Fundamental Rights in Europe and North-America (PARTE B – I CAPITOLO – I PARTE) V. EUTHANASIA In the Italian juridical system, it is impossible to arrive at an ad hoc position on the subject of euthanasia.1 Whether the subject consents to the killing, compassionate euthanasia is regulated as a omicidio del consenziente - homicide of the consenting party - (Art. 579 of the penal code), with attenuated penalties in comparison to voluntary homicide and with the exclusion of the application of aggravating circumstances as in Art. 61 of the penal code. However the case in point of homicide of the consenting party rules out some of the features present in some circumstances which usually accompany the act of euthanasia, being seen as causes of invalidity of the consent, it serves, besides persons of less than eighteen years of age, for «a person infirm of mind, or who finds himself in a condition of mental deficiency, because of another illness or from alcohol or substance abuse» (Art. 579, Par. 3, of the penal code). In such cases, it is necessary to apply the more rigorous regulation of common voluntary homicide2, without expressly taking into account the subjective motive of mercy and the objective conditions of a fatal illness as attenuating circumstances, either on the basis of Art. 62b of the penal code, which takes into consideration the general extenuating circumstances, or on the basis of Art. 62 of the penal code which in Par.1 takes into consideration the extenuating circumstances of «having acted through motives of particular moral or social value». In the face of these extenuating circumstances, in cases of mercy killing there are usually specific aggravating circumstances such as familial relationships between the killer and the victim, the use of poisonous substances or premeditation, in which case the prevailing verdict may lead to the application of the maximum penalty. Cases of euthanasia seem easily classed as related to criminal cases in point of assisted suicide, regulated jointly with the instigation to suicide in Art. 580 of the penal code, which occur when the agent concurs in the execution of death by furnishing the material means or any other form of facilitation3. As things stand, the material gap – that is the absence of regulations on the subject of 1 The word euthanasia in the current debate is used exclusively in the sense of voluntary compassionate euthanasia, that is of painless killing, brought about by the request of the victim, through compassion for the special circumstances which invoke it. One distinguishes in the legal position between the case where one asks that medical treatment is no longer given, even if this will lead to his/her death (passive euthanasia) and the case where one asks for the application of a treatment that will lead directly and without pain to death (active euthanasia). 2 In this sense, see CORTE DI CASSAZIONE, 18 November 1954 [(5), 151 ff.]. 3 on the distinction between homicide with consent and assisted suicide, see Corte di cassazione, 6 February 1998 [(7), 456ff] 1 Fundamental Rights in Europe and North-America (PARTE B – I CAPITOLO – I PARTE) euthanasia – constitutes, in the Italian system, a false problem: the regulation exists and is, precisely, as dictated by the penal code, the hastening even by a few minutes of the moment of death, or the omission of interventions which could have prolonged life for a while, even if, pietatis causa, they integrate in the case in point penalties punishable in a very severe manner3. But, in contrast to the rigour of the penal regulations, there is, in the hospitals and in the courts, a daily reality where there are strong signals of widespread acceptance in the social conscience of the practice of euthanasia aimed at allowing a dignified death to those who find themselves in the final stages of an incurable illness. The real problem around which the whole Italian doctrinal debate circles is, then, that of evaluating the existence of any possible gap, not material, but axiological (ideological, substantial) in the current system: that is to put to the test the adequacy of the current regulations in the light of the principles drawn from the Constitution. V.1. THE RIGHT TO DIE (ACTIVE EUTHANASIA) The highly controversial question is whether one can find a constitutional cover for a «right to euthanasia», that is exercised through an active choice as to the time and manner of one’s own death, even if one requests the help of a doctor or another third party to procure, assist or accelerate the lethal event. The most widespread opinion in the Italian constitutional doctrine is the one that holds that a hypothetical law which recognises the legality of euthanasia, and with it a right to die, would offend inevitably against the letter and the spirit of the Italian Constitution in its personalised character, from the moment that Art. 2 of the Constitution, recognises and guarantees the inviolable rights of man, prohibits absolutely, albeit implicitly, the fulfilment of any act directed at interrupting or abbreviating the life of a person. In particular, a reading combining Art. 2 with Art. 32 of the Constitution – which imposes «health as a fundamental right of the individual» and «prohibits