothers who were created long ago in the Sierra Nevada by Sernkua, son of Aluna, the Mother creator of all things. The Kogi are the wise, elder brothers. They were made in order to care for the earth and all its inhabitants. Europeans are the foolish, younger brothers with a butterfly-like mind. Younger brother was eventually ejected from the Sierra and exiled to the lands across the sea. However, he was given the gift of technological know-how. He has now returned to the Sierra and is foolishly destroying it. Since all things, including technological inventions, have always existed in the mind of Aluna, and since younger brother’s technological know-how was a gift from Aluna, the Kogi deny Europeans’ greater technological know-how entails their superior understanding of nature (Ereira [66:118-120]). The Nahuatl-speaking peoples of Central Mexico explained the Conquest and Spanish military technology in several ways. According to one story recorded in Bernardino de Sahagun’s Florentine Codex, several groups of humans arrived by boat long ago at a place called Panutla or Pantla. From there they followed their god, Totecuyo, walking east to a place called Tamoanchan. After living there for some time, the humans were abandoned by Totecuyo and his priests, who returned to the east and took with them their mechanical arts. Totecuyo promised to return some day when the world was nearing its end. The Spanish were seen as long departed but now returning human beings. The Nahuas viewed the Spaniards’ technological skills, as they view all human inventions, knowledge, and art works, as gifts from the gods.22 Lastly, towards the end of the 19th century the Fipa of Tanzania explained the success of Europeans in terms of their being “monsters -- something, in their terms, at 22 Miguel Lopez Austin brought this explanation to my attention in personal correspondence (1/16/04). For more, see Lopez Austin [67]. 17 once sub- and super-human” (Willis [68:256]). What does this mean? I suggest we take a page from Western ideology. A common explanatory strategy employed by Western ideologists when confronted with instances of Western inferiority relative to non-Western peoples has been to appeal to the “fact” that non-Western peoples are more cunning, instinctual, and savage than Westerners. In this way their greater abilities and successes do not suggest epistemological superiority but rather closer proximity to the animal or natural realm. This permits them some measure of success vis-à-vis the West without being superior. I suggest we interpret the Tipa’s claim in this way: Europeans are at once “sub- and super-human.” 3.2. Declining “Taylor’s Challenge” Some indigenous peoples may simply decline to respond to “Taylor’s challenge.” First, some may regard the cosmos as fundamentally mysterious and hence ultimately unexplainable. Ermine [69] asserts the aim of some IKs is “to coexist with mystery in nature by celebrating mystery versus eradicating mystery by explaining it away (quoted in Aikenhead [70:220]). They do not therefore view explanation as epistemologically probative or as an essential ingredient of understanding nature, and therefore neither care about nor seek explanations. Thus they do not consider it a shortcoming that they have no explanation to offer Taylor. Indeed, it is common for IKs to reject what they see as Western philosophy’s (and religion’s) obsession with truth (as correspondence), belief, and worldview. What matters most to indigenous North Americans, for example, is how one lives -- not what one 18 believes. Indigenous North American philosophy is practice-centered; it is concerned with orthopraxy, not orthodoxy.23 Deloria, Jr., and Wildcat [38:6] write: Indians use a peculiar way of maintaining a metaphysical stance that can best be termed as "suspended judgment." People did not feel it obligatory that they reach a logical conclusion or that they could summarize the world of experience in a few words and sentences. Knowledge concerns how one conducts oneself in the world. It is not about producing rational arguments or deductive-nomological explanations, and the inability to produce these is not considered an epistemological shortcoming. Indeed, it is precisely the insistence upon rational proofs that is typically considered a shortcoming. Hence the very idea of discursively refuting Taylor is misplaced since it appeals to notions of propositional truth and falsity that these philosophies reject.24 Edmund Carpenter reports the Inuit shaman, Aua, responded to Knud Rasmussen’s endlessly annoying questions about Aua’s cosmological beliefs by saying, “… we explain nothing; we believe nothing…” (quoted in Rothenberg [71:77]). The Dinka’s response to such questions is: "We don't know," by which they mean, "The answer means nothing to us." It is not a confession of ignorance accompanied by a desire to learn the answer (Lienhardt [72:147]). Many indigenous cultures use silence to express indifference (see Plank [73]). Ritually oriented schools of many knowledge practices such as Shrine Shinto claim they teach no theology, doctrines, or beliefs. What they teach is method or ritual. Mircea Eliade relates the anecdote of an American philosopher who asked a Shinto priest why Japanese Shinto lacked a theology. The priest responded, "We have no theology. We 23 See Hester and Cheney [58]. Other philosophies concerned with orthopraxy include Conquest-era indigenous Nahua philosophy and Classical Confucianism and Taoism. 24 I owe this point to David Turnbull (personal correspondence). 19 dance." 