OUTLINE of Mill`s Utilitarianism

advertisement
OUTLINE OF J.S. MILL’S UTILITARIANISM
CHAPTER I – General Remarks
205,1 There are few areas in which there is a greater lack of unanimity than the
question of the foundation of morality.
205,2 A similar confusion exists regarding the foundations of the sciences. Luckily,
progress in the sciences doesn’t depend on this.
206,2 Our moral faculty supplies us only with the general principles of moral
judgments. There is general agreement that morality must be deduced from principles.
There ought to be some one fundamental principle or set of principles at the root of all
morality.
207, 2 Despite the lack of agreement on what the principle is, it is easy to show the
tacit influence of a standard not recognized, the greatest happiness principle. At least
everybody admits that human happiness is of prime consideration as a basis for morality.
207, 3—208, 1 I will now try to give “the Utilitarian or Happiness theory” such proof as
it is possible to attain. This should enable us to decide whether to give or withhold assent
to the theory.
208, 2 In order to do this, I must explain what Utilitarianism is and what rational
grounds can be given for accepting it.
CHAPTER II—What Utilitarianism Is
209, 1 “Utility” and “pleasure” are not opposed to each other, despite the common
misconception.
210, 1 To speak of utility as the foundation of morals is to assert the greatest happiness
principle, and happiness means pleasure and the absence of pain.
210, 2
To some people, this seems to reduce human life to the level of pigs.
210, 3 But, as the Epicureans have always answered, human pleasures are on a much
higher level than those of pigs. These include “pleasures of the intellect, of the feelings
and imagination, and of the moral sentiments [italics added].”
211, 1 We should not rely on the Epicureans alone for our theory. Many Stoic and
Christian elements need to be added. But clearly, some kinds of pleasure are inherently
more desirable and more valuable than others.
211, 2 But how are we to decide which kinds of pleasures are higher and which are
lower? Ask the people who are familiar with all the kinds listed.
Outline of J.S. Mill’s Utilitarianism
2
211, 3—212, 1 “It is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better
Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied.” And this is—by and large—the consensus of
mankind.
212, 2—213, 1 Granted that at times people yield to their lower impulses. In general,
the people who know both prefer the higher.
213, 2
“From this verdict of the only competent judges…there can be no appeal.”
213, 3—214,1 In any case, we base this judgment on the common, rather than the
individual good.
214, 2
Sums up the preceding paragraphs.
214, 3 In opposition to the view just stated, some people argue that happiness cannot be
our end, a) because it is unattainable and b) because we are unworthy of it.
214, 4—215, 1 But human happiness doesn’t have to be perfect or ecstatic. He defines
it as “an existence made up of few and transitory pains, many and various pleasures, with
a decided predominance of the active over the passive, and having as the foundation of
the whole, not to expect more from life than it is capable of bestowing.”
215, 2—216,1 He answers objections: great numbers of mankind have been satisfied
with much less than the above. “The main constituents of a satisfied life appear to
be…tranquility, and excitement.” When those “who are tolerably fortunate in their
outward lot” complain, it is because of “selfishness and want of mental cultivation.”
216, 2—217,1 There is no reason why the happy life just described shouldn’t be
available to “everyone born in a civilized country…[M]ost of the positive ills of the
world
are
in
themselves
removable…Poverty
may
be
completely
extinguished…[D]isease may be indefinitely reduced…[by] the progress of science….All
the grand sources…of human suffering are in a great degree, many of them almost
entirely, conquerable by human care and effort…”
217, 2 “Unquestionably it is possible to do without happiness; it is done involuntarily
by nineteen-twentieths of mankind…, but this is not as it should be.
217, 3—218, 1
can inspire.
218, 2
Self-sacrifice for others is noble and the Stoics show the tranquility it
While self-sacrifice is noble, it is not in itself good.
218, 3—219, 1 The Golden Rule, Christianity, et al. instill the common interest of the
individual and society.
Outline of J.S. Mill’s Utilitarianism
3
219, 2—220, 1 Ninety-nine percent of our actions are done for motives other than duty.
We must not forget to distinguish the morality of an action from the moral worth of the
agent.
He provides an implied standard for judging the moral worth of our actions, based on
whether or not they can be generalized. This suggests a continuum from act utilitarianism
through rule utilitarianism to Kant’s categorical imperative.
220, 2—221, 1 While we don’t want to confuse the value of an action with the moral
worth of the person who does it, “in the long run the best proof of a good character is
good actions.”
221, 2—222, 1 But don’t expect unanimity. Even Utilitarians disagree about the
morality of actions as measured by their own standard.
222, 2—223, 1 Is Utilitarianism godless? Surely God desires human goodness and
happiness, but “we need a doctrine of ethics carefully [worked] out, to interpret [his will
to us].”
223, 2 He then makes his strongest statement of Rule Utilitarianism in rebutting the
accusation that Utility means only Expediency. With telling the truth as his example, he
describes the deep human need to be treated ethically as “transcendent expediency.” In
thus redefining expediency, he sounds a lot like Kant, except that, in contrast to Kant’s
inflexibility, Mill permits exceptions to moral imperatives when circumstances make
them necessary.
