1 Knox Ridley Kenny Smith Philosophy 3230 August 4, 2002 Thesis God is Perfect, Therefore Flawed Through out the history of philosophical explanations of God, whether it is a panentheistic, pantheistic, or a theistic God, the value of perfection has always been of utmost importance. In keeping with the theistic tradition, God is the highest state of being, and it is reasonable to assume that the state in which this ultimate being exists is perfect, therefore God is and exists in perfection. In this understanding, philosophers claim that the very essence of God is prefect. It is the goal of this paper to explore the meaning of the word “perfect” in relation to a theistic God, and pose some logical problems in relation to the semantics of this meaning. In light of the omnipredicates of the theistic tradition, God is considered supremely perfect, and though this is what is said and believed, I intend to show how this statement is not as easily understood in relation to some basic theistic claims about God’s nature. This paper will draw logic from St. Anslem’s essay, the Ontological Essay, and apply it to our dualistic understanding of God’s nature to show that the nature of God, in our relative understanding, is dependant on it’s opposing force, and prove that though God’s nature may be understood and experienced by relative understandings, for God to retain perfection, “he” must transcend dualistic definitions. 2 St. Anslem’s intentions were to logically prove that God existed. This paper is not concerned with proving God’s existence; but in assuming that this omnipredicated being exists, how it relates to the claim of being the perfect being. Before we discuss the meaning of perfection, we will look at the logic of St. Anslem’s Ontological Essay to lay down a foundation for this paper. St. Anslem claimed that God is that which no higher conception could be conceived. If you are to conceive of a higher conception, then the initial conception was not God. He then went on to claim that it is greater to exist in reality than to exist in only understanding, therefore God must exist. Anslem is assuming that existence is greater than non-existence. It is a reasonable assumption, but not one that can be completely understood due to any existing being’s ignorance of the experience of not existing. For, to experience not existing is a contradiction in and of it self, due to the fact that not existing warrants no experience at all. So, we assume that it is greater to have the characteristic in which we are most familiar with. This is also true in the experience of life and death. Most people assume that life is greater than death, but this cannot be known for sure, due to the fact that no one has experienced death and explained it in relation of life. Due to our ignorance of death, it is impossible to directly claim that it is greater than life, the only way death could conceivably be greater than life is if existence occurred in death to create a new experience, therefore making death impossible. It is that which we are most familiar, and comfortable with, in our subjective experiences, that earns our judgment of greatness making that which we define as perfection to be the accumulation of subjectively preffered extremes on a relative scale. 3 Proving value judgements of greatness is not the issue here, but how dualistic terms work together so that we may experience and define our experience of value judging is. Within our relative world of understanding we define perfection in relation to what it is not. We attribute God with being good because we cannot conceive of “him” to be bad through what we know bad to be. It is through the direct or indirect experience of what each of us considers to be bad, that we fully understand what it is like to be good. This is how our dualistic or relative understanding works: we know what the feeling of hot is in relation to being cold, we know what tall is in relation to that which is small. That which is, only is in relation to that which it is not. Each understanding is dependent on its adversary, or opposing force. Through this system of understanding the world, we attribute God “his” characteristics. Through the experience of evil, we conclude that God is all-good. Through the experience of weakness, we attribute God as being all-powerful. Through the experience of ignorance, we attribute God as being all-knowing. And through the continuous experience of all the attributes God is not in our imperfect world, we see God as the “perfect” being. This is what I will call relative perfection, and it is not based in what is actually greater, but what is preferred. Because of the value judgements it is based in, relative perfection is spurious in nature. This reason is because it is impossible to claim what is greater, due to the fact that value judgements are based in subjectivity, and are dependent on being what they are in relation to what they are not. Imagine a world that was all good. In this world goodness would not exist because we would not know what it is like to not experience 4 goodness all the time. Experiencing good is dependent on understanding, and experiencing directly, or indirectly that which is bad. Through this understanding it is impossible to claim that good is greater than bad, because they are both equally as important in understanding which we prefer to experience. I can claim through my own personal experience what I prefer: good over bad, life over death, knowledge over ignorance, etc., but to claim that knowledge is greater than ignorance is an impossible claim to defend. I could give some reasonable examples why I believe one value judgement to be greater, and even show the amazing benefits of one over the other, but the fact is that I know what I prefer in relation to it’s opposing force, or forces. It is because of what I do not like, that I am able to experience what I do like. In realizing this, I can appreciate and understand who I am through celebrating what I am not. If it were not for the bad, if everything was good, then goodness would not exist, because we would have no relative understanding of what good is in relation to what it is not. It is reasonable to say that God as arelativly perfect being, like me, is everything that “he” is not, therefore depends on what “he” is not to be what “he” is. What God is in relation to what “he” is not is relative perfection. It is through relative perfection that we may understand, and experience God’s nature in the relative world of existence. Without the relative claims which oppose that which is relative perfection, relative perefection would not exist. Anslem claimed that God is the highest conception that could be conceived, in