25 James Boyd reports commonly hearing Shrine Shinto priests and laity using the word “kotoagesezu” or “word not saying” or “no doctrine” when talking about Shinto.26 Discursively refuting Taylor is misconceived. If, however, Shrine Shinto priests were to respond with dance – or ritual, music, poetry, narrative, or pictorial art for that matter -would Taylor find these acceptable? Second, some indigenous peoples may decline to engage with Taylor since as Deloria, Jr., writes, “[w]hen we talk with non-Indians about nature, there is really nothing that we can say in universal western concepts that is going to make a lot of sense [to them] (Deloria, et al. [37:224]; see also Posey [43]). A third response deconstructs “Taylor’s challenge.” Some indigenous peoples may simply refuse to be interrogated in the court of “imperialist reason” (Mignolo [75:186]): i.e. one that presupposes their inferiority as well as rigs the rules against their participating effectively. This response situates Taylor’s argument within the context of over 500 years of Western debates over the epistemological (biological, moral, etc.) status of indigenous peoples that have, in turn, taken place within the larger context of over 500 years of Western imperialism, genocide, racism, and ethnocide. The question concerning the comparative epistemological merits of MWS and IKs has always, as Linda Tuhiwai Smith observes, been viewed “through imperial eyes.” It: assumes that Western ideas about the most fundamental things are the only ideas possible to hold, certainly the only rational ideas, the only ideas that make sense of the world, of reality, of social life and of human beings. It is an approach to indigenous peoples which still conveys a sense of innate superiority… (Smith [76:56]). 25 I owe this anecdote to James Boyd (personal correspondence, 7/19/06). The anecdote occurs in Eliade [74: 31]. 26 James Boyd, personal correspondence 7/19/06. Many scholars also interpret some schools of Buddhism as advocating a method, not a theology. 20 Taylor seems oblivious to the fact that his “challenge” is fraught with “the asymmetrical situation of the other, the concrete empirical impossibility that the ‘excluded,’ ‘dominated,’ or ‘compelled,’ can intervene effectively...” (Dussel [13: footnote #15]). Indigenous deconstruction asks: Who asks such questions as “Are indigenous beliefs epistemologically justified?” and “Are indigenous peoples rational?”, and why do they ask them? Who bears the burden of proof? Who is in the position to demand selfvalidation, and from whom is self-validation being demanded? Whose concepts, standards, rules, and criteria govern this exchange? Who has the Gatling Gun pointed at her head, and who is doing the pointing? In short, the nature, content, form and participants of the controversy reflect “the will of the winners in political and military struggles” (Schutte [77:50]).27 Responding to “Taylor’s challenge” on Taylor’s terms is simply a fool’s errand. 4. Global Polycentric Epistemology 4.1. Introduction Indigenous knowledges face an ever-growing threat of extinction through genocide of indigenous peoples, ethnocide of indigenous cultures and languages, and ecocide of indigenous habitats. Gatling guns have been replaced by global warming, death squads, globalization, neoliberalism, theft of land, predatory religions (e.g. Mormonism and Evangelical Protestantism) and corporate as well as “New Age” 27 Jagger [4:5] writes: Empirical discussions are always infused with power, which influences who is able to participate and who is excluded, who speaks and who listens, whose remarks are heard and whose are dismissed, which topics are addressed and which are not, what is questioned and what is taken for granted, even whether a discussion takes place at all. 21 piracy.28 As Smith [76:107] wrote on the eve of the new century, “For indigenous peoples, the beginning of a new century is really a continuation of a struggle that began 500 years ago.” More optimistically, however, she observes indigenous peoples are now better organized and better able to respond to such threats than ever before. Indigenous peoples are thus currently spread across a spectrum of hope and despair (Smith [76]). I employ the definition of “indigeneity” adopted by the Special Rapporteur of the UN Economic and Social Council Sub-Commission on Prevention of Discrimination and Protection of Minorities: Indigenous communities, peoples and nations are those which, having a historical continuity with pre-invasion and pre-colonial societies that have developed on their territories, consider themselves distinct from other sectors of the societies now prevailing in those territories, or parts of them. They form at present nondominant sectors of society and are determined to preserve, develop and transmit to future generations their ancestral territories, and their ethnic identity, as the basis of their continued existence as peoples, in accordance with their own cultural patterns, social institutions and legal systems.29 I understand indigenous knowledge to include activities such as shamanism, sorcery, ceremony, ritual, and mysticism as well as farming, weaving, storytelling, navigating, building, hunting, painting, singing, cooking, dancing, playing music, animal husbandry, astronomy, botany, medicine, mathematics, toolmaking, and childrearing. Regarding IKs (and indigeneity generally), I do not assume: (a) essentialism, i.e. that IK has a stable and enduring essence which if lost, results in its no longer being indigenous; (b) ahistoricalism, i.e. that IK’s have not, do not, and cannot change over time; (c) reificationism, i.e. that IK’s are discrete, bounded, and impermeable entities over and above the activities of their practitioners; (d) ecological romanticization, i.e. that 28 See Posey [43], Smith [76], Hughes [78], Hess [16], Shiva [79], Third World Network [22], Alvares [80], Greene [81], The Zapatistas [82], and Indigenous Knowledge and Development Monitor [83]. 29 Quoted in Hughes [78:15]. For further discussion, see Hughes [78], Posey [43], and Smith [76]. 22 IKs are ecologically non-destructive, ideal or perfect; (e) moral romanticization, i.e. that IK’s are neither oppressive of cultural sub-groups (such as women) nor the product of such oppressions; (g) purity, i.e. that IKs are pure (rather than syncretic or hybrid), and; (h) homogeneity, i.e. that all practitioners of IK think and act uniformly.30 4.2. Polycentric Global Epistemology One possible future for IKs lies in what I call polycentric global epistemology (PGE). This view draws heavily from scholars who characterize their work as “postEurocentric,” “postcolonial,” “post-Enlightenment,” “global,” “multicultural,” “feminist,” “polycentric,” “pluricentric,” “transmodern,” and “emancipatory”.31 A necessary prerequisite of this undertaking as well as its first and foremost goal is the survival and self-determination of indigenous peoples and their knowledges.32 As Fisher urges, “the fundamental issue is not what Native peoples can offer national societies, but instead how national societies can be prodded into recognizing and honoring the rights of Native peoples to self-determination” (quoted in Hess [16:233]). Any undertaking like polycentric global epistemology faces a daunting number of questions. Will there be one or many dialogues? Who will participate? How much commonality concerning assumptions, norms and goals is needed? Who speaks with an indigenous or Western voice? What is the goal of this endeavor? How will it be 30 For further discussion, see: Shiva [20, 21, 79], Smith [76], Harding [3, 24], Hess [16], Shohat and Stam [5], Hughes [78], Posey [43], Narayan [84], Schutte [77], Greene [81], and Garcia Canclini [85]. This list of caveats also applies to discussions of Western, science, and technology. 