224, 1—225, 1 Like any ethical system, Utilitarianism requires intermediate rules to
get from its general principles to specific actions. But we shouldn’t be silly enough to
think that human society hasn’t built up at least a modest store of practical moral wisdom.
Utilitarianism draws on this and develops its own intermediate rules based on it, and
thereby provides a clearer explanation of traditional rules.
225, 2—226, 1 Like all systems, Utilitarianism faces difficult and exceptional cases, as
well as individuals who don’t live up to the standard it sets. But judge it on its merits,
compared with other systems, in deciding difficult questions.
CHAPTER THREE
Of the Ultimate Sanction of the Principle of Utility
227, 1
It is hard to provide a new foundation for traditional, customary morality.
227, 2 This will continue until improved education creates a greater feeling of unity
with our fellow creatures.
Outline of J.S. Mill’s Utilitarianism
4
228, 2 People desire the approval of others and of God. The resulting system of
rewards and punishment provide external sanctions of human behavior. There is no
reason why these motives shouldn’t attach themselves to Utilitarianism.
228, 3—229,1 Then there is the internal sanction of duty, as expressed in conscience,
the pain attendant on violation of our duty.
229, 2
The ultimate sanction of all morality is this subjective feeling of conscience.
229, 3—230, 1 He attempts to rebut Kant on the nature of our sense of duty, asserting
that it is a subjective feeling and that its strength or weakness is independent of Kant’s
epistemology.
230, 2 On the other hand, if Kant’s “transcendental” basis of morality reinforces
conscience, so much the better for Utilitarianism.
230, 3 Moral feelings are not innate, but are the natural outgrowth of our nature.
However, they are subject to a wide variety of good and bad influences.
230, 4—231, 1 If there were no natural basis for Utilitarianism, it might well be
rebutted or ignored.
231, 2—232, 1 But there is a firm basis—the social feelings of mankind, which tend to
be democratic. That is, as much as circumstances permit, we tend to treat each other as
equals.
In this regard, when he speaks of “the contagion of sympathy,” he sounds like Hume,
adding that “[A]n improving state of the human mind” tends to increase our sense of
unity with other human beings. He tries to make a kind of religion out of this sense, with
or without a belief in God.
233, 1 “In the early state of human advancement in which we now live,” the feeling of
unity with the rest of humanity is only partly developed and subordinate to selfish
feelings. But it is “the ultimate sanction of the greatest-happiness morality.”
CHAPTER IV
Of What Sort of Proof the Principle of Utility Is Susceptible
234, 1 First principles are not proven, but are discovered in sense-experience or in our
minds.
234, 2 How then can the Utilitarian principle of happiness “make good its claim to be
believed”?
234, 3 How do we know that happiness is desirable? Because the mass of mankind
desire it. This is all the proof we can have, but it’s also all the proof we need. “Happiness
Outline of J.S. Mill’s Utilitarianism
5
has made out its title as one of the ends of conduct, and consequently one of the criteria
of morality.”
234, 4—235, 1
But what about other ends, like virtue, that people desire and aim for?
235, 2 Virtue, music, health, etc. are desirable in themselves; they are means to
happiness, but are also parts of happiness itself.
235, 3—236, 2 Thus, “the means have become part of the end….Happiness is not an
abstract idea…”
236, 3—237, 1 Virtue is the highest of these qualities. It is “above all things important
to the general happiness.”
237, 2 “Those who desire virtue for its own sake, desire it either because the
consciousness of it is a pleasure, or because the consciousness of being without it is a
pain.”
237, 3 “[H]uman nature is so constituted as to desire nothing which is not either a part
of happiness or a means of happiness…If so, happiness is the sole end of human action,
and…the criterion of morality.”
237, 4—238,1
The desirable and the pleasant are equivalent.
238, 2—239, 1 Will is not essentially different from desire. Desire is a passive mental
state, and will an active one. It is desire generalized and made active. The virtuous will
springs from the desire to be virtuous. The virtuous will is “a means to good, not
intrinsically a good” and does not contradict the idea that happiness is our sole end.
239, 2
Thus we have the proof of the principle of utility.
CHAPTER FIVE
On the Connexion between Justice and Utility
240, 1 Justice has always been conceived of as divorced from Utility or Happiness;
hence the concept of justice has always been one of the strongest obstacles to the
acceptance of Utilitarianism.
240, 2—241, 1 A sense or feeling of justice seems to be bestowed on us by nature.
People tend to think it has a totally different origin than expediency or utility.
To investigate this subject, we need to ask whether justice is an irreducible idea that
we have or a composite one?
241, 2 What is the distinguishing characteristic or characteristics of justice? Is it or are
they always present in it or is the sentiment inexplicable?
Outline of J.S. Mill’s Utilitarianism
241, 3—244, 1
6
He groups the attributes of justice under six headings:
241, 4
It is unjust to violate liberty or legal rights
242, 2
It is unjust to deprive people of something to which they have a moral right.
242, 3
Everybody should obtain what they deserve, and not what they don’t.