the violation of the limits imposed by respect for the human being» - would lead to the conclusion that the Constitution intends to safeguard the right to life as a right to physical and biological existence, from conception to death, without either quantitative or qualitative ulterior specifications, and therefore also to life in the 4 With the specification of right that, according to Law 29 December 1993, no. 578 (regulations for the verification and certification of death), published in «Gazzetta Ufficiale», no. 5, 8 January 1994 – through which, ex Article 1, «death is identified with the irrevocable cessation of the functions of the brain» - the possibility of speaking of the killing of a person, and therefore of euthanasia, is excluded when on e intervenes with direct actions to «unplug the life support system» in subjects with a flat encephalogram, already having suffered a cerebral death. 2 Fundamental Rights in Europe and North-America (PARTE B – I CAPITOLO – I PARTE) terminal phases of illness. In consequence any constitutional cover for a «right of active choice over one’s own death»would be precluded4, a major reason being if such a right is configured as «the right to be killed» by a third party, on whom would be laid a corresponding – and clearly unlawful - «duty to kill»5. But the doctrine is anything but unanimous on the reading that comes from the constitutional dictates about the «right to die and to be helped to die», and there are those who give an interpretation diametrically opposed to the same constitutional regulations and the same principle of «respect of the person», and who see, in fact, precisely in the joint reading of Articles 2 and 32 of the Constitution the legitimating – rather than the excluding - basis of the right to the active choice of one’s own death. Those who make such a reading of the constitutional charter are convinced that life itself is protected, not only in the merely biological sense of’«being alive», but in the weightier sense of the biographical fact of’«having a life» which is significant and rewarding for the person who lives it: the respect of the person, the respect of their freedom, the respect of their dignity as sanctioned in the Constitution would impose, in consequence, also the respect of a decision which goes against their own life, qualifying such a decision in fact as an authentic «right». And it would undoubtedly be a violation of the principle of equality (Art. 3, Par. 1of the Constitution) if such a right were denied precisely to those who, finding themselves in an impossible position to procure their own death (because for example, although their intellectual functions may be unimpaired, their body is totally paralysed), or not wishing to go through a long and protracted period of dying (such as might happen by refusing food or other treatment which keeps them alive), ask other persons to help them carry out their wish in the quickest and least painful way possible6. V.2. Right to refuse treatment and the right to be left to die (passive euthanasia) Less ambiguous are the indications that can be drawn from the basic Charter as to the definition in law of the right to be allowed to die. Art. 32, Par. 1 of the Constitution defines health both as a «fundamental right of the individual» and as in the «interests of the community», such that the question could arise if, in case of conflict between the individual profile and the social profile, health as a right or as a 4 NICOTRA GUERRERA [(5), 147]. D’AGOSTINO [(2), ]; D’ALOIA [(3), 615]. 6 ALGOSTINO [(1), 3218]. 5 3 Fundamental Rights in Europe and North-America (PARTE B – I CAPITOLO – I PARTE) duty should prevail. For the jurisprudence7 and the clearly dominant doctrine8, Par. 2 of Art. 32 in the Constitution – for which «nobody can be obliged to follow a specific health treatment unless by the provisions of law», and in no case may the law violate «the limits imposed by respect for the person» - removes any doubt on the subject: the constitutional regulation (often read jointly with Art. 13, Par.1 of the Constitution, which guarantees the inviolability of personal liberty) becomes almost unanimously interpreted in the sense that health treatments can be legitimately imposed only in exceptional and absolute cases in which there is a law to provide for it, and that which is necessary to safeguard public interests – in primis, the health of other associates – not otherwise guaranteed (other than in cases in which the justification of the state of necessity applies). In all other cases, the Constitution gives absolute priority to the principle of individual self-determination, such that any health treatment administered in absence of or contrary to the consent of the right-holder would be illegal, even if it is to safeguard his well-being9. Every patient, then, has the sanctioned constitutional right to have his refusal of diagnostic and therapeutic actions respected; everyone has the right not to follow treatment; the right to loss of health; the right, also, to be allowed to die10. This is the negative implication of the right to health guaranteed in the Constitution. In this way the refusal of a patient who is legally capable11, conscious and informed12, not only