31 See Alvares [80], Harding [3, 24], Hess [16], Jaggar [4], Narayan [83], Turnbull [49], and Smith [76]. Shohat and Stam [5] and Schutte [77] reject liberal conceptions of pluralism in favor of what they call “polycentric multiculturalism” and “pluricentricism,” respectively. Dussell [13] characterizes such dialogue as “transmodern.” Shohat and Stam borrow “polycentric” from Amin [86]. 32 Indigenous peoples commonly argue that survival and self-determination necessarily include respect, decolonization, survival of culture and language, retention of land, economic development, social justice, emancipation of oppressed groups, and environmental responsibility (see Aikenhead [70], Smith [76], Hughes [78], and Hess [16]). For discussion of current indigenous projects, see Indigenous Knowledge and Development Monitor [83] and Center for World Indigenous Studies [87]. 23 structured? What are standards of evaluating alternative knowledges? And lastly, who decides the foregoing questions? While I believe, generally speaking, that this is something that needs to be negotiated continuously between those participating in PGE rather than dictated in advance, I offer the following tentative suggestions First, will there be one or many epistemological dialogues? I suggest there be a multitude of ongoing dialogues consisting of a variety of participants: some between Western and indigenous epistemologists and knowers, others between indigenous epistemologists and knowers themselves (and possibly closed to outsiders).33 Polycentric global epistemology consists of a polylogue of a variety of mutual epistemological “others.” Second, I suggest PGE functions as a way-seeking enterprise. Unlike truthseekers who “want to get to the bottom of things, to establish facts, principles, theories that characterize the way things [really] are,” way-seekers “search out those forms of action,” those knowledge practices, those ways of getting on in the world, that promote explicitly moral and social-political goals such as human emancipation (e.g. of women, working people, and indigenous peoples), self-determination, harmonious social existence, mutual respect, cooperation, and ecological sustainability. One enters PGE with way-seekers’ questions: "How, by what means, may this or that be brought into the service of human emancipation and well-being?"34 or “What would it be like to live that way?” Harding [24:156] writes, “Our methodological and epistemological choices are always also ethical and political choices,” and their adequacy is to be assessed in terms of their ability to shape future morally and politically desirable “futures.” They are always 33 Jaggar [4] offers compelling reasons for excluding dominant groups from participating in marginal groups’ discussions. I borrow the term “polylogue” from the Forum for Intercultural Philosophy [88]. 24 practical choices concerning the kinds of relations we want to have with one another and our environment. PGE is, borrowing from Shiva, an “ecological and a feminist project that legitimizes ways of knowing and being that create wealth by enhancing life and diversity, and which delegitimizes the knowledge and practices of a culture of death as the basis for capital accumulation…”35 Polycentric global epistemology is therefore not a theoretical endeavor in search of the correct definition of evidence, knowledge or epistemology. It does not presume there is a single epistemological good or that its polylogues will converge on a single cognitive good as the ideal end of inquiry. PGE does not, in the tradition of Western discourse theory, define epistemological justification or knowledge in terms of universal consensus under conditions of domination-free communication. It is not a Rawlsian-style constructivist justification procedure. It does not seek unanimity regarding specific knowledge-claims, definitions of knowledge or knowledge practices. Lastly, it does not function as a world assembly for resolving epistemological disputes or ratifying the knowledges of particular communities. Third, PGE begins by recognizing that the world contains a variety of dynamic knowledge practices, sites, or perspectives and that these are all equally inescapably local. All knowledges and epistemologies are local in the sense that they proceed from specific vantage points and have their “social basis in a particular culture, class and gender” (Shiva [90:283]), “are produced/constructed by people in places with specific practices” (Turnbull [49:29]), and “are ‘situated’ in power relationships, value 34 35 The preceding quotations are from Hall and Ames [35:104]. See also Harding [3,24]. Quoted in Escobar [89:143]. See also Harding [3, 24]. 