Lecture 6 Reconstructing Emery’s Open System Theory David M. Boje Oct 8 2006 I intend to deconstruct and reconstruct Fred and Merrelyn Emery’s open system theory (OST) principles. Emery’s OST comes out of Emery and Trist (1960, 1965) classic work on four types of system (1)/environment (2) linkages known as extended ‘causal field’: L11 (internal system), L22 (organization-to-organization environment), L12 (planning by organization to exploit environment), and L21 (organization learning from environment). The contribution of the model is to note that the causal field has changed from random and opportunistic links to the turbulent field. The naivety of the theory is in assuming every L22 is now a turbulent field, that the organization is linked to one environment rather than to multiple quite differentiated ones, that abstract grand universalistic principles explain the phenomenon, and that a ‘search conference’ (workshop) can convey the principles and carry about a transformation of maladaptive relations into adaptive ones. The OST model is rooted in the 1950s socio-technical system (STS) tradition of Trist and Bamforth’s coal mine study. It aims as M. Emery (1997, 2000) summarized, to go beyond the OST and General System Theory (GST) of von Bertalanffy. And this is why you wrote your second assignment as a deconstruction of von Bertalanffy for leaving out the social. It is the social that STS adds as amendment to GST. Emerys STS theory is rooted in several key concepts: contextualism, directive correlation, purposive systems, abduction, and harmony values to tame turbulence (M. Emery, 1997, 2000). CONTEXTUALISM Contextualism is a theory pioneered by Stephen Pepper called four world hypotheses. Each one is rooted in a root metaphor: formalism (in framework), mechanistic (in machine), organicism (in tree), and contextualism (in stranding or branching Historic Event in the present). It is awesome to include the ‘historical event in the present’ yet it is still not the kind of interactive complexity model that Boulding (1956) envisioned. It is a 2 by 2. For Boulding these are ‘sign’ (metaphoric relations), not the kind of languaged communicative, social or as Bakhtin (1973, 1981, 1990, 1993) puts it more dialogic relation of people with brains, soul, spirit, or other transcendental consciousness. The exception is the in contextualism there is some sense of retrospective, historical sensemaking. Emerys see the relation between contextualism, its stranded branching, feeling your way, muddling through (in Lindblom’s terms) to be directly analogous to the directive correlation of Sommerhoff (1969). Emerys are to be complimented for using ‘historical event in the present.’ Yet there is more that they could do with this. Emerys spend time in the Search Conference (SC) workshop on having participants discuss the history of their organization and its involvement in the history of the extended social field (i.e. L22). But, they do not see how multiple histories, or stories of environment, intertwine in the moment, in the very way that Pepper’s contextualism points to, the here-and-nowness of unfolding storytelling relationship to unfolding systemicity (Boje, 2006a). In short, there is something in contextualism that could be developed and resituated to be a more complete rendition of the kind of OST that Emerys envision, but do not accomplish. DIRECTIVE CORRELATION Directive correlation is rooted in Sommerhoff’s (1969) abstract formal, and universal principles. It is an ‘arrow of time’ (von Bertalanffy, 1968) linear model from t0 (starting conditions), t1 (goal/plan/learning) to t2 (changed condition of O & E from the goal/learn acts). Organization (system) and environment (other organizations) are said to be correlated in terms of direction when planning and learning are in alignment. When the planning and learning align its defined as an ‘adaptive’ relation, otherwise its ‘maladaptive.’ In short, organizations and environments may or may not be adaptively linked. Again, the Emerys are to be complimented for looking at how organization and environment are directively correlated across time periods. We need more longitudinal research to sort out what even with LISREL causal modeling cannot be sorted out sufficiently in cross section research at one time point. The problem the Emerys have not dealt with is how they posit a longitudinal model but research it only at cross-section interval of what people espouse at the SC workshop. Their next theory leap is to make all people and all systems purposive, ecological learners. PURPOSIVE SYSTEMS “Organizations” according to M. Emery (2000: 625) “may or may not be systems.” All human systems by their definition are