PHILOSOPHY READINGS AD MMII UNITS 3& 4 It is not for nothing that I have been a philologist. Philology is that venerable art which demands of its votaries one thing above all: to go aside, to take time, to become still, to become slow … It teaches to read well, that is to say, to read slowly, deeply, looking cautiously fore and aft, with reservations, with doors left open, with delicate eyes and fingers. Nietzsche Daybreak. Aristotle Ethics Aristotle NICOMACHEAN ETHICS Book I [Extract drawn from Aristotle, Ethics, translated by J.A.K. Thomson, Penguin, 1976. Footnotes not directly relevant to our purposes have been removed. Those added are marked DV.] Every rational activity aims at some end or good. One end (like one activity) may be subordinate to another. i Every art and every investigation, and similarly every action and pursuit, is considered to aim at some good. Hence the Good has been rightly defined as ‘that at which all things aim. Clearly, however, there is some difference between the ends at which they aim: some are activities and others results distinct from the activities. Where there are ends distinct from the actions, the results are by nature superior to the activities. Since there are many actions, arts and sciences, it follows that their ends are many too – the end of medical science is health; of military science, victory; economic science,1 wealth. In the case of all skills of this kind that come under a single ‘faculty’2 - as a skill in making bridles or any other part of a horse’s trappings comes under horsemanship, while this and every kind of military action comes under military science, so in the same way other skills subordinate to yet others - in all these the ends of the directive arts are to be preferred in every case to those of the subordinate ones, because it is for the sake of the former that latter are pursued also. It makes no difference whether ends of the actions are the activities themselves or something apart from them, as in the case of the sciences we have mentioned. If, then, our activities have some end which we want for its own sake, and for the sake of which we want all the other ends - if we do not choose everything for the sake of something else (for this will involve an infinite progression, so that our aim will be pointless and ineffectual) - it is clear that this must be the Good, that is the supreme good. Does it not follow, then, that a knowledge of the Good is of great importance to us for the conduct of our lives? Are we not more likely to achieve our aim if we have a target? If this is so, we must try to describe at least in outline what the Good really is, and by which of the sciences or faculties3 it is studied. The science that studies the supreme Good for man is politics ii. Presumably this would be the most authoritative and directive science. Clearly this description fits the science of politics; for it is political science that prescribes what subjects are to be taught in states, and which of these the different sections of the community are to learn, and up to what point.4 We see also that under this science come those faculties which are most highly esteemed; e.g. the arts of war, of property management, and of public speaking. But if politics makes use of the other sciences, and also lays down what we should do and from what we should refrain, its end must include theirs; and this end must be the good for man. For even if the good of the community coincides with that of the individual, it is clearly a greater and more perfect thing to achieve and preserve that of a community; for 1 i.e. household or property management. For dunamis see Glossary. 3 Here ‘faculty’ (dunamis) means ‘art’ or ‘practical science’. 4 Or perhaps ‘up to what age’. 2 3 Aristotle Ethics while it is desirable to secure what is good in the case of an individual, to do so in the case of a people or a state is something finer and more sublime. Such, then, is the aim of our investigation; and it is a kind of political science.5 Politics is not an exact science iii. Our account of this science will be adequate if it achieves such clarity as the subjectmatter allows; for the same degree of precision is not to be expected in all discussions. Any more than in all the products of handicraft. Instances of morally fine and just conduct - which is what politics investigates - involve so much difference and variety that they are widely believed to be such only by convention and not by nature. Instances of goods involve a similar kind of variety, for the reason that they often have hurtful consequences. People have been destroyed before now by their money, and others by their courage. Therefore in discussing subjects, and arguing from evidence, conditioned in this way, we must be satisfied with a broad outline of the truth; that is, in arguing about what is for the most part so from premisses which are for the most part true we must be content to draw conclusions that are similarly qualified. The same procedure, then, should be observed in receiving our several types of statement; for it is a mark of the trained mind never to expect more precision in the treatment of any subject than the nature of that subject permits; for demanding logical demonstrations from a teacher of rhetoric is clearly about as reasonable as accepting mere plausibility from a mathematician. The student should have some general knowledge and experience of life Since in every case a man judges rightly what he understands, and of this only is a good critic, it follows that while in a special field the good critic is a specialist, the good critic in general is the man with a general education. That is why a young man is not a fit person to attend lectures on political science, because he is not versed in the practical business of life from which politics draws its premisses and subject-matter. Besides, he tends to follow his feelings, with the result that he will make no headway and derive no benefit from his course, since the object of it is not knowledge but action. It makes no difference whether he is young in age or youthful in character; the defect is due not to lack of years but to living, and pursuing one’s various aims, under sway of the feelings; for to people like this knowledge becomes as unprofitable as it is for the incontinent.6 On the other hand for those who regulate their impulses and act in accordance with principle7 a knowledge of these subjects will be of great advantage. So much by way of introductory remarks about the student, the proper attitude towards instruction, and the proposed course. The end is no doubt happiness, but views of happiness differ iv. To resume. Since all knowledge and every pursuit aims at some good, what do we take to be the end of political science - what is the highest of all practical goods? Well, so far as the name goes there is pretty general agreement. ‘It is happiness’, say both ordinary and cultured people; and they identify happiness with living well or doing well.8 But when it comes to saying in what happiness consists, opinions differ, and the account given by the generality of mankind is not at all like that of the wise. The former take it to be something obvious and 5 A. seems to regard ethics not as a species of politics but as a sort of introduction to it. Those who know what is right but fail to do it; cf 1145b8ff. 7 The difficult word logos; see Glossary. 8 The Greek phrases are ambiguous, connoting both prosperity and right conduct. 6 4 Aristotle Ethics familiar, like pleasure or money or eminence, and there are various other views; and often the same person actually changes his opinion: when he falls ill he says that it is health, and when he is hard up that it is money. Conscious of their own ignorance, most people are impressed by anyone who pontificates and says something that is over their heads. Some,9 however, have held the view that over and above these particular goods there is another which is good in itself and the cause of whatever goodness there is in all these others. It would no doubt be rather futile to examine all these opinions; enough if we consider those which are most prevalent or seem to have something to be said for them. Learners must start from beliefs that are, accepted or at least familiar We must not overlook the difference that it makes whether we argue from or to first principles. Plato too used very properly to raise this question, inquiring whether the procedure was from or to first principles - just as on a racetrack they run either from the judges’ stand to the far end, or in the reverse direction.10 We must start from what is known. But things are known in two senses: known to us and known absolutely. Presumably we must start from what is known to us. So if anyone wants to make a serious study of ethics, 11 or of political science generally, he must have been well trained in his habits. For the starting-point is the fact; and if this is sufficiently clear there will be no need to ascertain the reason why. Such a person can easily grasp the first principles12 if he is not in possession of them already; but one who has neither of these qualifications had better take to heart what Hesiod says: 13 That man is best who sees the truth himself; Good too is he who listens to wise counsel. But who is neither wise himself nor willing To ponder wisdom is not worth a straw. The three types of life. Neither pleasure nor public honour seem to be an adequate end; the contemplative life will be considered later v. But let us resume from the point at which we digressed. To judge by their lives, the masses and the most vulgar seem - not unreasonably - to believe that the Good or happiness is pleasure. Accordingly they ask for nothing better than the life of enjoyment. (Broadly speaking, there are three main types of life: the one just mentioned, the political, and thirdly the contemplative.14) The utter servility of the masses comes out in their preference for a bovine existence; still, their view obtains consideration from the fact that many of those who are in positions of power share the tastes of Sardanapalus. 15 Cultured people, however, and men of affairs identify the Good with honour, because this is (broadly speaking) the goal of political life. Yet it appears to be too superficial to be the required answer. Honour is felt to depend more on those who confer than on him who receives it; and we feel instinctively that the Good is something proper to its possessor and not easily taken from him. Again, people seem to seek honour in order to convince themselves of their own goodness; at any rate it is by intelligent men, and in a community where they are known, and for their goodness, that they seek to be honoured; so evidently in their view goodness is superior to honour. One might even be inclined to suppose that goodness rather than honour is the end pursued in 9 Plato and his followers in the Academy. According as the race is one length of the stadium or two (‘there and back’). 11 ‘Fine and just things’. 12 Moral values. 13 Works and Days 291-4. 14 Cf. Plato, Republic 581c; the division is attributed to Pythagoras. 15 An Assyrian king of legendary sensuality. 10 5 Aristotle Ethics public life. But even this appears to be somewhat deficient as an end, because the possession of goodness is thought to be compatible even with being asleep, or with leading a life of inactivity, and also with incurring the most atrocious suffering and misfortune; and nobody would call such a life happy - unless he was defending a paradox.16 So much for these views: they have been fully treated in current discussions.17 The third type of life is the contemplative, and this we shall examine later.’ As for the life of the business man, it does not give him much freedom of action. Besides, wealth is obviously not the good that we are seeking, because it serves only as a means; i.e. for getting something else. Hence the earlier suggestions might be supposed to be more likely ends, because they are appreciated on their own account; but evidently they too are inadequate, and many attacks on them have been published.18 What is the Good for man? It must be the ultimate end or object of human life: something that is in itself completely satisfying. Happiness fits this description. vii. Let us now turn back again to the good which is the object of our search, and ask what it can possibly be; because it appears to vary with the action or art. It is one thing in medicine and another in strategy, and similarly in all the other sciences. What, then, is the good of each particular one? Surely it is that for the sake of which everything else is done. In medicine this is health; in strategy, victory; in architecture, a building - different things in different arts, but in every action and pursuit it is the end, since it is for the sake of this that everything else is done. Consequently if there is any one thing that is the end of all actions, this will be the practical good - or goods, if there are more than one. Thus while changing its ground the argument has reached the same conclusion as before.19 We must try, however, to make our meaning still clearer. Since there are evidently more ends than one, and of these we choose some (e.g. wealth or musical instruments or tools generally) as means to something else, it is clear that not all of them are final ends, whereas the supreme good is obviously something final. So if there is only one final end, this will be the good of which we are in search; and if there are more than one, it will be the most final of these. Now we call an object pursued for its own sake more final than one pursued because of something else, and one which is never choosable because of another more final than those which are choosable because of it as well as for their own sakes; and that which is always choosable for its own sake and never because of something else we call final without any qualification. Well, happiness more than anything else is thought to be just such an end, because we always choose it for itself, and never for any other reason. It is different with honour, pleasure, intelligence and good qualities20 generally. We do choose them partly for themselves (because we should choose each one of them irrespectively of any consequences); but we choose them also for the sake of our happiness, in the belief that they will be instrumental in promoting it. On the other hand nobody chooses happiness for their sake, or in general for any other reason. 16 A thesis, i.e. a paradoxical generalization by a leading philosopher; cf Topics 104b19ff., where examples are quoted. [DV: Note that the ‘paradox’ or ‘thesis’ criticised here by Aristotle is very similar to the claim that drew Callicles into the argument with Socrates in the Gorgias. 17 Apparently at a popular level. 18 In Book X. 19 In the first two chapters. 20 Or ‘virtues’. 6 Aristotle Ethics The same conclusion seems to follow from another consideration. It is a generally accepted view that the perfect good is self-sufficient. By self-sufficient we mean not what is sufficient for oneself alone living a solitary life,21 but something that includes parents, wife and children, friends and fellow-citizens in general; for man is by nature a social being. (We must set some limit to these, for if we extend the application to grandparents and grandchildren and friends of friends it will proceed to infinity; but we must consider this point later.22) A selfsufficient thing, then, we take to be one which by itself makes life desirable’ and in no way deficient; and we believe that happiness is such a thing. What is more, we regard it as the most desirable of all things, not reckoned as one item among many; if it were so reckoned, happiness would obviously be more desirable23 by the addition of even the least good, because the addition makes the sum of goods greater, and the greater of two goods is always more desirable. Happiness, then, is found to be something perfect and self-sufficient, being the end to which our actions are directed. But what is happiness? If we consider what the function of man is, we find that happiness is a virtuous activity of the soul. But presumably to say that happiness is the supreme good seems a platitude, and some more distinctive account of it is still required. This might perhaps be achieved by grasping what is the function of man. If we take a flautist24 or a sculptor or any artist - or in general any class of men who have a specific function or activity - his goodness and proficiency is considered to lie in the performance of that function; and the same will be true of man, assuming that man has a function. But is it likely that whereas joiners and shoemakers have certain functions or activities, man as such has none, but has been left by nature a functionless being? Just as we can see that eye and hand and foot and every one of our members has some function, should we not assume that in like manner a human being has a function over and above these particular functions? What, then, can this possibly be? Clearly life is a thing shared also by plants, and we are looking for man’s proper function; so we must exclude from our definition the life that consists in nutrition and growth. Next in order would be a sort of sentient life; but this too we see is shared by horses and cattle and animals of all kinds. There remains, then, a practical life of the rational part. As this life also has two meanings, we must lay down that we intend here life determined by activity, because this is accepted as the stricter sense.25 Now if the function of man is an activity of the soul in accordance with, or implying, a rational principle; and if we hold that the function of an individual and of a good individual of the same kind - e.g. of a harpist and of a good harpist, and so on generally – is generically the same, the latter’s distinctive excellence being attached to the name of the function (because the function of the harpist is. to play the harp, but that of the good harpist is to play it well); and if we assume that the function of man is a kind of life, viz., an activity or series of actions of the soul, implying a rational principle; and if the function of a good man is to perform these well and rightly; and if every function is performed well when performed in accordance with its proper excellence: if all this is so, the conclusion is that the good for man is an activity of soul in accordance with virtue, or if there are more kinds of virtue than one, in accordance with the best and most perfect kind. 21 The Greek word (autarkis) normally carries the sense of independence. In chs. ix and x, and in Book IX. ch. x. 23 Here and in the following lines the meaning is really ‘choosable’, hairetos. 24 The Greek aulos was not a flute but a reed instrument. 25 The other being life as a state, implying no more than the possession of reason. 22 7 Aristotle Ethics There is a further qualification: in a complete lifetime. One swallow does not make a summer; neither does one day. Similarly neither can one day, or a brief space of time, make a man blessed26 and happy. This sketch can be elaborated later, but great precision is not to be expected This may stand as an outline account of the Good; for presumably we should first rough out a sketch and then fill in the details afterwards. When the outline has been satisfactorily drawn, it may be supposed that anybody can carry on the work and fill in the detail; 27 and that in such a case time is a good source of invention or cooperation. In fact this is how progress in the arts has been made; for anyone can fill in the gaps. But we must still remember the caution given above, and not look for the same degree of exactness in all our studies, but only for as much as the subject-matter in each case allows, and so far as is appropriate to the investigation. For example, a carpenter’s interest in the right angle is different from a geometrician’s: the former is concerned with it only so far as it is useful for his work, but the other wants to know what it is or what its properties are, because his gaze is set on the truth. We ought to follow this procedure in other studies as well, in order to prevent the swamping of main by side issues. We must not even demand to know the explanation in all cases alike; there are some in which it is quite enough if the fact itself is exhibited, e.g. in the case of first principles; the fact is primary and a starting-point.28 Some starting points are grasped by induction, some by perception,29 some by a kind of habituation, others in other ways. We must try to investigate each type in accordance with its nature. We must also make a point of formulating them correctly, because they have a great importance for the understanding of what follows. By common consent the beginning is more than half the whole task,30 and throws a flood of light on many of the aspects of the inquiry. Our view of happiness is supported by popular beliefs viii. We must examine our principle not only as reached logically, from a conclusion and premisses, but also in the light of what is commonly said about it; because if a statement is true all the data are in harmony with it, while if it is false they soon reveal a discrepancy. Now goods have been classified31 under three heads, as (a) external, (b) of the soul, and (c) of the body. Of these we say that goods of the soul are good in the strictest and fullest sense, and we rank actions and activities of soul as goods of the soul; so that according to this view, which is of long standing and accepted by philosophers, our definition will be correct. We are right, too, in saying that the end consists in certain actions or activities, because this puts it among goods of the soul and not among external goods. Our definition is also supported by the belief that the happy man lives and fares well; because what we have described is 26 makarios The metaphor is taken from architecture or large-scale sculpture, in which the master supplies only the overall design. 28 The same Greek word arche means ‘beginning’ or ‘starting-point’ and ‘first principle’. In every science a first principle is primary because it is the cause or ground of all that follows from it, while being itself indemonstrable because there is no higher principle to which it can be referred. 29 aisthesis usually means ‘sensation’, but it can, and probably does here convey the sense of direct perception or intuition, which perceives the truth immediately. 30 The phrase is proverbial. 31 By Plato: Euthydemus 279A-B, Philebus 48E, Laws 743E. 27 8 Aristotle Ethics virtually a kind of good life or prosperity.32 Again, our definition seems to include all the required constituents of happiness; for some think that it is virtue, others prudence, 33 and others wisdom;34 others that it is these, or one of these, with the addition of pleasure, or not in total separation from it; and others further include favourable external conditions. Some of these views are popular beliefs of long standing; others are those of a few distinguished men. It is reasonable to suppose that neither group is entirely mistaken, but is right in some respect, or even in most. Now our definition is in harmony with those who say that happiness is virtue, or a particular virtue; because an activity in accordance with virtue implies virtue. But presumably it makes no little difference whether we think of the supreme good as consisting in the possession or in the exercise of virtue: in a state of mind or in an activity. For it is possible for the state to be present in a person without effecting any good result (e.g. if he is asleep or quiescent in some other way), but not for the activity: he will necessarily act, and act well. Just as at the Olympic Games it is not the best-looking or the strongest men present that are crowned with wreaths, but the competitors (because it is from them that the winners come), so it is those who act that rightly win the honours and rewards in life. Moreover, the life of such people is in itself pleasant. For pleasure is an experience of the soul,35 and each individual finds pleasure in that of which he is said to be fond. For example, a horse gives pleasure to one who is fond of horses, and a spectacle to one who is fond of sight-seeing. In the same way just acts give pleasure to a lover of justice, and virtuous conduct generally to the lover of virtue. Now most people find that the things which give them pleasure conflict, because they are not pleasant by nature; but lovers of beauty find pleasure in things that are pleasant by nature, and virtuous actions are of this kind, so that they are pleasant not only to this type of person but also in themselves. So their life does not need to have pleasure attached to it as a sort of accessory, but contains its own pleasure in itself Indeed, we may go further and assert that anyone who does not delight in fine actions is not even a good man; for nobody would say that a man is just unless he enjoys acting justly, nor liberal unless he enjoys liberal actions, and similarly in all the other cases. If this is so, virtuous actions must be pleasurable in themselves. What is more, they are both good and fine, and each in the highest degree, assuming that the good man is right in his judgement of them; and his judgement is as we have described.36 So happiness is the best, the finest, the most pleasurable thing of all; and these qualities are not separated as the inscription at Delos37 suggests: justice is loveliest, and health is best, But sweetest to obtain is heart’s desire. All these attributes belong to the best activities; and it is these, or the one that is best of them, that we identify with happiness. The Greek phrase can mean ‘acting well’ or ‘faring well’. phronesis: see Glossary. 34 sophia: see Glossary. 35 Of the conscious self. 36 In the preceding lines. 37 On the entrance to the temple of Leto. The lines (which are quoted at the beginning of the Eudemian Ethics) are also found, slightly altered, in Theognis 225f., and paraphrased in Sophocles (Creusa), fr. 326. [DECV: Delos is an Aegean island which was significant for a shrine to Apollo which was second in importance only to the Oracle at Delphi.] 32 33 9 Aristotle Ethics Nevertheless it seems clear that happiness needs the addition of external goods, as we have said; for it is difficult if not impossible to do fine deeds without any resources. Many can only be done by the help of friends, or wealth, or political influence. There are also certain advantages, such as good ancestry or good children, or personal beauty, the lack of which mars our felicity; for a man is scarcely happy if he is very ugly to look at, or of low birth, or solitary and childless; and presumably even less so if he has children or friends who are quite worthless, or if he had good ones who are now dead. So, as we said, happiness seems to require this sort of prosperity too; which is why some identify it with good fortune, although others identify it with virtue. How is happiness acquired? ix. From this springs another problem. Is happiness something that can be learnt, or acquired by habituation, or cultivated in some other way, or does it come to us by a sort of divine dispensation, or even by chance? Well, in the first place, if anything is a gift of the gods to men, it is reasonable that happiness should be such a gift, especially since of all human possessions it is the best. This point, however, would perhaps be considered more appropriately by another branch of study.38 Yet even if happiness is not sent by a divine power, but is acquired by moral goodness and by some kind of study or training, it seems clearly to be one of our most divine possessions; for the crown and end of goodness is surely of all things the best: something divine and blissful. Also on this view39 happiness will be something widely shared; for it can attach, through some form of study or application, to anyone who is not handicapped by some incapacity for goodness. And, assuming that it is better to win happiness by the means described than by chance, it is reasonable that this should in fact be so, since it is natural for nature’s effects to be the finest possible, and similarly for the effects of art and of any other cause,40 especially those of the best kind.41 That the most important and finest thing of all should be left to chance would be a gross disharmony. The problem also receives some light from our definition, for in it happiness has been described as a kind of virtuous activity of soul; whereas all the other goods either are necessary preconditions of happiness or naturally contribute to it and serve as its instruments. This will agree with what we said at the outset:’ we suggested that the end of political science is the highest good; and the chief concern of this science is to endue the citizens with certain qualities, namely virtue and the readiness to do fine deeds. Naturally, therefore, we do not speak of an ox or a horse or any other animal as happy, because none of them can take part in this sort of activity. For the same reason no child is happy either, because its age debars it as yet from such activities; if children are so described, it is by way of congratulation on their future promise. For, as we said above, happiness demands not only complete goodness but a complete life. In the course of life we encounter many reverses and all kinds of vicissitudes, and in old age even the most prosperous of men may be involved in great misfortunes, as we are told about Priam in the Trojan poems.42 Nobody calls happy a man who suffered fortunes like his and met a miserable end. i.e. what A. calls ‘first philosophy’: a combination of theology and metaphysics. That it is acquired by human effort. 40 i.e. efficient cause. 41 Of cause, viz. mind or intelligence. 42 i.e. the epics about the Trojan War; cf. Iliad xxii. 37-78, xxiv. 160ff., and for the account of Priam’s death (derived from the lost Iliu Persis) Virgil, Aeneid ii. 506-58. (Appendix V) 38 39 10 Aristotle Ethics Book X Recapitulation: the nature of happiness vi. Now that we have finished our discussion of the virtues, of friendship, and of pleasures, it remains for us to give an outline account of happiness, since we hold it to be the end of human conduct. It may make our treatment of the subject more concise if we recapitulate what has been said already. We said, then, that happiness is not a state, since if it were it might belong even to a man who slept all through his life, passing a vegetable existence; or to a victim of the greatest misfortunes. So if this is unacceptable, and we ought rather to refer happiness to some activity, as we said earlier; and if activities are either necessary and to be chosen for the sake of something else, or to be chosen for themselves: clearly we must class happiness as one of those to be chosen for themselves, and not as one of the other kind, because it does not need anything else: it is self sufficient. The activities that are to be chosen for themselves are those from which nothing is required beyond the exercise of the activity; and such a description is thought to fit actions that accord with goodness; because the doing of fine and good actions is one of the things that are to be chosen for themselves. Happiness must be distinguished from amusement Pleasant amusements are also thought to belong to this class, because they are not chosen as means to something else: in fact their effects are more harmful than beneficial, since they make people neglect their bodies and their property. However, most of those who are regarded as happy have recourse to such occupations, and that is why those who show some dexterity in them are highly esteemed at the courts of tyrants; they make themselves agreeable by providing the sort of entertainment that their patrons want, and such persons are in demand. So these amusements are thought to be conducive to happiness, because men in positions of power devote their leisure to them. But what people of this kind do is probably no evidence, because virtue and intelligence, which are the sources of serious activities, do not depend upon positions of power; and if these persons, never having tasted pure and refined pleasure, have recourse to physical pleasures, that is no reason why the latter should be regarded as worthier of choice. Children, too, believe that the things they prize are the most important; so it is natural that just as different things seem valuable to children and adults, so they should seem different also to good and bad men. Thus, as we have often said, it is the things that seem valuable and pleasant to the good man that are really such. But to each individual it is the activity in accordance with his own disposition that is most desirable, and therefore to the good man virtuous activity is most desirable. It follows that happiness does not consist in amusement. Indeed it would be paradoxical if the end were amusement; if we toiled and suffered all our lives long to amuse ourselves. For we choose practically everything for the sake of something else, except happiness, because it is the end. To spend effort and toil for the sake of amusement seems silly and unduly childish; but on the other hand the maxim of Anacharsis,43 ‘Play to work harder’, seems to be on the right lines, because amusement is a form of relaxation, and people need relaxation because they cannot exert themselves continuously. Therefore relaxation is not an end, because it is taken for the sake of the activity. But the happy life seems to be lived in accordance with goodness, and such a 43 A Scythian sage who visited Greece in the early sixth century, and to whom a number of maxims were attributed. [DV: Scythians were a semi-nomadic people to the North, inhabitants of what is now Russia.] 11 Aristotle Ethics life implies seriousness and does not consist in amusing oneself. Also we maintain that serious things are better than those that are merely comical and amusing, and that the activity of a man, or part of a man, is always more serious in proportion as it is better. Therefore the activity of the better part is superior, and eo ipso more conducive to happiness. Anybody can enjoy bodily pleasures - a slave no less than the best of men - but nobody attributes a part in happiness to a slave, unless he also attributes to him a life of his own. 44 Therefore happiness does not consist in occupations of this kind, but in activities in accordance with virtue, as we have said before. Happiness and contemplation vii. If happiness is an activity in accordance with virtue, it is reasonable to assume that it is in accordance with the highest virtue, and this will be the virtue of the best part of us. Whether this is the intellect or something else that we regard as naturally ruling and guiding us, and possessing insight into things noble and divine – either as being actually divine itself or as being more divine than any other part of us – it is the activity of this part, in accordance with the virtue proper to it, that will be perfect happiness. We have already said that it is a contemplative activity. This may be regarded as consonant both with our earlier arguments and with the truth. For contemplation is both the highest form of activity (since the intellect is the highest thing in us, and the objects that it apprehends are the highest things that can be known), and also it is the most continuous, because we are more capable of continuous contemplation than we are of any practical activity. Also we assume that happiness must contain an admixture of pleasure; now activity in accordance with philosophic wisdom is admittedly the most pleasant of the virtuous activities; at any rate philosophy is held to entail pleasures that are marvellous in purity and permanence; and it stands to reason that those who possess knowledge pass their time more pleasantly than those who are still in pursuit of it. Again, the quality that we call self-sufficiency will belong in the highest degree to the contemplative activity. The wise man, no less than the just one and all the rest, requires the necessaries of life; but, given an adequate supply of these, the just man also needs people with and towards whom he can perform just actions, and similarly with the temperate man, the brave man, and each of the others; but the wise man can practise contemplation by himself, and the wiser he is, the more he can do it. No doubt he does it better with the help of fellow-workers; but for all that he is the most self-sufficient of men. Again, contemplation would seem to be the only activity that is appreciated for its own sake; because nothing is gained from it except the act of contemplation, whereas from practical activities we expect to gain something more or less over and above the action. Since happiness is thought to imply leisure, it must be an intellectual, not a practical activity Also it is commonly believed that happiness depends on leisure; because we occupy ourselves so that we may have leisure, just as we make war in order that we may live at peace. Now the exercise of the practical virtues takes place in politics or in warfare, and these professions seem to have no place for leisure. This is certainly true of the military profession, for nobody chooses to make war or provokes it for the sake of making war; a man would be regarded as a bloodthirsty monster if he made his friends45 into enemies in order to bring about battles and slaughter. The politician’s profession also makes leisure impossible, since besides the business of politics it aims at securing positions of power and honour, or the 44 45 Which he does not; cf. Politics I 280a32. i.e. friendly states (cf. I 157a26). 12 Aristotle Ethics happiness of the politician himself and of his fellow-citizens - a happiness separate from politics, and one which we clearly pursue as separate. If, then, politics and warfare, although pre-eminent in nobility and grandeur among practical activities in accordance with goodness, are incompatible with leisure and, not being desirable in themselves, are directed towards some other end, whereas the activity of the intellect is considered to excel46 in seriousness, taking as it does the form of contemplation, and to aim at no other end beyond itself, and to possess a pleasure peculiar to itself, which intensifies its activity; and if it is evident that self-sufficiency and leisuredness and such freedom from fatigue as is humanly possible, together with all the other attributes assigned to the supremely happy man, are those that accord with this activity; then this activity will be the perfect happiness for man - provided that it is allowed a full span of life; for nothing that pertains to happiness is incomplete. Life on this plane is not too high for the divine element But such a life will be too high for human attainment; for any man who lives it will do so not as a human being but in virtue of something divine within him, and in proportion as this divine element is superior to the composite being,47 so will its activity be superior to that of the other kind of virtue.48 So if the intellect is divine compared with man, the life of the intellect must be divine compared with the life of a human being. And we ought not to listen to those who warn us that ‘man should think the thoughts of man’, or ‘mortal thoughts fit mortal minds’;49 but we ought, so far as in us lies, to put on immortality, and do all that we can to, live in conformity with the highest that is in us; for even if it is small in bulk, in power and preciousness it far excels all the rest. Indeed it would seem that this is the true self of the individual, since it is the authoritative and better part of him; so it would be an odd thing if a man chose to live someone else’s life instead of his own. Moreover what we said above will apply here too: that what is best and most pleasant for any given creature-is that which is proper to it. Therefore for man, too, the best and most pleasant life is the life of the intellect, since the intellect is in the fullest sense the man. So this life will also be the happiest. 46 To excel other leisured occupations. Probably composite soul, although the word (suntheton) is generally used of the composite whole consisting of soul and body. 48 Moral virtue. 49 Cf. Rhetoric 1394b24, Pindar, Isthmians v.20; similar maxims are common in the Greek dramatists. 