25 assumptions, and historical frameworks” (Chambers and Gillespie [27:235]).36 All are partial, incomplete, and hence “prison houses” – although also “cultural resources”-- for knowledge production (Harding [24:11]). In doing so PGE “levels the playing field” (Harding [24:11]) between Western and indigenous knowledges. In so doing it also decenters and provincializes Western epistemology (and philosophy generally).37 It rejects the assumption that the knowledge practices and epistemological activities of Western thinkers constitute knowledge and epistemology proper, whereas those of indigenous thinkers constitute mere ethnoknowledge and ethnoepistemology, respectively. Western epistemology no longer serves as the benchmark by which epistemology per se is defined or by which other epistemologies are evaluated. It is not the apogee of epistemological development but rather one epistemological trajectory, one ethnoepistemology, among many. Its questions, concepts, definitions, distinctions, and concerns are no more universal – and no less local -- than those of Yoruba, Zapotec, Maori, Han, and Washo philosophers. In sum PGE requires Western epistemologists to “open up to the plurality of forms of knowledge” and epistemologies “that exist in the world and recognize that objective, detached scientific knowledge” and Western epistemology are simply two possibilities “among many” (Escobar [89:143]).38 36 See Harding [3, 24] for additional discussion. I borrow the concept of provincializing Western thought from Chakrabarty [91]. See also Maffie [54]. 38 PGE rejects the arrogant ethnocentricism and provincialism expressed by such prominent Western philosophers as: Edmund Husserl who claimed the expression "Western philosophy" is tautalogous, the expression "non-western philosophy", oxymoronic (quoted Gupta and Mohanty [92:xi]); Emmanuel Levinas who is quoted as having remarked, "I always say -- but in private -- that the Greeks and the Bible are all that is serious in humanity. Everything else is dancing" (quoted in Bernasconi [93:185]); and Richard Rorty who argues that looking for philosophy outside of the West is "pointless" since philosophy is unique to Western culture (quoted in Hallen [94:17]). 37 26 Fourth, PGE involves a commitment not only to the inclusion but more crucially to the privileging of indigenous knowledges. Shohat and Stam [5:48] write: Polycentricism is not about “touchy-feely” sensitivity towards other groups; it is about dispersing power, about empowering the disempowered, about transforming subordinating institutions and discourses. [It] demands changes not just in images but in power relations. PGE thus rejects add-diversity-and-stir-style pluralism that preaches formal equality, tolerance, and inclusion but effectively reinforces inequality and represses difference. It embraces the lessons of the standpoint epistemologies of Marx [95], Marcuse [96], Harding [97], Collins [98] and others39 which give greater weight to the voices of the marginalized and oppressed (e.g. women, indigenous people, and workers). PGE “does not preach a pseudo-equality of viewpoints; its sympathies go to the underrepresented, the marginalized and oppressed” (Shohat and Stam [5:48]). Fifth, PGE advocates conserving epistemological diversity. Conservation is understood not in terms of embalming particular space-time slices of indigenous knowledges through gene banks, ethnographies, or museum dioramas but rather in terms of providing the resources (e.g., time, funding, space, etc.) needed for the continuing selfdetermination and development of indigenous knowledge practices.40 As the UNESCOsponsored World Conference on Science in Budapest (1999) declares: Government and non-government organizations should sustain traditional knowledge systems through active support to the societies that are the keepers and developers of this knowledge, their ways of life, their languages, their social organizations and the environments in which they live…41 39 40 See also Shohat and Stam [5], Turnbull [49] and Schutte [77]. Nor is conservation understood in terms of top-down raiding and piracy by corporations looking for profits or disenchanted Westerners looking for spiritual renewal. See Alvares [80], Posey [43], Hughes [78], Shiva [79], Shohat and Stam [5], the Zapatistas [82], and Chambers and Gillespie [27]. 41 UNESCO [99] quoted in Chambers and Gillespie [27:234]. 27 Conserving involves empowering indigenous peoples to develop their own knowledge practices and epistemologies. It requires, in short, “a world in which many worlds fit,” as the EZLN (The Zapatistas [82]) is fond of putting it. PGE accordingly embraces a “polyculture” (Shiva [79: 122-124]) of diverse knowledge systems and epistemologies; a world in which many knowledges fit (to borrow from the EZLN). Conversely, it resists the creation of an epistemological “monoculture” that silences and eliminates alternative knowledge systems. According to Shiva [79:122], MWS is one such “monoculture of the mind” that “shrink[s] the human potential to innovate and create…”42 “Polycultures,” by contrast, “recover diversity in knowledge production, and provide a countervailing force to the globalized, centralized, homogenized systems of [knowledge] production that are destroying the livelihoods, cultures, and ecosystems everywhere” (Shiva [79:124]).43 Seventh, PGE accordingly embraces Foucault’s [100:81] call for an “insurrection of subjugated knowledges” along with Shiva’s goals of “democratizing knowledge” and democratically empowering of people’s lives.44 It embraces Alvares’ [18:229] call for an 42 Shiva [79:284] writes: Dominant scientific knowledge breeds a monoculture of the mind by making space for local alternatives to disappear, very much like monocultures of introduced plant varieties leading to the displacement and destruction of local diversity. Dominant knowledge also destroys the very conditions for alternatives to exist. 43 See also Alvares [18], The Zapatistas [82], and Harding [3, 24]. Turnbull [49:27] writes: All attempts at universalization involve the denial, erasure or suppression of some form of being or knowing. Whenever transcendental values, logic, or a common human nature or communicative capacity are invoked in the name of commensurability, some kind of violence is committed to differing ways of understanding the world that are subtended by incommensurable spatial practical and narratives of identity. 