purposive because all people are purposive. All “people are defined as open, purposive, systems” and “have the potential for ideal seeking” (p. 625) and “ecological learning” (p. 626). F. Emery asserts that four values are needed for the purposive people to be ideal seeking and to tame the turbulent environment of interorganizational relationships (p. 626): homonomy, a sense of belongingness and interdependence; nurturance, cultivating those means which contribute to health and beauty; humanity, expressing what is fitting for us as people, superordinate to institutions; and beauty, that which is aesthetically ordered and intrinsically attractive. My rebel voice asks why these four values, and not a multitude of other values? These are not just any values, they are aesthetic values. While I appreciate the cooperative emphasis that is quite unique given the competitive (variation-selectionretention) Darwinian values of most management and organization theory (especially strategy), there is something quite dogmatic in Emery’s these values or the highway, pronouncement. My resituation is to investigate what are the aesthetic values of people in organizations and those environments that are or are not directively correlated. Further, if we raise the level of complexity, we can ask about architectonic questions. Kant’s archetectonics separated aesthetic, from cognitive, and ethic. Bakhtin’s (1990, 1993) puts them into interanimated dialogical relationship. The missing terms of the Emery dualism is cognitive/rationalism (purposive, rational, correlated) in relation to the aesthetics values (and not just 4 of them) and to ethics of human and organization behavior (which is completely missing). Filling in-between-the-lines, the resituation becomes what are the relationships between the architectonically dialogic complexities of cognitive, aesthetic, and ethics? The other side of the story is when people are not rational, not purposive, not adaptive, not maladaptive, just plain irrational. What happens when you introduce the reality of people having many different rationalities, many perspectives, and worldviews about values, aesthetics, and ethics? The dualities of rational-irrational, purposivenonpurposive, adaptive-maladaptive, directed-undirected plague this theory. The second critique of purposive system stems form Emerys alliance with Ackoff. For Ackoff machine systems (p. 635-636) are what Emereys call DP1 parts relations, whereas in purposive systems (unlike mechanistic systems), DP2 is people as parts doing functions and the base concept that people unlike animals or machines make changes to their environment and react to their social environment. This is a breakthrough concept and both Ackoff and the Emerys are to be congratulated. They add the social and the social and mindfulness that is completely missing from von Bertalanffy. Yet, there is an important reductionism going on in the Emerys work. They take off with Ackoff’s duality Huamn/Mechanistic (& animal as machine) systems, and reduce it to a formalist, abstract, set of universal principles. You will see how this ia an Achilles heel. Emerys reduce all complexity down their main duality DP1/DP2. DP1 (design principle 1, redundancy of parts directed & coordinated one level up the hierarchy) is dualistic to DP2 (design principle 2, redundancy of functions, i.e. multiskilling of parts to do multiple functions). Emerys reverse the hierarchy making DP2 (multi-skilling in self-managing teams) dialectic to DP1 (people directed in their task by hierarchical supervision). Reading more closely, “people” are redefined as just “parts” in the duality (p. 627). What is the effect on complexity? Their theory moves their model down the Boulding (1956) levels-scale of complexity from network (level 8) to organic (level 5, ecological learners) to (level 4, open system), to (level 3, control by rational & aesthetic values), to level 2 (mechanistic people are parts of the machine). DP1 then becomes a metaphor for “representative democracies” or “talking heads” and DP2 for “participatory democracies” (p. 629). SC (search conference) is said by M. Emery to be the purest form of DP2, which is participatory democracy. My rebel voice cries out, what kind of participatory democracy does not have debate, reduces dialectical forces to harmony aesthetics, and pushes an abstract set of universalistic principles for how to be rational, adaptive, correlated, and calls this participative democracy? In other words, M. Emery posits that SC is not a committee of dialoguers, but has something else going on. But if it is not dialogue, not debate, not dialectic, and not dialogical, then what is it? M. Emery’s answer is that by putting