47 13 Epicurus Letter to Menoeceus Epicurus LETTER TO MENOECEUS Epicurus to Menoeceus, greetings: Let no one be slow to seek wisdom when he is young nor weary in the search of it when he has grown old. For no age is too early or too late for the health of the soul. And to say that the season for studying philosophy has not yet come, or that it is past and gone, is like saying that the season for happiness is not yet or that it is now no more. Therefore, both old and young alike ought to seek wisdom, the former in order that, as age comes over him, he may be young in good things because of the grace of what has been, and the latter in order that, while he is young, he may at the same time be old, because he has no fear of the things which are to come. So we must exercise ourselves in the things which bring happiness, since, if that be present, we have everything, and, if that be absent, all our actions are directed towards attaining it. Those things which without ceasing I have declared unto you, do them, and exercise yourself in them, holding them to be the elements of right life. First believe that God is a living being immortal and blessed, according to the notion of a god indicated by the common sense of mankind; and so believing, you shall not affirm of him anything that is foreign to his immortality or that is repugnant to his blessedness. Believe about him whatever may uphold both his blessedness and his immortality. For there are gods, and the knowledge of them is manifest; but they are not such as the multitude believe, seeing that men do not steadfastly maintain the notions they form respecting them. Not the man who denies the gods worshipped by the multitude, but he who affirms of the gods what the multitude believes about them is truly impious. For the utterances of the multitude about the gods are not true preconceptions but false assumptions; hence it is that the greatest evils happen to the wicked and the greatest blessings happen to the good from the hand of the gods, seeing that they are always favourable to their own good qualities and take pleasure in men like themselves, but reject as alien whatever is not of their kind. Accustom yourself to believing that death is nothing to us, for good and evil imply the capacity for sensation, and death is the privation of all sentience; therefore a correct understanding that death is nothing to us makes the mortality of life enjoyable, not by adding to life a limitless time, but by taking away the yearning after immortality. For life has no terrors for him who has thoroughly understood that there are no terrors for him in ceasing to live. Foolish, therefore, is the man who says that he fears death, not because it will pain when it comes, but because it pains in the prospect. Whatever causes no annoyance when it is present, causes only a groundless pain in the expectation. Death, therefore, the most awful of evils, is nothing to us, seeing that, when we are, death is not come, and, when death is come, we are not. It is nothing, then, either to the living or to the dead, for with the living it is not and the dead exist no longer. But in the world, at one time men shun death as the greatest of all evils, and at another time choose it as a respite from the evils in life. The wise man does not deprecate life nor does he fear the cessation of life. The thought of life is no offence to him, nor is the cessation of life regarded as an evil. And even as men choose of food not merely and simply the larger portion, but the more pleasant, so the wise seek to enjoy the time which is most pleasant and not merely that which is longest. And he who admonishes the young to live well and the old to make a good end speaks foolishly, not merely because of the desirability of life, but 14 Epicurus Letter to Menoeceus because the same exercise at once teaches to live well and to die well. Much worse is he who says that it were good not to be born, but when once one is born to pass quickly through the gates of Hades. For if he truly believes this, why does he not depart from life? It would be easy for him to do so once he were firmly convinced. If he speaks only in jest, his words are foolishness as those who hear him do not believe. We must remember that the future is neither wholly ours nor wholly not ours, so that neither must we count upon it as quite certain to come nor despair of it as quite certain not to come. We must also reflect that of desires some are natural, others are groundless; and that of the natural some are necessary as well as natural, and some natural only. And of the necessary desires some are necessary if we are to be happy, some if the body is to be rid of uneasiness, some if we are even to live. He who has a clear and certain understanding of these things will direct every preference and aversion toward securing health of body and tranquillity of mind, seeing that this is the sum and end of a blessed life. For the end of all our actions is to be free from pain and fear, and, when once we have attained all this, the tempest of the soul is laid; seeing that the living creature has no need to go in search of something that is lacking, nor to look for anything else by which the good of the soul and of the body will be fulfilled. When we are pained because of the absence of pleasure, then, and then only, do we feel the need of pleasure. Wherefore we call pleasure the alpha and omega of a blessed life. Pleasure is our first and kindred good. It is the starting-point of every choice and of every aversion, and to it we come back, inasmuch as we make feeling the rule by which to judge of every good thing. And since pleasure is our first and native good, for that reason we do not choose every pleasure whatsoever, but will often pass over many pleasures when a greater annoyance ensues from them. And often we consider pains superior to pleasures when submission to the pains for a long time brings us as a consequence a greater pleasure. While therefore all pleasure because it is naturally akin to us is good, not all pleasure is should be chosen, just as all pain is an evil and yet not all pain is to be shunned. It is, however, by measuring one against another, and by looking at the conveniences and inconveniences, that all these matters must be judged. Sometimes we treat the good as an evil, and the evil, on the contrary, as a good. Again, we regard independence of outward things as a great good, not so as in all cases to use little, but so as to be contented with little if we have not much, being honestly persuaded that they have the sweetest enjoyment of luxury who stand least in need of it, and that whatever is natural is easily procured and only the vain and worthless hard to win. Plain fare gives as much pleasure as a costly diet, when once the pain of want has been removed, while bread and water confer the highest possible pleasure when they are brought to hungry lips. To habituate one’s self, therefore, to simple and inexpensive diet supplies all that is needful for health, and enables a man to meet the necessary requirements of life without shrinking, and it places us in a better condition when we approach at intervals a costly fare and renders us fearless of fortune. When we say, then, that pleasure is the end and aim, we do not mean the pleasures of the prodigal or the pleasures of sensuality, as we are understood to do by some through ignorance, prejudice, or willful misrepresentation. By pleasure we mean the absence of pain in the body and of trouble in the soul. It is not an unbroken succession of drinking-bouts and of revelry, not sexual lust, not the enjoyment of the fish and other delicacies of a luxurious table, which produce a pleasant life; it is sober reasoning, searching out the grounds of every choice and avoidance, and banishing those beliefs through which the greatest tumults take 15 Epicurus Letter to Menoeceus possession of the soul. Of all this, the beginning and the greatest good is wisdom. Therefore wisdom is a more precious thing even than philosophy; from it spring all the other virtues, for it teaches that we cannot live pleasantly without living wisely, honourably, and justly; nor live wisely, honourably, and justly without living pleasantly. For the virtues have grown into one with a pleasant life, and a pleasant life is inseparable from them. Who, then, is superior in your judgment to such a man? He holds a holy belief concerning the gods, and is altogether free from the fear of death. He has diligently considered the end fixed by nature, and understands how easily the limit of good things can be reached and attained, and how either the duration or the intensity of evils is but slight. Fate, which some introduce as sovereign over all things, he scorns, affirming rather that some things happen of necessity, others by chance, others through our own agency. For he sees that necessity destroys responsibility and that chance is inconstant; whereas our own actions are autonomous, and it is to them that praise and blame naturally attach. It were better, indeed, to accept the legends of the gods than to bow beneath that yoke of destiny which the natural philosophers have imposed. The one holds out some faint hope that we may escape if we honour the gods, while the necessity of the naturalists is deaf to all entreaties. Nor does he hold chance to be a god, as the world in general does, for in the acts of a god there is no disorder; nor to be a cause, though an uncertain one, for he believes that no good or evil is dispensed by chance to men so as to make life blessed, though it supplies the starting-point of great good and great evil. He believes that the misfortune of the wise is better than the prosperity of the fool. It is better, in short, that what is well judged in action should not owe its successful issue to the aid of chance. Exercise yourself in these and related precepts day and night, both by yourself and with one who is like-minded; then never, either in waking or in dream, will you be disturbed, but will live as a god among men. For man loses all semblance of mortality by living in the midst of immortal blessings. 16 Cicero De Finibus Marcus Tullius Cicero DE FINIBUS (On Ends or Goals) [Extracts drawn from B. Inwood and C. P. Gerson, Hellenistic Philosophy, second edition. Hackett Publishing, 1997.] Cicero On Goals 3.16 – 34 16. The school whose views I follow [a Stoic speaks – Cato] holds that every animal, as soon as it is born (for this should be our starting point), is congenial to itself and inclined to preserve itself and its constitution, and to like those things which preserve that constitution; but it finds uncongenial its own death and those things which seem to threaten it. They confirm this by [noting] that before pleasure or pain can affect them, babies seek what is salutary and spurn what is not, and this would not happen unless they loved their constitution and feared death. They could not, however, desire anything unless they had a perception of themselves and consequently loved themselves. From this one ought to see that the principle [of human action] is derived from self-love. 17. Most Stoics do not think that pleasure should be classed among the primary natural things; and I strongly agree with them, for fear that, if nature seemed to have classed pleasure among the primary objects of impulse, then many shameful consequences would follow. It seems, however, to be a sufficient argument as to why we love those things which were first accepted because of nature (to say) that there is no one (when he has a choice) who would not prefer to have all the parts of his body in a sound condition to having them dwarfed or twisted, though equally useful. They think, moreover, that acts of cognition (which we may call grasps or perceptions or, if these terms are either displeasing or harder to understand, katalepseis) are, then, to be accepted for their own sake, since they have in themselves something which as it were includes and contains the truth. And this can be seen in babies, who, we see, are delighted if they figure something out for themselves, even if it does not do them any good. 18. We also think that the crafts are to be taken for their own sake, both because there is in them something worth taking and also because these consist of acts of cognition and contain something which is rational and methodical. They think, though, that we find false assent more uncongenial than anything else which is contrary to nature.... 20. Let us move on, then, since we began from these natural principles and what follows should be consistent with them. There follows this primary division: them, say that what has value (we are to call it that, I think) is that which is either itself in accordance with nature or productive of it, so that it is worthy of selection because it has a certain ‘weight’ which is worth valuing (and this value they call axia); by contrast, what is opposite to the above is disvalued. The starting point being, then, so constituted that what is natural is to be taken for its own sake and what is unnatural is to be rejected, the first appropriate action (for that is what I call kathekon) is that it should preserve itself in its natural constitution; and then that it should retain what is according to nature and reject what is contrary to nature. After this [pattern of] selection and rejection is discovered, there then follows appropriate selection, and then constant [appropriate] selection, and finally [selection] which is stable and in agreement with nature; and here for the first time we begin to have and to understand something which can truly be called good. 21. For man’s first sense of congeniality is to what is according to nature; but as soon as he gets an understanding, or rather a conception (which they call an ennoia) and sees the ordering and, I might say, concord of things which are to be done, he then values that more highly than all those things which he loved in the beginning, and he 17 Cicero De Finibus comes to a conclusion by intelligence and reasoning, with the result that he decides that this is what the highest good for man consists in, which is to be praised and chosen for its own sake. And since it is placed in what the Stoics call homologia, let us call it agreement, if you please. Since, therefore, this constitutes the good, to which all things are to be referred, honourable actions and the honourable itself – which is considered to be the only good – although it arises later [in our lives], nevertheless it is the only thing which is to be chosen in virtue of its own character and value; but none of the primary natural things is to be chosen for its own sake. 22. Since, however, those things which I called appropriate actions proceed from the starting points [established] by nature, it is necessary that they be referred to them; so it is right to say all appropriate actions are referred to acquisition of the natural principles, not however in the sense that this is the highest good, since honourable action is not among the primarily and naturally congenial things. That, as I said, is posterior and arises later. But [such action) is natural and encourages us to choose it much earlier than all the earlier mentioned things. But here one must first remove a misunderstanding, so that no one might think that there are two highest goods. For just as, if it is someone’s purpose to direct a spear or arrow at something, we say that his highest goal is to do everything he can in order to direct it at [the target], in the same sense that we say that our highest goal is a good. The archer in this comparison is to do all that he can to direct [his arrow at the target]; and yet doing all that he can to attain his purpose would be like the highest goal of the sort which we say is the highest good in life; actually striking [the target], though, is as it were to be selected and not to be chosen. 23. Since all appropriate actions proceed from the natural principles, it is necessary that wisdom itself proceed from them as well. But just as it often happens that he who is introduced to someone puts a higher value on the man to whom he is introduced than on the man by whom he was introduced, just so it is in no way surprising that we are first introduced to wisdom by the starting points [established] by nature, but that later on wisdom itself becomes dearer to us than the things which brought us to wisdom. And just as our limbs were given us in such a way that they seem to have been given for the sake of a certain way of life, similarly the impulse in our soul, which is called horme in Greek, seems not to have been given for the sake of any old type of life but for a certain kind of living; and similarly for reason and perfected reason. 24. Just as an actor or dancer has not been assigned just any old [type of delivery or movement but rather a certain definite [type], so too life is to be lived in a certain definite manner, not in any old [manner]. And we call that manner ‘in agreement’ and consonant. And we do not think that wisdom is like navigation or medicine, but rather like the craft of acting or dancing which I just mentioned; thus its goal, i.e., the [proper] execution of the craft, depends on it itself and is not sought outside itself. There is also another point of dissimilarity between wisdom and these crafts, viz. that in them proper actions do not contain all the components [lit. parts] which constitute the art; but things called ‘right’ or ‘rightly done’, if I may call them that, though the Greeks call them katorthomata [morally perfect actions], contain all the features of virtue. Only wisdom is totally self-contained, and this is not the case with the other crafts. 25. But it is misguided to compare the highest goal of medicine or navigation with that of wisdom; for wisdom embraces magnanimity and justice and an ability to judge that everything which happens to a [mere] human being is beneath it – and this does not apply to 18 Cicero De Finibus the rest of the crafts. But no one can possess the very virtues which I just mentioned unless he has firmly decided that there is nothing except what is honourable or shameful which makes a difference or distinguishes one [thing or situation] from another. 26. Let us now see how splendidly, these further points follow from what we have already expounded. So, since the goal is to live consistently and in agreement with nature, it follows necessarily that all wise men always live happy, perfect and fortunate lives, that they are impeded by nothing, hindered by nothing and in need of nothing. The key not only to the doctrines of which I am speaking, but also to our life and fortune is that we should judge that only what is honourable is good. This point can be elaborated and developed fully and copiously, with all the choicest words and profoundest sentiments which rhetorical art can produce; but I prefer the short and pointed syllogisms of the Stoics. 29. What? Could anyone deny that we could never have a man who is of steadfast and reliable spirit, a man you could call brave, unless it is firmly established that pain is not a bad thing? For just as someone who regards death as a bad thing cannot help but fear it, in the same way, no one can be indifferent to and despise something which he regards as bad. Once this point is established and assented to, our next premiss is that magnanimous and stronghearted men are able to despise and ignore everything which fortune can bring to bear against man. Consequently, it is proven that there is nothing bad which is not also shameful. But the man we refer to is lofty and superior, magnanimous, truly brave, looks down on all merely human concerns; the man, I say, whom we wish to produce, whom we are looking for, should certainly have faith in himself and his life, both past and future, and should think well of himself, believing that nothing bad can happen to a wise man. And from this one can again prove the same old point, that only the honourable is good, i.e., that to live happily is to live honourably, i.e., virtuously. 30. I am not unaware that there is a variety of views held by philosophers, by which I mean those who place the highest good, which I call the goal, in the mind. Even though some of them have gone wrong, still I prefer them, whatever their views, who locate the highest good in the mind and virtue, to those three who have separated the highest good from virtue by placing either pleasure or freedom from pain or the primary natural things among the highest goods; I even prefer them to the other three who thought that virtue would be deficient without some addition and so added to it one or other of the three things mentioned above. 31. But those who think that the highest good is to live with knowledge and who claim that things are absolutely indifferent and that this was why the wise man would be happy, because he did not prefer one thing to any other in even the slightest degree – they are particularly absurd; so too are those who, as certain Academics are said to have held, believe that the highest good and greatest duty of the wise man is to resist his presentations and steadfastly to withhold his assent. Normally one gives a full answer to each of these views separately. But there is no need to prolong what is perfectly clear; and what is more obvious than that the very prudence which we are seeking and praising would he utterly destroyed if there were no grounds for choosing between those which are contrary to nature and those which are according to nature. When we eliminate, therefore, those views I have mentioned and those which are similar to them, all that is left is [the view] that the highest good is to live by making use of a knowledge of what happens naturally, selecting what is according to nature and rejecting what is contrary to nature, i.e., to live consistently and in agreement with nature. 32. When in the other crafts something is said to be craftsmanlike, one must suppose that what is meant is something which is, in a way posterior and consequent, which they [the 19 Cicero De Finibus Greeks] call epigennematikon [supervenient]; but when we say that something is done wisely we mean that it is from the outset thoroughly right. For whatever is undertaken by a wise man must immediately be complete in all its parts; for it is in this that we find what we call that which is worth choosing. For just as it is a [moral] mistake to betray one’s country, to attack one’s parents, to rob temples (and these are [moral] mistakes because of the outcome [of the action]), so too it is a [moral] mistake to fear, to grieve, and to suffer desire, even quite independently of their outcome. Rather, just as the latter are not dependent on their posterior consequences, but are [moral] mistakes right from the outset, similarly the actions which proceed from virtue are to be judged to be right from the outset and not by their ultimate completion. … 62. Again, they think it important to understand that nature has brought it about that children are loved by their parents. For from this starting point we can follow the development of the shared society which unites the human race. One ought to see this first of all from the form and organs of the body which show that nature has a rational scheme for reproduction; but it would be inconsistent for nature to want offspring to be born and yet not to see to it that they are loved once they are born. The power of nature can be seen even in the beasts; when we see the effort they go to in bearing and rearing their offspring, we seem to be listening to the voice of nature herself. So, just as it is obvious that we naturally shrink from pain, so too it is apparent that we are driven by nature herself to love those whom we bear. 63. From this it develops naturally that there is among men a common and natural congeniality of men with each other, with the result that it is right for them to feel that other men, just because they are men, are not alien to them.... So we are naturally suited to [living in] gatherings, groups and states. 64. They also hold that the cosmos is ruled by the will of the gods, that it is like a city or state shared by gods and men, and that each and every one of us is a part of this cosmos. From which it naturally follows that we put the common advantage ahead of our own. For just as the laws put the well-being of all ahead of the well-being of individuals, so too the good and wise man, who is obedient to the laws and not unaware of his civic duty, looks out for the advantage of all more than for that of any one person or his own. 67. But just as they think that the bonds of justice unite men with each other, so too they deny that there is any bond of justice between man and beast. Chrysippus expressed it well, saying that everything else was born for the sake of men and gods, but they were born for the sake of their own community and society, with the result that men can use beasts for their own advantage without injustice… 70. They also think that friendship should be cultivated because it falls into the class of beneficial things. Although some [Stoics] say that in a friendship a friend’s reason is just as dear to the wise man as is his own, while others say that each man’s reason is dearer to himself, even this latter group admits that to deprive someone of something in order to appropriate it for oneself is inconsistent with justice, which is a virtue we are naturally committed to. So the school I am speaking of does not at all approve of the view that justice or friendship should be welcomed or approved of because of its advantages. For the very same advantages could just as well undermine and overthrow them. Indeed, neither justice nor friendship can exist at all unless they are chosen for their own sake. 20 Martin Luther King What is Man? Martin Luther King ‘What is Man?’ From ‘THE MEASURE OF A MAN’ (Fortress Press, Philadelphia, 1959) [Number within square brackets refer to page numbers in this edition.] he question “What is man?” is one of the most important questions confronting any generation. The whole political, social, and economic structure of a society is largely determined by its answer to this pressing question. Indeed, the conflict which we witness in the world today between totalitarianism and democracy is at bottom a conflict over the question “What is man?”1 T In our generation the asking of this question has risen to extensive proportions. But although there is widespread agreement in asking the question, there is fantastic disagreement in answering it. For instance, there are those who look upon man as little more than an animal. They would say that man is a cosmic accident, that his whole life can be explained by matter in motion. Then there are those who would lift man almost to the position of a god. They would probably agree with Shakespeare’s Hamlet, [11] What a piece of work is man! How noble in faculty! How infinite in reason; in form and moving how express and admirable; in apprehension how like a God; in action how like an angel! The beauty of the world, the paragon of animals.2 There are still others who would seek to be a little more realistic about man. They would avoid the extremes of a pessimistic naturalism and an optimistic humanism and seek to combine the truths of both. They see within man a strange dualism, something of a dichotomy. So they would cry out with Carlyle, “There are depths in man that go down to the lowest hell, and heights that reach the highest heaven, for are not both heaven and hell made out of him everlasting miracle and mystery that he is?”3 1 King is preaching in the context of the Cold War and consequently when he speaks of ‘totalitarianism’ he presumably has communism principally in mind. He may also be thinking of Fascism and the Second World War. Communism and fascism have in common collectivist accounts of human nature; by contrast, democracy tends to be individualistic. King may have other differences in mind. 2 King makes no acknowledgement of Hamlet’s irony in this speech. It is a disconcerting characteristic of this style of preaching to quote Biblical and other texts with scant regard for the original meaning or context. Here is a more representative selection from Hamlet’s speech: I have of late – whereof I know not – lost all my mirth, foregone all custom of exercises; and indeed it goes so heavily with my disposition that this goodly frame the earth, seems to me like a sterile promontory; the most excellent canopy the air, look you, this proud o’erhanging firmament, this majestical roof fretted with golden fire, why it appears no other thing to me than a foul and pestilent congregation of vapours. What a piece of work is a man! How noble in reason! How infinite in faculty! In form and moving, how express and admirable! In action how like an angel! In apprehension, how like a god! The beauty of the world! The paragon of animals! And yet to me, what is this quintessence of dust? (Shakespeare, Hamlet, Act II, sc 2). Hardly a ringing endorsement of human nature! This raises a difficulty. Where are we to find the optimistic humanism that King identifies in his sermon? Presumably it is the same Renaissance humanism that is Hamlet’s target. 3 “There are depths in man that go the length of lowest Hell, as there are heights that reach highest Heaven; – for are not both Heaven and Hell made out of him, made by him, everlasting Miracle 21 Martin Luther King What is Man? One day the psalmist4 looked up and noticed the vastness of the cosmic order. He noticed the infinite expanse of the solar [12] system; he noticed the beautiful stars; he gazed at the moon with all its scintillating beauty, and he said in the midst of all of this, “What is man?” He comes forth with an answer: “Thou hast made him a little lower than the angels, and crowned him with glory and honour.” Goodspeed, Moffatt, and the Revised Standard Version would say, “Thou hast made him a little less than divine, a little less than God, and crowned him with glory and honour.”5 It is this realistic position that I would like to use as a basis of our thinking together and our meditation on the question “What is man? Now let us notice first that man is a biological being with a physical body. This is why the psalmist says, “Thou hast made him less than God.” We don’t think of God as a being with a body. God is a being of pure spirit, lifted above the categories of [13] time and space; but man, being less than God, is in time. He is in nature, and he can never disown his kinship with animate nature. The psalmist goes on to say that God made man that way. Since God made him that way there is nothing wrong with it. We read in the book of Genesis that everything God makes is good; therefore there is nothing wrong with having a body.6 This is one of the things that distinguish the Christian doctrine of man from the Greek doctrine. The Greeks, under the impetus of Plato, felt that the body was evil, almost inherently depraved, and the soul could never reach its full maturity until it broke loose from the prison of the body.7 This is not Christian doctrine, for Christianity does not see the body as the principle of evil; it says the will is the principle of evil. So the body in Christianity is sacred and [14] significant. That means in any doctrine of man that we must be concerned with man’s physical well-being. It may be true that man cannot live by bread alone, but the mere fact that Jesus added the “alone” means that man cannot live without bread.8 Religion must never overlook this, and any religion that professes to be concerned about the souls of men and is not concerned about the economic conditions that damn the soul, the social conditions that corrupt men, and the city governments that cripple them, is a dry, dead, do-nothing religion in need of new blood.9 For it overlooks the basic fact that man is a biological being with a physical body. This must stand as a principle in any doctrine of man. But this isn’t the only part, and we must never stop here if our doctrine of man is to be realistic and thoroughly Christian. Some people stop here. They are the naturalists or [15] the materialists; they are the Marxists; and they would see man merely as an animal. Some years ago a group of chemists who had a flair for statistics decided to work out the worth of man’s body in terms of the market values of that day. They got together and did a lot and Mystery as he is?” Thomas Carlyle (1795-1881), The French Revolution, Book II, chapter 3.I.iv. 4 Psalmist = the author of the biblical Book of Psalms. Traditionally King David is the author of most of the Psalms, including this one. Martin Luther King is referring to Psalm 8, verse 5. 5 Good speed and Moffatt are commentators on the Bible. The Revised Standard Version is a commonly used English translation of the Bible. 6 King has his sights trained on certain strains within Christianity – Protestant and Catholic – that seem to regard the body as intrinsically evil. This, he claims, is a corruption of genuine Christianity. He is surely right and yet the view would not be so persistent if it did not have some Biblical support. 7 While there is some justice in this as an account of Plato, it is a gross oversimplification to attribute this view to the Greeks in general. 8 “Man does not live by bread alone, but by every word that proceeds from the mouth of God.” (Matthew 4: 4; cf. Luke 4: 4). 9 Again King has his sights trained on certain of his fellow Christians. He is critical of the view that religion has no business with political action. 22 Martin Luther King What is Man? of work, and finally they came to this conclusion: The average man has enough fat in him to make about seven bars of soap, enough iron to make a medium-sized nail, enough sugar to fill a shaker, enough lime to whitewash a chicken coop, enough phosphorus for about 2,220 match tips, and enough magnesium for a dose of magnesia. When all of this was added up in terms of the market values of that day it came to about ninety-eight cents. Now, I guess, since the standards of living are a little higher today, you could get about a dollar ninety-eight for the average man. This is interesting. Think about it. Man’s [16] bodily stuff is worth only ninety-eight cents. But can we explain the whole of man in terms of ninety-eight cents? Can we explain the artistic genius of a Michelangelo in terms of ninety-eight cents? Can we explain the poetic genius of a Shakespeare in terms of ninety-eight cents? Can we explain the spiritual genius of Jesus of Nazareth in terms of ninety-eight cents? Can we explain the mystery of the human soul in terms of ninety-eight cents? Oh, no. There is something within man that cannot be explained in terms of dollars and cents. There is something within man that cannot be reduced to chemical and biological terms, for man is more than a tiny vagary of whirling electrons. He is more than a wisp of smoke from a limitless smouldering. Man is a child of God. This brings us to another basic point in the doctrine of man – that man is a being of [17] spirit. This is what the psalmist means when he says, “Thou hast crowned him with glory and honour.” Man has rational capacity; man has a mind; man can reason. This distinguishes him from the lower animals. And so, somehow, man is in nature, and yet he is above nature; he is in time, and yet he is above time; he is in space, and yet he is above space. This means that he can do things that lower animals could never do. He can think a poem and write it; he can think a symphony and compose it; he can think up a great civilization and create it. Man is God’s marvellous creation, crowned with glory and honour, and because of this you can’t quite hem him in. You can put him in Bedford’s prison, but somehow his mind will break out through the bars to scratch across the pages of history a Pilgrim’s Progress.10 You can bring him down in his wretched old age, with his body broken [18] down and his vision all but gone, and yet in the form of a Handel, he will look up and imagine that he hears the very angels singing, and he will come back and scratch across the pages of history a “Hallelujah Chorus”.11 This is man. He is God’s marvellous creation. Through his mind he can leap oceans, break through walls, and transcend the categories of time and space. The stars may be marvellous, but not so marvellous as the mind of man that comprehended them. This is what the biblical writers mean when they say that man is made in the image of God. Man has rational capacity; he has the unique ability to have fellowship with God. Man is a being of spirit. There is another principle that must go in any doctrine of man that is realistic. It is the recognition that man is a sinner. Man is a free being made in the image of God. He is [21] different from lower animals. He is not guided merely by instinct. He has the ability to choose between alternatives, so he can choose the good or the evil, the high or the low. As we look at man, we must admit that he has misused his freedom. Some of the image of God is gone. Therefore, man is a sinner in need of God’s divine grace. So often we try to deny A classic work of English devotional literature, Pilgrim’s Progress was written by John Bunyan (1628-1688). It is the classic expression of Puritan spirituality – incidentally, a severe version of that ‘anti-body’ strain of Christianity that King criticized earlier in the sermon. After the end of the English Civil War and the Restoration of the Monarchy under Charles II, Bunyan spent 12 years in prison as a ‘non-conformist’ – for holding a service not in accordance with the practices of the Church of England. 11 A famous chorus from the oratorio Messiah, written by George Frederic Handel. 10 23 Martin Luther King What is Man? this fact. We hate to face it. There are times even in our theological thinking when we have become all too sentimental about man. We have explained his shortcomings in terms of errors or lags of nature. We have sometimes felt that progress was inevitable, and that man was gradually evolving into a higher state of perfection. But if we are honest and realistic, we must admit that it isn’t like that, for man is a sinner. We take the new depth psychology, and misuse it to explain our bad [22] deeds. We find ourselves saying that they are due to phobias, to inner conflicts. Or, in Freudian terms, we say that man’s misdeeds are due to a conflict between the id and the superego.12 But when we look at ourselves hard enough we come to see that the conflict is between God and man. There is something within all of us that causes us to see the truth in Plato’s statement that the personality is like a charioteer with two headstrong horses, each wanting to go in different directions.13 There is something within all of us that causes us to cry out with Augustine, “Lord, make me pure, but not yet.”14 There is something within all of us that causes us to affirm with the apostle Paul, “The good that I would, I do not; and the evil that I would not, I do.”15 And so in a real sense the “isness” of our present nature is out of harmony with the eternal “oughtness” that forever confronts us. We know how to love, and yet we hate. We take the precious lives that God has given us and throw them away in riotous living. We are unfaithful to those to whom we should be faithful.16 We are disloyal to those ideals to which we should be loyal. “All we like sheep have gone as astray”.17 I don’t know about you, but when I look at myself hard enough I don’t feel like crying with the Pharisee, “Lord, I thank thee that I am not like other men,” but I find myself crying out, “Lord, be merciful unto me, a sinner.”18 We are sinners in need of God’s divine grace. When 12 Freud distinguished the mind into three parts, the ego, the superego and the id. The Ego is our familiar self – the person that you call ‘I’. The Id is the realm of instincts and desires – these desires are generally unconscious. The Superego is the part of mind that has internalised moral and social norms. If you like, it is the Freudian equivalent of the conscience. To put it very crudely, who we are – our Ego – is a compromise between the forces of the Id and the Superego. 13 Plato introduces this image in the Phaedrus (246aff). Plato’s three-part division of the soul is clearly an inspiration for Freud’s division of the mind. 14 Augustine Confessions, Book 8, chapter 7. “Give me chastity and continence but not yet”. Augustine (354-430CE) was the greatest of the Latin Church Fathers. The so-called Fathers of the Church are influential writers who worked during the first 1,000 years of the Christian Church. It was during this period that many of the Church’s central doctrines were formulated. Consequently, these writers have a special authority within the mainstream Christian Churches, Orthodox, Catholic and Protestant. Most of the important Church Fathers were Greek speakers from the Eastern Mediterranean but a few wrote in Latin. Augustine was born in Hippo in North Africa and his Confessions chronicle his search for the truth from the Manichaean faith through Neo-Platonist philosophy to Christianity. During his youth he kept a mistress and chastity was a major obstacle to his conversion. Augustine’s doctrines were very influential during the Reformation. The anti body strand of Christianity that King has already criticized owes much to Augustine. 15 Romans 7: 19. “For I do not do the good I want, but the evil I do not want is what I do.” 16 There have been persistent claims that, like Augustine, King had personal difficulties with the Seventh Commandment – “Thou shalt not commit adultery”. 17 Isaiah 53: 6. This text is used in another chorus from Handel’s Messiah. 18 King is referring to one of Jesus’ parables. Here is the full text: “(10) Two men went up into the temple to pray, one a Pharisee and the other a tax collector. (11) The Pharisee stood and prayed thus with himself, `God, I thank thee that I am not like other men, extortioners, unjust, adulterers, or even like this tax collector. (12) I fast twice a week, I give tithes of all that I get.’ (13) But the tax collector, standing far off, would not even lift up his eyes to heaven, but beat his breast, saying, ‘God, be merciful to me a sinner!’ (14) I tell you, this man went down to his house justified rather than the other; for every one who exalts himself will be humbled, but he who humbles himself will be exalted.” (Luke 18: 10-14) 24 Martin Luther King What is Man? we come to our collective lives, our sin is even greater. One theologian could write a book entitled Moral Man and Immoral Society.19 In our collective lives our sin rises to even greater heights. See how we treat each other. Races trample over races; nations trample over [26] nations. We go to war and destroy the values and the lives that God has given us. We leave the battlefields of the world painted with blood, and we end up with wars that burden us with national debts higher than mountains of gold, filling our nations with orphans and widows, sending thousands of men home psychologically deranged and physically handicapped. This is the tragic plight of man. As we look at all of that, we know that man isn’t made for that. We know that man is made for the stars, created for the everlasting, born for eternity. We know that man is crowned with glory and honour, and so long as he lives on the low level he will be frustrated, disillusioned, and bewildered. Jesus told a parable one day, the parable of the prodigal son. 20 He talked about a boy who left home and went away into a far country, where he wasted his substance and even his character. Then a famine broke out, and this boy ended up in a hog pen. There are many insights to be gained from this parable. One, I think, is this: that man is not made for the far country of evil. Whenever he moves away from his Father’s house he finds himself facing a famine, and he finds himself frustrated and disillusioned. But the parable does not end there. That’s the beauty of it. We read that one day the boy came to himself and decided to rise up and go back home. We watch him as he travels up the dusty road that he had once come down. He had a little speech that he had made up: “I am not worthy of being called thy son.” But he did not get a chance to make that speech, because a loving father saw him from afar and ran out to the boy with outstretched arms, saying, “I am happy to have you back home. Come home, I still love you.” [29] This is the glory of our religion: that when man decides to rise up from his mistakes, from his sin, from his evil, there is a loving God saying, “Come home, I still love you.” Oh, I can hear a voice crying out today, saying to Western civilization: “You strayed away to the far country of colonialism and imperialism. You have trampled over one billion six hundred million of your coloured brothers in Africa and Asia. But, O Western Civilization, if you will come to yourself, rise up, and come back home, I will take you in.” It seems that I can hear a voice saying to America: “You started out right. You wrote in your Declaration of Independence that all men are created equal and endowed by their Creator with certain inalienable rights. Among these are life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness.’ But, America, you [30] strayed away from that sublime principle. You left the house of your great heritage and strayed away into a far country of segregation and discrimination. 21 You have trampled over sixteen million of your brothers. You have deprived them of the basic goods of life. You have taken from them their self-respect and their sense of dignity. You have treated them as if they were things rather than persons.22 Because of this a famine has broken out in By the influential U.S. theologian Reinhold Niebuhr, published in 1932. “In this classic study, Niebuhr draws a sharp distinction between the moral and social behaviour of individuals versus social groups – national, racial, and economic. He shows how this distinction then requires political policies which a purely individualistic ethic will necessarily find embarrassing.” http://www.religion-online.org/ 20 Luke 15: 11 – 32. 21 Not surprisingly, King concludes with his own spiritual and political mission – the abolition of segregation and discrimination. There is also an implicit exhortation to his fellow Blacks to act in a spirit of forgiveness and non-violence. 22 This turn of phrase echoes one version of Kant’s Categorical Imperative: “So act as to treat humanity … as an end and never as a means only.” (Groundwork towards a Metaphysic of Morals) 19 25 Martin Luther King What is Man? your land. In the midst of all your material wealth, you are spiritually and morally povertystricken, unable to speak to the conscience of this world. America, in this famine situation, if ill come to yourself and rise up and you will decide to come back home, I will take you in, for you are made for something high and something noble and something good.” To every man there openeth A Way, and Ways, and a Way, And the High Soul climbs the High Way, And the Low Soul gropes the Low, And in between, on the misty flats, The rest drift to and fro. But to every man there openeth A High Way, and a Low, And every man decideth The Way his soul shall go. (John Oxenham23) 0 God, our gracious heavenly Father, we thank thee for the inspiration of Jesus the Christ, who came to this world to show us the way. And grant that we will see in that life the fact that we are made for that which is high and noble and good. Help us to live in line with that high calling, that great destiny. In the name of Jesus we pray. Amen.24 23 24 According to Kant, to treat someone as a means is to treat them as a thing. We will consider Kant further when we read Sartre and Murdoch. Pseudonym of William Arthur Dunkerley, English poet, 1852-1941. It is traditional for a Christian sermon to end with a prayer. Non-Christians may also be puzzled by the phrase ‘Jesus the Christ’. Christ is not a surname but a title meaning ‘Anointed’. 26 Friedrich Nietzsche The Gay Science Friedrich Nietzsche THE GAY SCIENCE Book V: We Fearless Ones [Translated by Walter Kaufman. Vintage Books, 1974. Unless otherwise noted, footnotes derive from this edition.] §343: The meaning of our cheerfulness.1 – The greatest recent event – that “God is dead,”2 that the belief in the Christian god has become unbelievable3 – is already beginning to cast its first shadows over Europe. For the few at least, whose eyes – the suspicion in whose eyes is strong and subtle enough for this spectacle, some sun seems to have set and some ancient and profound trust has been turned into doubt; to them our old world must appear daily more like evening, more mistrustful, stranger, “older.” But in the main one may say: The event itself is far too great, too distant, too remote from the multitude’s capacity for comprehension even for the tidings of it to be thought of as having arrived as yet. Much less may one suppose that many people know as yet what this event really means – and how much must collapse now that this faith has been undermined because it was built upon this faith, propped up by it, grown into it; for example, the whole of our European morality. This long plenitude and sequence of breakdown, destruction, ruin, and cataclysm that is now impending – who could guess enough of it today to be compelled to play the teacher and advance proclaimer of this monstrous logic of terror, the prophet of a gloom and an eclipse of the sun whose like has probably never yet occurred on earth? Even we born guessers of riddles who are, as it were, waiting on the mountains,4 posted between today and tomorrow, stretched in the contradiction between today and tomorrow, we firstlings and premature births of the coming century, to whom the shadows that must soon envelop Europe really should have appeared by now – why is it that even we look forward to the approaching gloom without any real sense of involvement and above all without any worry and fear for ourselves?5 Are we perhaps still too much under the impression of the initial consequences of this event – and these initial consequences, the consequences for ourselves, are quite the opposite of what one might perhaps expect: They are not at all sad and gloomy but rather like a new and scarcely describable kind of light, happiness, relief, exhilaration, encouragement, dawn. Indeed, we philosophers and “free spirits” feel, when we hear the news that “the old god is dead,” as if a new dawn shone on us; our heart overflows with gratitude, amazement, premonitions, expectation. At long last the horizon appears free to us again, even if it should not be bright; at long last our ships may venture out again, venture out to face any danger; all the daring of the lover of knowledge is permitted again; the sea, our sea, lies open again; perhaps there has never yet been such an “open sea.” – §344: How we, too, are still pious. – In science convictions have no rights of citizenship, as one says with good reason. Only when they decide to descend to the modesty of hypotheses, of a provisional experimental point of view, of a regulative fiction, they may be granted admission and even a certain value in the that realm of knowledge – though always with the restriction that they remain under police supervision, under the police of mistrust. – But does this not mean, if you consider it more precisely, that a conviction may obtain admission to 1 2 3 Heiterkeit: a reference to the title and tenor of The Gay Science. Cf. sections 108fr. and 125 above, as well as 108n. This clause is clearly offered as an explanation of “God is dead.” 4 Posted in high places so that they will see as soon as possible what is approaching from a distance. 5 A gloss on the title of Book V. 27 Friedrich Nietzsche The Gay Science science only when it ceases to be a conviction? Would it not be the first step in the discipline of the scientific spirit that one would not permit oneself any more convictions? Probably this is so; only we still have to ask: To make it possible for this discipline to begin, must there not be some commanding and prior conviction – even one that is so commanding and unconditional that it sacrifices all other convictions to itself? We see that science also rests on a faith; there simply is no science “without presuppositions.” The question whether truth is needed must not only have been affirmed in advance, but affirmed to such a degree that the principle, the faith, the conviction finds expression: “Nothing is needed more than truth, and in relation to it everything else has only second-rate value.” This unconditional will to truth – what is it? Is it the will not to allow oneself to be deceived? Or is it the will not to deceive? For the will to truth could be interpreted in the second way, too – if only the special case “I do not want to deceive myself” is subsumed under the generalization “I do not want to deceive.” But why not deceive? But why not allow oneself to be deceived? Note that the reasons for the former principle belong to an altogether different realm from those for the second. One does not want to allow oneself to be deceived because one assumes that it is harmful; dangerous, calamitous to be deceived. In this sense, science would be a long-range prudence, a caution, a utility; but one could object in all fairness: How is that? Is wanting not to allow oneself to be deceived really less harmful, less dangerous, less calamitous? What do you know in advance of the character of existence to be able to decide whether the greater advantage is on the side of the unconditionally mistrustful or of the unconditionally trusting? But if both should be required, much trust as well as much mistrust, from where would science then be permitted to take its unconditional faith or conviction on which it rests, that truth is more important than any other thing, including every other conviction? Precisely this conviction could never have come into being if both truth and untruth constantly proved to be useful which is the case. Thus – the faith in science, which after all exists undeniably, cannot owe its origin to such a calculus of utility; it must have originated in spite of the fact that the disutility and dangerousness of “the will to truth,” of “truth at any price” is proved to it constantly. “At any price”: how well we understand these words once we have offered and slaughtered one faith after another on this altar! Consequently, “will to truth” does not mean “I will not allow myself to be deceived” but – there is no alternative – “I will not deceive, not even myself”; and with that we stand on moral ground. For you only have to ask yourself carefully, “Why do you not want to deceive?” especially if it should seem – and it does seem! – as if life aimed at semblance, meaning error, deception, simulation, delusion, self-delusion, and when the great sweep of life has actually always shown itself to be on the side of the most unscrupulous polytropoi.6 6 This Greek word (Nietzsche uses the Greek characters) is applied to Odysseus in the first line of the Odyssey. There is no English equivalent. The meaning ranges from ‘much turned’ to ‘much traveled, versatile, wily, and manifold’. Nietzsche’s point is, of course, that Odysseus owed his survival on many occasions to his virtuosity in deception: At this point we should remember the arguments in sections 110 and 111 above. If life often depends on deception – on deceiving oneself as well as others then the unconditional desire for truth, truth at any price, depends on a standard independent of our survival – a standard to which we willingly sacrifice ourselves. To that extent we am still “pious.” Without a doubt, Nietzsche includes himself when he says, a few lines later, “we seekers after knowledge today, we godless anti-metaphysicians.” Cf. his impassioned insistence on the intellectual conscience in sections 2, 319, and 335. 28 Friedrich Nietzsche The Gay Science Charitably interpreted, such a resolve might perhaps be a quixotism,7 a minor slightly mad enthusiasm; but it might also be something more serious, namely, a principle that is hostile to life and destructive. – “Will to truth” – that might be a concealed will to death.8 Thus the question “Why science?” leads back to the moral problem: Why have morality at all when life, nature, and history are “not moral”? No doubt, those who are truthful in that audacious and ultimate sense that is presupposed by the faith in science thus affirm another world than the world of life, nature, and history; and insofar as they affirm this “other world” - look, must they not by the same token negate its counterpart, this world, our world? – But you will have gathered what I am driving at, namely, that it is still a metaphysical faith upon which our faith in science rests – that even we seekers after knowledge today, we godless anti-metaphysicians still take our fire, too, from the flame lit by a faith that is thousands of years old, that Christian faith which was also the faith of Plato, that God is the truth, that truth is divine. – But what if this should become more and more incredible, if nothing should prove to be divine any more unless it were error, blindness, the lie – if God himself should prove to be our most enduring lie? – 9 §345: Morality as a problem. – The lack of personality always takes its revenge: A weakened, thin, extinguished personality that denies itself is no longer fit for anything good-least of all for philosophy. “Selflessness” has no value either in heaven or on earth. All great problems demand great love, and of that only strong, round, secure spirits who have a firm grip on themselves are capable. It makes the most telling difference whether a thinker has a personal relationship to his problems and finds in them his destiny, his distress, and his greatest happiness, or an “impersonal” one, meaning that he can do no better than to touch them and grasp them with the antennae of cold, curious thought. In the latter case nothing will come of it; that much one can promise in advance, for even if great problems should allow themselves to be grasped by them they would not permit frogs and weaklings to hold on to them; such has been their taste from time immemorial – a taste, incidentally, that they share with all redoubtable females. Why is it then that I have never yet encountered anybody, not even in books, who approached morality in this personal way and who knew morality as a problem, and this problem as his own personal distress, torment, voluptuousness, and passion? It is evident that up to now morality was no problem at all but, on the contrary, precisely that on which after all mistrust, discord, and contradiction one could agree – the hallowed place of peace where our thinkers took a rest even from themselves, took a deep breath, and felt revived. I see nobody who ventured a critique of moral valuations; I miss even the slightest attempts of scientific curiosity, of the refined, experimental imagination of psychologists and historians that readily anticipates a problem and catches it in flight without quite knowing what it has caught. I have scarcely detected a few meagre preliminary efforts to explore the history of the origins of these feelings and valuations (which is something quite different from a critique and again different from a history of ethical systems). In one particular case I have done everything to encourage a sympathy and talent for this kind of history – in vain, as it seems to me today.10 7 It is relevant that Nietzsche loved Don Quixote and tended to identify himself with him. See Kaufmann, 71. 8 The notion of a will to death was resurrected by Freud in Beyond the Pleasure Principle, in 1920. 9 Nietzsche quotes from this section in the third essay of his Genealogy of Morals, section 24 (BWN, 588), and says at the end of section 24. “Whoever feels that this has been stated too briefly should read the section of The Gay Science entitled ‘How we, too, are still pious’ (section 344), or preferably the entire fifth book ...” 10 The preface to the Genealogy of Morals (BWN, 453f. and 457) shows that Nietzsche is alluding to Paul Rée, the author of The Source of Moral Perception (1877) and The Origin of Knowledge (1885). 29 Friedrich Nietzsche The Gay Science These historians of morality (mostly Englishmen) do not amount to much. Usually they themselves are still quite unsuspectingly obedient to one particular morality and, without knowing it, serve that as shield-bearers and followers – for example, by sharing that popular superstition of Christian Europe which people keep mouthing so guilelessly to this day, that what is characteristic of moral actions is selflessness, self-sacrifice, or sympathy and pity. Their usual mistaken premise is that they affirm some consensus of the nations, at least of tame nations, concerning certain principles of morals, and then they infer from this that these principles must be unconditionally binding also for you and me; or, conversely, they see the truth that among different nations moral valuations are necessarily different and then infer from this that no morality is at all binding. Both procedures are equally childish. The mistake made by the more refined among them is that they uncover and criticize the perhaps foolish opinions of a people about their morality, or of humanity about all human morality – opinions about its origin, religious sanction, the superstition of free will, 11 and things of that sort-and then suppose that they have criticized the morality itself. But the value of a command “thou shalt” is still fundamentally different from and independent of such opinions about it and the weeds of error that may have overgrown it-just as certainly as the value of a medication for a sick person is completely independent of whether he thinks about medicine scientifically or the way old women do. Even if a morality has grown out of an error, the realization of this fact would not as much as touch the problem of its value.12 Thus nobody up to now has examined the value of that most famous of all medicines which is called morality; and the first step would be – for once to question it. Well then, precisely this is our task. – 13 §346: Our question mark. – But you do not understand this? Indeed, people will have trouble understanding us. We are looking for words; perhaps we are also looking for ears. Who are we anyway? If we simply called ourselves, using an old expression, godless, or unbelievers, or perhaps immoralists, we do not believe that this would even come close to designating us: We are all three in such an advanced stage that one – that you, my curious friends – could never comprehend how we feel at this point. Ours is no longer the bitterness and passion of the person who has torn himself away and still feels compelled to turn his unbelief into a new belief, a purpose, a martyrdom. We have become cold, hard, and tough in the realization that the way of this world is anything but divine; even by human standards it is not rational, merciful, or just. We know it well, the world in which we live is ungodly, immoral, “inhuman”; we have interpreted it far too long in a false and mendacious way, in accordance with the wishes of our reverence, which is to say, according to our needs. For man is a reverent animal. But he is also mistrustful; and that the world is not worth what we thought it was, that is about as certain as anything of which our mistrust has finally got hold. The more mistrust, the more philosophy. We are far from claiming that the world is worth less; indeed it would seem laughable to us today if man were to insist on inventing values that were supposed to excel the value of the actual world. This is precisely what we have turned our backs on as an extravagant aberration of human vanity and unreason that for a long time was not recognized as such. It found its Cf. the section on “The error of free will” in Twilight of the Idols (VPN, 499ff.) and Beyond Good and Evil, section 19 (BWN, 215-17). APPENDIX II. 12 What is here suggested is that the value of a morality depends on its relation to health, or life, or ultimately power. 13 The task is to question whether the effects of morality on those who are moral are beneficial. This question, of course, does not commit one to the assumption that there is only one standard of value. One might make a start by comparing what has become of man under different moralities and by asking what might become of him without any morality. 11 30 Friedrich Nietzsche The Gay Science final expression in modern pessimism,14 and a more ancient and stronger expression in the teaching of Buddha; but it is part of Christianity also, if more doubtfully and ambiguously so but not for that reason any less seductive. The whole pose of “man against the world,” of man as a “world-negating” principle, of man as the measure of the value of things, as judge of the world who in the end places existence itself upon his scales and finds it wanting – the monstrous insipidity of this pose has finally come home to us and we are sick of it. We laugh as soon as we encounter the juxtaposition of “man and world,” separated by the sublime presumption of the little word “and.” But look, when we laugh like that, have we not simply carried the contempt for man one step further? And thus also pessimism, the contempt for that existence which is knowable by us? Have we not exposed ourselves to the suspicion of an opposition – an opposition between the world in which we were at home up to now with our reverences that perhaps made it possible for us to endure life, and another world that consists of us – an inexorable, fundamental, and deepest suspicion about ourselves that is more and more gaining worse and worse control of us Europeans and that could easily confront coming generations with the terrifying Either/Or: “Either abolish your reverences or – yourselves!” The latter would be nihilism; but would not the former also be-nihilism?15 – This is our question mark. §347: Believers and their need to believe. – How much one needs a faith16 in order to flourish, how much that is “firm” and that one does not wish to be shaken because one clings to it, that is a measure of the degree of one’s strength (or, to put the point more clearly, of one’s weakness).17 Christianity, it seems to me, is still needed by most people in old Europe even today;18 therefore it still finds believers. For this is how man is: An article of faith could be refuted before him a thousand times - if he needed it, he would consider it “true” again and again, in accordance with that famous “proof of strength” of which the Bible speaks.19 Metaphysics is still needed by some; but so is that impetuous demand for certainty20 that today discharges itself among large numbers of people in a scientific-positivistic form. The Schopenhauer’s philosophy. A few interpreters of Nietzsche have claimed that he was, by his own lights, a nihilist; but they have generally failed to specify the meaning of this term. Here two forms of nihilism are mentioned, and it is clear that Nietzsche is not a nihilist in either sense. 16 In German there is only one word for belief and faith, Glaube; and to believe is glauben. 17 This crucial point, which recurs elsewhere in Nietzsche’s writings, makes clear, we might say, “how he is not pious,” and thus needs to be considered in interpreting section 50 above. 18 This was written in 1886. 19 Nietzsche also refers to the “proof of strength” in section 50 of The Antichrist and in notes 171 and 452 of The Will to Power. But it is only in the passage above that Nietzsche claims that “the Bible speaks” of it. The reference is to I Corinthians 2:4. Here is the whole passage I Corinthians 2: 1-5: 14 15 When I came to you, brethren, I did not come proclaiming to you the testimony of God in lofty words or wisdom. For I decided to know nothing except Jesus Christ and him crucified. And I was with you in weakness and in much fear and trembling and my speech and message were not in the plausible words of wisdom but in demonstration of the Spirit and of power, that you faith might not rest in the wisdom of men but in the power of God. (Revised Standard Version) At first glance, this critique of the “demand for certainty” may seem to be at odds with section 2 above where “the desire for certainty” is what “separates the higher human beings from the lower.” But when both passages are read in context, the contradiction disappears. Section 2 deals with “The intellectual conscience” and the importance of giving ourselves an account of what speaks for and against our beliefs. What is attacked is the easy certainty of those who fail to consider objections. Actually, “the desire for certainty” is not the best phrase for what is clearly meant; “the desire for intellectual cleanliness” would be better: what counts is the desire to determine whether one is entitled to feel certain. 20 31 Friedrich Nietzsche The Gay Science demand that one wants by all means that something should be firm (while on account of the ardour of this demand one is easier and more negligent about the demonstration of this certainty) – this, too, is still the demand for a support, a prop, in short, that instinct of weakness which, to be sure, does not create religious, metaphysical systems, and convictions of all kinds but-conserves them. Actually, what is steaming around all of these positivistic systems is the vapour of a certain pessimistic gloom, something that smells of weariness, fatalism, disappointment, and fear of new disappointments-or else ostentatious wrath, a bad mood, the anarchism of indignation, and whatever other symptoms and masquerades of the feeling of weakness there may be. Even the vehemence with which our most intelligent contemporaries lose themselves in wretched nooks and crannies, for example, into patriotism (I mean what the French call chauvinisme and the Germans “German”) or into petty aesthetic creeds after the manner of French naturalisme (which drags up and bares only that part of nature which inspires nausea and simultaneous amazement – today people like to call this part la verite vraie21) or into nihilism a la Petersburg (meaning the belief in unbelief even to the point of martyrdom22) always manifests above all the need for a faith, a support, backbone, something to fall back on. Faith is always coveted most and needed most urgently where will is lacking; for will, as the affect of command, is the decisive sign of sovereignty and strength. In other words, the less one knows how to command, the more urgently one covets someone who commands, who commands severely – a god, prince, class, physician, father confessor, dogma, or party conscience. From this one might perhaps gather that the two world religions, Buddhism and Christianity, may have owed their origin and above all their sudden spread to a tremendous collapse and disease of the will. And that is what actually happened: both religions encountered a situation in which the will had become diseased, giving rise to a demand that had become utterly desperate for some “thou shalt.” Both religions taught fanaticism in ages in which the will had become exhausted, and thus they offered innumerable people some support, a new possibility of willing, some delight in willing. For fanaticism is the only “strength of the will” that even the weak and insecure can be brought to attain, being a sort of hypnotism of the whole system of the senses and the intellect for the benefit of an excessive nourishment (hypertrophy) of a single point of view and feeling that henceforth becomes dominant-which the Christian calls his faith. Once a human being reaches the fundamental conviction that he must be commanded, he becomes “a believer.” Conversely, one could conceive of such a pleasure and power of self-determination, such a freedom of the will23 that he spirit would take leave of all faith and every wish for certainty, being practiced in maintaining himself on insubstantial ropes and possibilities and dancing even near abysses. Such a spirit would be the free spirit par excellence.24 §348: On the origin of scholars. – In Europe scholars grow out of all kinds of classes and social conditions, like plants that require no particular soil. Therefore they belong by their very nature and quite involuntarily to the carriers of the democratic idea. But this origin betrays itself. Once one has trained one’s eyes to recognize in a scholarly treatise the scholar’s intellectual idiosyncrasy – every scholar has one – and to catch it in the act, one will almost 21 the true truth 22 Again it is clear that Nietzsche dissociates himself from nihilism. This conception of “freedom of the will” (alias, autonomy) does not involve any belief in what Nietzsche called “the superstition of free will” in section 345 (alias, the exemption of human actions from an otherwise universal determinism). See Appendix II. 24 Nietzsche still wants to be a free spirit in the best sense of that word – a liberated, autonomous spirit. Cf. Twilight, section 49 (VPN, 554). Cf. also The Antichrist, sections 50-55 (VPN, 631-42). 23 32 Friedrich Nietzsche The Gay Science always behold behind this the scholar’s “Preoccupations and history,” his family, and especially their crafts. Where the feeling finds expression “Now this has been proved and I am done with it,” it is generally the ancestor in the blood and instinct of the scholar who approves from his point of view “the finished job”; the faith in a proof is merely a symptom of what in a hard-working family has for ages been considered “good workmanship.” One example: When the sons of clerks and office workers of every kind, whose main task it has always been to bring order into diverse materials, to distribute it over different files, and in general to schematise things, become scholars, they manifest a tendency to consider a problem almost as solved when they have merely schematised it. There are philosophers who are fundamentally merely schematises; for them the formal aspect of their fathers’ occupation has become content. The talent for classifications, for tables of categories,25 betrays something; one pays a price for being the child of one’s parents. The son of an advocate will have to be an advocate as a scholar, too; he wants above all that his cause should be judged right, and next to that perhaps also that it should be right. The sons of Protestant ministers26 and school teachers may be recognized by their naive certainty when, as scholars, they consider their cause proved when they have merely stated it with vigour and warmth; they are thoroughly used to being believed, as that was part of their fathers’ job. A Jew, on the other hand, in keeping with the business circles and the past of his people, is least of all used to being believed. Consider Jewish scholars in this light: All of them have a high regard for logic, that is for compelling agreement by force of reasons; they know, with that they are bound to win even where they encounter race and class prejudices and where one does not like to believe them. For nothing is more democratic than logic; it is no respecter of persons and makes no distinction between crooked and straight noses. (Incidentally, Europe owes the Jews no small thanks for making people think more logically and for establishing cleanlier intellectual habits – nobody more so than the Germans who are a lamentably deraisonnable”27 race who to this day are still in need of having their “heads washed” first. Wherever Jews have won influence they have taught men to make finer distinctions, more rigorous inferences, and to write in a more luminous and cleanly fashion; their task was ever to bring a people “to listen to raison.28) §349: Once more the origin of scholars. – The wish to preserve oneself is the symptom of a condition of distress, of a limitation of the really fundamental instinct of life which aims at the expansion of power and, wishing for that, frequently risks and even sacrifices selfpreservation.29 It should be considered symptomatic when some philosophers – for example, Spinoza who was consumptive – considered the instinct of self-preservation decisive and had to see it that way; for they were individuals in conditions of distress. That our modern natural sciences have become so thoroughly entangled in this Spinozistic dogma (most recently and worst of all, Darwinism with its incomprehensibly one-sided doctrine of the “struggle for existence”) is probably due to the origins of most natural scientists: In this respect they belong to the “common people” their ancestors were poor and undistinguished people who knew the difficulties of survival only too well at firsthand. The whole of English Darwinism breathes something like the musty air of English overpopulation, 25 An allusion to Kant. Nietzsche’s father and grandfathers had been Protestant ministers. He may not have realized that further back many of his ancestors had been butchers. 27 unreasonable. 28 reason. The French words underline Nietzsche’s determination to dissociate himself from the Germans – and from German anti-Semitism. 29 This whole section provides some reasons for Nietzsche’s doctrine of the will to power as opposed to the more fashionable notion of a will to life or survival. 26 33 Friedrich Nietzsche The Gay Science like the smell of the distress and overcrowding of small people.30 But a natural scientist should come out of his human nook; and in nature it is not conditions of distress that are dominant but overflow and squandering, even to the point of absurdity. The struggle for existence is only an exception, a temporary restriction of the will to life. The great and small struggle always revolves around superiority, around growth and expansion, around power-in accordance with the will to power which is the will of life. §350: In honor of the homines religiosi.31 – The fight against the church is certainly among other things – for it means many things – also the fight of the more common, merrier, more familiar, ingenuous, and superficial type against the dominion of the graver, deeper, more meditative, that is, more evil and suspicious human beings who brood with an enduring suspicion about the value of existence and also about their own value; the common instinct of the People, their sensuous jollity, their “good heart” rebelled against them. The entire Roman church rests upon a southern suspicion about the nature of man, and this is always misunderstood in the north. The European south has inherited this suspicion from the depths of the Orient, from primeval and mysterious Asia and its contemplation. Protestantism already is a people’s rebellion for the benefit of the ingenuous, guileless, and superficial (the north has always been more good-natured and shallower than the south); but it was only the French Revolution that actually and solemnly placed the sceptre in the hands of “the good human being” (the sheep, the ass, the goose, and all who are incurably shallow squallers, ripe for the nut house of “modern ideas”). §351: In honour of the priestly type. – I rather think that it is precisely from what the common people32 take for wisdom (and who today is not “common people”?) – this clever, bovine piety, peace of mind, and meekness of country pastors that lies in the meadow and observes life seriously while ruminating – that the philosophers have always felt most remote, probably because they were not sufficiently “common people” or country pastors for that. It is likely that they of all people will be the last to learn to believe that the common people could possibly understand anything of what is most remote from them: the great passion of the seeker after knowledge who lives and must live continually in the thundercloud of the highest problems and the heaviest responsibilities (by no means as an observer, outside, indifferent, secure, and objective). The common people revere an altogether different human type when they construct their ideal of “the sage,” and they are amply entitled to lavish the best words and honours on this type – namely, the mild, serious and simple-minded, chaste priestly type and what is related to it. When the common people stand in awe of wisdom, their praise is intended for this type. And to whom would the common people have more reason to show gratitude than these men who belong to them and come from among them but as men who are consecrated, selected, and sacrificed for the welfare of the common people-they themselves believe that they are being sacrificed to God. It is to these men that the common people can spill their hearts with impunity, to them one can get rid of one’s secrets, worries, and worse matters (for as a human being “communicates himself” he gets rid of himself, and when one “has confessed” one forgets). It is a deep need that commands this; for the filth of the soul also requires sewers with pure and purifying waters in them, it requires rapid streams of love and strong, humble, pure hearts who are willing to perform such a service of non-public hygiene, sacrificing themselves – for this does involve a sacrifice, and a priest is and remains a human sacrifice. Cf. “Anti-Darwin” in Twilight (VPN, 522f.): “One should not mistake Malthus for nature.” Thomas Robert Malthus (1766 -1834) had published his immensely influential An Essay on the Principle of Population in 1798. 31 the religious, or the religious type. 32 Throughout this section Volk is rendered as common people. Quotation marks are Nietzsche’s. 30 34 Friedrich Nietzsche The Gay Science The common people attribute wisdom to such serious men of “faith” who have become quiet, meaning that they have acquired knowledge and are “certain”33 compared to one’s own uncertainty. Who would want to deny them this word and this reverence? – But it is also fair, conversely, when philosophers consider priests as still common people” and not men of knowledge – above all, because they simply do not believe in any “men of knowledge”; in this belief, or rather superstition, they smell the “common people.” It was modesty that invented the word “philosopher” in Greece and left the magnificent overweening presumption in calling oneself wise to the actors of the spirit - the modesty of such monsters of pride and sovereignty as Pythagoras, as Plato – .34 §352: How morality is scarcely dispensable. – A naked human being is generally a shameful sight. I am speaking of us Europeans (and not even of female Europeans!). Suppose that, owing to some magician’s malice, the most cheerful company at table suddenly saw itself disrobed and undressed; I believe that not only their cheerfulness would vanish and that the strongest appetite would be discouraged –35 it seems that we Europeans simply cannot dispense with that masquerade which one calls clothes. Now consider the way “moral man” is dressed up, how he is veiled behind moral formulas and concepts of decency – the way our actions are benevolently concealed by the concepts of duty, virtue, sense of community; honourableness, self-denial – should the reasons for all this not be equally good? I am not suggesting that all this is meant to mask human malice and villainy – the wild animal in us; my idea is, on the contrary, that it is precisely as tame animals that we are a shameful sight and in need of the moral disguise, that the “inner man” in Europe is not by a long shot bad enough to show himself without shame (or to be beautiful). The European disguises himself with morality because he has become a sick, sickly, crippled animal that has good reasons for being “tame”; for he is almost an abortion, scarce half made up,36 weak, awkward. It is not the ferocity of the beast of prey that requires a moral disguise but the herd animal with its profound mediocrity, timidity, and boredom with itself. With morality the European dresses up – let us confess it – to look nobler, more important, respectable, “divine” – 37 §353: On the origin of religions. – The distinctive invention of the founders of religions is, first: to posit a particular kind of life and everyday customs that have the effect of a discipline voluntatis and at the same time abolish boredom – and then to bestow on this life style an interpretation that makes it appear to be illuminated by the highest value so that this life style becomes something for which one fights and under certain circumstances sacrifices one’s life. sicher means secure as well as certain, and Unsicherheit means insecurity as well as uncertainty. 