44 See also The Zapatistas [82]. Shiva [90:300] writes: Democratizing of knowledge becomes a central precondition for human liberation because the contemporary knowledge system excludes the humane by its very structure. Such a process of democratization would involve a redefining of knowledge such that the local and diverse become legitimate as knowledge, and they are viewed as indispensable knowledge because concreteness is the reality, and globalization and universalization are abstraction which have violated the concrete and hence the real. Such a shift from globalizing to the local knowledge is important to the project of human freedom because 28 end to the “tyranny of science” and the “scientific imperium.” This involves providing indigenous peoples the resources needed for evaluating the epistemologies and knowledge-claims of others as well as the resources needed for advancing their own epistemologies and knowledge-claims. Eight, PGE requires that participants approach other participants and their knowledges with attitudes of recognition, respect, learning, careful listening, and consideration, and a readiness to be transformed. Schutte [77:52] writes: … the other’s differences … [are] acknowledged as sites of appreciation, desire, recognition, caring and respect. [The other] is not abjected, derided, persecuted out of view, or legalized out of existence, but – departing from the premise that the other is also a human – neither is she subjected to the demand that she be the double, or reflected mirror image of ourselves. 45 Ninth, what is the format of PGE? One of the most intriguing suggestions in this regard is Turnbull’s [49:29-30] proposal for an “interstitial third space” that is: … spatial, narratological, and performative. It would have to handle incommensurability, materiality, movement, practices, and ideas. It would have to have space for encounters that enable emergence through tension… [It would be] a social space that includes a physical performance space … a trading zone in which differing traditions are narrated and performed together and in which actors can move, make connections, produce new spaces and trails. A theatre of diversity … in which narratives of commensurability and differing knowledge traditions are held in tension with one another. it frees knowledge from the dependence on established regimes of thought, making it simultaneously more autonomous and more authentic. Democratization based on such an “insurrection of subjugated knowledge” is both desirable and necessary component of the larger process of democratization. 45 See also Jaggar [4], Harding [3, 24], The Zapatistas [82], Hess [16], Shiva [20], Shohat and Stam [5], and UNESCO [101]. IK’s “demand respect,” write Chambers and Gillespie [27:235], “as powerful cultural expressions of ways of knowing nature – ways that have clear implications for how humans should live and prosper in particular environments”. 29 I understand Turnbull as suggesting we maximize diversity and inclusiveness by placing as few as possible restrictions upon inquiry. Embracing epistemological alterity requires that “the other be heard in her difference” (Schutte [77:55]). I thus suggest we place as few as possible restrictions upon the kinds of knowledges invited to participate. We should not, for example, restrict participation to those knowledge practices that: pursue “the proper” ends (e.g. maximizing truth or minimizing falsehood); define knowledge in terms of rationality or correspondence truth; conceive knowledge as theoretical; or advocate discursive argumentation or empirical methodologies. Shamanism, divination, religion, myth, and mysticism participate alongside Western-style sciences. I suggest we also place as few as possible restrictions upon the manner in which alternative knowledges present themselves. Poetry, song, dance, music, proverbs, narrative, pictures, plastic art, and ritual and ceremonial performance exist alongside discursive argument and scientific experiment.46 We should also place few, if any, restrictions upon the locations of these polylogues. They may occur atop pyramids or hills, or in rain forests, academic debating clubs, and science laboratories. Lastly, I see no reason to place restrictions upon metaphysical assumptions. Knowledge practices may presuppose natural or supernatural ontologies, intentional or mechanistic accounts of causality, linear or cyclical accounts of time, and materialism or spiritualism. They need share no common view regarding human nature, cognition, or well-being. PGE does not presume there is a single best way for all humans to live or know nature, or a single best way for any one group to realize its own conception of human well-being. 46 PGE differs from Jaggar [4] and Harding [24] who restrict participation on the basis of rationality and empirical orientation (respectively). For further argument, see Anzaldua [102] and Schutte [77]. 30 Knowledge practices and their epistemologies are evaluated as practical activities or “toolboxes” (Harding [3]) for “way-seekers.” Since they carry moral, political, social, economic, and environmental presuppositions and consequences, one asks of them, "How, by what means, may this or that be brought into the service of human emancipation and well-being?" and “What kind of life do they foster?” 47 As a wayseeking philosophy, PGE refuses to draw hard and fast distinctions between such traditional Western philosophical categories as epistemology, philosophy of science, moral, social, and political philosophy. What does the process polycentric global epistemology look like? I suggest PGE involves a creative process of aesthetic ordering.48 Participants function as artists who create new knowledge practices from the ingredients of existing ones. New knowledges emerge from the manner in which participants refashion, revise, re-imagine, combine, and juxtapose these ingredients. New knowledges are hybrids resulting from repeated “border crossings”.49 They are not logically derived from existing knowledges. This process makes no appeal to universal or transcendental ideals, facts, or principles. It is artistic rather than algorithmic, as it is closer to cooking, composing music, and painting than, say, mathematics. The resulting order is aesthetic rather than rational; contingent rather than necessary; local rather than universal, and hypothetical rather than categorical. It emerges from below rather being dictated or deduced from “on high.” By exposing participants to the alternative knowledges, epistemologies, ontologies, and value-orientations as well as to the critical scrutiny of other participants, PGE promotes greater self-awareness and self-criticism regarding the unstated limitations 47 48 See Harding [24], Roth [103] and Rorty [47] for a similar claims. This discussion is indebted to Hall and Ames [35, 55] and Turnbull [49]. 