keeping with this logic, this ultimate conception could only exist in an ultimate environment that one could call perfection. This means, that this ultimate state could not 5 be defined in relation to what it is not because each dualistic interpretation is understood and categorized in a hierarchical system of understanding. In other words, this state must transcend language. In basic human understanding, dualistic terms work together to explain greater meanings. I am using the word “greater” as a value judgment here only because the “greater meanings” are the cause of the meanings below it; “greater in this sense is synonymous with a more broud interpretation. For example, we know what a male is in relation to a female, and these two understandings working together and are a function of what we know to be human beings, or animals. We know what human beings are in relation to animals, and these two work together to create what we know to be reason. It is reason that separates humans from animals, and we know what reason is in relation to instincts, and these two work together to create what we consider to be love and fear. We understand love from fear, and these two emotions work together to create our experience of life. We understand life in relation to death, and how all of these experiences work together is what I will call ultimate perfection. Ultimate perfection is void of value judgments. Each dualistic term works together with it’s opposing force, or forces, to create a greater meaning of understanding. Therefore if something has a dualistic relation it cannot be the ultimate experience, or greatest experience. There will always be a higher field in which dualistic or relative terms define themselves. Ultimate perfection is, in this sense, the matrix in which all dualistic experiences exist. Perfection that acts like a matrix for us to drastically define what we see as perfect in relation to what we think is not perfect, is what ultimate perfection is. Since relative 6 perfection is a function of ultimate perfection, it is reasonable to assume that ultimate perfection is greater than relative perfection. Therefore, God must exist in ultimate perfection, but rely on relative perfection in order to experience “himself” as God. If this notion of Perfection is true, then it is reasonable to think that God must exist in both ideas of perfection. The true essence of God, like ultimate perfection, transcends, dualistic and relative understandings. But, in the relative world, if this essence was all that exited, if it had nothing other than itself, it would not be able to experience itself as it is. It is through our subjective experiences that we create relative perfection in relation to what it is not, in order to experience the relative essence of God. This would mean in a theistic sense that God is all good, all-powerful, and all knowing, but only because of the experiences of badness, weakness, and ignorance. But, it would also mean that there is another aspect of God that transcends relative definitions of character. This aspect can best be defined by language in ultimate perfection by simply saying, “God is.” In relative perfection, our relative understanding of what perfection is, God is all knowing, all-powerful, and all good. To help prove the idea of God not being limited to relative definitions, and being beyond dualistic understandings, I will pose a question and then try to explain it. Would God remain perfect if one of the omnipredicates attributed to God no longer existed? Most theistic philosophers claim that God is the omnipredicates, and to remove one of them would be to abolish theism all together. So, in the theistic tradition, if God were not all of the omnipredicates, then God would no longer be perfect, in a relative sense, because he would be missing a piece of “him” that originally made “him” perfect. 7 Assume for argument, that humans are the only intelligent life in the universe. Imagine that a meteor suddenly, and with out warning, collided with earth and wiped out the human population. With out human interaction, and our experiences with each other, would God still be all-powerful, all knowing, and all good? God could still experience himself as all-powerful without intelligent life, through the creation of physical space, and the ability to intervene when ever desired. God could also experience himself as all knowing, maybe not to such a detailed extent with knowing what all humans thoughts, emotions and actions are at once, but God could still know what meteors would collide with what planets, or when a star will collapse. So, basically, God’s knowledge would be limited to unintelligent physical interactions. But, I do not believe God could retain the claim of being all-good without intelligent interaction. Without our experience of goodness, love, wisdom, compassion, all of these godlike attributes would be no more. How could a comet show its love? How could a black hole exhibit mercy? Unintelligent matter cannot use reason to express God’s nature of goodness. If God only exists and is understood in relative perfection, or through subjective experience, then through the annihilation of intelligent life, God would lose a piece of his character. If goodness no longer existed, then God would have no way of defining himself as good, therefor making himself no longer good. God would still remain all-powerful, and following from this characteristic, be able to recreate intelligent life in order to retain the essence of experiencing himself as all-good in relative perfection. This may be true, but God would have to know what goodness is in order to recreate the experience, and if goodness no longer exists in reality, 8 there would have to be some remaining, fundamental knowledge of goodness beyond our relative understanding in order for God to know that goodness is what he wants to recreate. With the understanding of ultimate perfection, God could still retain his essence in ultimate perfection, but be unwilling to experience it in relative perfection. Therefore, allowing God the knowledge of a quality without fully relying on the direct experience in order to be God. In conclusion, we understand God through knowing what he is not. How dualistic forces, value judgments, work together to allow us the experience of our subjective preferences is ultimate perfection. The sum total of all of our relative preferences is how we define relative perfection, and because relative perfection is dependant on what it is not, it cannot be the highest state of being. Though the nature of God can be experienced in relative perfection, there must be an element of God that transcends dualistic definitions and simply is. 9