people directly into DP2 structures, they avoid the “stages of group formation, ‘forming, storming, norming, and performing’” (p. 628). This is a BME (beginning, middle, end) narrative structure. DP1 is B, DP2 is M, and the E is the adaptive harmonius perfectly working organization. It seems to deny the very primise of contextualism. A change in design principle (DP1 to DP2) is said to be a complexity property that transform maladaptive to adaptive, undirected to directed and to purposive “learning organization” (p. 628). The DP2/DP1 duality has the effect of moving from OST to control system theory. DP2 is said to be variety increasing, while DP1 is variety decreasing (p. 628). As DP2 trumps DP1 at every turn, the result is not a dialectic of DP2 (deviationamplification) with DP1 (deviation-counteracting). In short, the two cybernetics that define what is OST, are not theorized by Emerys as interdependent, dialectic, or dialogic. It’s a one-way path where DP2 succeeds DP1. It’s a linear, not a dynamic plot. One has to ask what kind of ‘learning organization’ is this? It’s a deviation-amplifying feedback loop. DP1 is defined as error that DP2 attenuates. “DP2 structures are variety increasing and provide opportunities for setting goals and challenges and receiving feedback” (M. Emery, 2000: 628). A resituation can look at how DP2 and DP1 interplay, interact, and are interdependent in open systems and their many environments. It would move away from the all or nothingness of DP2. It would also look at the limits of DP2, how the form of participative democracy, is participatory at SC, but in a quite narrow range of participation, and does not deal with the issue of corporate governance, once the SC is over and done. Type I, placid environment, to M Emery (p. 629) means completely uniform values. Type II, ‘clustered, placid’ means the placid values are clustered. Type III, ‘distributed reactive’ means the organizations are engaged in competitive strategies. Type IV, ‘turbulent environment’ in the model, means that the extended social field has not developed shared placid-values to bring it under control. There is an explicit teleology of BME in the narrative. Type 1 is placid values of premodernity. Type II is clustered placid years 1945–1953 following WWII accompanied by end of hierarchical domination of organizations by the State. Type III is the growth of large corporations that take over market share in the environment and further evade control by the State. Type IV (turbulence) the social field does not have the value set to revert to type III. In Type IV, the ideal seeking solution is provided in the Emery OST: “This involves a shift from a society based on hierarchical domination to a participative democracy where all systems want to be and are purposeful and responsible” (p. 629). The goals of directive correlation come from the model itself: “Cultural change is produced by an integrated sequence of activities in which there is an individual goal for each stage and, at the same time, an ultimate goal to the whole sequence” (p. 630). A new duality crops up, Planned/Dynamic. The OST is to be “continuously dynamic” in time series T0 to T4 (etc), which can be “planned and mapped” (p. 630). However, the workshop is T0 with some reflexive narrating on what is the history of the organization and the extended field. Then the workshop is all about convening the people to do planning in ways that changes the system of intra and interorganizational relations. Measures of how successful these changes are has been limited to whether people continue to use the DP2 language terms, and less into the actual organization and interorganizational outcomes. Again, the Emerys are to be congratulated for getting beyond strategic planning and into the participatory procedures for strategic implementation. However, more research of a longitudinal nature is necessary. The duality of planned/dynamic is also critical to examine. The whole premise of muddling thorugh, chaos theory and the like is that planned change is not the same as bumping the dynamics of on-going in-the-moment systemicity into a new pattern. The problem once again is that planning sets in motion the counteracting forces, but not the amplifying ones. The Emerys’ solution is to have two workshops SC and PDW (Participative Design Workshop). Yet this is not the same as bumping along the dynamics into some new improvised direction (see work on systemicity imrpov in Boje 2006a). MATERIAL/ABSTRACT-UNIVERSALS DUALITY (p. 633). This is an amazing table of dualities I shall call material/abstract-universals. If we reverse it and ask what is it that Emerys are doing, we get the following readings. First they set