31 of participants’ philosophical horizons. It promotes Fanon’s [106:44] notion of mutual “reciprocal relativization,” i.e. the idea that alternative knowledges and epistemologies come to perceive the limitation of their own orientations. It presents participants with new ways of thinking about old problems or new methods for solving them. It reveals new problems with accepted solutions. It enables participants to combine the strengths and eliminate the weaknesses of different knowledge practices. It helps indigenous peoples deconstruct past and resist future epistemological (cultural) colonization. And it helps Western peoples deconstruct past and resist future epistemological (cultural) colonizing of indigenous peoples. Finally, PGE creates a trading zone that enables mutual sharing, borrowing, and learning as well as collaborative projects. A variety of collaborative projects and pluralisms are possible and indeed many currently exist. The Nisga of British Columbia, for example, successfully implemented a salmon protection program integrating indigenous technology and wisdom practices with Western statistical methods of data analysis to provide more reliable fish counts (Snively and Corsiglia [107]). Hess [16:194] writes, “Today most medical systems in the world are complex mixtures of Western and local or non-western medical systems.” Elkin [108] discusses the integration of Western and indigenous healing practices in Australia, while Schaefer [109], Huber and Sandstrom [110] and Knab [111] discuss the integration of Western and indigenous in healing and curing practices in Mexico. Recent exchanges between The Dalai Lama and 49 See Anzaldua [102], Harding [3] and Guillermo Gomez-Pena, [104, 105]. 32 Western psychologists suggest that Western discussions of mental health can benefit greatly from Tibetan Buddhism models of mental health (The Dalai Lama, et al.[112]).50 Finally, one collaborative project currently commands our attention above all others: constructing alternative knowledges that address global environmental destruction and warming. 5. Conclusion My aim in critiquing Taylor has not been to refute the argument of a lone philosopher but to help close a longlived chapter in Western philosophical apologetics as well as help create the conceptual resources needed for imagining a future in which many knowledges coexist. Polycentric global dialogue represents one such future. More practically, and more pressingly, I hope this essay helps slow the West’s juggernaut-like rush to exterminate indigenous knowledges, cultures, and peoples in the process of refashioning the world in its own image. Acknowledgements This paper has benefited from input by James Boyd, Delfina de la Cruz, Julie Greene, Sandra Harding, Josh Haddock, Kaplan Hasanoglu, Alberto Hernandez-Lemus, Alfredo Lopez Austin, Urbano Francisco Martinez, Scott Pratt, Paul Roth, Joanna Sanchez, Philip Turetzky, David Turnbull, and Sean Waters References [1] Charles Taylor, Rationality, in: Martin Hollis and Steven Lukes (Eds.), Rationality and Relativism, MIT Press 1982, Cambridge, pp. 87-105. 50 Thanks to Sean Waters for bringing this exchange my attention. See Hess [16] and Goonatilake [113] for additional examples, and Harding [24] for a useful taxonomy of different kinds of projects. 33 [2] Daniel R. Headrick, The Tools of Empire: Technology and European Imperialism in the Nineteenth Century, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1981. [3] Sandra Harding, Is Science Multicultural? Postcolonialisms, Feminisms, and Epistemologies, Indiana University Press, Bloomington, 1988. [4] Alison Jaggar, Globalizing Feminist Ethics, in: Uma Narayan and Sandra Harding (Eds.), Decentering the Center, Indiana University Press, Bloomington, 2000, pp. 1-25. [5] Ella Shohat and Robert Stam, Unthinking Eurocentricism: Multiculturalism and the Media, Routledge, London, 1994. [6] G. Gutierrez, Ciencia-cultural y Dependencia, Editorial Guadalupe, Buenos Aires, 1974. [7] Richard Levins and Richard Lewontin, The Dialectical Biologist, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1985. [8] J. M. Blaut, The Colonizer’s Model of the World: Geographical Diffusionism and Eurocentric History, Guilford Press, New York, 1993. [9] Enrique Dussel, The Invention of the Americas: Eclipse of the “other” and the Myth of Modernity, Michael D. Barber (Trans.), Continuum Books, New York, 1995. [10] Anne Salmond, Maori Epistemologies, in: Joanna Overing (Ed.), Reason and Morality, Tavistock Publications, London, 1985, pp. 240-263. [11] Larry Laudan, Science and Relativism, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1990. [12] Emevwo Biakolo, Categories of Cross-Cultural Cognition and the African Condition, in: The African Philosophy Reader, first ed., P.H. Coetzee and A.D.J. Roux (Eds.), Routledge, New York, 1998, pp. 1-14. [13] Enrique Dussel, Eurocentricism and Modernity, Boundary 2 20 (1993) 65-76. 34 [14] David Turnbull, Masons, Tricksters, and Cartographers, Routledge, New York, 2000. [15] Bruno Latour, Science in Action, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1987. [16] David Hess, Science and Technology in a Multicultural World, Columbia University Press, New York, 1995. [17] Claude Alvares, Science, Colonialism, and Violence: A Luddite View,” in: Ashis Nandy (Ed.) Science, Hegemony and Violence Oxford University Press, Delhi, 1990, pp. 68-112. [18] Claude Alvares, “Science,” in: Wolgang Sachs (Ed.), Development Dictionary: A Guide to Knowledge as Power, Zed Books, London, 1992, pp. 219-232. [19] Claude Alvares, Science, Development, and Violence: The Revolt against Modernity, Oxford University Press, Delhi, 1992. [20] Vandana Shiva, Staying Alive: Women, Ecology, and Development, Zed Books, London, 1989. [21] Vandana Shiva, The Violence of the Green Revolution, Zed Books, London, 1991. [22] Third World Network, Modern Science in Crisis: A Third World Response, Third World Network, Penang, Malaysia, 1988. [23] Arturo Escobar, Planning, in: Wolgang Sachs (Ed.), Development Dictionary: A Guide to Knowledge as Power, Zed Books, London, 1992, pp. 132-145. [24] Sandra Harding, Science and Social Inequality: Feminist and Postcolonial Issues, University of Illinois Press, Urbana, 2006. [25] Wolgang Sachs, Environment, in: Wolgang Sachs (Ed.), Development Dictionary: A Guide to Knowledge as Power, Zed Books, London, 1992, pp. 27-37. 