Nietzsche-Seminar Reflective Report, 17.04.2009 Florian Häubi 0844675 „Nietzsche’s Genealogical Psychology: The Problem of Self-Deception“ Robert B. Pippin Introduction Robert Pippins paper entitled “Nietzsche’s Genealogical Psychology: The Problem of SelfDeception”, is an attempt to understand Nietzsche’s notion of psychology and what it means when Nietzsche thought of psychology as first philosophy. Since this inquiry has multiple dimensions, Pippin focuses on the question of how Nietzsche understood psychology and what he meant by psychological explanations. A decisive element in order to answer these questions is the phenomenon of “self-deception”. This phenomenon which is Nietzsche’s main concern in his mature period is fundamental to understand what Nietzsche means by human mindedness. According to Pippin, Nietzsche did not deal with the paradox of self-deception within a dualistic framework, that is, on the one hand, a psychological area, and on the other hand, a drive theory. Rather, Nietzsche had a more extended conception of the psychological domain, so that unconscious motives, desires or ends are to be found within the psychological, and not in an extra-psychological area of drives or instincts. A further main point of Pippin’s paper is Nietzsche’s account of self-knowledge. It is only with a correct understanding of selfknowledge that the paradox of self-deception can be explained as a plausible characteristic of one’s psychology and be applied for a theory of agency. The first chapter of this paper will give a short summary of Pippin’s paper. The second chapter will present the most important points made during the discussion and in the third chapter I will formulate two critical remarks on the topic of the self and self-knowledge. The fourth chapter will give a conclusion. I. Summary After a short introduction, Pippin turns to give some passages from Die fröhliche Wissenschaft in order to show Nietzsche’s conception of human psychology. Pippin claims that when Nietzsche contrasts “consciousness” with “instincts”, he thinks of human psychology as double natured. Furthermore, he suggests that it is this psychological picture which lies behind many of Nietzsche’s famous claims, e.g. that all philosophy is an 1 Nietzsche-Seminar Reflective Report, 17.04.2009 Florian Häubi 0844675 expression of one’s own psychology or that the Christian religion was not motivated by consciously held reasons (e.g. revelation), but by ressentiment and hatred of their masters. It is because of such passages that Nietzsche is seen by many interpreters as a psychological reductionist. According to this interpretation, Nietzsche thinks that human conduct can be best explained by reference to basic drives and not by taking up consciously held reasons or motives. At the end, all human behavior is reducible to one master-drive - “der Wille zur Macht” – which is omnipresent but unconscious. In the beginning of the third part, Pippin gives some reasons why he thinks that this interpretation is not fully adequate. Nietzsche is not merely putting in contrast “instinct” and “conscious mind”. Nietzsche’s point is more sophisticated. Drives and instincts are not just unnoticed or beyond conscious control, but hidden, and this concealment of the drives and instincts is accomplished by us. According to Nietzsche, “real motives […] are often exactly the opposite of what is avowed, even sincerely avowed, and most problematically, the real motives are hidden because the agent hides them.”1 Pippin claims that what is at stake for Nietzsche here is a “general principle”. This “general principle” is expressed in FW §8, where Nietzsche writes that the unknown qualities of a person “sich wie hinter das Nichts zu verstecken wissen”. Pippin suggests that Nietzsche was highly interested in the psychological phenomenon - the “general principle” - of “self-deception”. The point is that Nietzsche was not satisfied with the traditional accounts since they tried to explain the phenomenon “as either the determination of conscious thought and choice by non-conscious corporeal drives” or “as the working of unconscious desires and impulses […]”.2 Therefore, he dismisses the traditional dualistic approach to capture the phenomenon of self-deceit. What is needed is a threefold approach to this phenomenon, which can be formulated in three correlating theses: 1. Self-deception is an attempt to escape from another and truer self-understanding. 2. The other and truer self-understanding is hidden. 3. What is hidden is hidden by us. Here, Pippin makes clear that these questions not only matter for the phenomenon at issue, but also for an understanding of “the role of such self-ascriptions in the economy of agency.”3 Therefore, the following pages of his paper deal with the consequences of Nietzsche’s account of self-deception for a theory of agency. 1 Pippin, p. 6. Pippin, p. 7. 3 Pippin, p. 10. 2 2 Nietzsche-Seminar Reflective Report, 17.04.2009 Florian Häubi 0844675 In part IV, Pippin takes up an objection against the conventional view ascribed to Nietzsche. According to this traditional view, Nietzsche proposes that human conduct is causally determined by somatic forces, which are “outside the psychological”. But given this picture of causal determination by drives of which one is unaware, Pippin describes the following problem: “[…] if, in effect, I am rebelling and do not know that I am rebelling, it is hard to see how I could experience any psychological satisfaction from rebelling.” 