242, 4—243,1
expectations
It is unjust to break faith: to break a promise or disappoint
243, 2
It is injust to show partiality.
243, 3
Allied to impartiality is equality, i.e. giving people equal treatment
244, 2
How are all these different senses connected?
244, 3—245, 1 He gives etymologies (word origins) from various languages (Latin,
Greek, German, and French) of the word ‘justice.’
“[T]he primitive element…in the formation of the notion of justice…was conformity
to law.”
245, 2—246, 1 This concept of justice has been extended to activities not regulated by
statutes or courts.
246, 2 We call an action wrong if people should be punished for doing it. Duty is what
we may right be compelled to do.
246, 3—247, 1 He explains the distinction between perfect and imperfect obligations.
In the latter case, the particular occasions are left to our choice. “[T]his distinction
exactly coincides with that which exists between justice and the other obligations of
morality.”
248, 2 Does the feeling which accompanies the idea of justice come from nature or
could it have grown up out of the idea itself?
248, 3
The sentiment does not arise from an idea of expediency.
248, 4 “[T]he two essential ingredients in the sentiment of justice” is the desire for
vengeance and the knowledge that there is some specific victim of injustice.
248, 5 The desire to punish comes from the impulse of self-defense and the feeling
of sympathy.
Outline of J.S. Mill’s Utilitarianism
7
248, 6 It is natural for us to resent harm and retaliate in response to it. We differ
from animals a) in extending this response to all other humans and b) through our greater
intelligence extending the notion of community of interest to society as a whole.
248, 7—249, 1
The desire for vengeance is moral when it serves the common good.
249, 2 Resentment becomes moral when it is turned into “a rule which all rational
beings might adopt with benefit to their collective interest.” He specifically cites Kant in
support of this view.
249, 3—250, 1 “To recapitulate: the idea of justice supposes two things: a rule of
conduct, and a sentiment which sanctions the rule. The first must be supposed common to
all mankind, and intended for their good. The other (the sentiment) is a desire that
punishment may be suffered by those who infringe the rule….And the sentiment of
justice appears to me to be, the animal desire to repel or retaliate a hurt or damage to
oneself, or to those with whom one sympathizes, widened so as to include all persons, by
the human capacity of enlarged sympathy, and the human conception of intelligent selfinterest. From the latter elements, the feeling derives its morality; from the former, its
peculiar impressiveness, and energy of self-assertion.”
250, 2 Definition of a ‘right’: “a valid claim on society to protect [a person] in the
possession of it.”
250, 3—251, 1 The utility of justice is based on our fundamental need for security. On
security our whole lives depend.
251, 2
What other basis for justice can be found?
251, 3—252, 1 Don’t say the concept of utility is uncertain compared with justice;
there’s as much controversy about the one as the other.
252, 2—253, 1 Give examples of the controversy about justice in the many
disagreements about the legitimacy of inflicting punishment.
253, 2
used.
Then there’s all the disagreement about what standard of punishment should be
253, 3—254, 1 Then there are all the questions regarding social and economic justice
in the distribution of society’s goods: should society focus on merit or on need?
254, 2—255, 1
Similar disputes arise regarding taxation.
255, 2 Nevertheless, justice is not identical with expediency. It is based on “the
essentials of human well-being,” regarding which we all have rights.
Outline of J.S. Mill’s Utilitarianism
8
255, 3—256, 1 The moral rules against hurting one another are the most vital ones to
us, and thus the most useful. He gives a general list of them (256, 1).
256, 2 Not only is returning evil for evil intimately connected with our idea of justice,
but of rewarding good with good. Breach of friendship or breach of promise is similarly
essential to our idea of justice and also helps place justice above expediency.
257, 1
The currently prevailing rules of justice reflect the principles we have stated.
257, 2—259, 1 Such judicial virtues are impartiality and equality of treatment.
Equality must prevail “except when some recognized social expediency requires the
reverse.” (258,1)
“The entire history of social improvement” has tended to erase distinctions between
“slaves and freemen, nobles and serfs, patricians and plebeians; and so it will be, and in
part already is, with the aristocracies of colour, race, and sex.” (259, 1)
259, 2 “[J]ustice is a name for certain moral requirements, which, regarded
collectively, stand higher in the scale of social utility, and are therefore of more
paramount obligation, than any others; though particular cases may occur in which some
other social duty is so important, as to overrule any one of the general maxims of justice.”
259, 3 These considerations “resolve…the only real difficulty in the utilitarian theory
of morals.” Justice is equivalent to expediency; we simply have to remove the conflicting
sentiments that attach to these two terms. When we do that, justice “no longer presents
itself as a stumbling-block to the utilitarian ethics. Justice remains the appropriate name
for certain social utilities which are vastly more important, and therefore more absolute
and imperative, than any others are as a class…; and which, therefore…are…guarded by
a sentiment…distinguished from the milder feeling which attaches to the mere idea of
promoting human pleasure or convenience, at once by the more definite nature of its
commands, and by the sterner character of its sanctions.”
© Robert Greene, 2007
Philosophy 308
Spring 2007
UW-Eau Claire
Download