35 [26] Tim Flannery, The Weather Makers: The History and Future Impact of Climate Change, Atlantic Monthly Press, New York, 2006. [27] David Wade Chambers and Richard Gillespie, Locality in the History of Science: Colonial Science, Technoscience, and Indigenous Knowledge, Osiris 15 (2001) 221-240. [28] Robert Klee, Introduction to the Philosophy of Science: Cutting Nature at its Seams, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1997. [29] Peter Godfrey-Smith, Theory and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 2003. [30] Richard Boyd, The Current Status of Scientific Realism, in: Jarrett Leplin (Ed.), Scientific Realism, University of California Press, Berkeley, 1984, pp. 41-82. [31] Jarrett Leplin (Ed.), Scientific Realism, University of California Press, Berkeley, 1984. [32] Aime Cesaire, Discourse on Colonialism, Joan Pinkham (Trans.), Monthly Review Press, New York, 2000. [33] Richard Wolin, The Seduction of Unreason, Princeton University Press, Princeton, 2004. [34] David Hall, Just How Provincial Is Western Philosophy? ‘Truth’ in Comparative Context, Social Epistemology 15 4 (2001) 285-298. [35] David Hall and Roger Ames, Thinking from the Han: Self, Truth, and Transcendence in Chinese and Western Culture, State University of New York Press, Albany, 1998. [36] Gregory Cajete, Native Science, Clear Light Publishers, Santa Fe, 2000. 36 [37] Barbara Deloria, Kristen Foehner, and Sam Scinta (Eds.), Spirit and Reason: A Vine Deloria Jr., Reader, Fulcrum Publishers, Golden, CO, 1999. [38] Vine Deloria, Jr., and Daniel R. Wildcat, Power and Place, American Indian Graduate Center and Fulcrum Resources, Golden, CO, 2001. [39] Scott L. Pratt, Native Pragmatism: Rethinking the Roots of American Philosophy, Indiana University Press, Bloomington, 2002. [40] James Maffie, To Walk in Balance: An encounter between Contemporary Western Science and Conquest-era Nahua Philosophy, in: Robert Figueroa and Sandra Harding (Eds.), Science and other Cultures Routledge, New York, 2003, pp. 70-91. [41] James Maffie Aztec Philosophy, The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2005 http://www.iep.utm.edu/a/aztec.htm. [42] Paget Henry, Caliban’s Reason: Introducing Afro-Caribbean Philosophy, Routledge, New York, 2000. [43] Darrell A. Posey, Upsetting The Sacred Balance: Can The Study Of Indigenous Knowledge Reflect Cosmic Connectedness? Paper Prepared For Association of Social Anthropologists of The Commonwealth Conference April 2, 2000, http://www.asa2000.anthropology.ac.uk/posey/posey.html [44] William James, Pragmatism, The World Publishing Company, New York, 1955. [45] John Dewey, Experience and Nature, second ed., Dover Publications, New York, 1929. [46] Nancy Cartwright, The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999. 37 [47] Richard Rorty, The Consequences of Pragmatism, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1982. [48] John Dupre, The Disorder of Things, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1993. [49] David Turnbull, Multiplicity, Criticism, and Knowing what to do Next: way-finding in a Transmodern world. Response to Meera Nanda’s Prophets Facing Backwards, Social Epistemology 19 1 (2006) 19-32. [50] Peter Galison and David Stump (Eds.), The Disunity of Science: Boundaries, Contexts, and Power, Stanford University Press, Stanford, 1996. [51] Helen Verran, On Seeing the Generative Possibilities of Dalit neo-Buddhist Thought, Social Epistemology 19 1 (2006) 33-48. [52] James Maffie, Why Care about Nezahualcoyotl? Veritism and Nahua Philosophy, Philosophy of the Social Sciences 32 1 (2002) 71-90. [53] James Maffie (Ed.), Truth from the Perspective of Comparative World Philosophy, a special issue of Social Epistemology 15 4 (2001). [54] James Maffie, “Ethnoepistemology,” The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2005, http://www.iep.utm.edu/e/ethno-ep.htm. [55] David Hall and Roger Ames, Thinking Through Confucius, State University Press of New York, Albany, 1987. [56] Chad Hansen, A Daoist Theory of Chinese Thought, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1992. [57] Lee Hester and Jim Cheney, Truth and Native American Epistemology, Social Epistemology 15 4 (2001) 319-334. 38 [58] Willard Gingerich, Heidegger and the Aztecs: The Poetics of Knowing in PreHispanic Nahuatl Poetry, in: B. Swann and A. Krupat (Eds.), Recovering the Word: Essays on Native American Literature, University of California Press, Berkeley, 1987, pp. 85-112. [59] Miguel Leon-Portilla, Aztec Thought and Culture, Jack Emory Davis (Trans.), University of Oklahoma Press, Norman, 1963. [60] Gordon Brotherston, Native Numeracy in Tropical America, Social Epistemology 15 4 (2001) 299-318. [61] Henri Frankfurt and H.A. Frankfurt, Introduction, in: Henri Frankurt, et al. The Intellectual Adventure of Ancient Man, University of Chicago Press, 1964, pp. 3-30. [62] David Lindberg, The Beginnings of Western Science, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1992. [63] Barry Hallen, The Good, The Bad, and the Beautiful: Discourse about Values in Yoruba Culture, Indiana University Press, Bloomington, 2000. [64] John Middleton (Ed.), Magic, Witchcraft, and Cunning, University of Texas Press, Austin, 1967. [65] Bernard R. Ortiz de Montellano, Aztec Medicine, Health, and Nutrition, Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick, 1990. [66] Alan Ereira, The Elder Brothers: A Lost South American People and their Wisdom, Vintage Books, New York, 1990. [67] Miguel Lopez Austin, Tamoanchan, Tlalocan: Places of Mist, Bernardino R. Ortiz de Montellano and Thelma Ortiz de Montellano (Trans.), University Press of Colorado, Niwot, 1997. 