4 Instead, for Pippin the following view is more adequate for Nietzsche: “Drives have intentional content […] and that means that if they are to explain behavior they cannot determine the psychological from ‘outside the psychological’, as extra-psychological phenomena.”5 Nietzsche is not proposing an extra-psychological drive theory, but offers a more complex theory of psychological explanations. Although he goes beyond what the agent would consciously avow, he still remains “inside” the psychological explicable. At this point, Pippin turns to explicate Freud’s notion of the unconscious, which he considers to be in line with Nietzsche’s account. However, as it is the case for Nietzsche, there are two possible interpretations of Freud. The first account considers the Freudian notion of the unconsciousness to be a “dramatic extension of the domain of the psychological.”6 That is, acts – although ‘guided’ by unconscious reasons or motives – remain psychologically explicable, since the psychological domain includes also unconscious motives, ends and desires. The second account thinks of the unconscious as a kind of “second mind”. The drives are seen as brute, non-intentional forces affecting the conscious mind. They do not attempt anything and are not motivated. Actions are then explained in terms of “being seized by a material force”, “something has taken hold on me” or “something is happening to me”. The “second mind” influences and directs the agent from “outside” the psychological. Pippin claims that Nietzsche is much closer to the former conception of the Freudian unconsciousness than to the latter. In part V, Pippin considers a possible objection against the concept of self-deception which was brought forward by Rüdiger Bittner. Bittner suggests that we would do best to give up the notion of self-deception, since it is not possible to explain how it can happen that someone produces a false story, knowing that it is a false story. However, Pippin argues that Bittner seems to operate with a somewhat facile concept of self-knowledge. For Bittner, there seems 4 Pippin, p. 5-6. Pippin, p. 6. 6 Pippin, p. 13. 5 3 Nietzsche-Seminar Reflective Report, 17.04.2009 Florian Häubi 0844675 to be a clear disjunction between knowing one’s own mind and not knowing it. Therefore, in part V, Pippin works out Nietzsche’s conception of self-knowledge. The central issue of Nietzsche’s conception of self-knowledge - which can be found e.g. in FW §13 - “concerns the complexities of interpretation, interpreting the motives one ascribes to oneself and to others, and the meaning of the deed itself.”7 Pippin claims that Nietzsche renounces selfknowledge as introspectable or observational. Since self-knowledge for Nietzsche is the result of interpretation, any claims about oneself become provisional and contestable. As a consequence, the problem of self-deceit becomes more tractable. By taking up the Prologue and the paragraphs 127 and 151 from FW, Pippin claims that, although instincts and drives appear in Nietzsche often as brute natural forces, it is remarkable “how far he goes in denying the immediacy of even any such supposedly immediate inner experience.”8 In part VI, Pippin takes up the notion of self-deception and its consequences for a theory of agency. The paradox of self-deception reveals a picture which Nietzsche rejects. According to this picture, one has, on the one hand, real and determinate motives and intentions which causally influence bodily actions. On the other hand, there are fictional motives and intentions which are made up by a subject who believes that these motives are the causally effecting ones. According to Pippin, Nietzsche proposes another account, which can be summarized as follows: “In telegraphic form: self-knowledge is not observational, but interpretative […]; action explanation is not causal and motives cannot be understood as fixed, datable mental items, but self-ascribing a motive is more like provisionally trying out an interpretation.”9 Given this conception of self-knowledge, self-deception does no more appear to be so paradoxical, since it is not perceived as an active looking away from some real, determinate, causally effective motives, but as replacing an unpleasant interpretation of one’s actions with a more pleasant, plausible interpretation. At the end of his paper Pippin points out two elements in order to mark the difference between, on the one hand, some self-serving interpretation, and on the other hand, practical self-knowledge. First, the inaccuracy of self-ascriptions can be confirmed by what occurs in the future, that is, what the agent does or does not do. In this way, the truth conditions for selfinterpretation are projected into the future. The second criterion for self-knowledge, which is mentioned by Pippin, is the concept of “consistency”, that is, “[…] in practical knowledge 7 Pippin, p. 18. Pippin, p. 19. 9 Pippin, p. 21. 8 4 Nietzsche-Seminar Reflective Report, 17.04.2009 Florian Häubi 0844675 what bears out and so confirms some self-interpretation turns on such issues as consistency with what one actually does and how else interprets one’s own and other’s motives.” 