33 34 The claim here is that not only Socrates made a point of not knowing matters of which many others falsely claimed to have knowledge but that even such “monsters of pride” as Plato did not believe they had knowledge. This claim is at the very least debatable. 35 Here the dash marks a real break; one is led to expect a continuation that does not materialize. It should be kept in mind that this was written in 1886, during the Victorian era. 36 etwas Halbes. literally, something half. The translation alludes to the opening monologue of Richard III: ... I, that am curtail’d of this fair proportion, Cheated of feature by dissembling Nature, Deform’d, unfinish’d, sent before my time Into this breathing world, scarce half made up ... 37 There is no period, as if the thought broke off as in a note. The central idea is close to Zarathustra’s “I have often laughed at the weaklings who thought themselves good because they had no claws” (“On those who are sublime,” VPN, 230): instead of standing revealed as a creature without claws, one pretends that one is ferocious and that only a high regard for morality keeps one from doing terrible things. Cf. also the section on “Whether we have become more moral” in Twilight (VPN, 538f.). 35 Friedrich Nietzsche The Gay Science Actually, the second of these two inventions is more essential. The first, the Way of life, was usually there before, but alongside other ways of life and without any sense of its special value. The significance and originality of the founder of a religion usually consists of his seeing it, selecting it, and guessing for the first time to what use it can be put, how it can be interpreted. Jesus (or Paul), for example, found how small people lived in the Roman provinces modest, virtuous, pinched life. He offered an exegesis, he read the highest meaning and value into it – and with this also the courage to despise every other way of life, the quiet Herrnhut38 fanaticism, the secret, subterranean self-confidence that grows and grows and finally is ready “to overcome the world” (that is, Rome and the upper classes throughout the Empire). Buddha likewise found a human type, in his case scattered through all classes and social strata of his people, that was good and good-natured from inertia (and above all inoffensive); also from inertia, this type lived abstinently, almost without needs. He understood how such a human type must inevitably roll, with its whole vis inertiae,39 into a faith that promises to prevent the recurrence of terrestrial troubles (meaning work and action in general). To understand that was his genius. To become the founder of a religion one must be psychologically infallible in one’s knowledge of a certain average type of souls who have not yet recognized that they belong together. It is he that brings them together. The founding of a religion therefore always becomes a long festival of recognition. – §354: On the “genius of the species.”40 – The problem of consciousness (more precisely, of becoming conscious of something) confronts us only when we begin to comprehend how we could dispense with it; and now physiology and the history of animals place us at the beginning of such comprehension (it took them two centuries to catch up with Leibniz’s suspicion which soared ahead). For we could think, feel, will, and remember, and we could also “act” in every sense of that word, and yet none of all this would have to “enter our consciousness” (as one says metaphorically). The whole of life would be possible without, as it were, seeing itself in a mirror. Even now, for that matter, by far the greatest portion of our life actually takes place without this mirror effect; and this is true even of our thinking, feeling, and willing life, however offensive this may sound to older philosophers. For what purpose, then, any consciousness at all when it is in the main superfluous? Now, if you are willing to listen to my answer and the perhaps extravagant surmise that it involves, it seems to me as if the subtlety and strength of consciousness always were proportionate” to a man’s (or animal’s) capacity for communication, and as if this capacity in turn were proportionate to the need for communication. But this last point is not to be understood as if the individual human being who happens to be a master in communicating and making understandable his needs must also be most dependent on others in his needs. But it does seem to me as if it were that way when we consider whole races and chains of generations: Where need and distress have forced men for a long time to communicate and to understand each other quickly and subtly, the ultimate result is an excess of this strength and art of communication – as it were, a capacity that has gradually been accumulated and now waits for an heir who might squander it. (Those who are called artists are these heirs; so are orators, preachers, writers – all of them people who always come at the end of a long chain, “late born” every one of them in the best sense of that word and, as I have said, by their nature squanderers.) 38 The Moravian brotherhood; cf. Will to Power, section 911 and 911n. force of inertia. 40 In the 1950s and 1960s many English speaking philosophers discussed the possibility of a “private language.” The literature on the subject was dominated by the work of Ludwig Wittgenstein (18891951) but might have profited from some attention to this section. Whether Wittgenstein knew it is uncertain; but the opening of the following section (355) reminds one of Wittgenstein’s style. 39 36 Friedrich Nietzsche The Gay Science Supposing that this observation is correct, I may now proceed to the surmise that consciousness has developed only under the pressure of the need for communication; that from the start it was needed and useful only between human beings (particularly between those who commanded and those who obeyed); and that it also developed only in proportion to the degree of this utility. Consciousness is really only a net of communication between human beings; it is only as such that it had to develop; a solitary human being who lived like a beast of prey would not have needed it. That our actions, thoughts, feelings, and movements enter our own consciousness – at least a part of them – that is the result of a “must” that for a terribly long time lorded it over man. As the most endangered animal, he needed help and protection, he needed his peers, he had to learn to express his distress and to make himself understood; and for all of this he needed “consciousness” first of all, he needed to “know” himself what distressed him, he needed to “know” how he felt, he needed to “know” what he thought. For, to say it once more: Man, like every living being, thinks continually without knowing it; the thinking that rises to consciousness is only the smallest part of all this – the most superficial and worst part – for only this conscious thinking takes the form of words, which is to say signs of communication, and this fact uncovers the origin of consciousness. In brief, the development of language and the development of consciousness (not of reason but merely of the way reason enters consciousness) go hand in hand. Add to this that not only language serves as a bridge between human beings but also a mien, a pressure, a gesture. The emergence of our sense impressions into our own consciousness, the ability to fix them and, as it were, exhibit them externally, increased proportionately with the need to communicate them to others by means of signs. The human being inventing signs is at the same time the human being who becomes ever more keenly conscious of himself. It was only as a social animal that man acquired self-consciousness – which he is still in the process of doing, more and more. My idea is, as you see, that consciousness does not really belong to man’s individual existence but rather to his social or herd nature; that, as follows from this, it has developed subtlety only insofar as this is required by social or herd utility. Consequently, given the best will in the world to understand ourselves as individually as possible, “to know ourselves,” each of us will always succeed in becoming conscious only of what is not individual but “average.” Our thoughts themselves are continually governed by the character of consciousness – by the “genius of the species” that commands it – and translated back into the perspective of the herd. Fundamentally, all our actions are altogether incomparably personal, unique, and infinitely individual; there is no doubt of that. But as soon as we translate them into consciousness they no longer seem to be. This is the essence of phenomenalism and perspectivism as I understand them: Owing to the nature of animal consciousness, the world of which we can become conscious is only a surface and sign-world, a world that is made common and meaner; whatever becomes conscious becomes by the same token shallow, thin, relatively stupid, general, sign, herd signal; all becoming conscious involves a great and thorough corruption, falsification, reduction to superficialities, and generalization. Ultimately, the growth of consciousness becomes a danger; and anyone who lives among the most conscious Europeans even knows that it is a disease. You will guess that it is not the opposition of subject and object that concerns me here: This distinction I leave to the epistemologists who have become entangled in the snares of grammar (the metaphysics of the people). It is even less the opposition of “thing-in-itself” and appearance; for we do not “know” nearly enough to be entitled to any such distinction. We simply lack any organ for knowledge,” for “truth”: we “know” (or believe or imagine) just as much as may be useful in the interests of the human herd, the species; and even what is here 37 Friedrich Nietzsche The Gay Science called “utility” is ultimately also a mere belief, something imaginary, and perhaps precisely that most calamitous stupidity of which we shall perish some day. 38 Jean Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism Jean-Paul Sartre ‘EXISTENTIALISM IS A HUMANISM’ My purpose here is to offer a defence of existentialism against several reproaches that have been laid against it. First, it has been reproached as an invitation to people to dwell in quietism of despair. For if every way to a solution is barred, one would have to regard any action in this world as entirely ineffective, and one would arrive finally at a contemplative philosophy. Moreover, since contemplation is a luxury, this would be only another bourgeois philosophy. This is, especially, the reproach made by the Communists. From another quarter we are reproached for having underlined all that is ignominious in the human situation, for depicting what is mean, sordid or base to the neglect of certain things that possess charm and beauty and belong to the brighter side of human nature: for example, according to the Catholic critic, Mlle. Mercier, we forget how an infant smiles. Both from this side and from the other we are also reproached for leaving out of account the solidarity of mankind and considering man in isolation. And this, say the Communists, is because we base our doctrine upon pure subjectivity — upon the Cartesian “I think”: which is the moment in which solitary man attains to himself; a position from which it is impossible to regain solidarity with other men who exist outside of the self. The ego cannot reach them through the cogito. From the Christian side, we are reproached as people who deny the reality and seriousness of human affairs. For since we ignore the commandments of God and all values prescribed as eternal, nothing remains but what is strictly voluntary. Everyone can do what he likes, and will be incapable, from such a point of view, of condemning either the point of view or the action of anyone else. It is to these various reproaches that I shall endeavour to reply today; that is why I have entitled this brief exposition “Existentialism is a Humanism.” Many may be surprised at the mention of humanism in this connection, but we shall try to see in what sense we understand it. In any case, we can begin by saying that existentialism, in our sense of the word, is a doctrine that does render human life possible; a doctrine, also, which affirms that every truth and every action imply both an environment and a human subjectivity. The essential charge laid against us is, of course, that of over-emphasis upon the evil side of human life. I have lately been told of a lady who, whenever she lets slip a vulgar expression in a moment of nervousness, excuses herself by exclaiming, ‘I believe I am becoming an existentialist.” So it appears that ugliness is being identified with existentialism. That is why some people say we are “naturalistic,” and if we are, it is strange to see how much we scandalise and horrify them, for no one seems to be much frightened or humiliated nowadays by what is properly called naturalism. Those who can quite well keep down a novel by Zola such as La Terre are sickened as soon as they read an existentialist novel.1 Those who appeal to the wisdom of the people — which is a sad wisdom — find ours sadder still. And yet, what could be more disillusioned than such sayings as “Charity begins at home” or “Promote a rogue and he’ll sue you for damage, knock him down and he’ll do you homage”? We all know how many common sayings can be quoted to this effect, and they all mean much the same — that you must not oppose the powers that be; that you must not fight against superior force; must not meddle in matters that are above your station. Or that any action not in accordance with some tradition is mere romanticism; or that any undertaking which has not the support of proven experience is foredoomed to frustration; and that since experience has shown men to be invariably inclined to evil, there must be firm rules to restrain them, otherwise we shall have 1 Emile Zola (1840-1902) was the leading ‘naturalist’ novelist. 39 Jean Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism anarchy. It is, however, the people who are forever mouthing these dismal proverbs and, whenever they are told of some more or less repulsive action, say “How like human nature!” — it is these very people, always harping upon realism, who complain that existentialism is too gloomy a view of things. Indeed their excessive protests make me suspect that what is annoying them is not so much our pessimism, but, much more likely, our optimism. For at bottom, what is alarming in the doctrine that I am about to try to explain to you is — is it not? — that it confronts man with a possibility of choice. To verify this, let us review the whole question upon the strictly philosophic level. What, then, is this that we call existentialism? Most of those who are making use of this word would be highly confused if required to explain its meaning. For since it has become fashionable, people cheerfully declare that this musician or that painter is “existentialist.” A columnist in Clartes signs himself “The Existentialist,” and, indeed, the word is now so loosely applied to so many things that it no longer means anything at all. It would appear that, for the lack of any novel doctrine such as that of surrealism,2 all those who are eager to join in the latest scandal or movement now seize upon this philosophy in which, however, they can find nothing to their purpose. For in truth this is of all teachings the least scandalous and the most austere: it is intended strictly for technicians and philosophers. All the same, it can easily be defined. The question is only complicated because there are two kinds of existentialists. There are, on the one hand, the Christians, amongst whom I shall name Jaspers and Gabriel Marcel, both professed Catholics; and on the other the existential atheists, amongst whom we must place Heidegger as well as the French existentialists and myself.3 What they have in common is simply the fact that they believe that existence comes before essence — or, if you will, that we must begin from the subjective. What exactly do we mean by that? If one considers an article of manufacture as, for example, a book or a paper-knife — one sees that it has been made by an artisan who had a conception of it; and he has paid attention, equally, to the conception of a paper-knife and to the pre-existent technique of production which is a part of that conception and is, at bottom, a formula. Thus the paper-knife is at the same time an article producible in a certain manner and one which, on the other hand, serve a definite purpose, for one cannot suppose that a man would produce a paper-knife without knowing what it was for. Let us say, then, of the paperknife that its essence — that is to say the sum of the formulae and the qualities which made its production and its definition possible — precedes its existence. The presence of such-and-such a paper-knife or book is thus determined before my eyes. Here, then, we are viewing the world from a technical standpoint, and we can say that production precedes existence. When we think of God as the creator, we are thinking of him, most of the time, as a supernal artisan. Whatever doctrine we may be considering, whether it be a doctrine like that of Descartes, or of Leibnitz himself, we always imply that the will follows, more or less, from the understanding or at least accompanies it, so that when God creates he knows precisely 2 Surrealism had been the rage in Paris on either side of the previous war. Surrealists sought to produce art that sprang from the unconscious mind “in the absence of all control exercised by the reason and outside all aesthetic and moral considerations” (Andre Breton, ‘What is Surrealism?’ Theories of Modern Art, ed. Herschel B. Chipp University of California Press, 1968). Surrealism was primarily an artistic movement with philosophical pretensions. In contrast, existentialism was a philosophical movement with artistic implications. Sartre is saying that in the absence of a new artistic movement, existentialism had been seized upon as a label for much that was going on in the arts. 3 Martin Heidegger (1889-1976), German existentialist. His most famous work was Being and Time (1927). He was a major influence on the young Sartre. 40 Jean Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism what he is creating.4 Thus, the conception of man in the mind of God is comparable to that of the paper-knife in the mind of the artisan: God makes man according to a procedure and a conception, exactly as the artisan manufactures a paper-knife, following a definition and a formula. Thus each individual man is the realisation of a certain conception which dwells in the divine understanding. In the philosophic atheism of the eighteenth century, the notion of God is suppressed, but not, for all that, the idea that essence is prior to existence; something of that idea we still find everywhere, in Diderot, in Voltaire and even in Kant. 5 Man possesses a human nature; that “human nature,” which is the conception of human being, is found in every man; which means that each man is a particular example of a universal conception, the conception of Man. In Kant, this universality goes so far that the wild man of the woods, man in the state of nature and the bourgeois are all contained in the same definition and have the same fundamental qualities. Here again, the essence of man precedes that historic existence which we confront in experience. Atheistic existentialism, of which I am a representative, declares with greater consistency that if God does not exist there is at least one being whose existence comes before its essence, a being which exists before it can be defined by any conception of it. That being is man or, as Heidegger has it, the human reality. What do we mean by saying that existence precedes essence? We mean that man first of all exists, encounters himself, surges up in the world — and defines himself afterwards. If man as the existentialist sees him is not definable, it is because to begin with he is nothing. He will not be anything until later, and then he will be what he makes of himself. Thus, there is no human nature, because there is no God to have a conception of it. Man simply is. Not that he is simply what he conceives himself to be, but he is what he wills, and as he conceives himself after already existing — as he wills to be after that leap towards existence. Man is nothing else but that which he makes of himself. That is the first principle of existentialism. And this is what people call its “subjectivity,” using the word as a reproach against us. But what do we mean to say by this, but that man is of a greater dignity than a stone or a table? For we mean to say that man primarily exists — that man is, before all else, something which propels itself towards a future and is aware that it is doing so. Man is, indeed, a project which possesses a subjective life, instead of being a kind of moss, or a fungus or a cauliflower. Before that projection of the self nothing exists; not even in the heaven of intelligence: man will only attain existence when he is what he purposes to be. Not, however, what he may wish to be. For what we usually understand by wishing or willing is a conscious decision taken — much more often than not — after we have made ourselves what we are. I may wish to join a party, to write a book or to marry — but in such a case what is usually called my will is probably a manifestation of a prior and more spontaneous decision. If, however, it is true that existence is prior to essence, man is responsible for what he is. Thus, the first effect of existentialism is that it puts every man in possession of himself as he is, and places the entire responsibility for his existence squarely upon his own shoulders. And, when we say that man is responsible for himself, we do not mean that he is responsible only for his own individuality, but that he is responsible for all men. The word “subjectivism” is to be understood in two senses, and our adversaries play upon only one of them. Subjectivism means, on the one hand, the freedom of the individual subject and, on the other, that man cannot pass beyond human subjectivity. It is the latter which is the deeper meaning of existentialism. When we say that man chooses himself, we do 4 5 Gottlob Liebniz (1646-1716) is famous (or infamous) for the doctrine that this is ‘the best of all possible worlds’. This is the idea that a good God must have chosen the best of all possible worlds. To put this very crudely, this doctrine imagines God choosing a world from the possible options like a person choosing an outfit from their wardrobe. Leibniz’s view was parodied mercilessly in Voltaire’s novelette, Candide. Denis Diderot (1713-1784) and Voltaire (pseudonym of Francois-Marie Arouet, 1694-1778). Both men were leading writers of the French Enlightenment. 41 Jean Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism mean that every one of us must choose himself; but by that we also mean that in choosing for himself he chooses for all men. For in effect, of all the actions a man may take in order to create himself as he wills to be, there is not one which is not creative, at the same time, of an image of man such as he believes he ought to be. To choose between this or that is at the same time to affirm the value of that which is chosen; for we are unable ever to choose the worse. What we choose is always the better; and nothing can be better for us unless it is better for all. If, moreover, existence precedes essence and we will to exist at the same time as we fashion our image, that image is valid for all and for the entire epoch in which we find ourselves. Our responsibility is thus much greater than we had supposed, for it concerns mankind as a whole. If I am a worker, for instance, I may choose to join a Christian rather than a Communist trade union. And if, by that membership, I choose to signify that resignation is, after all, the attitude that best becomes a man, that man’s kingdom is not upon this earth, I do not commit myself alone to that view. Resignation is my will for everyone, and my action is, in consequence, a commitment on behalf of all mankind. Or if, to take a more personal case, I decide to marry and to have children, even though this decision proceeds simply from my situation, from my passion or my desire, I am thereby committing not only myself, but humanity as a whole, to the practice of monogamy. I am thus responsible for myself and for all men, and I am creating a certain image of man as I would have him to be. In fashioning myself I fashion man. This may enable us to understand what is meant by such terms — perhaps a little grandiloquent — as anguish, abandonment and despair. As you will soon see, it is very simple. First, what do we mean by anguish? — The existentialist frankly states that man is in anguish. His meaning is as follows: When a man commits himself to anything, fully realising that he is not only choosing what he will be, but is thereby at the same time a legislator deciding for the whole of mankind — in such a moment a man cannot escape from the sense of complete and profound responsibility. There are many, indeed, who show no such anxiety. But we affirm that they are merely disguising their anguish or are in flight from it. Certainly, many people think that in what they are doing they commit no one but themselves to anything: and if you ask them, “What would happen if everyone did so?” they shrug their shoulders and reply, “Everyone does not do so.” But in truth, one ought always to ask oneself what would happen if everyone did as one is doing; nor can one escape from that disturbing thought except by a kind of self-deception. The man who lies in self-excuse, by saying “Everyone will not do it” must be ill at ease in his conscience, for the act of lying implies the universal value which it denies. By its very disguise his anguish reveals itself. This is the anguish that Kierkegaard called “the anguish of Abraham.” You know the story6: An angel commanded Abraham to sacrifice his son: and obedience was obligatory, if it really was an angel who had appeared and said, “Thou, Abraham, shalt sacrifice thy son.” But anyone in such a case would wonder, first, whether it was indeed an angel and secondly, whether I am really Abraham. Where are the proofs? A certain mad woman who suffered from hallucinations said that people were telephoning to her, and giving her orders. The doctor asked, “But who is it that speaks to you?” She replied: “He says it is God.” And what, indeed, could prove to her that it was God? If an angel appears to me, what is the proof that it is an angel; or, if I hear voices, who can prove that they proceed from heaven and not from hell, or from my own subconsciousness or some pathological condition? Who can prove that they are really addressed to me? Who, then, can prove that I am the proper person to impose, by my own choice, my conception of man upon mankind? I shall never find any proof whatever; there will be no sign to convince me of it. If a voice speaks to me, it is still I myself who must decide whether the voice is or is not that of an angel. If I regard a certain course of action as good, it is only I who 6 Genesis chapter 22. Those who do not know the story may be interested to know that this was a test of Abraham’s faith. At the last moment, an angel intervened and told Abraham to substitute a ram. 42 Jean Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism choose to say that it is good and not bad. There is nothing to show that I am Abraham: nevertheless I also am obliged at every instant to perform actions which are examples. Everything happens to every man as though the whole human race had its eyes fixed upon what he is doing and regulated its conduct accordingly. So every man ought to say, “Am I really a man who has the right to act in such a manner that humanity regulates itself by what I do.” If a man does not say that, he is dissembling his anguish. Clearly, the anguish with which we are concerned here is not one that could lead to quietism or inaction. It is anguish pure and simple, of the kind well known to all those who have borne responsibilities. When, for instance, a military leader takes upon himself the responsibility for the attack and sends a number of men to their death, he chooses to do it and at bottom he alone chooses. No doubt under a higher command, but its orders, which are more general, require interpretation by him and upon that interpretation depends the life of ten, fourteen or twenty men. In making the decision, he cannot but feel a certain anguish. All leaders know that anguish. It does not prevent their acting, on the contrary it is the very condition of their action, for the action presupposes that there is a plurality of possibilities, and in choosing one of these, they realize that it has value only because it is chosen. Now it is anguish of that kind which existentialism describes, and moreover, as we shall see, makes explicit through direct responsibility towards other men who are concerned. Far from being a screen which could separate us from action, it is a condition of action itself. And when we speak of “abandonment” — a favourite word of Heidegger — we only mean to say that God does not exist, and that it is necessary to draw the consequences of his absence right to the end. The existentialist is strongly opposed to a certain type of secular moralism which seeks to suppress God at the least possible expense. Towards 1880, when the French professors endeavoured to formulate a secular morality, they said something like this: God is a useless and costly hypothesis, so we will do without it. However, if we are to have morality, a society and a law-abiding world, it is essential that certain values should be taken seriously; they must have an a priori existence ascribed to them. It must be considered obligatory a priori to be honest, not to lie, not to beat one’s wife, to bring up children and so forth; so we are going to do a little work on this subject, which will enable us to show that these values exist all the same, inscribed in an intelligible heaven although, of course, there is no God. In other words — and this is, I believe, the purport of all that we in France call radicalism — nothing will be changed if God does not exist; we shall rediscover the same norms of honesty, progress and humanity, and we shall have disposed of God as an out-of-date hypothesis which will die away quietly of itself. The existentialist, on the contrary, finds it extremely embarrassing that God does not exist, for there disappears with Him all possibility of finding values in an intelligible heaven. There can no longer be any good a priori, since there is no infinite and perfect consciousness to think it. It is nowhere written that “the good” exists, that one must be honest or must not lie, since we are now upon the plane where there are only men. Dostoyevsky once wrote “if God did not exist, everything would be permitted” 7; and that, for existentialism, is the starting point. Everything is indeed permitted if God does not exist, and man is in consequence forlorn, for he cannot find anything to depend upon either within or outside himself. He discovers forthwith, that he is without excuse. For if indeed existence precedes essence, one will never be able to explain one’s action by reference to a given and specific human nature; in other words, there is no determinism — man is free, man is freedom. Nor, on the other hand, if God does not exist, are we provided with any values or commands that could legitimise our behaviour. Thus we have neither behind us, nor before us in a luminous realm of values, any means of justification or excuse. — We are left alone, without excuse. That is what I mean when I say that man is condemned to be free. This quote is generally thought to be found in Dostoyevsky’s The Brother’s Karamazov. Although it is a sentiment that is in keeping with the character of Ivan Karamazov, the phrase does not appear in the novel. 7 43 Jean Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism Condemned, because he did not create himself, yet is nevertheless at liberty, and from the moment that he is thrown into this world he is responsible for everything he does. The existentialist does not believe in the power of passion. He will never regard a grand passion as a destructive torrent upon which a man is swept into certain actions as by fate, and which, therefore, is an excuse for them. He thinks that man is responsible for his passion. Neither will an existentialist think that a man can find help through some sign being vouchsafed upon earth for his orientation: for he thinks that the man himself interprets the sign as he chooses. He thinks that every man, without any support or help whatever, is condemned at every instant to invent man. As Ponge has written in a very fine article, “Man is the future of man.” That is exactly true. Only, if one took this to mean that the future is laid up in Heaven, that God knows what it is, it would be false, for then it would no longer even be a future. If, however, it means that, whatever man may now appear to be, there is a future to be fashioned, a virgin future that awaits him — then it is a true saying. But in the present one is forsaken. As an example by which you may the better understand this state of abandonment, I will refer to the case of a pupil of mine, who sought me out in the following circumstances. His father was quarrelling with his mother and was also inclined to be a “collaborator”; his elder brother had been killed in the German offensive of 1940 and this young man, with a sentiment somewhat primitive but generous, burned to avenge him. His mother was living alone with him, deeply afflicted by the semi-treason of his father and by the death of her eldest son, and her one consolation was in this young man. But he, at this moment, had the choice between going to England to join the Free French Forces or of staying near his mother and helping her to live. He fully realised that this woman lived only for him and that his disappearance — or perhaps his death — would plunge her into despair. He also realised that, concretely and in fact, every action he performed on his mother’s behalf would be sure of effect in the sense of aiding her to live, whereas anything he did in order to go and fight would be an ambiguous action which might vanish like water into sand and serve no purpose. For instance, to set out for England he would have to wait indefinitely in a Spanish camp on the way through Spain; or, on arriving in England or in Algiers he might be put into an office to fill up forms. Consequently, he found himself confronted by two very different modes of action; the one concrete, immediate, but directed towards only one individual; and the other an action addressed to an end infinitely greater, a national collectivity, but for that very reason ambiguous — and it might be frustrated on the way. At the same time, he was hesitating between two kinds of morality; on the one side the morality of sympathy, of personal devotion and, on the other side, a morality of wider scope but of more debatable validity. He had to choose between those two. What could help him to choose? Could the Christian doctrine? No. Christian doctrine says: Act with charity, love your neighbour, deny yourself for others, choose the way which is hardest, and so forth. But which is the harder road? To whom does one owe the more brotherly love, the patriot or the mother? Which is the more useful aim, the general one of fighting in and for the whole community, or the precise aim of helping one particular person to live? Who can give an answer to that a priori? No one. Nor is it given in any ethical scripture. The Kantian ethic says, Never regard another as a means, but always as an end. Very well; if I remain with my mother, I shall be regarding her as the end and not as a means: but by the same token I am in danger of treating as means those who are fighting on my behalf; and the converse is also true, that if I go to the aid of the combatants I shall be treating them as the end at the risk of treating my mother as a means. If values are uncertain, if they are still too abstract to determine the particular, concrete case under consideration, nothing remains but to trust in our instincts. That is what this young man tried to do; and when I saw him he said, “In the end, it is feeling that counts; the direction in which it is really pushing me is the one I ought to choose. If I feel that I love my mother enough to sacrifice everything else for her — my will to be avenged, all my longings for action and adventure then I stay with her. If, on the contrary, I feel that my love for her is not enough, I 44 Jean Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism go.” But how does one estimate the strength of a feeling? The value of his feeling for his mother was determined precisely by the fact that he was standing by her. I may say that I love a certain friend enough to sacrifice such or such a sum of money for him, but I cannot prove that unless I have done it. I may say, “I love my mother enough to remain with her,” if actually I have remained with her. I can only estimate the strength of this affection if I have performed an action by which it is defined and ratified. But if I then appeal to this affection to justify my action, I find myself drawn into a vicious circle. Moreover, as Gide8 has very well said, a sentiment which is play-acting and one which is vital are two things that are hardly distinguishable one from another. To decide that I love my mother by staying beside her, and to play a comedy the upshot of which is that I do so — these are nearly the same thing. In other words, feeling is formed by the deeds that one does; therefore I cannot consult it as a guide to action. And that is to say that I can neither seek within myself for an authentic impulse to action, nor can I expect, from some ethic, formulae that will enable me to act. You may say that the youth did, at least, go to a professor to ask for advice. But if you seek counsel — from a priest, for example you have selected that priest; and at bottom you already knew, more or less, what he would advise. In other words, to choose an adviser is nevertheless to commit oneself by that choice. If you are a Christian, you will say, Consult a priest; but there are collaborationists, priests who are resisters and priests who wait for the tide to turn: which will you choose? Had this young man chosen a priest of the resistance, or one of the collaboration, he would have decided beforehand the kind of advice he was to receive. Similarly, in coming to me, he knew what advice I should give him, and I had but one reply to make. You are free, therefore choose that is to say, invent. No rule of general morality can show you what you ought to do: no signs are vouchsafed in this world. The Catholics will reply, “Oh, but they are!” Very well; still, it is I myself, in every case, who have to interpret the signs. While I was imprisoned, I made the acquaintance of a somewhat remarkable man, a Jesuit, who had become a member of that order in the following manner. In his life he had suffered a succession of rather severe setbacks. His father had died when he was a child, leaving him in poverty, and he had been awarded a free scholarship in a religious institution, where he had been made continually to feel that he was accepted for charity’s sake, and, in consequence, he had been denied several of those distinctions and honours which gratify children. Later, about the age of eighteen, he came to grief in a sentimental affair; and finally, at twenty-two — this was a trifle in itself, but it was the last drop that overflowed his cup — he failed in his military examination. This young man, then, could regard himself as a total failure: it was a sign — but a sign of what? He might have taken refuge in bitterness or despair. But he took it — very cleverly for him as a sign that he was not intended for secular success, and that only the attainments of religion, those of sanctity and of faith, were accessible to him. He interpreted his record as a message from God, and became a member of the Order. Who can doubt but that this decision as to the meaning of the sign was his, and his alone? One could have drawn quite different conclusions from such a series of reverses — as, for example, that he had better become a carpenter or a revolutionary. For the decipherment of the sign, however, he bears the entire responsibility. That is what “abandonment” implies, that we ourselves decide our being. And with this abandonment goes anguish. As for “despair,” the meaning of this expression is extremely simple. It merely means that we limit ourselves to a reliance upon that which is within our wills, or within the sum of the probabilities which render our action feasible. Whenever one wills anything, there are always these elements of probability. If I am counting upon a visit from a friend, who may be coming by train or by tram, I presuppose that the train will arrive at the appointed time, or that the tram will not be derailed. I remain in the realm of possibilities; but one does not rely upon any 8 French novelist Andre Gide (1869-1951). 