up abstract universal principles (DP1, DP2, Directive Correlation, etc) and then they turn around and claim to be doing grounded, in-the-moment of the act --- materiality. Do you see this? Do you read how the table self-deconstructs, revealing they are doing that which they marginalize. A resituation would set up the dialectic relation between materialabstract (universal). Emerys OST ends up being imprisoned in abstract universal static boundaries. It is revealing that M. Emery accuses Kant of idealism, when much of the article thus far is all about ideal-seeking, purposive-seeking people. And what we have been studying about Kant is that he is the father of architectonics, of transcendental aesthetics (of time and space thinking) as well as pure reason (ability of people to think through relations that are not just retrospective sensemaking). Also interesting is that Kant’s universal is not the absolutist universalism that M. Emery is critiquing. That is, for Kant, many individuals have very different maxims (categoricals) that they seek to make universal. In other words, it is quite a dynamic (even stakeholder type) theory. The universals to which M. Emery objects is Pepper’s formalism (frameworks) hypothesis of universalistic categories. There is some other ways that M. Emery makes statements that self-deconstructs her own ways of doing SC, and the dualizing universal principles. For example ((M. Emery, 2000: 637): “In OST(E) the people who inhabit and purposefully change the world also use conversation as preparation for concerted action (de Laguna, 1927) with a huge range of skills, motives, and affects (Tomkins, 1963).” The purposive change is done through conversation, and as we note in this class, through, embedded acts of storytelling in those conversations, where a range of logics, viewpoints, and ideologies are expressed. And this is the very definition of polyphonic dialogism as a dynamic process. And here is an excellent view, this quote, of the ways in which storytelling and systemicity intersect in the moment of the act (Bakhtin, 1990, 1993). Where’s the self-deconstruction you ask? It is in the principles and the static structures of the workshops and the concepts themselves. They do not live up to the polyphonic more dynamic systemicity storytelling of the here-and-now unfolding conversations that are contextualized. As M. Emery recites the history of sociotechnical system (p. 637), she narrates how Trist, then Emery and Trist, are able to resituate von Bertalanffy’s OST into the more complete human and technical OST of the Emerys. She cites Emery and Trist (p. 637) critique of von Bertalanffy for leaving out the social, and there is Pepper, even that early in the work of Emery and Trist, the focus on contextualism, how it is different from formalism, mechanism, and organicism. The question arises, where does OST go from here? There are clues in M. Emery’s paper. She is to be congratulated for leaving such fine clues. For example, in the way she interprets Pepper, there is a time, a single arrow of time. However, in a Bakhtin (1981) perspective, there are at least 10 ways of temporalizing, and when we enter the social we no longer have the one way of temporalizing. This brings out the interaction of multiple ways of temporalizing, and Pepper and the Emerys are only clinging to one of them. Emerys have the insight the in contextualism, organizations as systemicities are changing over time, and the environment which is people and organizations at the level of the social) is also changing over time. Yes, F. Emery is to be congratulated for as early back as 1959 he did conceptualize L22 (organization-to-organization environment) as part of strategic planning process (M. Emery, 2000: 638). And Ackoff and Emery (1972) are to be congratulated for their collaboration for moving from evolution to co-evolution of organization and environment co-changing in directive correlation. And yes, Emery and Trist do go beyond von Bertalanffy’s OST, but one can ask a critical question here. Does the “allure of abstract universals” also remain just as strong in the OST of the Emerys? (p. 638). Are not the “genotypical organizational design principles” (p. 639) of the Emerys just as genotypical as those of von Bertalanffy, or for that matter the metaphoric universals of Katz and Kuhn? I like M. Emery’s title “The Current version of Emery OST.” It suggests there is a family of sociotechnical system theories. It suggests that there are more versions that are possible in post-Tavistock era, in post-sociotechnical system theory, in post-OST era. In these notes I have tried to be respectful and appreciative of the many contributions that the Emerys have made