2. Discussion 2.1. Relationship between psychology and genealogy, physiology, sociology One point made during the discussion dealt with the question of how we are to think of the relationship between psychology and other approaches/sciences such as genealogy, physiology or sociology. Concerning the relationship between psychology and genealogy, Pippin made clear that he understands Nietzsche’s genealogical work as historical psychology. For Nietzsche, psychology is not a science in the sense that it describes objectively a certain kind of behavior from the third person point of view, but it is based on the first person point of view and is rather interpretative than observational. Accordingly, these elements are decisive for Nietzsche’s genealogical method. Moreover, psychology, as well as genealogy, do not only try to understand the hidden and ‘real’ motives within a certain set of actions, but try to understand the reasons why these motives have been hidden. Pippin did not answer explicitly the question regarding the relation of psychology to physiology and sociology. However, regarding physiology, Pippin’s paper gives some hints. It seems that Pippin – although he stresses the primacy of psychological explanations in Nietzsche – does not deny completely a drive theory in Nietzsche or a kind of naturalistic account. That is, physiology can still be applied in this area. But what Pippin seems to claim is that “despite the fact that we are so used to the notion that Nietzsche has some sort of ‘drive’ theory or that he is offering a ‘naturalistic’ account of human conduct […], we can at least see how far he is from such a model of psychic dynamics.”10 And in another passage he writes: “It is of course true that Nietzsche often appeals to ‘instincts’ or ‘drives’ as if he were appealing to brute natural forces. But it is also extraordinary how far he goes in denying the immediacy of even any such supposedly immediate inner experience.”11 Regarding sociology, the critical remark can be formulated as follows. Since Pippin is thinking of self-deception in terms of “self-serving” and “self-aggrandizing” interpretations, the underlying element of this happening is the will to power. However, Nietzsche thinks of power always as a relationship between different parts of a system. That is, if one is to 10 11 Pippin, p. 17. Pippin, p. 19. 5 Nietzsche-Seminar Reflective Report, 17.04.2009 Florian Häubi 0844675 describe and to explain the phenomenon of self-deception psychologically, a sociological account cannot be dismissed, precisely because of the understanding of power as a relation. The point is that within the concept of self-conception the other is always involved as the other part of the power-relation and cannot be left aside. 2.2. The problem of forgetting Which role does Nietzsche’s notion of “Vergessen” as a vis activa play within the concept of self-deception? It seems that this notion can perfectly be described in terms of the dualistic conception of the psychological, which Pippin claims to be something that Nietzsche is sceptical about. According to the dualistic picture, “Vergessen” is described as an active but unconscious force regulating the consciously held believes. However, Pippin pointed out that Nietzsche’s notion of forgetting would come down to the same problematic like selfdeception. If one describes “Vergessen” as kind of force “outside” the psychological, it is hard to see how “Vergessen” could ever be described by Nietzsche as something with a specific purpose. The point is that “Vergessen” cannot belong to the domain of brute and irrational drives, since “Vergessen”, as Nietzsche understands it, is intentional. Nietzsche does not claim that forgetting is arbitrary and completely accidental, but rather directed and with a specific purpose. “Vergessen” has to be an intentional drive, that is, within the psychological, since otherwise it could not be explained how one can get psychological satisfaction from it and gain a “Form der starken Gesundheit”. 2.3. Nietzsche’s conception of the self and the subject The main critique on Pippin’s paper was that he does not work out Nietzsche’s conception of the self. Indeed, it is hard to see how we can talk of self-deception, self-knowledge and selfinterpretation without explaining how we understand the self to which these concepts are referring. However, during the discussion Pippin made some general remarks about how he would describe Nietzsche’s conception of the self. Therefore, I will first summarize his view on this issue and then work out some critical remarks. Pippin formulated the following guiding lines for an understanding of Nietzsche’s conception of the self. 6 Nietzsche-Seminar Reflective Report, 17.04.2009 Florian Häubi 0844675 1) Nietzsche does not try to explain human conduct mechanically. That is, Nietzsche does not think that man is the product of bio-physiological forces. The subject is not for Nietzsche a mere epiphenomenon. 2) Nietzsche is not at all willing to give up concepts like agent or subject. Rather, he tries to reformulate them. His critique mainly turns against these concepts insofar as they are constituted by Christian morality. 