45 Jean Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism possibilities beyond those that are strictly concerned in one’s action. Beyond the point at which the possibilities under consideration cease to affect my action, I ought to disinterest myself. For there is no God and no prevenient design, which can adapt the world and all its possibilities to my will. When Descartes said, “Conquer yourself rather than the world,” what he meant was, at bottom, the same — that we should act without hope. Marxists, to whom I have said this, have answered: “Your action is limited, obviously, by your death; but you can rely upon the help of others. That is, you can count both upon what the others are doing to help you elsewhere, as in China and in Russia, and upon what they will do later, after your death, to take up your action and carry it forward to its final accomplishment which will be the revolution. Moreover you must rely upon this; not to do so is immoral.” To this I rejoin, first, that I shall always count upon my comrades-in-arms in the struggle, in so far as they are committed, as I am, to a definite, common cause; and in the unity of a party or a group which I can more or less control — that is, in which I am enrolled as a militant and whose movements at every moment are known to me. In that respect, to rely upon the unity and the will of the party is exactly like my reckoning that the train will run to time or that the tram will not be derailed. But I cannot count upon men whom I do not know, I cannot base my confidence upon human goodness or upon man’s interest in the good of society, seeing that man is free and that there is no human nature which I can take as foundational. I do not know where the Russian revolution will lead. I can admire it and take it as an example in so far as it is evident, today, that the proletariat plays a part in Russia which it has attained in no other nation. But I cannot affirm that this will necessarily lead to the triumph of the proletariat: I must confine myself to what I can see. Nor can I be sure that comrades-in-arms will take up my work after my death and carry it to the maximum perfection, seeing that those men are free agents and will freely decide, tomorrow, what man is then to be. Tomorrow, after my death, some men may decide to establish Fascism, and the others may be so cowardly or so slack as to let them do so. If so, Fascism will then be the truth of man, and so much the worse for us. In reality, things will be such as men have decided they shall be. Does that mean that I should abandon myself to quietism? No. First I ought to commit myself and then act my commitment, according to the time-honoured formula that “one need not hope in order to undertake one’s work.” Nor does this mean that I should not belong to a party, but only that I should be without illusion and that I should do what I can. For instance, if I ask myself “Will the social ideal as such, ever become a reality?” I cannot tell, I only know that whatever may be in my power to make it so, I shall do; beyond that, I can count upon nothing. Quietism is the attitude of people who say, “let others do what I cannot do.” The doctrine I am presenting before you is precisely the opposite of this, since it declares that there is no reality except in action. It goes further, indeed, and adds, “Man is nothing else but what he purposes, he exists only in so far as he realises himself, he is therefore nothing else but the sum of his actions, nothing else but what his life is.” Hence we can well understand why some people are horrified by our teaching. For many have but one resource to sustain them in their misery, and that is to think, “Circumstances have been against me, I was worthy to be something much better than I have been. I admit I have never had a great love or a great friendship; but that is because I never met a man or a woman who were worthy of it; if I have not written any very good books, it is because I had not the leisure to do so; or, if I have had no children to whom I could devote myself it is because I did not find the man I could have lived with. So there remains within me a wide range of abilities, inclinations and potentialities, unused but perfectly viable, which endow me with a worthiness that could never be inferred from the mere history of my actions.” But in reality and for the existentialist, there is no love apart from the deeds of love; no potentiality of love other than that which is manifested in loving; there is no genius other than that which is expressed in works of art. The genius of Proust is the totality of the works of Proust; the genius of Racine is the series of his tragedies, outside 46 Jean Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism of which there is nothing.9 Why should we attribute to Racine the capacity to write yet another tragedy when that is precisely what he — did not write? In life, a man commits himself, draws his own portrait and there is nothing but that portrait. No doubt this thought may seem comfortless to one who has not made a success of his life. On the other hand, it puts everyone in a position to understand that reality alone is reliable; that dreams, expectations and hopes serve to define a man only as deceptive dreams abortive hopes, expectations unfulfilled; that is to say, they define him negatively, not positively. Nevertheless, when one says, “You are nothing else but what you live,” it does not imply that an artist is to be judged solely by his works of art, for a thousand other things contribute no less to his definition as a man. What we mean to say is that a man is no other than a series of undertakings, that he is the sum, the organisation, the set of relations that constitute these undertakings. In the light of all this, what people reproach us with is not, after all, our pessimism, but the sternness of our optimism. If people condemn our works of fiction, in which we describe characters that are base, weak, cowardly and sometimes even frankly evil, it is not only because those characters are base, weak, cowardly or evil. For suppose that, like Zola, we showed that the behaviour of these characters was caused by their heredity, or by the action of their environment upon them, or by determining factors, psychic or organic. People would be reassured, they would say, “You see, that is what we are like, no one can do anything about it.” But the existentialist, when he portrays a coward, shows him as responsible for his cowardice. He is not like that on account of a cowardly heart or lungs or cerebrum, he has not become like that through his physiological organism; he is like that because he has made himself into a coward through cowardly actions. There is no such thing as a cowardly temperament. There are nervous temperaments; there is what is called impoverished blood, and there are also rich temperaments. But the man whose blood is poor is not a coward for all that, for what produces cowardice is the act of giving up or giving way; and a temperament is not an action. A coward is defined by the deed that he has done. What people feel obscurely, and with horror, is that the coward as we present him is guilty of being a coward. What people would prefer would be to be born either a coward or a hero. One of the charges most often laid against the Chemins de la Liberte is something like this “But, after all, these people being so base, how can you make them into heroes?”10 That objection is really rather comic, for it implies that people are born heroes: and that is, at bottom, what such people would like to think. If you are born cowards, you can be quite content. You can do nothing about it and you will be cowards all your lives whatever you do; and if you are born heroes you can again be quite content; you will be heroes all your lives eating and drinking heroically. Whereas the existentialist says that the coward makes himself cowardly, the hero makes himself heroic; and that there is always a possibility for the coward to give up cowardice and for the hero to stop being a hero. What counts is the total commitment, and it is not by a particular case or particular action that you are committed altogether. We have now, I think, dealt with a certain number of the reproaches against existentialism. You have seen that it cannot be regarded as a philosophy of quietism since it defines man by his action; nor as a pessimistic description of man, for no doctrine is more optimistic, the destiny of man is placed within himself. Nor is it an attempt to discourage man from action since it tells him that there is no hope except in his action, and that the one thing which permits him to have life is the deed. Upon this level therefore, what we are considering is an ethic of action and self-commitment. However, we are still reproached, upon these few data, 9 Marcel Proust (1871-1922), great modernist novelist, most famous for À la Recherche du temps perdu (Remembrance of Things Past); Jean Racine (1639-1699), French dramatist author of classic tragedies. Arguably, these two are the greatest exponents of French modernism and classicism respectively. 10 Chemins de la liberte is Sartre’s trilogy of novels set during the Nazi occupation of France. 47 Jean Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism for confining man within his individual subjectivity. There again people badly misunderstand us. Our point of departure is, indeed, the subjectivity of the individual, and that for strictly philosophic reasons. It is not because we are bourgeois, but because we seek to base our teaching upon the truth, and not upon a collection of fine theories, full of hope but lacking real foundations. And at the point of departure there cannot be any other truth than this, I think, therefore I am, which is the absolute truth of consciousness as it attains to itself. Every theory which begins with man, outside of this moment of self-attainment, is a theory which thereby suppresses the truth, for outside of the Cartesian cogito, all objects are no more than probable, and any doctrine of probabilities which is not attached to a truth will crumble into nothing. In order to define the probable one must possess the true. Before there can be any truth whatever, then, there must be an absolute truth, and there is such a truth which is simple, easily attained and within the reach of everybody; it consists in one’s immediate sense of one’s self. In the second place, this theory alone is compatible with the dignity of man, it is the only one which does not make man into an object. All kinds of materialism lead one to treat every man including oneself as an object — that is, as a set of pre-determined reactions, in no way different from the patterns of qualities and phenomena which constitute a table, or a chair or a stone. Our aim is precisely to establish the human kingdom as a pattern of values in distinction from the material world. But the subjectivity which we thus postulate as the standard of truth is no narrowly individual subjectivism, for as we have demonstrated, it is not only one’s own self that one discovers in the cogito, but those of others too. Contrary to the philosophy of Descartes, contrary to that of Kant, when we say “I think” we are attaining to ourselves in the presence of the other, and we are just as certain of the other as we are of ourselves. Thus the man who discovers himself directly in the cogito also discovers all the others, and discovers them as the condition of his own existence. He recognises that he cannot be anything (in the sense in which one says one is spiritual, or that one is wicked or jealous) unless others recognise him as such. I cannot obtain any truth whatsoever about myself, except through the mediation of another. The other is indispensable to my existence, and equally so to any knowledge I can have of myself. Under these conditions, the intimate discovery of myself is at the same time the revelation of the other as a freedom which confronts mine. and which cannot think or will without doing so either for or against me. Thus, at once, we find ourselves in a world which is, let us say, that of “inter-subjectivity”. It is in this world that man has to decide what he is and what others are. Furthermore, although it is impossible to find in each and every man a universal essence that can be called human nature, there is nevertheless a human universality of condition. It is not by chance that the thinkers of today are so much more ready to speak of the condition than of the nature of man. By his condition they understand, with more or less clarity, all the limitations which a priori define man’s fundamental situation in the universe. His historical situations are variable: man may be born a slave in a pagan society or may be a feudal baron, or a proletarian. But what never vary are the necessities of being in the world, of having to labour and to die there. These limitations are neither subjective nor objective, or rather there is both a subjective and an objective aspect of them. Objective, because we meet with them everywhere and they are everywhere recognisable: and subjective because they are lived and are nothing if man does not live them — if, that is to say, he does not freely determine himself and his existence in relation to them. And, diverse though man’s purpose may be, at least none of them is wholly foreign to me, since every human purpose presents itself as an attempt either to surpass these limitations, or to widen them, or else to deny or to accommodate oneself to them. Consequently every purpose, however individual it may be, is of universal value. Every purpose, even that of a Chinese, an Indian or a Negro, can be understood by a 48 Jean Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism European. To say it can be understood, means that the European of 1945 may be striving out of a certain situation towards the same limitations in the same way, and that he may reconceive in himself the purpose of the Chinese, of the Indian or the African. In every purpose there is universality, in this sense that every purpose is comprehensible to every man. Not that this or that purpose defines man for ever, but that it may be entertained again and again. There is always some way of understanding an idiot, a child, a primitive man or a foreigner if one has sufficient information. In this sense we may say that there is a human universality, but it is not something given; it is being perpetually made. I make this universality in choosing myself; I also make it by understanding the purpose of any other man, of whatever epoch. This absoluteness of the act of choice does not alter the relativity of each epoch. What is at the very heart and centre of existentialism, is the absolute character of the free commitment, by which every man realises himself in realising a type of humanity — a commitment always understandable, no matter to whom in no matter what epoch — and its bearing upon the relativity of the cultural pattern which may result from such absolute commitment. One must observe equally the relativity of Cartesianism and the absolute character of the Cartesian commitment. In this sense you may say, if you like, that every one of us makes the absolute by breathing, by eating, by sleeping or by behaving in any fashion whatsoever. There is no difference between free being — being as self-committal, as existence choosing its essence — and absolute being And there is no difference whatever between being as an absolute, temporarily localised that is, localised in history — and universally intelligible being. This does not completely refute the charge of subjectivism. Indeed that objection appears in several other forms, of which the first is as follows. People say to us, “Then it does not matter what you do,” and they say this in various ways. First they tax us with anarchy; then they say, “You cannot judge others, for there is no reason for preferring one purpose to another”; finally, they may say, “Everything being merely voluntary in this choice of yours, you give away with one hand what you pretend to gain with the other.” These three are not very serious objections. As to the first, to say that it does not matter what you choose is not correct. In one sense choice is possible, but what is not possible is not to choose. I can always choose, but I must know that if I do not choose, that is still a choice. This, although it may appear merely formal, is of great importance as a limit to fantasy and caprice. For, when I confront a real situation — for example, that I am a sexual being, able to have relations with a being of the other sex and able to have children — I am obliged to choose my attitude to it, and in every respect I bear the responsibility of the choice which, in committing myself, also commits the whole of humanity. Even if my choice is determined by no a priori value whatever, it can have nothing to do with caprice: and if anyone thinks that this is only Gide’s theory of the acte gratuit over again, he has failed to see the enormous difference between this theory and that of Gide. Gide does not know what a situation is, his “act” is one of pure caprice. In our view, on the contrary, man finds himself in an organised situation in which he is himself involved: his choice involves mankind in its entirety, and he cannot avoid choosing. Either he must remain single, or he must marry without having children, or he must marry and have children. In any case, and whichever he may choose, it is impossible for him, in respect of this situation, not to take complete responsibility. Doubtless he chooses without reference to any pre-established value, but it is unjust to tax him with caprice. Rather let us say that the moral choice is comparable to the construction of a work of art. But here I must at once digress to make it quite clear that we are not propounding an aesthetic morality, for our adversaries are disingenuous enough to reproach us even with that. I mention the work of art only by way of comparison. That being understood, does anyone reproach an 49 Jean Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism artist, when he paints a picture, for not following rules established a priori. Does one ever ask what is the picture that he ought to paint? As everyone knows, there is no pre-defined picture for him to make; the artist applies himself to the composition of a picture, and the picture that ought to be made is precisely that which he will have made. As everyone knows, there are no aesthetic values a priori, but there are values which will appear in due course in the coherence of the picture, in the relation between the will to create and the finished work. No one can tell what the painting of tomorrow will be like; one cannot judge a painting until it is done. What has that to do with morality? We are in the same creative situation. We never speak of a work of art as irresponsible; when we are discussing a canvas by Picasso, we understand very well that the composition became what it is at the time when he was painting it, and that his works are part and parcel of his entire life. It is the same upon the plane of morality. There is this in common between art and morality, that in both we have to do with creation and invention. We cannot decide a priori what it is that should be done. I think it was made sufficiently clear to you in the case of that student who came to see me, that to whatever ethical system he might appeal, the Kantian or any other, he could find no sort of guidance whatever; he was obliged to invent the law for himself. Certainly we cannot say that this man, in choosing to remain with his mother — that is, in taking sentiment, personal devotion and concrete charity as his moral foundations — would be making an irresponsible choice, nor could we do so if he preferred the sacrifice of going away to England. Man makes himself; he is not found ready-made; he makes himself by the choice of his morality, and he cannot but choose a morality, such is the pressure of circumstances upon him. We define man only in relation to his commitments; it is therefore absurd to reproach us for irresponsibility in our choice. In the second place, people say to us, “You are unable to judge others.” This is true in one sense and false in another. It is true in this sense, that whenever a man chooses his purpose and his commitment in all clearness and in all sincerity, whatever that purpose may be, it is impossible for him to prefer another. It is true in the sense that we do not believe in progress. Progress implies amelioration; but man is always the same, facing a situation which is always changing. and choice remains always a choice in the situation. The moral problem has not changed since the time when it was a choice between slavery and anti-slavery — from the time of the war of Secession, for example, until the present moment when one chooses between the M.R.P. [Mouvement Republicain Populaire] 11 and the Communists. We can judge, nevertheless, for, as I have said, one chooses in view of others, and in view of others one chooses himself. One can judge, first – and perhaps this is not a judgment of value, but it is a logical judgment – that in certain cases choice is founded upon an error, and in others upon the truth. One can judge a man by saying that he deceives himself. Since we have defined the situation of man as one of free choice, without excuse and without help, any man who takes refuge behind the excuse of his passions, or by inventing some deterministic doctrine, is a self-deceiver. One may object: “But why should he not choose to deceive himself?” I reply that it is not for me to judge him morally, but I define his self-deception as an error. Here one cannot avoid pronouncing a judgment of truth. The self-deception is evidently a falsehood, because it is a dissimulation of man’s complete liberty of commitment. Upon this same level, I say that it is also a self-deception if I choose to declare that certain values are incumbent upon me; I am in contradiction with myself if I will these values and at the same time say that they impose themselves upon me. If anyone says to me, “And what if I wish to deceive myself?” I answer, “There is no reason why you should not, but I declare that you are doing so, and that the attitude of strict consistency alone is that of good faith.” Furthermore, I can pronounce a moral judgment. For I declare that freedom, in respect of concrete circumstances, can have no other end and aim but itself; and when once a man has 11 = the political party of the Catholic Left. 50 Jean Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism seen that values depend upon himself, in that state of forsakenness he can will only one thing, and that is freedom as the foundation of all values. That does not mean that he wills it in the abstract: it simply means that the actions of men of good faith have, as their ultimate significance, the quest of freedom itself as such. A man who belongs to some communist or revolutionary society wills certain concrete ends, which imply the will to freedom, but that freedom is willed in community. We will freedom for freedom’s sake, in and through particular circumstances. And in thus willing freedom, we discover that it depends entirely upon the freedom of others and that the freedom of others depends upon our own. Obviously, freedom as the definition of a man does not depend upon others, but as soon as there is a commitment, I am obliged to will the liberty of others at the same time as my own. I cannot make liberty my aim unless I make that of others equally my aim. Consequently, when I recognise, as entirely authentic, that man is a being whose existence precedes his essence, and that he is a free being who cannot, in any circumstances, but will his freedom, at the same time I realize that I cannot not will the freedom of others. Thus, in the name of that will to freedom which is implied in freedom itself, I can form judgments upon those who seek to hide from themselves the wholly voluntary nature of their existence and its complete freedom. Those who hide from this total freedom, in a guise of solemnity or with deterministic excuses, I shall call cowards. Others, who try to show that their existence is necessary, when it is merely an accident of the appearance of the human race on earth — I shall call scum. But neither cowards nor scum can be identified except upon the plane of strict authenticity. Thus, although the content of morality is variable, a certain form of this morality is universal. Kant declared that freedom is a will both to itself and to the freedom of others. Agreed: but he thinks that the formal and the universal suffice for the constitution of a morality. We think, on the contrary, that principles that are too abstract break down when we come to defining action. To take once again the case of that student; by what authority, in the name of what golden rule of morality, do you think he could have decided, in perfect peace of mind, either to abandon his mother or to remain with her? There are no means of judging. The content is always concrete, and therefore unpredictable; it has always to be invented. The one thing that counts, is to know whether the invention is made in the name of freedom. Let us, for example, examine the two following cases, and you will see how far they are similar in spite of their difference. Let us take The Mill on the Floss. We find here a certain young woman, Maggie Tulliver, who is an incarnation of the value of passion and is aware of it. She is in love with a young man, Stephen, who is engaged to another, an insignificant young woman. This Maggie Tulliver, instead of heedlessly seeking her own happiness, chooses in the name of human solidarity to sacrifice herself and to give up the man she loves. On the other hand, La Sanseverina in Stendhal’s Chartreuse de Parme, believing that it is passion which endows man with his real value, would have declared that a grand passion justifies its sacrifices, and must be preferred to the banality of such conjugal love as would unite Stephen to the little goose he was engaged to marry. It is the latter that she would have chosen to sacrifice in realising her own happiness, and, as Stendhal shows, she would also sacrifice herself upon the plane of passion if life made that demand upon her. Here we are facing two clearly opposed moralities; but I claim that they are equivalent, seeing that in both cases the overruling aim is freedom. You can imagine two attitudes exactly similar in effect, in that one girl might prefer, in resignation, to give up her lover while the other preferred, in fulfilment of sexual desire, to ignore the prior engagement of the man she loved; and, externally, these two cases might appear the same as the two we have just cited, while being in fact entirely different. The attitude of La Sanseverina is much nearer to that of Maggie Tulliver than to one of careless greed. Thus, you see, the second objection is at once true and false. One can choose anything, but only if it is upon the plane of free commitment. The third objection, stated by saying, “You take with one hand what you give with the other,” means, at bottom, “your values are not serious, since you choose them yourselves.” To that I 51 Jean Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism can only say that I am very sorry that it should be so; but if I have excluded God the Father, there must be somebody to invent values. We have to take things as they are. And moreover, to say that we invent values means neither more nor less than this; that there is no sense in life a priori. Life is nothing until it is lived; but it is yours to make sense of, and the value of it is nothing else but the sense that you choose. Therefore, you can see that there is a possibility of creating a human community. I have been reproached for suggesting that existentialism is a form of humanism: people have said to me, “But you have written in your Nausée that the humanists are wrong, you have even ridiculed a certain type of humanism, why do you now go back upon that?” In reality, the word humanism has two very different meanings. One may understand by humanism a theory which upholds man as the end-in-itself and as the supreme value. Humanism in this sense appears, for instance, in Cocteau’s story Round the World in 80 Hours, in which one of the characters declares, because he is flying over mountains in an airplane, “Man is magnificent!” This signifies that although I, personally have not built aeroplanes I have the benefit of those particular inventions and that I personally, being a man, can consider myself responsible for, and honoured by, achievements that are peculiar to some men. It is to assume that we can ascribe value to man according to the most distinguished deeds of certain men. That kind of humanism is absurd, for only the dog or the horse would be in a position to pronounce a general judgment upon man and declare that he is magnificent, which they have never been such fools as to do — at least, not as far as I know. But neither is it admissible that a man should pronounce judgment upon Man. Existentialism dispenses with any judgment of this sort: an existentialist will never take man as the end, since man is still to be determined. And we have no right to believe that humanity is something to which we could set up a cult, after the manner of Auguste Comte. The cult of humanity ends in Comtian humanism, shut in upon itself, and — this must be said — in Fascism. We do not want a humanism like that. But there is another sense of the word, of which the fundamental meaning is this: Man is all the time outside of himself: it is in projecting and losing himself beyond himself that he makes man to exist; and, on the other band, it is by pursuing transcendent aims that he himself is able to exist. Since man is thus self-surpassing, and can grasp objects only in relation to his self-surpassing, he is himself the heart and centre of his transcendence. There is no other universe except the human universe, the universe of human subjectivity. This relation of transcendence as constitutive of man (not in the sense that God is transcendent, but in the sense of self-surpassing) with subjectivity (in such a sense that man is not shut up in himself but forever present in a human universe) — it is this that we call existential humanism. This is humanism, because we remind man that there is no legislator but himself; that he himself, thus abandoned, must decide for himself; also because we show that it is not by turning back upon himself, but always by seeking, beyond himself, an aim which is one of liberation or of some particular realisation, that man can realize himself as truly human. You can see from these few reflections that nothing could be more unjust than the objections people raise against us. Existentialism is nothing else but an attempt to draw the full conclusions from a consistently atheistic position. Its intention is not in the least that of plunging men into despair. And if by despair one means as the Christians do — any attitude of unbelief, the despair of the existentialists is something different. Existentialism is not atheist in the sense that it would exhaust itself in demonstrations of the non-existence of God. It declares, rather, that even if God existed that would make no difference from its point of view. Not that we believe God does exist, but we think that the real problem is not that of His existence; what man needs is to find himself again and to understand that nothing can save him from himself, not even a valid proof of the existence of God. In this sense existentialism is optimistic. It is a doctrine of action, and it is only by self-deception, by confounding their own despair with ours that Christians can describe us as without hope. 52 Jean Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism Jean-Paul Sartre 1946 Source: Existentialism from Dostoyevsky to Sartre Translator: Walter Kaufman 53 Iris Murdoch The Sovereignty of Good Iris Murdoch ‘The Sovereignty of Good over other concepts’ THE SOVEREIGNTY OF GOOD (Extract) (Ark Paperbacks, 1985) [Numbers in Square brackets refer to pagination in this edition.] [78] Moral philosophy is the examination of the most important of all human activities, and I think that two things are required of it. The examination should be realistic. Human nature, as opposed to the natures of other hypothetical spiritual beings, has certain discoverable attributes, and these should be suitably considered in any discussion of morality. Secondly, since an ethical system cannot but commend an ideal, it should commend a worthy ideal. Ethics should not be merely an analysis of ordinary mediocre conduct, it should be a hypothesis about good conduct and about how this can be achieved. How can we make ourselves better? is a question moral philosophers should attempt to answer. And if I am right the answer will come partly at least in the form of explanatory and persuasive metaphors. The metaphors which I myself favour and the philosopher under whose banner I am fighting I will make clear shortly. First, however, I wish to mention very briefly two fundamental assumptions of my argument. If either of these is denied what follows will be less convincing. I assume that human beings are naturally selfish and that human life has no external point or telos. That human beings are naturally selfish seems true on the evidence, whenever and wherever we look at them, in spite of a very small number of apparent exceptions. About the quality of this selfishness modern psychology has had something to tell us. The psyche is a historically determined individual relentlessly looking after itself. In some ways it resembles a machine; in order to operate it needs sources of energy, and it is predisposed to certain patterns of activity. 1 The area of its vaunted freedom of choice is not usually very great. One of its main pastimes is daydreaming. It is reluctant to face unpleasant realities. Its consciousness is not normally a transparent glass through which [79] it views the world, but a cloud of more or less fantastic reverie designed to protect the psyche from pain. It constantly seeks consolation, either through imagined inflation of self or through fictions of a theological nature. Even its loving is more often than not an assertion of self. I think we can probably recognize ourselves in this rather depressing description. That human life has no external point or telos is a view as difficult to argue as its opposite, and I shall simply assert it. I can see no evidence to suggest that human life is not something self-contained. There are properly many patterns and purposes within life, but there is no general and as it were externally guaranteed pattern or purpose of the kind for which philosophers and theologians used to search. We are what we seem to be, transient mortal creatures subject to necessity and chance. This is to say that there is, in my view, no God in the traditional sense of that term; and the traditional sense is perhaps the only sense. When Bonhoeffer says that God wants us to live as if there were no God, I suspect he is misusing words.2 Equally the various metaphysical substitutes for God – Reason, Science, History are 1 Here Murdoch is alluding particularly to Freud, according to whom the psyche re-enacts certain patterns of behaviour and whose energy is provided by the instinctive drives of the id. 2 Dietrich Bonhoeffer was a German Protestant theologian active in German resistance against the Nazis. He was arrested and imprisoned in 1943 and executed in 1945 for involvement in a plot against 54 Iris Murdoch The Sovereignty of Good false deities. Our destiny can be examined but it cannot be justified or totally explained. We are simply here. And if there is any kind of sense or unity in human life, and the dream of this does not cease to haunt us, it is of some other kind and must be sought within a human experience which has nothing outside it. The idea of life as self-enclosed and purposeless is of course not simply a product of the despair of our own age. It is the natural product of the advance of science and has developed over a long period. It has already in fact occasioned a whole era in the history of philosophy, beginning with Kant and leading on to the existentialism and the analytic philosophy of the present day. The chief characteristic of this phase of philosophy can be briefly stated: Kant [80] abolished God and made man God in His stead. We are still living in the age of the Kantian man, or Kantian man-god. Kant’s conclusive exposure of the so-called proofs of the existence of God, his analysis of the limitations of speculative reason, together with his eloquent portrayal of the dignity of rational man, has had results which might possibly dismay him. How recognizable, how familiar to us, is the man so beautifully portrayed in the Grundlegung, who confronted even with Christ turns away to consider the judgment of his own conscience and to hear the voice of his own reason.3 Stripped of the exiguous metaphysical background which Kant was prepared to allow him, this man is with us still, free, independent, lonely, powerful, rational, responsible, brave the hero of so many novels and books of moral philosophy. The raison d’etre of this attractive but misleading creature is not far to seek. He is the offspring of the age of science, confidently rational and yet increasingly aware of his alienation from the material universe which his discoveries reveal; and since he is not a Hegelian (Kant, not Hegel, has provided Western ethics with its dominating image) his alienation is without cure. He is the ideal citizen of the liberal state, a warning held up to tyrants. He has the virtue which the age requires and admires, courage. It is not such a very long step from Kant to Nietzsche, and from Nietzsche to existentialism and the Anglo-Saxon ethical doctrines which in some ways closely resemble it. In fact Kant’s man had already received a glorious incarnation nearly a century earlier in the work of Milton: his proper name is Lucifer.4 The centre of this type of post-Kantian moral philosophy is the notion of the will as the creator of value. Values which were previously in some sense inscribed in the heavens and guaranteed by God collapse into the human will. There is no transcendent reality. The idea of the good remains indefinable and empty so that human choice may fill it. The sovereign moral concept is freedom, or possibly courage in a [81] sense which identifies it with freedom, will, power. This concept inhabits a quite separate top level of human activity since it is the guarantor of the secondary values created by choice. Act, choice, decision, responsibility, independence are emphasized in this philosophy of puritanical origin and apparent austerity. It must be said in its favour that this image of human nature has been the the life of Adolf Hitler. Theologically, he advocated a convergence between religious and secular views of life and Christian involvement in secular problems. His works include Ethics, The Cost of Discipleship and Letters and Papers from Prison. 3 Grundlegung refers to Kant’s Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals. From the Second Section of that work, “… every example of it that is set before me must first itself be tested by principles of morality, whether it is worthy to serve as an original example, i.e., as a pattern … Even the Holy One of the Gospels must first be compared with our own ideal of moral perfection before we can recognize him as such …” Immanuel Kant, Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals, translated Thomas Kingsmill Abbott. P 263. 4 Lucifer = Satan. Murdoch is referring to Milton’s Paradise Lost. 55 Iris Murdoch The Sovereignty of Good inspiration of political liberalism. However, as Hume once wisely observed, good political philosophy is not necessarily good moral philosophy. This impression is indeed an austere one, but there is something still to be added to it. What place, one might ask, is left in this stern picture of solitary all-responsible man for the life of the emotions? In fact the emotions have a rather significant place. They enter through a back door left open by Kant and the whole romantic movement has followed after. Puritanism and romanticism are natural partners and we are still living with their partnership. Kant held a very interesting theory about the relation of the emotions to the reason. He did not officially recognize the emotions as part of the structure of morality. When he speaks of love he tells us to distinguish between practical love which is a matter of rational actions, and pathological love which is a mere matter of feeling. He wants to segregate the messy warm empirical psyche from the clean operations of the reason. However, in a footnote in the Grundlegung he allows a subordinate place to a particular emotion, that of Achtung, or respect for the moral law. This emotion is a kind of suffering pride which accompanies, though it does not motivate, the recognition of duty. It is an actual experience of freedom (akin to the existentialist Angst), the realization that although swayed by passions we are also capable of rational conduct. A close relation of this concept is Kant’s handsome conception of the Sublime.5 We experience the Sublime when we confront the awful contingency of nature or of human fate [82] and return into ourselves with a proud shudder of rational power.6 How abject we are, and yet our consciousness is of an infinite value. Here it is Belial not Satan who speaks. For who would lose, Though full of pain, this intellectual being, Those thoughts that wander through eternity ...7 The emotions are allowed to return to the scene as a kind of allowable, rather painful, thrill which is a by-product of our status as dignified rational beings. What appears in Kant as a footnote and a side-issue takes, however, a central place in the development which his philosophy underwent in the romantic movement. I would sum this up by saying that romanticism tended to transform the idea of death into the idea of suffering. To do this is of course an age-old human temptation. Few ideas invented by humanity have more power to console than the idea of purgatory. To buy back evil by suffering in the embrace of Good: what could be more satisfying, or as a romantic might say, more thrilling? 