to sociotechnical system theory, to and OST that goes beyond von Bertalanffy. I have suggested the outlines of a resituation, a way to move forward and fulfill my mentor Lou Pondy’s dream to go beyond OST. RESITUATION OF OST Pepper’s (1942) contextualism is actually a much richer theory than the Emerys have yet to explore. For example, Pepper (1942: 232) is not just looking at past and completed “historic event” as its root metaphor. That would make it no more that Weickian retrospective sensemaking control narratives (Boje, 2006a; Weick, 1995). Rather by contextualism, Pepper (1942: 232) says he means “the event alive in the present … what it is going on now, the dynamic dramatic active event.” As in Bakhtin’s (1993) Philosophy of the Act, Pepper (1942: 233) tells us “these acts or events are all intrinsically complex, composed of interconnected activities with continuously changing patterns. They are like incidents in the plot of a novel or drama.” Pepper’s contextualism gets at the very intersection of storytelling (multi-plotting) and systemicity (interconnected dramatic events that are constantly changing) in the moment. What we now call emergence, Pepper calls ‘novelty’ and its relation to ‘change.’ It is this emergence (novelty & change) that escapes the notice of universal structure theories. He has a sort of early version of chaos theory. He focuses on the disorder, and the order that comes out of disorder. The concepts of novelty and change interact with what he means as context, which is the concepts of quality and texture (p. 235). Past events have texture and quality, and with emergent novelty and change those context patterns alter the texture and quality. The texture is theorized as having strands, and quality refers to the total meaning of each event (p. 238). We intuit texture patterns, and the quality (meanings) of those textures. Pepper posits a paradox of situation that has escaped the Emery’s theory of OST. That is, “the paradox of the situation arises only if one tries to impose a linear scheme of ‘time’ on the intuited event” (Pepper, 1942:240). For example in control narratives, a linear dimension of time is imposed to order events into beginning, middle, and end (BME). Pepper’s solution to the paradox is to posit a duality of “qualitative Present” and “schematic present” (p. 241). Ho points out the mechanism (mechanistic world hypothesis) overlays that schematic line of time, “slices along a line” (p. 241). To the contextualist the linear time sequencing, the line, is an artificial invention of the mechanists. The contextualist, says Pepper, distinguishes “between qualitative time (often called ‘duration’) and schematic time” (p. 242). Bergson, of course, calls qualitative time, the dureé. Quality works by fusion. “”Where fusion occurs, the qualities of the details are completely merged in the quality of the whole” (p. 243). Narrative, then is a qualitative fusion of the details of event into a unitary wholeness, with the sequence overlay of the plot schematic. I said above that context of texture has strands. Indeed strands and stranding is related to my conception of antenarrative (Boje, 2001). Antenarrative strands make connections to outlying antenarratives and narratives, constituting fusion in context of connections. I call them trajectories, rather than lines, to keep the nonlinearity of antenarrating in focus. Whereas narrative has a vertical control cosmology, antenarrative has more of the “horizontal cosmology” (Pepper, p. 250) or what is called by Stein (1935) the’ landscape’ of here-and-now, or Bakhtin (1993) in-the-moment of Being, i.e. the act. Antenarratives are socially initiated but often fail to reach satisfaction (i.e. coherence). Pepper would explain this as ‘blocking.’ In blocking “strands to not always form smoothly from their initiations to their satisfactions: (p. 255). Antenarratives as intertwining context, texture, quality, and fusion, do not always run so smoothly, and can just fall out of realization. Blocking is disorder, and involves “some degree of novelty” or what we now call emergence (p. 255). “After the conflict of blockage has occurred, it is theoretically possible to account for it in terms of the past history of each strand and show how their references lead to a conflict” (p. 256). Constituent antenarrative strands can just unravel and disintegrate. The clearest example Pepper gives is the hunter whose path to chase the deer is obstructed by a stream (p. 262). “The strand of his purpose is thereby blocked” (p. 262). I am sure it is this very sentence in which M. Emery sees the purposiveness humans theorized as open purpose-seeking systems. The act of the hunter has an instrumental