3) The self, for Nietzsche, is not an object. Therefore, there is no way of having access to oneself through introspection. 4) A more positive account of Nietzsche’s conception of the self would have to take into consideration what it means to project oneself into the future. The self is something like a picture that one has of oneself. In other words, it is a commitment to what one wants to become, rather than something that is given beforehand. 5) Self-ascriptions are a constitutive element for the conception of the self. Selfascriptions have to be seen as dynamic, not punctual and a kind of self-engagement. That is, I am what I ascribed to myself before. Although these points were rather sketched than fully worked out, one can see in which direction Pippin intends to go. In the discussion several suggestions and objections to Pippin’s remarks were made. First, it seems that Pippin does not justice to the many passages in Nietzsche where he perceives the self as a plurality and not as a stable unity. However, Pippin made clear that he is not convinced that Nietzsche in these passages is really suggesting a conception of the self, according to which one would be an ever new subject, without unity or continuity. Instead, Pippin suggested that one has to think the plurality of the self in line with the plurality of possible self-interpretations. Second, Pippin has to explain why one should follow the picture of oneself that one projected into the future. Pippin did not work out this point in detail, but he suggested that a possible account for this question would have to take up Nietzsche’s notion of “Redlichkeit”. Third, it is still not clear what is actually making the self-ascriptions or the selfinterpretations, which are taken to play a decisive role for an understanding of the self. It seems that in order to answer this question, one would have to take into account Nietzsche’s notion of the “Leib”. 7 Nietzsche-Seminar Reflective Report, 17.04.2009 Florian Häubi 0844675 3. Critical points I would like to bring forward two critical remarks on Pippin’s understanding of Nietzsche’s conception of self and self-knowledge. The first point deals with the question of whether it is possible to integrate Nietzsche’s notion of a “Granit von geistigem Fatum”12 in Pippin’s conception of the self as a dynamic process of projecting oneself into the future, or not. The second point deals with self-knowledge. According to Pippin, Nietzsche does not think that one can gain self-knowledge through introspection or observation. However, I would like to show that Nietzsche does in some way think of self-knowledge in terms of an observational model. 3.1. Nietzsche’s notion of the “Granit von geistigem Fatum” Pippin points out that Nietzsche did not perceive the self as something given, as an object or as an “ego”. Although this seems to be correct insofar as Nietzsche clearly criticizes and abandons such traditional conceptions of the self, in his works he does talk about something stable deep down in us, e.g. “einen Granit von geistigem Fatum”. I think that one has to take this notion seriously and has to answer the question of which role this predestined and unchangeable element plays within Nietzsche’s conception of the self and self-knowledge. It seems to me that this poses some questions for Pippin’s account. First, how can we solve the tension between, on the one hand, an understanding of the self as the result of commitments to one’s own dynamic self-ascriptions, and, on the other hand, the self as determined through something deep down in us? Second, does the notion of a predestined and unchangeable element give any criteria for selfknowledge, additional to e.g. consistency, which is mentioned by Pippin? Third, in the way that Pippin presents self-interpretation or self-ascriptions, it seems that one is free to choose one possible interpretation/ascription or another one. However, since Nietzsche makes clear that there is “etwas Unbelehrbares […] von vorherbestimmter 12 KSA 5, 170. 8 Nietzsche-Seminar Reflective Report, 17.04.2009 Florian Häubi 0844675 Entscheidung und Antwort” and an „unwandelbares ‚das bin ich‘“13, it seems that this kind of freedom is fundamentally restricted. 3.2. Self-knowledge in terms of an observational model In his paper Pippin writes that Nietzsche rejects any introspectable or observational conception of self-knowledge.14 However, I do not think that one can take both together. Although Nietzsche does not think that one can gain self-knowledge through introspection, he does think of self-knowledge in terms of an observational model. I would like to bring forward this claim in three steps. 