5 Kant discusses the ‘Sublime’ in his Critique of Judgement (1791). 6 Probably the most famous expression of this notion of the Sublime is from the Pensées of Blaise Pascal: Man is a mere reed, the weakest thing in nature; but he is a thinking reed. The entire universe need not arm itself to crush him; a vapour, a drop of water, is sufficient to cause his death. But if the universe were to crush him, man would still be nobler than his destroyer, because he knows that he dies, and also the advantage that the universe has over him; but the universe knows nothing of this. Our whole dignity, therefore, consists in thought. From this we must rise, not from space and time which we cannot fill. Let us endeavour then to think aright, this is the principle of morality. 7 Pascal, Pensées 391 [I74-347] H. 3. (trans. John Warrington, Everyman, 1960). John Milton, Paradise Lost. Book ii. Line 146 56 Iris Murdoch The Sovereignty of Good Indeed the central image of Christianity lends itself just this illegitimate transformation. The Imitatio Christi in the later work of Kierkegaard is a distinguished instance of romantic selfindulgence on this theme, though it may seem unkind to say this of a great and most endearing writer who really did suffer for telling his society some truths. 8 The idea of a rather exciting suffering freedom soon began to enliven the austerity of the puritan half of the Kantian picture, and with this went a taming and beautifying of the idea of death, a cult of pseudo-death and pseudo-transience. Death becomes Liebestöd, painful and exhilarating, or at worst charming and sweetly tearful.9 I speak here of course, not of the great romantic artists and thinkers at their best, but of the general beaten track which leads from Kant to the popular philosophies of the present day. When the neo-Kantian Lucifer gets a glimpse of real death and real chance [83] he takes refuge in sublime emotions and veils with an image of tortured freedom that which has been rightly said to be the proper study of philosophers. When Kant wanted to find something clean and pure outside the mess of the selfish empirical psyche he followed a sound instinct but, in my view, looked in the wrong place. His inquiry led him back again into the self, now pictured as angelic, and inside this angel-self his followers have tended to remain. I want now to return to the beginning and look again at the powerful energy system of the self-defensive psyche in the light of the question, How can we make ourselves better? With such an opponent to deal with one may doubt whether the idea of the proud, naked will directed towards right action is a realistic and sufficient formula. I think that the ordinary man, with the simple religious conceptions which make sense for him, has usually held a more just view of the matter than the voluntaristic philosopher,10 and a view incidentally which is in better accord with the findings of modern psychology. Religion normally emphasizes states of mind as well as actions and regards states of mind as the genetic background of action: pureness of heart, meekness of spirit. Religion provides devices for the purification of states of mind. The believer feels that he needs, and can receive, extra help. ‘Not I, but Christ.’11 The real existence of such help is often used as an argument for the truth of religious doctrines. Of course prayer and sacraments may be ‘misused’ by the believer as mere instruments of consolation. But, whatever one thinks of its theological context, it does seem that prayer can actually induce a better quality of consciousness and provide an energy for good action which would not otherwise be available. Modern psychology here supports the ordinary person’s, or ordinary believer’s, instinctive sense of the importance of his states of mind and the availability of supplementary energy. Psychology might indeed prompt contemporary behaviouristic [84] philosophers to reexamine their discarded concepts of experience’ and ‘consciousness’. By opening our eyes we do not necessarily see what confronts us. We are anxiety-ridden animals. Our minds are continually active, fabricating an anxious, usually self-preoccupied, often falsifying veil which partially conceals the world. Our states of consciousness differ in quality, our fantasies and reveries are not trivial and unimportant, they are profoundly connected with our energies and our ability to choose and act. And if quality of consciousness matters, then anything 8 Imitatio Christi = the imitation of Christ. Søren Kierkegaard (1813-1855), Danish philosopher and theologian regarded as a pre-cursor of existentialism. 9 Liebestod, literally ‘love’s death’. In the first instance, it refers to Richard Wagner’s Tristan und Isolde which climaxes in the death of both lovers. More generally, it refers to the romantic notion that love is only genuine if it is fatal to one or both parties. 10 I.e., in this context, a philosopher who regards the will as the source of value. Callicles, Nietzsche and Sartre are all voluntarists. 11 Cf. “I have been crucified with Christ, it is no longer I who live, but Christ who lives in me....” Galatians 2:20 57 Iris Murdoch The Sovereignty of Good which alters consciousness in the direction of unselfishness, objectivity and realism is to be connected with virtue. Following a hint in Plato (Phaedrus 250) I shall start by speaking of what is perhaps the most obvious thing in our surroundings which is an occasion of ‘unselfing’, and that is what is popularly called beauty. Recent philosophers tend to avoid this term because they prefer to talk of reasons rather than of experiences. But the implication of experience with beauty seems to me to be something of great importance which should not be by-passed in favour of analysis of critical vocabularies.12 Beauty is the convenient and traditional name of something which art and nature share, and which gives a fairly clear sense to the idea of quality of experience and change of consciousness. I am looking out of window in an anxious and resentful state of mind, oblivious of my surroundings, brooding perhaps on some damage done to my prestige. Then suddenly I observe a hovering kestrel. In a moment everything is altered. The brooding self with its hurt vanity has disappeared. There is nothing now but kestrel. And when I return to thinking of the other matter it seems less important. And of course this is something which we may also do deliberately: give attention to nature in order to clear our minds of selfish care. It may seem odd to start the argument against what I have roughly labelled as ‘romanticism’ by using the case of attention to [85] nature. In fact I do not think that any of the great romantics really believed that we receive but what we give and in our life alone does nature live,13 although the lesser ones tended to follow Kant’s lead and use nature as an occasion for exalted self-feeling. The great romantics, including the one I have just quoted, transcended ‘romanticism’. A self-directed enjoyment of nature seems to me to be something forced. More naturally, as well as more properly, we take a self-forgetful pleasure in the sheer alien pointless independent existence of animals, birds, stones and trees. ‘Not how the world is, but that it is, is the mystical.’14 I take this starting-point, not because I think it is the most important place of moral change, but because I think it is the most accessible one. It is so patently a good thing to take delight in flowers and animals that people who bring home potted plants and watch kestrels might even be surprised at the notion that these things have anything to do with virtue. The surprise is a product of the fact that, as Plato pointed out, beauty is the only spiritual thing which we love by instinct. When we move from beauty in nature to beauty in art we are already in a more difficult region. The experience of art is more easily degraded than the experience of nature. A great deal of art, perhaps most art, actually is self-consoling fantasy, and even great art cannot guarantee the quality of its consumer’s consciousness. However, great art exists and is sometimes properly experienced and even a shallow experience of what is great can have its effect. Art, and by ‘art’ from now on I mean good art, not fantasy art, affords us a pure delight in the independent existence of what is excellent. Both in its genesis and its enjoyment it is a thing totally opposed to selfish obsession. It invigorates our best faculties and, to use Platonic language, inspires love in the highest part of the soul. It is able to do this partly by virtue of something which it shares with nature: a perfection of form which invites “analysis of critical vocabularies” was the focus of aesthetics at the time and remains the focus of much aesthetics. However in more recent years, some aestheticians have begun to write about beauty, which was a central topic of aesthetics in the 18th and 19th centuries. 13 Murdoch is quoting directly from Samuel Taylor Coleridge’s poem Dejection: An Ode (1802): “O Lady! we receive but what we give,/ And in our life alone does Nature live”. Her reference to Kant alludes again to his idea of the Sublime. 14 Murdoch is quoting Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus 6.44. 12 58 Iris Murdoch The Sovereignty of Good unpossessive contemplation [86] and resists absorption into the selfish dream life of the consciousness. Art however, considered as a sacrament or a source of good energy, possesses an extra dimension. Art is less accessible than nature but also more edifying since it is actually a human product, and certain arts are actually ‘about’ human affairs in a direct sense. Art is a human product and virtues as well as talents are required of the artist. The good artist, in relation to his art, is brave, truthful, patient, humble; and even in non-representational art we may receive intuitions of these qualities.15 One may also suggest, more cautiously, that nonrepresentational art does seem to express more positively something which is to do with virtue. The spiritual role of music has often been acknowledged, though theorists have been chary of analysing it. However that may be, the representational arts, which more evidently hold the mirror up to nature, seem to be concerned with morality in a way which is not simply an effect of our intuition of the artist’s discipline. These arts, especially literature and painting, show us the peculiar sense in which the concept of virtue is tied on to the human condition. They show us the absolute pointlessness of virtue while exhibiting its supreme importance; the enjoyment of art is a training in the love of virtue. The pointlessness of art is not the pointlessness of a game; it is the pointlessness of human life itself, and form in art is properly the simulation of the self-contained aimlessness of the universe. Good art reveals what we are usually too selfish and too timid to recognize, the minute and absolutely random detail of the world, and reveals it together with a sense of unity and form. This form often seems to us mysterious because it resists the easy patterns of the fantasy, whereas there is nothing mysterious about the forms of bad art since they are the recognizable and familiar rat-runs of selfish day-dreaming. Good art shows us how difficult it is to be objective by showing us how differently the world looks to an objective vision. [87] We are presented with a truthful image of the human condition in a form which can be steadily contemplated; and indeed this is the only context in which many of us are capable of contemplating it at all. Art transcends selfish and obsessive limitations of personality and can enlarge the sensibility of its consumer. It is a kind of goodness by proxy. Most of all it exhibits to us the connection, in human beings, of clear realistic vision with compassion. The realism of a great artist is not a photographic realism, it is essentially both pity and justice. Herein we find a remarkable redemption of our tendency to conceal death and chance by the invention of forms. Any story which we tell about ourselves consoles us since it imposes pattern upon something which might otherwise seem intolerably chancy and incomplete. However, human life is chancy and incomplete. It is the role of tragedy, and also of comedy, and of painting to show us suffering without a thrill and death without a consolation. Or if there is any consolation it is the austere consolation of a beauty which teaches that nothing in life is of any value except the attempt to be virtuous. Masochism is the artist’s greatest and most subtle enemy. It is not easy to portray death, real death, not fake prettified death. Even Tolstoy did not really manage it in Ivan Ilyich,16 although he did elsewhere. The great deaths of literature are few, but they show us with an exemplary clarity the way in which art invigorates us by a juxtaposition, almost an identification, of pointlessness and value. The 15 Representational arts = painting, sculpture, literature; Non-representational arts = music, architecture. 16 Murdoch refers to Tolstoy’s novella The Death of Ivan Ilyich (1886). 59 Iris Murdoch The Sovereignty of Good death of Patroclus, the death of Cordelia, the death of Petya Rostov.17 All is vanity. The only thing which is of real importance is the ability to see it all clearly and respond to it justly which is inseparable from virtue. Perhaps one of the greatest achievements of all is to join this sense of absolute mortality not to the tragic but to the comic. Shallow and Silence. Stefan Trofimovich Verhovensky.18 Art then is not a diversion or a side-issue, it is the most [88] educational of all human activities and a place in which the nature of morality can be seen. Art gives a clear sense to many ideas which seem more puzzling when we meet with them elsewhere, and it is a clue to what happens elsewhere. An understanding of any art involves a recognition of hierarchy and authority. There are very evident degrees of merit, there are heights and distances; even Shakespeare is not perfect. Good art, unlike bad art, unlike ‘happenings’, 19 is something preeminently outside us and resistant to our consciousness. We surrender ourselves to its authority with a love which is unpossessive and unselfish. Art shows us the only sense in which the permanent and incorruptible is compatible with the transient; and whether representational or not it reveals to us aspects of our world which our ordinary dull dreamconsciousness is unable to see. Art pierces the veil and gives sense to the notion of a reality which lies beyond appearance; it exhibits virtue in its true guise in the context of death and chance. Plato held that beauty could be a starting-point of the good life, but he came to mistrust art and we can see played out in that great spirit the peculiarly distressing struggle between the artist and the saint. Plato allowed to the beauty of the lovely boy an awakening power which he denied to the beauty of nature or of art. He seems to have come to believe that all art is bad art, a mere fiction and consolation which distorts reality. About nature he seems, in the context of the theory of forms, to have been at least once in doubt. Are there forms of mud, hair and dirt? If there are then nature is redeemed into the area of truthful vision. (My previous argument assumes of course, in Platonic terms, that there are.) Another startingpoint, or road, which Plato speaks of more often however is the way of the technai, the sciences, crafts, and intellectual disciplines excluding the arts. I think there is a way of the intellect, a sense in which intellectual disciplines are moral disciplines, and this is not too difficult [89] to discern. There are important bridge ideas between morality and other at first sight different human activities, and these ideas are perhaps most clearly seen in the context of the technai. And as when we use the nature of art as a clue, we may be able to learn more about the central area of morality if we examine what are essentially the same concepts more simply on display elsewhere. I mean such concepts as justice, accuracy, truthfulness, realism, humility, courage as the ability to sustain clear vision, love as attachment or even passion without sentiment or self. The techne which Plato thought was most important was mathematics, because it was most rigorous and abstract. I shall take an example of a techne more congenial to myself: learning a language. If I am learning, for instance, Russian, I am confronted by an authoritative structure which commands my respect. The task is difficult and the goal is distant and perhaps never entirely attainable. My work is a progressive revelation of something which exists independently of me. Attention is rewarded by a knowledge of reality. Love of Russian The death of Patroclus – Homer, Iliad, Book 16; the death of Cordelia – Shakespeare, King Lear Act 5, scene 3; the death of Petya Rostov – Tolstoy, War and Peace Book 14, chapter 11. 18 Main character of Dostoyevsky’s The Devils, also known in English as The Possessed. 19 ‘Happenings’ is species of ‘performance art’. 17 60 Iris Murdoch The Sovereignty of Good leads me away from myself towards something alien to me, something which my consciousness cannot take over, swallow up, deny or make unreal. The honesty and humility required of the student-not to pretend to know what one does not know – is the preparation for the honesty and humility of the scholar who does not even feel tempted to suppress the fact which damns his theory. Of course a techne can be misused; a scientist might feel he ought to give up a certain branch of study if he knew that his discoveries would be used wickedly. But apart from special contexts, studying is normally an exercise of virtue as well as of talent, and shows us a fundamental way in which virtue is related to the real world. I suggested that we could see most clearly in the case of the technai, the nature of concepts very central to morality such as justice, truthfulness or humility. We can see too the [90] growth and the inter-connection of these concepts, as when what looks like mere accuracy at one end looks more like justice or courage or even love at the other. Developing a Sprachefuhl20 is developing a judicious respectful sensibility to something which is very like another organism. An intellectual discipline can play the same kind of role as that which I have attributed to art, it can stretch the imagination, enlarge the vision and strengthen the judgment. When Plato made mathematics the king techne he was regarding mathematical thought as leading the mind away from the material world and enabling it to perceive a reality of a new kind, very unlike ordinary appearances. And one might regard other disciplines, history, philology, chemistry, as presenting us with a new kind of subject-matter and showing us a new reality behind appearance. These studies are not only an exercise in virtue, they might be thought of as introductory images of the spiritual life. But they are not the spiritual life itself and the mind which has ascended no farther has not achieved the whole of virtue. I want now to make a closer approach to the central subject of my argument, the Good. Beauty and the technai are, to use Plato’s image, the text written in large letters. The concept Good itself is the much harder to discern but essentially similar text written in small letters. In intellectual disciplines and in the enjoyment of art and nature we discover value in our ability to forget self, to be realistic, to perceive justly. We use our imagination not to escape the world but to join it, and this exhilarates us because of the distance between our ordinary dulled consciousness and an apprehension of the real. The value concepts are here patently tied on to the world, they are stretched as it were between the truth-seeking mind and the world, they are not moving about on their own as adjuncts of the personal will. The authority of morals is the authority of truth, that is of reality. We can see the length, the extension, of these concepts as patient attention [91] transforms accuracy without interval into just discernment. Here too we can see it as natural to the particular kind of creatures that we are that love should be inseparable from justice, and clear vision from respect for the real. That virtue operates in exactly the same kind of way in the central area of morality is less easy to perceive. Human beings are far more complicated and enigmatic and ambiguous than languages or mathematical concepts, and selfishness operates in a much more devious and frenzied manner in our relations with them. Ignorance, muddle, fear, wishful thinking, lack of tests often make us feel that moral choice is something arbitrary, a matter for personal will rather than for attentive study. Our attachments tend to be selfish and strong, and the transformation of our loves from selfishness to unselfishness is sometimes hard even to conceive of. Yet is the situation really so different? Should a retarded child be kept at home or sent to an institution? Should an elderly relation who is a trouble-maker be cared for or asked to go away? Should an unhappy marriage be continued for the sake of the children? 20 a feel for a language. 61 Iris Murdoch The Sovereignty of Good Should I leave my family in order to do political work? Should I neglect them in order to practise my art? The love which brings the right answer is an exercise of justice and realism and really looking. The difficulty is to keep the attention fixed upon the real situation and to prevent it from returning surreptitiously to the self with consolations of self-pity, resentment, fantasy and despair. The refusal to attend may even induce a fictitious sense of freedom: I may as well toss a coin. Of course virtue is good habit and dutiful action. But the background condition of such habit and such action, in human beings, is a just mode of vision and a good quality of consciousness. It is a task to come to see the world as it is. A philosophy which leaves duty without a context and exalts the idea of freedom and power as a separate top level value ignores this task and obscures the relation between virtue and reality. We act [92] rightly ‘when the time comes’ not out of strength of will but out of the quality of our usual attachments and with the kind of energy and discernment which we have available. And to this the whole activity of our consciousness is relevant. The central explanatory image which joins together the different aspects of the picture which I have been trying to exhibit is the concept of Good. It is a concept which is not easy to understand partly because it has so many false doubles, jumped-up intermediaries invented by human selfishness to make the difficult task of virtue look easier and more attractive: History, God, Lucifer, Ideas of power, freedom, purpose, reward, even judgment are irrelevant. Mystics of all kinds have usually known this and have attempted by extremities of language to portray the nakedness and aloneness of Good, its absolute for-nothingness. One might say that true morality is a sort of unesoteric mysticism, having its source in an austere and unconsoled love of the Good. When Plato wants to explain Good he uses the image of the sun. The moral pilgrim emerges from the cave and begins to see the real world in the light of the sun, and last of all is able to look at the sun itself. I want now to comment on various aspects of this extremely rich metaphor.21 The sun is seen at the end of a long quest which involves a reorientation (the prisoners have to turn round) and an ascent. It is real, it is out there, but very distant. It gives light and energy and enables us to know truth. In its light we see the things of the world in their true relationships. Looking at it itself is supremely difficult and is unlike looking at things in its light. It is a different kind of thing from what it illuminates. Note the metaphor of ‘thing’ here. Good is a concept about which, and not only in philosophical language, we naturally use a Platonic terminology, when we speak about seeking the Good, or loving the Good. We may also speak seriously of ordinary things, people, works [93] of art, as being good, although we are also well aware of their imperfections. Good lives as it were on both sides of the barrier and we can combine the aspiration to complete goodness with a realistic sense of achievement within our limitations. For all our frailty the command ‘be perfect’ has sense for us. The concept Good resists collapse into the selfish empirical consciousness. It is not a mere value tag of the choosing will, and functional and casual uses of ‘good’ (a good knife, a good fellow) are not, as some philosophers have wished to argue, clues to the structure of the concept. The proper and serious use of the term refers us to a perfection which is perhaps never exemplified in the world we know (‘There is no good in us’) and which carries with it the ideas of hierarchy and transcendence. How do we know that the very great are not the perfect? We see differences, we sense directions, and we know that the Good is still somewhere beyond. The self, the place where we live, is a place of illusion. Goodness is 21 In the Myth of the Cave, Plato likens our situation to prisoners who have been chained in a Cave and are forced to look at shadows cast upon the wall of the cave rather than real objects. We will study this text in some detail in Unit 4. 62 Iris Murdoch The Sovereignty of Good connected with the attempt to see the unself, to see and to respond to the real world in the light of a virtuous consciousness. This is the non-metaphysical meaning of the idea of transcendence to which philosophers have so constantly resorted in their explanations of goodness. ‘Good is a transcendent reality’ means that virtue is the attempt to pierce the veil of selfish consciousness and join the world as it really is. It is an empirical fact about human nature that this attempt cannot be entirely successful. 63 Plato Phaedo Plato PHAEDO [This translation is taken from Plato, The Last Days of Socrates, Penguin 1959.] [105a] ‘Well, see whether you accept this definition: Not only does an opposite not admit its opposite, but if anything is accompanied by a Form which has an opposite, and meets that opposite, then the thing which is accompanied never admits the opposite of the Form by which it is accompanied. Let me refresh your memory; there is no harm in hearing a thing several times. Five will not admit the Form of Even, nor will ten, which is double five, admit the Form of Odd. Twin has an opposite of its own, but [105b] at the same time it will not admit the Form of Odd. Nor will one and a half, or other fractions such as a half or threequarters and so on, admit the form of Whole, assuming that you follow me and agree.’ ‘I follow and agree perfectly,’ said Cebes. ‘Then run over the same ground with me from the beginning; and don’t answer in the exact terms of the question, but follow my example. I say this because besides the “safe answer” that I described at first, as the result of this discussion I now see another means of safety. Suppose, for instance, that you ask me what must become present in a body to make it hot, I shall not return the safe but simplistic answer that it is heat, but a more sophisticated one, [105c] based on the results of our discussion - namely that it is fire. And if you ask what must become present in a body to make it diseased, I shall say not disease but fever. Similarly if you ask what must become present in a number to make it odd, I shall say not oddness but unity; and so on. See whether you have a sufficient grasp now of what I want from you.’ ‘Quite sufficient.’ Socrates argues that the soul is such a thing which always brings a quality to that which it occupies, and cannot itself be coupled with the opposite quality. It must retire or perish. ‘Then tell me, what must be present in a body to make it alive?’ ‘Soul.’ ‘Is this always so?’ [105d] ‘Of course.’ ‘So whenever soul takes possession of a body, it always brings living with it?’ ‘Yes, it does.’ ‘Is there an opposite to living, or not?’ ‘Yes, there is.’ ‘What?’ ‘Dying.’ ‘Does it follow, then, from our earlier agreement, that soul will never admit the opposite of that which accompanies it?’ ‘Most definitely,’ said Cebes. ‘Well, now, what name did we apply just now to that which does not admit the Form of even?’ 64 Plato Phaedo ‘Uneven.’ ‘And what do we call that which does not admit justice, or culture?’ [105e] ‘Uncultured; and the other unjust.’ ‘Very good. And what do we call that which does not admit dying?’ ‘Un-dying.’ ‘And soul does not admit death?’ ‘No. ‘So soul is un-dying.’ ‘Yes, it is un-dying.’ ‘Well,’ said Socrates, ‘can we say that that has been proved? What do you think?’ ‘Most completely, Socrates.’ The argument is concluded. What is ‘un-dying’ cannot surely perish; therefore it must withdraw. ‘Here is another question for you, Cebes. If the uneven were [106a] necessarily imperishable, would not three be imperishable?’ ‘Of course.’ ‘Then again, if what is un-hot were necessarily imperishable, when you applied heat to snow, would not the snow withdraw still intact and unmelted? It could not cease to exist, nor on the other hand could it remain where it was and admit the heat.’ ‘That is true.’ ‘In the same way I assume that if what is un-cold were imperishable, when anything cold approached fire, it could never go out or cease to exist; it would depart and be gone unharmed.’ ‘That must be so.’ [106b] ‘Are we not bound to say the same of the un-dying? If what is un-dying is also imperishable, it is impossible that at the approach of death soul should cease to be. It follows from what we have already said that it cannot admit death, or be dead; just as we said that three cannot be even, nor can odd; nor can fire be cold, nor can the heat which is in the fire. “But,” it may be objected, “granting (as has been agreed) that odd does not become even at [106c] the approach of even, why should it not cease to exist, and something even take its place?” In reply to this we could not insist that the odd does not cease to exist - because what is un-even is not imperishable; but if this were conceded, we could easily insist that, at the approach of even, odd and three retire and depart. And we could be equally insistent about fire and heat and all the rest of them, could we not?’ ‘Certainly.’ ‘So now in the case of the un-dying, if it is conceded that this is also imperishable, soul will be imperishable as well as un-dying. [106d] ‘Otherwise we shall need another argument.’ ‘There is no need on that account,’ said Cebes. ‘If what is undying and eternal cannot avoid destruction, it is hard to see how anything else can.’ 65 Plato Phaedo ‘And I imagine that it would be admitted by everyone,’ said Socrates, ‘that God at any rate, and the Form of Life, and anything else that is un-dying, can never cease to exist.’ ‘Yes indeed; by all men certainly, and even more, I suppose, by the gods.’ [106e] ‘Then since what is un-dying is also indestructible, if soul is really un-dying, surely it must be imperishable too.’ ‘Quite inevitably.’ ‘So it appears that when death comes to a man, the mortal part of him dies, but the un-dying part retires at the approach of death and escapes unharmed and indestructible.’ ‘Evidently.’ ‘Then it is as certain as anything can be, Cebes, that soul is undying and imperishable, and that our souls will really exist in the next world.’ ‘Well, Socrates,’ said Cebes, ‘for my part I have no criticisms, [107a] and no doubt about the truth of your argument. But if Simmias here or anyone else has any criticism to make, he had better not keep it to himself; because if anyone wants to say or hear any more about this subject, I don’t see to what other occasion he is to defer it.’ Socrates gives his view of the nature of the universe and of the soul’s fate after death. The material is myth-like, and comparable with ‘myths’ of the after-life with which the Gorgias and Republic conclude. It makes no profession of ascertainable literal truth. It has clearly been composed specifically for the Phaedo, in such a way as to reflect the gulf between the hazy world of sensation and the clear world of the intellect that the rest of the work has already pointed to. It also suggests an enormous gap between the painful or at least unattractive environment which awaits the common man after death and the bright visions of a higher world which await the philosopher. It therefore performs a protreptic purpose, encouraging Socrates’ followers to go on with their mission after his death so that they may look forward to the day when they may follow him. ‘As a matter of fact,’ said Simmias, I have no doubts myself either now, in view of what you have just been saying. All the [107b] same, the subject is so vast, and I have such a poor opinion of our weak human nature, that I can’t help still feeling some misgivings.’ ‘Quite right, Simmias,’ said Socrates, land what is more, even if you find our original assumptions convincing, they still need more accurate consideration. If you and your friends examine them closely enough, I believe that you will arrive at the truth of the matter, in so far as it is possible for the human mind to attain it; and if you are sure that you have done this, you will not need to inquire further.’ ‘That is true,’ said Simmias. [107c] ‘But there is a further point, gentlemen,’ said Socrates, ‘which deserves your attention. If the soul is immortal, it demands our care not only for that part of time which we call life, but for all time; and indeed it would seem now’ that it will be extremely dangerous to neglect it. If death were a release from everything, it would be a boon for the wicked, because by dying they would be released not only from the body but also from their own wicked-ness together with the soul; but as it is, since the soul has emerged as something immortal, it can have no escape or security from evil [107d] except by becoming as good and wise as it possibly can. For it takes nothing with it to the next world except its education and training; and these, we are told are of supreme importance in helping or harming those who have died at the very beginning of their journey to the other world. 66 Descartes Discourse on Method Rene Descartes THE DISCOURSE ON METHOD, PART V [Numbers in brackets refer to page numbers in Rene Descartes, The Philosophical Writings of Rene Descartes, edited by John Cottingham et al. Cambridge University Press, 1985)] I explained all these matters in sufficient detail in the treatise I previously intended to publish. And then I showed what structure the nerves and muscles of the human body must have in order to make the animal spirits inside them strong enough to move its limbs - as when we see severed heads continue to move about and bite the earth although they are no longer alive. I also indicated what changes must occur in the brain in order to cause waking, sleep and dreams; how light, sounds, smells, tastes, heat and the other qualities of external objects can imprint various ideas on the brain through the mediation of the senses; and how hunger, thirst, and the other internal passions can also send their ideas there. And I explained which part of the brain must be taken to be the ‘common sense,’ where these ideas are received; the memory, which preserves them; and the corporeal imagination, which can change them in various ways, form them into new ideas, and, by distributing the animal spirits to the muscles, make the parts of this body move in as many different ways as the parts of our bodies can move without being guided by the will, and in a manner which is just as appropriate to the objects of the senses and the internal passions. This will not seem at all strange to those who know how many kinds of automatons, or moving machines, the skill of man can construct with the use of very few parts, in comparison with the great multitude of bones, muscles, nerves, arteries, veins and all the other parts that are in the body of any animal. For they will regard this body as a machine which, having been made by the hands of God, is incomparably better ordered than any machine that can be devised by man, and contains in itself movements more wonderful than those in any such machine. I made special efforts to show that if any such machines had the organs and outward shape of a monkey or of some other animal that lacks reason, we should have no means of knowing that they did not possess entirely the same nature as these animals; whereas if any such machines bore a resemblance to our bodies and imitated our actions as closely as possible for all practical purposes, we should still have two very certain [140] means of recognizing that they were not real men. The first is that they could never use words, or put together other signs, as we do in order to declare our thoughts to others. For we can certainly conceive of a machine so constructed that it utters words, and even utters words which correspond to bodily actions causing a change in its organs (e.g. if you touch it in one spot it asks what you want of it, if you touch it in another it cries out that you are hurting it, and so on). But it is not conceivable that such a machine should produce different arrangements of words so as to give an appropriately meaningful answer to whatever is said in its presence, as the dullest of men can do. Secondly, even though such machines might do some things as well as we do them, or perhaps even better, they would inevitably fail in others, which would reveal that they were acting not through understanding but only from the disposition of their organs. For whereas reason is a universal instrument which can be used in all kinds of situations, these organs need some particular disposition for each particular action; hence it is for all practical purposes impossible for a machine to have enough different organs to make it act in all the contingencies of life in the way in which our reason makes us act. Now in just these two ways we can also know the difference between man and beast. For it is quite remarkable that there are no men so dull-witted or stupid – and this includes even 67 Descartes Discourse on Method madmen – that they are incapable of arranging various words together and forming an utterance from them in order to make their thoughts understood; whereas there is no other animal, however perfect and well-endowed it may be, that can do the like. This does not happen because they lack the necessary organs, for we see that magpies and parrots can utter words as we do, and yet they cannot speak as we do: that is, they cannot show that they are thinking what they are saying. On the other hand, men born deaf and dumb, and thus deprived of speech-organs as much as the beasts or even more so, normally invent their own signs to make themselves understood by those who, being regularly in their company, have the time to learn their language. This shows not merely that the beasts have less reason than men, but that they have no reason at all. For it patently requires very little reason to be able to speak; and since as much inequality can be observed among the animals of a given species as among human beings, and some animals are more easily trained than others, it would be incredible that a superior specimen of the monkey or parrot species should not be able to speak as well as the stupidest child – or at least as well as a child with a defective brain – if their souls were not completely different in nature from ours. And we must not confuse speech with the natural movements which express passions and which can be imitated by [141] machines as well as by animals. Nor should we think, like some of the ancients, that the beasts speak, although we do not understand their language. For if that were true, then since they have many organs that correspond to ours, they could make themselves understood by us as well as by their fellows. It is also a very remarkable fact that although many animals show more skill than we do in some of their actions, yet the same animals show none at all in many others; so what they do better does not prove that they have any intelligence, for if it did then they would have more intelligence than any of us and would excel us in everything. It proves rather that they have no intelligence at all, and that it is nature which acts in them according to the disposition of their organs. In the same way a clock, consisting only of wheels and springs, can count the hours and measure time more accurately than we can with all our wisdom. After that, I described the rational soul, and showed that, unlike the other things of which I had spoken, it cannot be derived in any way from the potentiality of matter, but must be specially created. And I showed how it is not sufficient for it to be lodged in the human body like a helmsman in his ship, except perhaps to move its limbs, but that it must be more closely joined and united with the body in order to have, besides this power of movement, feelings and appetites like ours and so constitute a real man. Here I dwelt a little upon the subject of the soul, because it is of the greatest importance. For after the error of those who deny God, which I believe I have already adequately refuted, there is none that leads weak minds further from the straight path of virtue than that of imagining that the souls of the beasts are of the same nature as ours, and hence that after this present life we have nothing to fear or to hope for, any more than flies and ants. But when we know how much the beasts differ from us, we understand much better the arguments which prove that our soul is of a nature entirely independent of the body, and consequently that it is not bound to die with it. And since we cannot see any other causes which destroy the soul, we are naturally led to conclude that it is immortal. 