reference, to cross the stream in order to kill the deer. Certainly there is no more instrumental texture and context than an organization, where every word is about exploiting various environments (which as Emerys point out is other organizations, which are all purpose seeking humans banding together). Like Kant, Pepper’s contextualists posit an apperception that is outside and a priori to retro perception (p. 266, bottom). It the instrumental context and texture, its all about the schemes (think narratives) that control them. Who are these early contextualists you ask? The answer is none other than William James and Charles Sanders Peirce. (p. 268). Welcome to pragmatism that Emerys call home. I suspect that the Emerys have what Pepper calls a “halfhearted contextualistic theory” (p. 272). They leave out novelty and the change theory is too linear and static, without enough emergence. It leaves out the systemicity the ways in which stranding is happening and the blocks. “For instance, the hunter was so sure that the hypothesis that he could not walk across the river was true that he did not even try to verify it” (p. 274). Like the Emerys, the hunters evidence of this is all based upon sensory empiric perception. Instead of following the implications of mutlistrandedness, the principles are piled one on top of another into a pyramid of static OST. Instead of positing several or many temporalities of the social, they integrate around the one arrow of time. There is not much in Emerys about symbols. In “contextualistic principles [it is] that the meaning of a symbol is found in the quality it leads to and that the quality of a strand takes up the qualities of its context” (p. 275). A narrative is no more than a tool, a symbolic model for the control of human systems, and for the control of natured environments, and other human systems (p. 275). This leads inevitably into integration with coherence theory and with causal sequencing that are ways of reducing contextualism to just a mere “formalism, mechanism, or organicism” (p. 278). PEIRCE’S ADBUCTION AND PRGAMATISM Abduction (or retroduction) is in between the induction of observation and experiment, and the deduction from formal frameworks to specific cases. Induction is all about the inference of some hypothesis that is not yet proved or falsifying a theory not yet disproved (Peirce, 1955: 150-156). “The abductive suggestion comes to us like flash. It is an act of insight, although of extremely fallible insight” (Peirce, 1955: 304). Looking more closely at Peirce’s pragmatism, it is not only crafted after James, but has its roots in the practicism of Immanuel Kant. Kant as Peirce remarks recognized the “inseparable connection between rational cognition and rational purpose” (p. 253). Pragmatism seeks “moral principle” (p. 253) in the sciences. Peirce remarks, “That systems ought to be constructed architectonically has been preached since Kant, but I do not think the full import of the maxim has by any means been apprehended” (Peirce, 1955: 316). What I would suggest as a resituation of Emerys’ OST is that we undertake a complete survey of architectonics, beginning with Kant, continuing through Bakhtin, and then we will have a way of exploring some adductive contextualist hypotheses about the relation of storytelling (particularly antenarrative trajectories) and systemicity. Why? Because with architectonics we get at the interplay of cognitive, aesthetic, and ethical. Fred Emery was a pioneer, pointing out the relation of abductive hypothesized aesthetic values to tame Type IV turbulent environments. Contextualism gets Emerys, and us, into history in the present moment, into the storytelling of which I am so found. Now with Peirce we see the import of architectonics, which Kant posited only with the cognitive pure reason. It remains for us to sort out an architectonics of answerability, to ask what is our complicity in this sea of systemicity, and what is our responsibility to change unethical into ethical practices of business. References Emery, M. 1997. Open System Theory is Alive and Well. Paper presented to ‘Retheorizing Sociotechnical Systems Theory’ symposium, Boston meeting of Academy of Management, ODC Division, session chair, D. Boje. Emery, M. 2000. The Current Version of Emery’s Open Systems Theory. Systemic Practice and Action Research, Vol. 13 (5): 623-643. Peirce, Charles S. 1955. Philsophical Writings of Peirce. Selected and edited with introduction by Justus Buchler. NY: Dover Publications, Inc. First publishined in 1950 under a different title by Routledge and Keegan Paul, Ltd. Pepper, S. 1942. World Hypotheses: A Study of Evidence. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.