1) One has to keep in mind that Nietzsche his highly sceptical about the possibility of having self-knowledge. Pippin also makes this point when he writes that any report of selfknowledge is “necessarily provisional and contestable.”15 Pippin comes to this conclusion by pointing out that, for Nietzsche, introspection and observation are insufficient methods in order to gain self-knowledge: “Like many earlier (Hegel) and later (Sartre, Wittgenstein, Heidegger) anti-Cartesians, Nietzsche does not think that self-knowledge is ever directly observational or introspectable, and this makes any claim for such knowledge necessarily provisional and contestable.”16 Here, I would like to make two points. First, Pippin is right when he stresses the fact that self-knowledge is never directly observational and this is not what I want to claim by saying that Nietzsche has an account of self-knowledge as observation. Second - and this is important - it is not so much because of Nietzsche’s critique on self-observation or introspection that self-knowledge becomes provisional and contestable. Rather, it is because of the constitution of the self that self-knowledge can never be fully achieved. The point is that because of the very constitution of the self as a “dunkle und verhüllte Sache”, self-knowledge is provisional and contestable and there is no way of having direct access to oneself. However, this is not to say that self-knowledge can only be a result of selfinterpretation. 2) By reading together the following two passages, I would like to show that Nietzsche thought of observation as a method to gain some sort of self-knowledge. In the third Untimely 13 KSA 5, 170. Pippin, p. 18; 20; 21. 15 Pippin, p. 18. 16 Pippin, p. 18. 14 9 Nietzsche-Seminar Reflective Report, 17.04.2009 Florian Häubi 0844675 Meditation Schopenhauer als Erzieher, Nietzsche criticizes introspection as a “quälerisches gefährliches Beginnen” and then goes on: “Und überdies: wozu wäre es nöthig, wenn doch alles Zeugnis von unserm Wesen ablegt, unsre Freund- und Feindschaften, unser Blick und Händedruck, unser Gedächtniss und das, was wir vergessen, unsre Bücher und die Züge unsrer Feder.”17 And in Die Fröhliche Wissenschaft 335 – a paragraph also quoted by Pippin – Nietzsche writes: “Wie viele Menschen verstehen denn zu beobachten! Und unter den wenigen, die es verstehen, - wie viele beobachten sich selber! ‚Jeder ist sich selber der Fernste‘ – das wissen alle Nierenprüfer, zu ihrem Unbehagen; und der Spruch ‚erkenne dich selbst!‘ ist, im Munde eines Gottes und zu Menschen geredet, beinahe eine Bosheit. Dass es aber so verzweifelt mit der Selbstbeobachtung steht, […]“18 This last quotation shows again Nietzsche’s scepticism about the possibility of having access to the self. Nevertheless, the quote from SE suggests that there is at least an ‘indirect’ access. The self can be found in all our expressions, since “alles Zeugniss von unserm Wesen ablegt.”19 Moreover, what the quotation from FW suggests is that, in order to find the self, one has to look at what is expressed. The point is: there is no direct access to the self. But, since everything is an expression of our self, one can have indirect access by observing and looking at these expressions. This is what I think Nietzsche means with “Selbstbeobachtung”. 3) However, one could object that what is presented here as self-observation is at the end nothing else than the kind of self-interpretation described by Pippin. I would tend to agree with this point, but I would not see it as an objection. I do not claim that one can gain secure knowledge about oneself through observation. Self-knowledge remains provisional and contestable. Moreover, I think that Pippin’s conception of self-knowledge as the result of selfinterpretation is not necessarily in contradiction with what I have just presented. Rather, the critique was directed against two other claims. First, Pippin does not distinguish between introspection and observation. I hope to have shown that Nietzsche does distinguish between these two. Second, Pippin claims that, since direct observation or introspection is not possible, self-knowledge is the result of interpretation. However, I do not think this is necessarily the case. Provisional and contestable self-knowledge can also be the result of self-observation, as I have described it, and needn’t be– at least in a first instance – a form of self-interpretation. 17 KSA 1, 340. KSA 3, 560. 19 KSA 1, 340. 18 10 Nietzsche-Seminar Reflective Report, 17.04.2009 Florian Häubi 0844675 4. Conclusions Robert Pippin’s paper is an attempt to work out what Nietzsche meant with psychological explanations. By focusing on the phenomenon of self-deception he presents Nietzsche’s picture of the psychological and tries to re-evaluate Nietzsche’s drive theory. As a consequence, the domain of the psychological is extended and Nietzsche’s understanding of psychological explanations becomes more complex. Pippin aims at reading Nietzsche in a more subtle manner and not as a radical who wants to get rid of concepts such as subject or agent. In particular, Pippin seems to be interested in keeping a theory of agency that includes a kind of responsibility. However, one might question if Nietzsche was not more radical in some points than Pippin presents it. In fact, there are explicit and radical passages in Nietzsche which seem to be hardly compatible with Pippin’s theory. At this point then, Pippin argues with the following polemical question: either we take what Nietzsche writes in this passage in its radical way and then we have to take its deflationary consequences, or we present a more sophisticated, alternative picture and try to integrate this passage through a less radical reading. Although I tend to agree with Pippin’s general approach, I am not sure whether this argument is legitimate and if it can convince interpreters who are willing to read Nietzsche in the most radical way. 11