39 [68] Roy Willis, The Indigenous Critique of Colonialism: A Case Study, in: Talal Asad (Ed.), Anthropology and the Colonial Encounter, Humanities Press, New York, 1973, pp. 245-256. [69] W. J. Ermine, Aboriginal Epistemology, in: M. Battiste and J. Barman (Eds.), First Nations Education in Canada: The Circle Unfolds, University of British Columbia Press, Vancouver, BC, 1995, pp. 101-112. [70] Glen S. Aikenhead, Toward a First Nations Cross-Cultural Science and Technology Curriculum, Science Education 81 (1997) 217-238. [71] Jerome Rothenberg, “We Explain Nothing, We Believe Nothing”: American Indian Poetry and the Problematics of Translation, in: Brian Swann (Ed.), On the Translation of Native American Literatures, Smithsonian Press, Washington, DC, 1992, pp. 64-79. [72] Godfrey Lienhardt, Self: Public, Private. Some African Representations, in: Michael Carruthers, Steven Collins, and Steven Lukes (Eds.), The Category of the Person, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1985, pp. 141-155. [73] Gary A. Plank, What Silence Means for Educators of American Indian Children, Journal of American Indian Education 34 1 (1994) 1-11. [74] Mircea Eliade, No Souvenirs: Journal 1957-1969, F.H. Johnson, Jr., (Trans.) New York, 1977. [75] Walter Mignolo, Local Histories /Global Designs, in: Pedro Lange-Churion and Eduardo Mendieta (Eds.), Latin America and Postmodernity, Humanities Press, Amherst, NY, 2001, pp. 177-212. [76] Linda Tuhiwai Smith, Decolonizing Methodologies: Research and Indigenous Practices, Zed Books, London, 1999. 40 [77] Ofelia Schutte, Cultural Alterity: Cross Cultural Communication and Feminist Theory in North-South Contexts, in: Uma Narayan and Sandra Harding (Eds.), Decentering the Center, Indiana University Press, Bloomington, 2000, pp. 47-65. [78] Lotte Hughes, The No-Nonsense Guide to Indigenous Peoples, Verso Books, London, 2003. [79] Vandana Shiva, Biopiracy: The Plunder of Nature and Knowledge, South End Press, Boston, 1997. [80] Claude Alvares, New Parading for Thinking We Have been Here Before, in: Ziauddin Sardar (Ed.), The Revenge of Athena: Science, Exploitation, and the Third World, Mansell Publications, New York, 1988, pp. 219-225. [81] Alex Greene, The Voice of Ix Chel: Fashining Maya Tradition in the Belizean Rain Forest, in: Candace Slater (Ed.), In Search of the Rain Forest, Duke University Press, Durham, 2003, pp. 101-132. [82] The Zapatistas, Zapatista Encuentro: Documents from the First Intercontinental Encounter for Humanity and Against Neoliberalism, Greg Ruggiero (Ed.), Seven Stories Press, New York, 2002. [83] Indigenous Knowledge and Development Monitor http://www.nuffic.nl/ciran/ikdm/ [84] Uma Narayan, “The Project of Feminist Epistemology: Perspectives from a Nonwestern Feminist,” in: Alison Jaggar and Susan Bordo (Eds.), Gender/ Body/ Knowledge: Feminist Reconstructions of Being and Knowing, Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick, 1989, pp. 256-272. 41 [85] Nestor Garcia Canclini, Hybrid Cultures: Strategies for Entering and Leaving Modernity, Christopher L. Chiappari and Silvia L. López (Trans.), University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1995. [86] Samir Amin, Delinking: Towards a Polycentric World, Zed, London, 1985. [87] Center for world Indigenous Studies, http://www.cwis.org/index.htm [88] Forum for Intercultural Philosophy, http://prof.polylog.org/index-en.htm. [89] Arturo Escobar, Planning, in: Wolgang Sachs (Ed.), Development Dictionary: A Guide to Knowledge as Power, Zed Books, London, 1992, pp. 133-145. [90] Vandana Shiva, Monocultures of the Mind, in: Jane Henry (Ed.), Creative Management, second edition, Sage, London, 2001, pp. 283-301. [91] Dipesh Chakrabarty, Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference, Princeton University Press, Princeton, 2000. [92] Bina Gupta and J. N. Mohanty, General Introduction, in: Bina Gupta and J. N. Mohanty (Eds.), Philosophical Questions East and West, Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham, MD, 2000, pp. xi-xxiv. [93] Robert Bernasconi, African Philosophy's Challenge to Continental Philosophy, in: Emmanuel Chukwadi Eze (Ed.), Postcolonial African Philosophy: A Critical Reader, Blackwell, Oxford, 1997, pp. 183-193. [94] Barry Hallen, Philosophy Doesn’t Translate: Richard Rorty and Multiculturalism, SAPINA 8 3 (1995), 1-42. [95] Karl Marx, Critique of the Gotha Program, in: Robert C. Tucker (Ed.), The MarxEngels Reader, second edition, W.W. Norton, New York, 1972, pp. 525-541. 42 [96] Herbert Marcuse, RepressiveTolerance, in: Robert Paul Wolff, Barrington Moore, Jr., and Herbert Marcuse, A Critique of Repressive Tolerance, Beacon Press, Boston, 1965, pp. 81-117. [97] Sandra Harding, Whose Science? Whose Knowledge? Thinking from Women’s Lives, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, 1991. [98] Patricia Hill Collins, Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and the Politics of Empowerment, Routledge, New York, 1990. [99] UNESCO, The Declaration on Science and the Use of Scientific Knowledge: Report of the World Conference on Science, UNESCO Publishing, 1999 [100] Michel Foucault, Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings 19721977, Pantheon Books, New York, 1980. [101] UNESCO, Domination or Sharing? Report on Indigenous Development and the Transfer of Knowledge, UNESCO Publishing, 1981. [102] Gloria Anzaldua, Borderlands/La Frontera: The New Mestiza, Aunt Lute Books, San Francisco, 1987. [103] Paul Roth, Politics and Epistemology: Rorty, MacIntyre, and the Ends of Philosophy, History of the Human Sciences 2 2 (1989) 171-191. [104] Guillermo Gomez-Pena, Dangerous Border Crossers, Routledge, New York, 2000. [105] Guillermo Gomez-Pena, The New World Border, City Lights, San Francisco, 1996. [106] Franz Fanon, Toward the African Revolution, Grove Press, New York, 1969. [107] Gloria Snively and John Corsiglia, Discovering Indigenous Science: Implications for Science Education, Science Education 85 (2001) 6-34. [108] A. P. Elkin, Aboriginal Men of High Distinction, St. Martin’s, New York, 1977. 43 [109] Stacy B. Schaefer, To Think with a Good Heart: Wixarika Women, Weavers, and Shamans, University of Utah Press, Salt Lake City, 2002. [110] Brad R. Hubner and Alan R. Sandstron [Eds.], Mesoamerican healers, University of Texas Press, Austin, 2001. [111] Timothy J. Knab, The Dialogue of Earth and Sky: Dreams, Curing and the Modern Aztec Underworld, University of Arizona Press, 2004. [112] The Dalai Lama, Herbert Benson, et al., “Tibetan and Western Models of Mental Health,” in: Daniel Goleman and Robert Thurman (Eds.), Mind Science: An East-West Dialogue, Wisdom Publications, Boston, 1991, pp. 91-102. [113] Susantha Goonatilake, Toward a Global Science: Mining Civilizational Knowledge Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN, 1998.