68 Alan Turing Computing Machinery and Intelligence A.M. Turing (1912 – 54) COMPUTING MACHINERY AND INTELLIGENCE [Originally published in Mind 59, no. 236 (1950), pp. 4-30. This extract follows Douglas Hofstadter & Daniel Dennett (eds), The Mind’s I (Penguin, 1974)] 1. The Imitation Game I propose to consider the question “Can machines think?” This should begin with definitions of the meaning of the terms “machine” and “think.” The definitions might be framed so as to reflect so far as possible the normal use of the words, but this attitude is dangerous. If the meaning of the words “machine” and “think” are to be found by examining how they are commonly used it is difficult to escape the conclusion that the meaning and the answer to the question, “Can machines think?” is to be sought in a statistical survey such as a Gallup poll. But this is absurd. Instead of attempting such a definition I shall replace the question by another, which is closely related to it and is expressed in relatively unambiguous words. The new form of the problem can be described in terms of a game which we call the “imitation game.” It is played with three people, a man (A), a woman (B), and an interrogator (C) who may be of either sex. The interrogator stays in a room apart from the other two. The object of the game for the interrogator is to determine which of the other two is the man and which is the woman. He knows them by labels X and Y, and at the end of the game he says either “X is A and Y is B” or “X is B and Y is A.” The interrogator is allowed to put questions to A and B thus: C: Will X please tell me the length of his or her hair? Now suppose X is actually A, then A must answer. It is A’s object in the game to try to cause C to make the wrong identification. His answer might therefore be “My hair is shingled, and the longest strands are about nine inches long.” In order that tones of voice may not help the interrogator the answers should be written, or better still, typewritten. The ideal arrangement is to have a teleprinter communicating between the two rooms. Alternatively the question and answers can be repeated by an intermediary. The object of the game for the third player (B) is to help the interrogator. The best strategy for her is probably to give truthful answers. She can add such things as “I am the woman, don’t listen to him!” to her answers, but it will avail nothing as the man can make similar remarks. We now ask the question, “What will happen when a machine takes the part of A in this game?” Will the interrogator decide wrongly as often when the game is played like this as he does when the game is played between a man and a woman? These questions replace our original, “Can machines think?” 2. Critique of the New Problem As well as asking, “What is the answer to this new form of the question,” one may ask, “Is this new question a worthy one to investigate?” This latter question we investigate without further ado, thereby cutting short an infinite regress. The new problem has the advantage of drawing a fairly sharp line between the physical and the intellectual capacities of a man. No engineer or chemist claims to be able to produce a material which is indistinguishable from the human skin. It is possible that at some time this 69 Alan Turing Computing Machinery and Intelligence might be done, but even supposing this invention available we should feel there was little point in trying to make a “thinking machine” more human by dressing it up in such artificial flesh. The form in which we have set the problem reflects this fact in the condition which prevents the interrogator from seeing or touching the other competitors, or hearing their voices. Some other advantages of the proposed criterion may be shown up by specimen questions and answers. Thus: Q: Please write me a sonnet on the subject of the Forth Bridge. A: Count me out on this one. I never could write poetry. Q: Add 34957 to 70764. A: (Pause about 30 seconds and then give as answer) 105621. Q: Do you play chess? A: Yes. Q: I have K at my K 1, and no other pieces. You have only K at K6 and R at R1. It is your move. What do you play? A: (After a pause of 15 seconds) R-R8 mate. The question and answer method seems to be suitable for introducing almost any one of the fields of human endeavour that we wish to include. We do not wish to penalize the machine for its inability to shine in beauty competitions, nor to penalize a man for losing in a race against an airplane. The conditions of our game make these disabilities irrelevant. The “witnesses” can brag, if they consider it advisable, as much as they please about their charms, strength or heroism, but the interrogator cannot demand practical demonstrations. The game may perhaps be criticized on the ground that the odds are weighted too heavily against the machine. If the man were to try and pretend to be the machine he would clearly make a very poor showing. He would be given away at once by slowness and inaccuracy in arithmetic. May not machines carry out something which ought to be described as thinking but which is very different from what a man does? This objection is a very strong one, but at least we can say that if, nevertheless, a machine can be constructed to play the imitation game satisfactorily, we need not be troubled by this objection. It might be urged that when playing the “imitation game” the best strategy for the machine may possibly be something other than imitation of the behaviour of a man. This may be, but I think it is unlikely that there is any great effect of this kind. In any case there is no intention to investigate here the theory of the game, and it will be assumed that the best strategy is to try to provide answers that would naturally be given by a man. 3. The Machines Concerned in the Came The question which we put in §1 will not be quite definite until we have specified what we mean by the word “machine.” It is natural that we should wish to permit every kind of engineering technique to be used in our machines. We also wish to allow the possibility that an engineer or team of engineers may construct a machine which works, but whose manner of operation cannot be satisfactorily described by its constructors because they have applied a method which is largely experimental. Finally, we wish to exclude from the machines men born in the usual manner. It is difficult to frame the definitions so as to satisfy these three conditions. One might for instance insist that the team of engineers should be all of one sex, but this would not really be satisfactory, for it is probably possible to rear a complete in- 70 Alan Turing Computing Machinery and Intelligence dividual from a single cell of the skin (say) of a man. To do so would be a feat of biological technique deserving of the very highest praise, but we would not be inclined to regard it as a case of “constructing a thinking machine.” This prompts us to abandon the requirement that every kind of technique should be permitted. We are the more ready to do so in view of the fact that the present interest in “thinking machines” has been aroused by a particular kind of machine, usually called an “electronic computer” or “digital computer.” Following this suggestion we only permit digital computers to take part in our game. … This special property of digital computers, that they can mimic any discrete state machine, is described by saying that they are universal machines. The existence of machines with this property has the important consequence that, considerations of speed apart, it is unnecessary to design various new machines to do various computing processes. They can all be done with one digital computer, suitably programmed for each case. It will be seen that as a consequence of this all digital computers are in a sense equivalent. 6. Contrary Views on the Main Question We may now consider the ground to have been cleared and we are ready to proceed to the debate on our question, “Can machines think?” … We cannot altogether abandon the original form of the problem, for opinions will differ as to the appropriateness of the substitution and we must at least listen to what has to be said in this connection. It will simplify matters for the reader if I explain first my own beliefs in the matter. Consider first the more accurate form of the question. I believe that in about fifty years’ time it will be possible to program computers, with a storage capacity of about 109, to make them play the imitation game so well that an average interrogator will not have more than 70 per cent chance of making the right identification after five minutes of questioning. The original question, “Can machines think?” I believe to be too meaningless to deserve discussion. Nevertheless I believe that at the end of the century the use of words and general educated opinion will have altered so much that one will be able to speak of machines thinking without expecting to be contradicted. I believe further that no useful purpose is served by concealing these beliefs. The popular view that scientists proceed inexorably from well-established fact to well-established fact, never being influenced by any unproved conjecture, is quite mistaken. Provided it is made clear which are proved facts and which are conjectures, no harm can result. Conjectures are of great importance since they suggest useful lines of research. I now proceed to consider opinions opposed to my own. (1) The Theological Objection. Thinking is a function of man’s immortal soul. God has given an immortal soul to every man and woman, but not to any other animal or to machines. Hence no animal or machine can think.1 I am unable to accept any part of this, but will attempt to reply in theological terms. I should find the argument more convincing if animals were classed with men, for there is a greater difference, to my mind, between the typical animate and the inanimate than there is between man and the other animals. The arbitrary character of the orthodox view becomes clearer if we consider how it might appear to a member of some other religious community. How do 1 Possibly this view is heretical. Saint Thomas Aquinas (Summa Theologica, quoted by Bertrand Russell, A History of Western Philosophy [New York: Simon & Schuster, 19451, p. 458) states that God cannot make a man to have no soul. But this may not be a real restriction on His powers, but only a result of the fact that men's, souls are immortal, and therefore indestructible. 71 Alan Turing Computing Machinery and Intelligence Christians regard the Moslem view that women have no souls? But let us leave this point aside and return to the main argument. It appears to me that the argument quoted above implies a serious restriction of the omnipotence of the Almighty. It is admitted that [381] there are certain things that He cannot do such as making one equal to two, but should we not believe that He has freedom to confer a soul on an elephant if He sees fit? We might expect that He would only exercise this power in conjunction with a mutation which provided the elephant with an appropriately improved brain to minister to the needs of this soul. An argument of exactly similar form may be made for the case of machines. It may seem different because it is more difficult to “swallow.” But this really only means that we think it would be less likely that He would consider the circumstances suitable for conferring a soul. The circumstances in question are discussed in the rest of this paper. In attempting to construct such machines we should not be irreverently usurping His power of creating souls, any more than we are in the procreation of children: rather we are, in either case, instruments of His will providing mansions for the souls that He creates. However, this is mere speculation. I am not very impressed with theological arguments whatever they may be used to support. Such arguments have often been found unsatisfactory in the past. In the time of Galileo it was argued that the texts, “And the sun stood still . . . and hasted not to go down about a whole day” (Joshua 10: 13) and “He laid the foundations of the earth, that it should not move at any time” (Psalm 105: 5) were an adequate refutation of the Copernican theory. With our present knowledge such an argument appears futile. When that knowledge was not available it made a quite different impression. (2) The “Heads in the Sand” Objection. “The consequences of machines thinking would be too dreadful. Let us hope and believe that they cannot do so.” This argument is seldom expressed quite so openly as in the form above. But it affects most of us who think about it at all. We like to believe that Man is in some subtle way superior to the rest of creation. It is best if he can be shown to be necessarily superior, for then there is no danger of him losing his commanding position. The popularity of the theological argument is clearly connected with this feeling. It is likely to be quite strong in intellectual people, since they value the power of thinking more highly than others, and are more inclined to base their belief in the superiority of Man on this power. I do not think that this argument is sufficiently substantial to require refutation. Consolation would be more appropriate: perhaps this should be sought in the transmigration of souls. (3) The Mathematical Objection. There are a number of results of mathematical logic which can be used to show that there are limitations to the powers of discrete state machines. The best known of these results is known as Gödel’s theorem, and shows that in any sufficiently powerful logical system statements can be formulated which can neither be proved nor disproved within the system, unless possibly the system itself is inconsistent. There are other, in some respects similar, results due to Church, Kleene, Rosser, and Turing. The latter result is the most convenient to consider, since it refers directly to machines, whereas the others can only be used in a comparatively indirect argument: for instance if Gödel’s theorem is to be used we need in addition to have some means of describing logical systems in terms of machines, and machines in terms of logical systems. The result in question refers to a type of machine which is essentially a digital computer with an infinite capacity. It states that there are certain things that such a machine cannot do. If it is rigged up to give answers to questions as in the imitation game, there will be some questions to which it will either give a wrong answer, or fail to give an answer at all however much time is allowed for a reply. 72 Alan Turing Computing Machinery and Intelligence There may, of course, be many such questions, and questions which cannot be answered by one machine may be satisfactorily answered by another. We are of course supposing for the present that the questions are of the kind to which an answer “Yes” or “No” is appropriate, rather than questions such as “What do you think of Picasso?” The questions that we know the machines must fail on are of this type, “Consider the machine specified as follows … Will this machine ever answer ‘Yes’ to any question?” The dots are to be replaced by a description of some machine in a standard form, which could be something like that used in §5. When the machine described bears a certain comparatively simple relation to the machine which is under interrogation, it can be shown that the answer is either wrong or not forthcoming. This is the mathematical result: it is argued that it proves a disability of machines to which the human intellect is not subject. The short answer to this argument is that although it is established that there are limitations to the powers of any particular machine, it has only been stated, without any sort of proof that no such limitations apply to the human intellect. But I do not think this view can be dismissed quite so lightly. Whenever one of these machines is asked the appropriate critical question, and gives a definite answer, we know that this answer must be wrong, and this gives us a certain feeling of superiority. Is this feeling illusory? It is no doubt quite genuine, but I do not think too much importance should be attached to it. We too often give wrong answers to questions ourselves to be justified in being very pleased at such evidence of fallibility on the part of the machines. Further, our superiority can only be felt on such an occasion in relation to the one machine over which we have scored our petty triumph. There would be no question of triumphing simultaneously over all machines. In short, then, there might be men cleverer than any given machine, but then again there might be other machines cleverer again, and so on. Those who hold to the mathematical argument would, I think, mostly be willing to accept the imitation game as a basis for discussion. Those who believe in the two previous objections would probably not be interested in any criteria. (4) The Argument from Consciousness. This argument is very well expressed in Professor Jefferson’s Lister Oration for 1949, from which I quote. “Not until a machine can write a sonnet or compose a concerto because of thoughts and emotions felt, and not by the chance fall of symbols, could we agree that machine equals brain that is, not only write it but know that it had written it. No mechanism could feel (and not merely artificially signal, an easy contrivance) pleasure at its successes, grief when its valves fuse, be warmed by flattery, be made miserable by its mistakes, be charmed by sex, be angry or depressed when it cannot get what it wants.” This argument appears to be a denial of the validity of our test. According to the most extreme form of this view the only way by which one could be sure that a machine thinks is to be the machine and to feel oneself thinking. One could then describe these feelings to the world, but of course no one would be justified in taking any notice. Likewise according to this view the only way to know that a man thinks is to be that particular man. It is in fact the solipsist point of view. It may be the most logical view to hold but it makes communication of ideas difficult. A is liable to believe “A thinks but B does not” while B believes “B thinks but A does not. “ Instead of arguing continually over this point it is usual to have the polite convention that everyone thinks. I am sure that Professor Jefferson does not wish to adopt the extreme and solipsist point of view. Probably he would be quite willing to accept the imitation game as a test. The game (with the player B omitted) is frequently used in practice 73 Alan Turing Computing Machinery and Intelligence under the name of viva voce to discover whether someone really understands something or has ‘learned it parrot fashion.” Let us listen in to a part of such a viva voce: INTERROGATOR: In the first line of your sonnet which reads “Shall I compare thee to a summer’s day,” would not “a spring day” do as well or better? WITNESS: It wouldn’t scan. INTERROGATOR: How about “a winter’s day.” That would scan all right. WITNESS: Yes, but nobody wants to be compared to a winter’s day. INTERROGATOR: Would you say Mr. Pickwick reminded you of Christmas? WITNESS: In a way. INTERROGATOR: Yet Christmas is a winter’s day, and I do not think Mr. Pickwick would mind the comparison. WITNESS: I don’t think you’re serious. By a winter’s day one means a typical winter’s day, rather than a special one like Christmas. And so on. What would Professor Jefferson say if the sonnet-writing machine was able to answer like this in the viva voce? I do not know whether he would regard the machine as “merely artificially signalling” these answers, but if the answers were as satisfactory and sustained as in the above passage I do not think he would describe it as “an easy contrivance”. This phrase is, I think, intended to cover such devices as the inclusion [383] in the machine of a record of someone reading a sonnet, with appropriate switching to turn it on from time to time. In short then, I think that most of those who support the argument from consciousness could be persuaded to abandon it rather than be forced into the solipsist position. They will then probably be willing to accept our test. I do not wish to give the impression that I think there is no mystery about consciousness. There is, for instance, something of a paradox connected with any attempt to localize it. But I do not think these mysteries necessarily need to be solved before we can answer the question with which we are concerned in this paper. (5) Arguments from Various Disabilities. These arguments take the form, “I grant you that you can make machines do all the things you have mentioned but you will never be able to make one to do X.” Numerous features X are suggested in this connection. I offer a selection: Be kind, resourceful, beautiful, friendly . . . have initiative, have a sense of humour, tell right from wrong, make mistakes..... fall in love, enjoy strawberries and cream..... I make someone fall in love with it, learn from experience . . . . use words properly, be the subject of its own thought . . . , have as much diversity of behaviour as a man, do something really new. . . . No support is usually offered for these statements. I believe they are mostly founded on the principle of scientific induction. A man has seen thousands of machines in his lifetime. From what he sees of them he draws a number of general conclusions. They are ugly, each is designed for a very limited purpose, when required for a minutely different purpose they are useless, the variety of behaviour of any one of them is very small, etc., etc. Naturally he concludes that these are necessary properties of machines in general. Many of these limitations are associated with the very small storage capacity of most machines. (I am assuming that the idea of storage capacity is extended in some way to cover machines other 74 Alan Turing Computing Machinery and Intelligence than discrete state machines. The exact definition does not matter as no mathematical accuracy is claimed in the present discussion.) A few years ago, when very little had been heard of digital computers, it was possible to elicit much incredulity concerning them, if one mentioned their properties without describing their construction. That was presumably due to a similar application of the principle of scientific induction. These applications of the principle are of course largely unconscious. When a burned child fears the fire and shows that he fears it by avoiding it, I should say that he was applying scientific induction. (I could of course also describe his behaviour in many other ways.) The works or customs of mankind do not seem to be very suitable material to which to apply scientific induction. A very large part of space-time must be investigated if reliable results are to be obtained. Otherwise we may (as most English children do) decide that everybody speaks English, and that it is silly to learn French. There are, however, special remarks to be made about many of the disabilities that have been mentioned. The inability to enjoy strawberries and cream may [strike] the reader as frivolous. Possibly a machine might be made to enjoy this delicious dish, but any attempt to make one do so would be idiotic. What is important about this disability is that it contributes to some of the other disabilities, e.g., to the difficulty of the same kind of friendliness occurring between man and machine as between white man and white man, or between black man and black man. The claim that “machines cannot make mistakes” seems a curious one. One is tempted to retort, “Are they any worse for that?” But let us adopt a more sympathetic attitude, and try to see what is really meant. I think this criticism can be explained in terms of the imitation game. It is claimed that the interrogator could distinguish the machine from the man simply by setting them a number of problems in arithmetic. The machine would be unmasked because of its deadly accuracy. The reply to this is simple. The machine (programmed for playing the game) would not attempt to give the right answers to the arithmetic problems. It would deliberately introduce mistakes in a manner calculated to confuse the interrogator. A mechanical fault would probably show itself through an unsuitable decision as to what sort of a mistake to make in the arithmetic. Even this interpretation of the criticism is not sufficiently sympathetic. But we cannot afford the [384] space to go into it much further. It seems to me that this criticism depends on a confusion between two kinds of mistakes. We may call them “errors of functioning” and “errors of conclusion. “ Errors of functioning are due to some mechanical or electrical fault which causes the machine to behave otherwise than it was designed to do. In philosophical discussions one likes to ignore the possibility of such errors; one is therefore discussing “abstract machines.” These abstract machines are mathematical fictions rather than physical objects. By definition they are incapable of errors of functioning. In this sense we can truly say that “machines can never make mistakes.” Errors of conclusion can only arise when some meaning is attached to the output signals from the machine. The machine might, for instance, type out mathematical equations, or sentences in English. When a false proposition is typed we say that the machine has committed an error of conclusion. There is clearly no reason at all for saying that a machine cannot make this kind of mistake. It might do nothing but type out repeatedly “O = 1. “ To take a less perverse example, it might have some method for drawing conclusions by scientific induction. We must expect such a method to lead occasionally to erroneous results. The claim that a machine cannot be the subject of its own thought can of course only be answered if it can be shown that the machine has some thought with some matter. Nevertheless, “the subject matter of a machine’s operations” does seem to mean something, at least to the 75 Alan Turing Computing Machinery and Intelligence people who deal with it. If, for instance, the machine was trying to find a solution of the equation x2 - 40x - 11 = 0 one would be tempted to describe this equation as part of the machine’s subject matter at that moment. In this sort of sense a machine undoubtedly can be its own subject matter. It may be used to help in making up its own programs, or to predict the effect of alterations in its own structure. By observing the results of its own behaviour it can modify its own programs so as to achieve some purpose more effectively. These are possibilities of the near future, rather than Utopian dreams. The criticism that a machine cannot have much diversity of behaviour is just a way of saying that it cannot have much storage capacity. Until fairly recently a storage capacity of even a thousand digits was very rare. The criticisms that we are considering here are often disguised forms of the argument from consciousness. Usually if one maintains that a machine can do one of these things, and describes the kind of method that the machine could use, one will not make much of an impression. It is thought that the method (whatever it may be, for it must be mechanical) is really rather base. Compare the parenthesis of Jefferson’s statement quoted above. (6) Lady Lovelace’s Objection. Our most detailed information of Babbage’s Analytical Engine comes from a memoir by Lady Lovelace. In it she states, “The Analytical Engine has no pretensions to originate anything. It can do whatever we know how to order it to perform” (her italics). This statement is quoted by Hartree who adds: “This does not imply that it may not be possible to construct electronic equipment which will ‘think for itself,’ or in which, in biological terms, one could set up a conditioned reflex, which would serve as a basis for ‘learning.’ Whether this is possible in principle or not is a stimulating and exciting question, suggested by some of these recent developments. But it did not seem that the machines constructed or projected at the time had this property.” I am in thorough agreement with Hartree over this. It will be noticed that he does not assert that the machines in question had not got the property, but rather that the evidence available to Lady Lovelace did not encourage her to believe that they had it. It is quite possible that the machines in question had in a sense got this property. For suppose that some discrete state machine has the property. The Analytical Engine was a universal digital computer, so that, if its storage capacity and speed were adequate, it could by suitable programming be made to mimic the machine in question. Probably this argument did not occur to the Countess or to Babbage. In any case, there was no obligation on them to claim all that could be claimed. This whole question will be considered again under the heading of learning machines. A variant of Lady Lovelace’s objection states that a machine can “never do anything really new. This may be parried for a moment with the saw, “There is nothing new under the sun”. Who can be certain that “original work” that he has done was not simply the growth of the seed planted in him by teaching, or the effect of following well-known general principles. A better variant of the objection says that a machine can never “take us by surprise.” This statement is a more direct challenge and can be met directly. Machines take me by surprise with great frequency. This is largely because I do not do sufficient calculation to decide what to expect them to do, or rather because, although I do a calculation, I do it in a hurried, slipshod fashion, taking risks. Perhaps I say to myself, “I suppose the voltage here ought to be the same as there: anyway let’s assume it is.” Naturally I am often wrong, and the result is a surprise for me, for by the time the experiment is done these assumptions have been forgotten. These admissions lay me open to lectures on the subject of my vicious ways, but do not throw any doubt on my credibility when I testify to the surprises I experience. 76 Alan Turing Computing Machinery and Intelligence I do not expect this reply to silence my critic. He will probably say that such surprises are due to some creative mental act on my part, and reflect no credit on the machine. This leads us back to the argument from consciousness, and far from the idea of surprise. It is a line of argument we must consider closed, but it is perhaps worth remarking that the appreciation of something as surprising requires as much of a “creative mental act” whether the surprising event originates from a man a book, a machine or anything else. The view that machines cannot give rise to surprises is due, I believe, to a fallacy to which philosophers and mathematicians are particularly subject. This is the assumption that as soon as a fact is presented to a mind all consequences of that fact spring into the mind simultaneously with it. It is a very useful assumption under many circumstances, but one too easily forgets that it is false. A natural consequence of doing so is that one then assumes that there is no virtue in the mere working out of consequences from data and general principles. (7) Argument from Continuity in the Nervous System. The nervous system is certainly not a discrete state machine. A small error in the information about the size of a nervous impulse impinging on a neuron, may make a large difference to the size of the outgoing impulse. It may be argued that, this being so, one cannot expect to be able to mimic the behaviour of the nervous system with a discrete state system. It is true that a discrete state machine must be different from a continuous machine. But if we adhere to the conditions of the imitation game, the interrogator will not be able to take any advantage of this difference. The situation can be made clearer if we consider some other simpler continuous machine. A differential analyzer will do very well. (A differential analyzer is a certain kind of machine not of the discrete state type used for some kinds of calculation.) Some of these provide their answers in a typed form, and so are suitable for taking part in the game. It would not be possible for a digital computer to predict exactly what answers the differential analyzer would give to a problem, but it would be, quite capable of giving the right sort of answer. For instance, if asked to give the value of (actually about 3.1416) it would be reasonable to choose at random between the values 3.12, 3.13, 3.14, 3.15, 3.16 with the probabilities of 0.05 0.15, 0.55, 0.19, 0.06 (say). Under these circumstances it would be very difficult for the interrogator to distinguish the differential analyzer from the digital computer. (8) The Argument from Informality of Behaviour. It is not possible to produce a set of rules purporting to describe what a man should do in every conceivable set of circumstances. One might for instance have a rule that one is to stop when one sees a red traffic light, and to go if one sees a green one, but what if by some fault both appear together? One may perhaps decide that it is safest to stop. But some further difficulty may well arise from this decision later. To attempt to provide rules of conduct to cover every eventuality, even those arising from traffic lights, appears to be impossible. With all this I agree. From this it is argued that we cannot be machines. I shall try to reproduce the argument, but I fear I shall hardly do it justice. It seems to run something like this. “If each man had a definite set of rules of conduct by which he regulated his life he would be no better than a machine. But there are no such rules, so men cannot be machines.” The undistributed middle is glaring. I do not think the argument is ever put quite like [386] this, but I believe this is the argument used nevertheless. There may however be a certain confusion between “rules of conduct” and “laws of behaviour” to cloud the issue. By “rules of conduct” I mean precepts such as “Stop if you see red lights,” on which one can act, and of which one can be conscious. By “laws of behaviour” I mean laws of nature as applied to a man’s body such as 77 Alan Turing Computing Machinery and Intelligence “if you pinch him he will squeak.” If we substitute “laws of behaviour which regulate his life” for “laws of conduct by which he regulates his life” in the argument quoted the undistributed middle is no longer insuperable. For we believe that it is not only true that being regulated by laws of behaviour implies being some sort of machine (though not necessarily a discrete state machine), but that conversely being such a machine implies being regulated by such laws. However, we cannot so easily convince ourselves of the absence of complete laws of behaviour as of complete rules of conduct. The only way we know of for finding such laws is scientific observation, and we certainly know of no circumstances under which we could say, “We have searched enough. There are no such laws. We can demonstrate more forcibly that any such statement would be unjustified. For suppose we could be sure of finding such laws if they existed. Then given a discrete state machine it should certainly be possible to discover by observation sufficient about it to predict its future behavior, and this within a reasonable time, say a thousand years. But this does not seem to be the case. I have set up on the Manchester computer a small program using only 1000 units of storage, whereby the machine supplied with one sixteen-figure number replies with another within two seconds. I would defy anyone to learn from these replies sufficient about the program to be able to predict any replies to untried values. (9) The Argument from Extra-Sensory-Perception. I assume that the reader is familiar with the idea of extra-sensory perception, and the meaning of the four items of it, viz., telepathy, clairvoyance, precognition and psychokinesis. These disturbing phenomena seem to deny all our usual scientific ideas. How we would like to discredit them! Unfortunately the statistical evidence, at least for telepathy, is overwhelming. It is very difficult to rearrange one’s ideas so as to fit these new facts in. Once one has accepted them it does not seem a very big step to believe in ghosts and bogies. The idea that our bodies move simply according to the known laws of physics, together with some others not yet discovered but somewhat similar, would be one of the first to go. This argument is to my mind quite a strong one. One can say in reply that many scientific theories seem to remain workable in practice, in spite of clashing with E.S.P.; that in fact one can get along very nicely if one forgets about it. This is rather cold comfort, and one fears that thinking is just the kind of phenomenon where E.S.P. may be especially relevant. A more specific argument based on E.S.P. might run as follows: “Let us play the imitation game, using a witnesses a man who is good as a telepathic receiver, and a digital computer. The interrogator can ask such questions as ‘What suit does the card in my right hand belong to?’ The man by telepathy or clairvoyance gives the right answer 130 times out of 400 cards. The machine can only guess at random, and perhaps get 104 right, so the interrogator makes the right identification.” There is an interesting possibility which opens here. Suppose the digital computer contains a random number generator. Then it will be natural to use this to decide what answer to give. But then the random number of generator will be subject to the psychokinetic powers of the interrogator. Perhaps this psychokinesis might cause the machine to guess right more often than would be expected on a probability calculation, so that the interrogator might still be unable to make the right identification. On the other hand, he might be able to guess right without any questioning, by clairvoyance. With E.S.P. anything may happen. If telepathy is admitted it will be necessary to tighten our test. The situation could be regarded as analogous to that which would occur if the interrogator were talking to himself 78 Alan Turing Computing Machinery and Intelligence and one of the competitors was listening with his ear to the wall. To put the competitors into a “telepathy-proof room” would satisfy all requirements. 79 D.M. Armstrong The Nature of Mind D.M. Armstrong THE NATURE OF MIND [D.M. Armstrong, The Nature of Mind and other essays, University of Queensland Press, 1980)] 1. Men have minds, that is to say, they perceive, they have sensations, emotions, beliefs, thoughts, purposes and desires. What is it to have a mind? What is it to perceive, to feel emotion, to have a belief or to have a purpose? Many contemporary philosophers think that the best clue we have to the nature of mind is furnished by the discoveries and hypotheses of modern science concerning the nature of man. 2. What does modern science have to say about the nature of man? There are, of course, all sorts of disagreements and divergencies in the views of individual scientists. But I think it is true to say that one view is steadily gaining ground, so that it bids fair to become established scientific doctrine. This is the view that we can give a complete account of man in purely physico-chemical terms. This view has received a tremendous impetus in recent decades from the new subject of molecular biology, a subject that promises to unravel the physical and chemical mechanisms that lie at the basis of life. Before that time, it received great encouragement from pioneering work in neurophysiology pointing to the likelihood of a purely electro-chemical account of the working of the brain. I think it is fair to say that those scientists who still reject the physico-chemical account of man do so primarily for philosophical, or moral or religious reasons, and only secondarily, and half-heartedly, for reasons of scientific detail. This is not to say that in the future new evidence and new problems may not to light that will force science to reconsider the physico-chemical view of man. But at present the drift of scientific thought is clearly set towards the physico-chemical hypothesis. And we have nothing better to go on than the present. 3. For me, then, and for many philosophers who think like me, the moral is clear. We must try to work out an account of the nature of mind which is compatible with the view that man is nothing but a physico-chemical mechanism. 