renders the abstention of the doctor from providing care lawful, but also a duty; and the conduct of the physician who nevertheless decides to follow a medical or surgical procedure is to be considered unacceptable as much constitutionally as ethically, and as such to commit, in the worst case, a penal offence ex Article 610 of the penal code or another crime against individual freedom, constituting violent coercion to undergo something explicitly refused. If the principles that inform the Constitution do not allow a generalised and indiscriminate imposition of the duty to be healthy or the duty to life, this does not mean that 7 CORTE CONSTITUTIONALE, 22 Cctober 1990, no. 471 [(1), 25 ss.]; CORTE CONSTITUTIONALE, 18 April 1996, no.118 [(4), 18 ff.]; CORTE DI CASSAZIONE, 15 January 1997, no. 364 [(6), 771 ff..]. 8 D’ALOIA [(3), 611]; LUCIANI [(4), 9]; 9 This reflection on Article 5 of the civil code does not lead to different results (approved by Royal Decree, 16 March 1942, no. 626), which forbids acts of disposal of the body which «cause a permanent diminution of physical integrity». According to the dominant interpretation, in fact, this article would forbid only positive acts of disposal of the body, of self-mutilation, not also the negative ones, which first and foremost is the refusal of medical treatments. 10 D’ALOIA [(3), 611]; LUCIANI [(4), 9]. 11 In the case of an incapable subject, because he/she is a minor, a right to refuse treatment cannot be made by the parents, in that their power with regard to the minor is not depicted «as […] personal liberty, but as a right and a duty which finds in the interests of the child, its functions and its limits.» (CORTE CONSTITUTIONALE, 27 March 1992, no. 132 [(2), 9 ff..]). In the law of merit, CORTE D’ASSISE DI CAGLIARI, 10 March 1982 [(7), 27 FF..] 4 Fundamental Rights in Europe and North-America (PARTE B – I CAPITOLO – I PARTE) in the Italian juridical system there is a principle of indifference in force towards the citizens13. On the contrary, the objective of material and social solidarity that permeates throughout the fundamental Charter summarises in a paradigmatic manner the awareness of the inseparability of the safeguarding of rights and of the guarantee of the material conditions for a dignified life (Art.3, Par. 2 of the Constitution). If a State that wants to commit itself realistically to the protection of the right to life, must stop short of a free and conscious choice, even extends to the point of renouncing life, then it must be held at the same time to free the individual from forms of privation which could lead him/her to come to the choice of death under the tormenting pressure exercised by conditions of need and suffering and from the impossibility of insuring for himself and his family a dignified life, even in conditions of illness, invalidity, or old age14. Encouraging palliative care and therapies to control pain; creating and guaranteeing systems for assistance and material and psychological support for the terminally ill and for their families constitute duties of the Italian State that emerge clearly from the constitutional Charter, even if today these objectives are still for the most part unachieved. Fulfilling them would not cancel the requests for euthanasia, but would constitute at least a guarantee that, for those who continue to ask for it, death is not an unavoidable choice without dignified alternatives. Documentation Constitutional regulations for reference: Articles 2; 3, 1°-2° paragraph; 13, 1° paragraph; 32, 1°-2° paragraph, Constitution. Decisions of the Constitutional Court and the Supreme Court: 1) CORTE CONSTITUTIONALE, 22 October 1990, no. 471, «Gazzetta Ufficiale», 31-10-1990, I special series, no. 43, 25 ff.; 2) CORTE CONSTITUTIONALE, 27 March 1992, no. 132, «Gazzetta Ufficiale», 8-4-1992, I special series, no. 15, 9 ff.; 3) CORTE CONSTITUTIONALE, 16 May 1994, no. 180, «Gazzetta ufficiale», 25-5-1994, I special series, no. 22, 19 ff.; 4) CORTE CONSTITUTIONALE, 18 aprile 1996, no. 118, «Gazzetta Ufficiale», 24-4-1996, I special series, no. 17, 18 ff.; 5) CORTE DI CASSAZIONE, 18 November 1954, in «Foro italiano», 1955, II, 151 ff; 6) CORTE DI CASSAZIONE, 15 January 1997, no. 364, in «Foro italiano», 1997, I, 771 ff.; 7) CORTE DI CASSAZIONE, 6 February 1998, in «Foro italiano», 12 13 CORTE DI CASSAZIONE, 15 January 1997, no. 364 [(6), 771 ff..]. In this sense, see CORTE CONSTITUTIONALE, 16 May 1994, no. 180 [(3), 19 ff.]. 5 Fundamental Rights in Europe and North-America (PARTE B – I CAPITOLO – I PARTE) 1998, 456 ss.; 8) CORTE DI ASSISE DI CAGLIARI, 10 March 1982, in «Foro italiano», 1983, II, 27 ss. Bibliografia: 1) ALGOSTINO A., I possibili confini del dovere alla salute, in «Giurisprudenza constitutionale», 1996, 1006 ff. 2) D’AGOSTINO F., Diritto e euthanasia, in «Bioetica», no.1, 1999, pp. 94 ff. 3) D’ALOIA A., Diritto di morire? La problematica dimensione constitutional della «fine della vita», in «Politica del right», no.4, 1998, 608 ss.; 4) LUCIANI M., Diritto salute – diritto constitutionale, in Enciclopedia giuridica, XXVII, Roma, 1991, 1 ff.; 5) NICOTRA GUERRERA I, «Vita» e sistema dei valori nella Constitutione Milano, 1997. 14 D’ALOIA [(3), 621]; NICOTRA GUERREREA [(5), 148ff.] 6