4. And in this paper, I shall be concerned to do just this: to sketch (in barest outline) what may be called a Materialist or Physicalist account of the mind. THE AUTHORITY OF SCIENCE 5. But before doing this, I should like to go back and consider a criticism of my position that must inevitably occur to some. What reason have I, it may be asked, for taking my stand on science? Even granting that I am right about what is the currently dominant scientific view of man, why should we concede science a special authority to decide questions about the nature of man? What of the authority of philosophy, of religion, of morality, or even of literature and art? Why do I set the authority of science above all these? Why this “scientism”? 6. It seems to me that the answer to this question is very simple. If we consider the search for truth, in all its fields, we find that it is only in science that men versed in their subject can, after investigation that is more or less prolonged, and which may in some cases extend beyond a single human lifetime, reach substantial agreement about 80 D.M. Armstrong The Nature of Mind what is the case. It is only as a result of scientific investigation that we ever seem to reach an intellectual consensus about controversial matters. 7. In the Epistle Dedicatory to De Corpore, Hobbes wrote of William Harvey, the discoverer of the circulation of the blood, that he was: “the only man I know, that conquering envy, hath established a new doctrine in his life-time.” 8. Before Copernicus, Galileo and Harvey, Hobbes remarks: “there was nothing certain in natural philosophy.” And we might add, with the exception of mathematics, there was nothing certain in any other learned discipline. 9. These remarks of Hobbes are incredibly revealing. They show us what a watershed in the intellectual history of the human race the seventeenth century was. Before that time, enquiry proceeded, as it were, in the dark. Men could not hope to see their doctrine established, that is to say, accepted by the vast majority of those properly versed in the subject under discussion. There was no intellectual consensus. Since that time, it has become a commonplace to see new doctrines, sometimes of the most farreaching kind, established to the satisfaction of the learned, often within the lifetime of their first proponents. Science has provided us with a method of deciding disputed questions. This is not to say, of course, that the consensus of those who are learned and competent in a subject cannot be mistaken. Of course such a consensus can be mistaken. Sometimes it has been mistaken. But, granting fallibility, what better authority have we than such a consensus? 10. Now this is of the utmost importance. For in philosophy, in religion, in such disciplines as literary criticism, in moral questions in so far as they are thought to be matters of truth and falsity, there has been a notable failure to achieve an intellectual consensus about disputed questions among the learned. Must we not then attach a peculiar authority to the discipline that can achieve a consensus? And if it presents us with a certain vision of the nature of man, is this not a powerful reason for accepting that vision? 11. I will not take up here the deeper question why it is that the methods of science have enabled us to achieve an intellectual consensus about so many disputed matters. That question, I think, could receive no brief or uncontroversial answer. I am resting my argument on the simple fact that, as a result of scientific investigation, such a consensus has been achieved. 12. It may be replied – it often is replied – that while science is all very well in its own sphere – the sphere of the physical, perhaps – there are matters of fact on which it is not competent to pronounce. And among such matters, it may be claimed, is the question: what is the whole nature of man? But I cannot see that this reply has much force. Science has provided us with an island of truths, or, perhaps one should say, a raft of truths, to bear us up on the sea of our disputatious ignorance. There may have to be revisions and refinements, new results may set old findings in a new perspective, but what science has given us will not be altogether superseded. Must we not therefore appeal to these relative certainties for guidance when we come to consider uncertainties elsewhere? Perhaps science cannot help us to decide whether or not there is a God, whether or not human beings have immortal souls, or whether or not the will is free. But if science cannot assist us, what can? I conclude that it is the scientific vision of man, and not the philosophical or religious or artistic or moral 81 D.M. Armstrong The Nature of Mind vision of man, that is the best clue we have to the nature of man. And it is rational to argue from the best evidence we have.1 DEFINING THE MENTAL 13. Having in this way attempted to justify my procedure, I turn back to my subject: the attempt to work out an account of mind, or, if you prefer, of mental process, within the framework of the physico-chemical, or, as we may call it, the Materialist view of man. 14. Now there is one account of mental process that is at once attractive to any philosopher sympathetic to a Materialist view of man: this is Behaviourism. Formulated originally by a psychologist, J.B. Watson, it attracted widespread interest and considerable support from scientifically oriented philosophers. Traditional philosophy had tended to think of the mind as a rather mysterious inward arena that lay behind, and was responsible for, the outward or physical behaviour of our bodies. Descartes thought of this inner arena as a spiritual substance, and it was this conception of the mind as spiritual object that Gilbert Ryle attacked, apparently in the interest of Behaviourism, in his important book The Concept of Mind (1949). He ridiculed the Cartesian view as the dogma of “the ghost in the machine”. The mind was not something behind the behaviour of the body, it was simply part of that physical behaviour. My anger with you is not some modification of a spiritual substance that somehow brings about aggressive behaviour; rather it is the aggressive behaviour itself; my addressing strong words to you, striking you, turning m on you, and so on. Thought is not an inner process that lies behind, and brings about, the words I speak and write: it is my speaking and writing. The mind is not an inner arena, it is outward act. 15. It is clear that such a view of mind fits in very well with completely Materialistic or Physicalist view of man. If there is no need to draw a distinction between mental processes and their expression in physical behaviour, but if instead the mental processes are identified with their so-called “expressions”, then the existence of mind stands in no conflict with the view that man is nothing but a physico-chemical mechanism. 16. However, the version of Behaviourism that I have just sketched is a very crude version, and its crudity lays it open to objections. One obvious difficulty is that it is our common experience that there can be mental processes going on although there is no behaviour occurring that could possibly be treated as expressions of those processes. A man may be angry, but give no bodily sign; he may think, but say or do nothing at all. 17. In my view, the most plausible attempt to refine Behaviourism with a view to meeting this objection was made by introducing the notion of a disposition to behave. (Dispositions to behave are particularly important part in Ryle’s account of the mind.) Let us consider the general notion of disposition first. Brittleness is a disposition, a disposition possessed by materials like glass. Brittle materials are those that, when subjected to relatively small forces break or shatter easily. But breaking and shattering 1 The view of science presented here has been challenged in recent years by new Irrationalist philosophies of science. See, in particular, Thomas Kuhn (1962) and Paul Feyerabend (1975). A complete treatment of the problem would involve answering their contentions. 82 D.M. Armstrong The Nature of Mind easily is not brittleness, rather it is the manifestation of brittleness. Brittleness itself is the tendency or liability of the material to break or easily. A piece of glass may never shatter or break throughout its whole history, but it is still the case that it is brittle: it is liable to shatter or break if dropped quite a small way or hit quite lightly. Now a disposition to behave is simply a tendency or liability of a person to behave in a certain way under certain circumstances. The brittleness of glass is a disposition that the glass retains throughout its history, but clearly there also could be dispositions that come and go. The dispositions to behave that are of interest to [6] the Behaviourist are, for the most part, of this temporary character. 18. Now how did Ryle and others use the notion of a disposition to behave to meet the obvious objection to Behaviourism that there can be mental process going on although the subject is engaging in no relevant behaviour? Their strategy was to argue that in such cases, although the subject was not behaving in any relevant way, he or she was disposed to behave in some relevant way. The glass does not shatter, but it is still brittle. The man does not behave, but he does have a disposition to behave. We can say he thinks although he does not speak or act because at that time he was disposed to speak or act in a certain way. If he had been asked, perhaps, he would have spoken or acted. We can say he is angry although he does not behave angrily, because he is disposed so to behave. If only one more word had been addressed to him, he would have burst out. And so on. In this way it was hoped that Behaviourism could be squared with the obvious facts. 19. It is very important to see just how these thinkers conceived of dispositions. I quote from Ryle: To possess a dispositional property is not to be in a particular state, or to undergo a particular change; it is to be bound or liable to be in a particular state, or to undergo a particular change, when a particular condition is realized.2 20. So to explain the breaking of a lightly struck glass on a particular occasion by saying it was brittle is, on this view of dispositions, simply to say that the glass broke because it is the sort of thing that regularly breaks when quite lightly struck. The breaking was the normal behaviour, or not abnormal behaviour, of such a thing. The brittleness is not to be conceived of as a cause for the breakage, or even, more vaguely, a factor in bringing about the breaking. Brittleness is just the fact that things of that sort break easily. 21. But although in this way the Behaviourists did something to deal with the objection that mental processes can occur in the absence of behaviour, it seems clear, now that the shouting and the dust have died, that they did not do enough. When I think, but my thoughts do not issue in any action, it seems as obvious as anything is obvious that there is something actually going on in me that constitutes my thought. It is not simply that I would speak or act if some conditions that are unfulfilled were to be fulfilled. Something is currently going on, in the strongest and most literal sense of “going on”, and this something is my thought. Rylean Behaviourism denies this, and so it is unsatisfactory as a theory of mind. Yet I know of no version of Behaviourism that is more satisfactory. The moral for those of us who wish to take physicalistic 2 Ryle, 1949: 43; emphasis added. 83 D.M. Armstrong The Nature of Mind view of man is that we must look for some other account of the nature of mind and of mental processes. 22. But perhaps we need not grieve too deeply about the failure of Behaviourism to produce a satisfactory theory of mind. Behaviourism is a profoundly unnatural account of mental processes. If somebody speaks and acts in certain ways, it is natural to speak of this speech and action as the expression of his thought. It is not at all natural to speak of his speech and action as identical with his thought. We naturally think of the thought as something quite distinct from the speech and action that, under suitable circumstances, brings the speech and action about. Thoughts are not to be identified with behaviour, we think; they lie behind behaviour. A man’s behaviour constitutes the reason we have for attributing certain mental processes to him, but the behaviour cannot be identified with the mental processes. 23. This suggests a very interesting line of thought about the mind. Behaviourism is certainly wrong, but perhaps it is not altogether wrong. Perhaps the Behaviourists are wrong in identifying the mind and mental occurrences with behaviour, but perhaps right in thinking that our notion of a mind and of individual mental states is logically tied to behaviour. For perhaps what we mean by a mental state is some state of the person that, under suitable circumstances, brings about a certain range of behaviour. Perhaps mind can be defined not as behaviour, but rather as the inner cause of certain behaviour. Thought is not speech under suitable circumstances, rather it is something within the person that, in suitable circumstances, brings about speech. And, in fact, I believe that this is the true account, or, at any rate, a true first account of what we mean by a mental state. 24. How does this line of thought link up with a purely Physicalist view of man? The position is that while it does not make such a Physicalist view inevitable, it does stake it possible. It does not entail, but it is compatible with, a purely Physicalist view of man. For if our notion of the mind and of mental states is nothing but that of a cause within the person of certain ranges of behaviour, then it becomes a scientific question, and not a question of logical analysis, what in fact the intrinsic nature of that cause is. The cause might be, as Descartes thought it was, a spiritual substance working through the pineal gland to produce the complex bodily behaviour of which men are, capable. It might be breath, or specially smooth and mobile atoms dispersed throughout the body; it might be many other things. But in fact the verdict of modern science seems to be that the sole cause of mind-betokening behaviour in man and the higher animals is the physicochemical workings of the central nervous system. And so, assuming we have correctly characterized our concept of a mental state as nothing but the cause of certain sorts of behaviour, then we can identify these mental states with purely physical states of the central nervous system. 25. At this point we may stop and go back to the Behaviourist’s dispositions. We saw that, according to him, the brittleness of glass or, to take another example, the elasticity of rubber, is not a state of the glass or the rubber, but is simply the fact that things of that sort behave in the way they do. But now let us consider how a scientist would think about brittleness or elasticity. Faced with the phenomenon of breakage under relatively small impacts, or the phenomenon of stretching when a force is applied followed by contraction when the force is removed, he will assume that there is some current state of the glass or the rubber that is responsible for the characteristic 84 D.M. Armstrong The Nature of Mind behaviour of samples of these two materials. At the beginning, he will not know what this state is, but he will endeavour to find out, and he may succeed in finding out. And when he has found out, he will very likely make remarks of. this sort: “We have discovered that the brittleness of glass is in fact a certain sort of pattern in the molecules of the glass.” That is to say, he will identify brittleness with the state of the glass that is responsible for the liability of the glass to break. For him, a disposition of an object is a state of the object. What makes the state a state of brittleness is the fact that it gives rise to the characteristic manifestations of brittleness. But the disposition itself is distinct from its manifestations: it is the state of the glass that gives rise to these manifestations in suitable circumstances. 26. This way of looking at dispositions is very different from Ryle and the Behaviourists. The great difference is this: If we treat dispositions as actual states, as I have suggested that scientists do, even if states the intrinsic nature of which may yet have to be discovered, then we can say that dispositions are actual causes, or causal factors, which, in suitable circumstances, actually bring about those happenings that are the manifestations of the disposition. A certain molecular constitution of glass that constitutes brittleness is actually responsible for the fact that, when the glass is struck, it breaks. 27. Now I cannot argue the matter here, because the detail of the argument is technical and difficult, but I believe that the view of dispositions as states, which is the view that is natural to science, is the correct one.3 I believe it can be shown quite strictly that to the extent that we admit the notion of dispositions at all, we are committed to the view that they are actual states of the object that has the disposition. I may add that I think that the same holds for the closely connected notions of capacities and powers. Here I will simply have to assume this step in my argument. 28. But perhaps it will be seen that the rejection of the idea mind is simply a certain range of man’s behaviour in favour of the view that mind is rather the inner cause of that range of man’s behaviour, is bound up with the rejection of the Rylean dispositions in favour of one that treats dispositions as states of objects and so as having actual causal power. The Behaviourists were wrong to identify the mind with behaviour. They were not so far off the mark when they tried to deal with cases where mental happenings occur in the absence of behaviour by saying that these are dispositions to behave. But in order to reach a correct view, I am suggesting, they would have to conceive of these dispositions as actual states of the person who has the disposition, states that have actual causal power to bring about behaviour in suitable circumstances. But to do this is to abandon the central inspiration of Behaviourism: that in talking about the mind we do not have to go behind outward behaviour to inner states. 29. And so two separate but interlocking lines of thought have pushed me in the same direction. The first line of thought is that it goes profoundly against the grain to think of the mind as behaviour. The mind is, rather, that which stands behind and brings about our complex behaviour. The second line of thought is that the Behaviourist’s dispositions, properly conceived, are really states that underlie behaviour and, under suitable circumstances, bring about behaviour. Putting these two together, we reach the conception of a mental state as a state of the person apt for producing certain ranges of behaviour. This formula: a mental state is a state of the person apt for 3 I develop the argument in Belief, Truth and Knowledge (1973), ch. 2, sect. 2. 85 D.M. Armstrong The Nature of Mind producing certain ranges of behaviour, I believe to be a very illuminating way of looking at the concept of a mental state. I have found it fruitful in the search for detailed logical analyses of the individual mental concepts. 30. I do not think that Hegel’s Dialectic has much to tell us about the nature of reality. But I think that human thought often moves in a dialectical way, from thesis to antithesis and then to the synthesis. Perhaps thought about the mind is a case in point. I have already said that classical philosophy has tended to think of the mind as an inner arena of some sort. This we may call the Thesis. Behaviourism moves to the opposite extreme: the mind is seen as outward behaviour. This is the Antithesis. My proposed Synthesis is that the mind is properly conceived as an inner principle, but a principle that is identified in terms of the outward behaviour it is apt for bringing about. This way of looking at the mind and mental states does not itself entail a Materialist or Physicalist view of man, for nothing is said in this analysis about the intrinsic nature of these mental states. But if we have, as I have argued that we do have, general scientific grounds for thinking that man is nothing but a physical mechanism, we can go on to argue that the mental states are in fact nothing but physical states of the central nervous system. THE PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS 31. Along these lines, then, I would look for an account of the mind that is compatible with a purely Materialist theory of man. There are, as may be imagined, all sorts of powerful objections be made to my view. But in the rest of this paper, I propose to do only one thing: I will develop one very important object objection to my view of the mind - an objection felt by many philosophers - then try to show how the objection should be met. 32. The view that our notion of mind is nothing but that of an inner principle apt for bringing about certain sorts of behaviour may be thought to share a certain weakness with Behaviourism. Modern philosophers have put the point about Behaviourism by saying that, although Behaviourism may be a satisfactory account of the mind from an other-person point of view, it will not do as a first-person account. To explain. In my encounters with other people, all I ever observe is their behaviour: their actions, their speech and so on. And so, if we simply consider other people, Behaviourism might seem to do full justice to the facts. But the trouble with Behaviourism is that it seems so unsatisfactory as applied to own case. In our own case, we seem to be aware of so much more than mere behaviour. 33. Suppose that now we conceive of the mind as an inner principle apt for bringing about certain sorts of behaviour. This again fits the other-person cases very well. Bodily behaviour of a very sophisticated sort is observed, quite different from the behaviour that ordinary physical objects display. It is inferred that this behaviour must spring from a very special sort of inner cause in the object that exhibits this behaviour. This inner cause is christened “the mind”, and those who take a Physicalist view of man argue that it is simply the central nervous system of the body observed. Compare this with the case of glass. Certain characteristic behaviour is observed: the breaking and shattering of the material when acted upon by relatively small forces. A special inner state of the glass is postulated to explain this behaviour. Those who take a purely Physicalist view of glass then argue that this state is a state of the glass. It is, perhaps, 86 D.M. Armstrong The Nature of Mind an arrangement of its molecules and not, say, the peculiarly malevolent disposition of the demons that dwell in glass. 34. But when we turn to our own case, the position may seem less plausible. We are conscious, we have experiences. Now can we say that to be conscious, to have experiences, is simply for something to go on within us apt for the causing of certain sorts of behaviour? Such an account does not seem to do any justice to the phenomena. And so it seems that our account of the mind, like Behaviourism, will fail to do justice to the first-person case. 35. In order to understand the objection better, it may be helpful to consider a particular case. If you have driven for a very long distance without a break, you may have had experience of a curious state of automatism, which can occur in these conditions. One can suddenly “come to” and realize that one has driven for long distances without being aware of what one was doing, or, indeed, without being aware of anything. One has kept the car on the road, used the brake and the clutch perhaps, yet all without any awareness of what one was doing. 36. Now if we consider this case, it is obvious that in some sense mental processes are still going on when one is in such an automatic state. Unless one’s will was still operating in some way, and unless one was still perceiving in some way, the car would not still be on the road. Yet, of course, something mental is lacking. Now, I think, when it is alleged that an account of mind as an inner principle apt for the production of certain sorts of behaviour leaves out consciousness or experience, what is alleged to have been left out is just whatever is missing in the automatic driving case. It is conceded that an account of mental processes as states of the person apt for the production of certain sorts of behaviour very possibly may be adequate to deal with such cases as that of automatic driving. It may be adequate to deal with most of the mental processes of animals, which perhaps spend most of their lives in this state of automatism. But, it is contended, it cannot deal with the consciousness that we normally enjoy. 37. I will now try to sketch an answer to this important and powerful objection. Let us begin in an apparently unlikely place and consider the way that an account of mental processes of the sort I am giving would deal with sense-perception. 38. Now psychologists, in particular, have long realized that there is a very close logical tie between sense-perception and selective behaviour. Suppose we want to decide whether an animal can perceive the difference between red and green. We might give the animal a choice between two pathways, over one of which a red light shines and over the other of which a green light shines. If the animal happens by chance to choose the green pathway, we reward it; if it happens to choose the other pathway, we do not reward it. If, after some trials, the animal systematically takes the green-lighted pathway, and if we become assured that the only relevant differences in the two pathways are the differences in the colour of the lights, we are entitled to say that the animal can see this colour difference. Using its eyes, it selects between red-lighted and green-lighted pathways. So we say it can see the difference between red and green. 39. Now a Behaviourist would be tempted to say that the animal’s regular selection of the green-lighted pathway was its perception of the colour difference. But this is unsatisfactory, because we all want to say that perception is something that goes on 87 D.M. Armstrong The Nature of Mind within the person or animal - within its mind - although, of course, this mental event is normally caused by the operation of the environment upon the organism. Suppose, however, that we speak instead of capacities for selective behaviour towards the current environment, and suppose we think of these capacities, like dispositions, as actual inner states of the organism. We can then think of the animal’s perception as a state within the animal apt, if the animal is so impelled, for selective behaviour between the red- and green-lighted pathways. 40. In general, we can think of perceptions as inner states or events apt for the production of certain sorts of selective behaviour towards our environment. To perceive is like acquiring a key to a door. You do not have to use the key: you can put it in your pocket and never bother about the door. But if you do want to open the door, the key may be essential. The blind man is a man who does not acquire certain keys and, as a result, is not able to operate in his environment in the way that somebody who has his sight can operate. It seems, then, a very promising view to take of perceptions that they are inner states defined by the sorts of selective behaviour that they enable the perceiver to exhibit, if so impelled. 41. Now how is this discussion of perception related to the question of consciousness or experience, the sort of thing that the driver who is in a state of automatism has not got, but which we normally do have? Simply this. My proposal is that consciousness, in this sense of the word, is nothing but perception or awareness of the state of our own mind. The driver in a state of automatism perceives, or is aware of, the road. If he did not, the car would be in a ditch. But he is not currently aware of his awareness of the road. He perceives the road, but he does not perceive his perceiving, or anything else that is going on in his mind. He is not, as we normally are, conscious of what is going on in his mind. 42. And so I conceive of consciousness or experience, in this sense of the words, in the way that Locke and Kant conceived it, as like perception. Kant, in a striking phrase, spoke of “Inner sense”. We cannot directly observe the minds of others, but each of us has the power to observe directly our own minds, and “perceive” what is going on there. The driver in the automatic state is one whose “inner eye” is shut: who is not currently aware of what is going on in his own mind. 43. Now if this account is along the right lines, why should we not give an account of this inner observation along the same lines as we have already given of perception? Why should we not conceive of it as an inner state, a state in this case directed towards other inner states and not to the environment, which enables us, if we are so impelled, to behave in a selective way towards our own states of mind? One who is aware, or conscious, of his thoughts or his emotions is one who has the capacity to make discriminations between his different mental states. His capacity might be exhibited in words. He might say that he was in an angry state of mind, when, and only when, he was in an angry state of mind. But such verbal behaviour would be the mere expression or result of the awareness. The awareness itself would be an inner state: the sort of inner state that gave the man a capacity for such behavioural expressions. 44. So I have argued that consciousness of our own mental state may be assimilated to perception of our own mental state, and that, like other perceptions, it may then be conceived of as an inner state or event giving a capacity for selective behaviour, in this case selective behaviour towards our own mental state. All this is meant to be 88 D.M. Armstrong The Nature of Mind simply a logical analysis of consciousness, and none of it entails, although it does not rule out, a purely Physicalist account of what these inner states are. But if we are convinced, on general scientific grounds, that a purely physical account of man is likely to be the true one, then there seems to be no bar to our identifying these inner states with purely physical states of the central nervous system. And so consciousness of our own mental state becomes simply the scanning of one part of our central nervous system by another. Consciousness is a self-scanning mechanism in the central nervous system. 45. As I have emphasized before, I have done no more than sketch a programme for a philosophy of mind. There are all sorts of expansions and elucidations to be made, and all sorts of doubts and difficulties to be stated and overcome. But I hope I have done enough to show that a purely Physicalist theory of the mind is an exciting and plausible intellectual option. 89 Plato, Republic Plato REPUBLIC [Translated by Robin Waterfield. Oxford World’s Classics, 1993.] Chapter 8 In a very important argument, Plato describes a philosopher as one who perceives things ‘in themselves’. A philosopher is awake rather than asleep; he has knowledge, while everyone else has mere belief or opinion, which is fallible and has less access to reality, because it can see no further than the sensible world, which is deceptive and deficient. Knowledge is correlated with the truth of things, which is a property of what each thing is itself, and which never changes; belief is correlated with the less real aspect of things, in which they are no more beautiful (say) than ugly. [475d] ‘Then a motley crowd of people will be philosophers,’ Glaucon said. ‘For instance, sightseers all do what they do because they enjoy learning, I suppose; and it would be very odd to count theatre-goers as philosophers, when they’d never go of their own accord to hear a lecture or spend time over anything like that, but they rush around the festivals of Dionysus to hear every theatrical troupe, as if they were getting paid for the use of their ears,1 and never miss a single festival, whether it’s being held in town or out of town. Are we to describe all these people and the disciples of other amusements as philosophers? And what about students of trivial branches of [475e] expertise?’ ‘No,’ I replied, ‘they’re not philosophers, but they resemble philosophers.’ ‘Who are the true philosophers you have in mind?’ he asked. ‘Sightseers of the truth,’ I answered. ‘That must be right, but what exactly does it mean?’ he asked. ‘It wouldn’t be easy to explain to anyone else,’ I said. ‘But you’ll grant me this, surely.’ ‘What?’ ‘Since beautiful is the opposite of ugly, they are two things.’ [476a] ‘Of course.’ ‘In so far as they are two, each of them is single?’ ‘Yes.’ ‘And the same principle applies to moral and immoral, good and bad, and everything of any type: in itself, each of them is single, but each of them has a plurality of manifestations because they appear all over the place, as they become associated with actions and bodies and one another.’ ‘You’re right,’ he said. 1 use of their ears: theatre-going counts as use of ears rather than eyes because that was the emphasis in Greek theatre. At one of the really big theatres, like that of Epidauros, from the back seats the actors would appear tiny. Festivals of Dionysus were the occasions of dramatic performances. 90 Plato, Republic ‘Well,’ I continued, ‘this is what enables me to distinguish the sightseers2 (to borrow your term) and the ones who want to acquire some expertise or other and the men of action from the [476b] people in question, the ones who are philosophers in the true sense of the term.’ ‘What do you mean?’ he asked. ‘Theatre-goers and sightseers are devoted to beautiful sounds and colours and shapes, and to works of art which consist of these elements, but their minds are constitutionally incapable of seeing and devoting themselves to beauty itself.’ ‘Yes, that’s certainly right,’ he said. ‘However, people with the ability to approach beauty itself and see beauty as it actually is are bound to be few and far between, aren’t they?’ ‘Definitely.’ [476c] ‘So does someone whose horizon is limited to beautiful things, with no conception of beauty itself, and who is incapable of following guidance as to how to gain knowledge of beauty itself, strike you as living in a dream-world or in the real world? Look at it this way. Isn’t dreaming precisely the state, whether one is asleep or awake, of taking something to be the real thing, when it is actually only a likeness?’ ‘Yes, that’s what I’d say dreaming is,’ he said. ‘And what about someone who does the opposite – who does [476d] think that there is such a thing as beauty itself, and has the ability to see it as well as the things which partake in it,3 and never gets them muddled up? Do you think he’s living in the real world or in a dreamworld?’ ‘Definitely in the real world,’ he said. ‘So wouldn’t we be right to describe the difference between their mental states by saying that while this person has knowledge, the other one has beliefs?’ ‘Yes.’ ‘Now, suppose this other person – the one we’re saying has beliefs, not knowledge – were to get cross with us and query the truth of our assertions. Will we be able to calm him down [476e] and gently convince him of our point of view, while keeping him in the dark about the poor state of his health?’ ‘We really ought to,’ he said. sightseers: literally ‘lovers of spectacles’. There has been controversy over whether ‘the many beautifuls’ (the literal translation) that this class of people is said to recognize are beautiful things or conceptions of beauty. … Plato is usually, however, concerned to contrast types with the things of this world. In fact, I am not sure the distinction between particulars and conceptions would have interested Plato much in this context, since his primary distinction is between an unchanging realm and a changing one, whatever its inhabitants. Thus at 479d he does suddenly mention conventional views about beauty. Adherence to convention is, in its way, just as unreliable a guide to truth as adherence to sense-impression, since convention is equally subject to alteration. 2 partake in it: this is one of the metaphors Plato tries out for the relation between ‘things in themselves’ or ‘types’ or ‘characters’ and their instances. Other metaphors are that the type is ‘present in’ the instances, and that the instances ‘imitate’ the type. The difficulty is the difficulty of explaining how a single thing can appear all over the place and yet remain single. 3 91 Plato, Republic ‘All right, but what shall we say to him, do you think? Perhaps this is what we should ask him. We’ll tell him that we don’t resent any knowledge he might have – indeed, we’d be delighted to see that he does know something-and then we’ll say, “But can you tell us, please, whether someone with knowledge knows something or nothing?” You’d better answer my questions for him.’ ‘My answer will be that he knows something,’ he said. ‘Something real or something unreal?’ [477a ] ‘Real. How could something unreal be known?’4 ‘We could look at the matter from more angles, but we’re happy enough with the idea that something completely real is completely accessible to knowledge, and something utterly unreal is entirely inaccessible to knowledge. Yes?’ ‘Perfectly happy.’ ‘All right. But if something is in a state of both reality and unreality, then it falls between that which is perfectly real and that which is utterly unreal, doesn’t it?’ ‘Yes.’ ‘So since the field of knowledge is reality, and since it must be incomprehension whose field is unreality, then we need to find out if there is in fact something which falls between [477b] incomprehension and knowledge, whose field is this intermediate, don’t we?’ ‘Yes.’ ‘Now, we acknowledge the existence of belief, don’t we?’ ‘Of course.’ ‘Is it a different faculty from knowledge, or is it the same?’ ‘Different.’ ‘Every faculty has its own distinctive abilities, so belief and knowledge must have different domains.’ ‘Yes.’ 4 be known: as commonly interpreted, Plato is thinking of knowing as a kind of direct apprehension of an object, as in ‘I know Joan.’ He is therefore overlooking the other main kind of knowing – propositional knowledge, as in ‘I know that two and two make four’ – because it is far from clear that talk of reality and unreality makes any sense in this case: is a ‘that …’ clause real or unreal? However, whether or not Plato was aware of these distinctions (he almost certainly was not), there is still plenty of value in the discussion. There is nothing to prevent one thinking along the following lines: whatever knowledge (of any kind) encompasses is real in the senses that (a) it fills me with certainty; (b) it allows me to give a coherent account of it; (c) its features which enable me to be certain about it are unchanging features. I could not be said to know that two and two make four, if they occasionally make some other number; and I could not be said to know Joan, if she even occasionally resembled someone else; and I could not he a know how to mend cars if their structure was unstable. However, even if all these things were unstable, I could believe that two and two make four, that the person I am seeing is Joan, and that this bolt goes in that hole. In other words, it is a sufficient interpretation of the passage to see that Plato is working with a portmanteau conception of knowledge, which covers aspects of the various subspecies of knowledge. 92 Plato, Republic ‘Now, since the natural field of knowledge is reality-its function is to know reality as reality ... Actually, I think there’s something else we need to get dear about first.’ ‘What?’ [477c] ‘Shall we count as a distinct class of things the faculties which give human beings and all other creatures their abilities? By “faculties” I mean things like sight and hearing. Do you understand the type of thing I have in mind?’ ‘Yes, I do,’ he said. ‘Let me tell you something that strikes me about them. I can’t distinguish one faculty from another the way I commonly distinguish other things, by looking at their colours or shapes or anything like that, because faculties don’t have any of those sorts of qualities for me to look at. The only aspect of a faculty [477d] I can look at is its field, its effect. This is what enables me to identify each of them as a particular faculty. Where I find a single domain and a single effect, I say there is a single faculty; and I distinguish faculties which have different fields and different effects. What about you? What do you do?’ ‘The same as you,’ he said. ‘Let’s go back to where we were before, then, Glaucon,’ I said. ‘Do you think that knowledge is a faculty, or does it belong in your opinion to some other class?’ ‘I think it belongs to that class,’ he said, ‘and is the most powerful of all the faculties. [477e] ‘And shall we classify belief as a faculty, or what?’ ‘As a faculty,’ he said. ‘Belief is precisely that which enables us to entertain beliefs.’ ‘Not long ago, however, you agreed that knowledge and belief were different.’ ‘Of course,’ he said. ‘One is infallible and the other is fallible, so anyone with any sense would keep them separate.’ ‘Good,’ I said. ‘There can be no doubt of our position: [478a] knowledge and belief are different.’ ‘Yes.’ ‘Since they’re different faculties, then, they have different natural fields, don’t they?’ ‘Necessarily.’ ‘The field of knowledge is reality, isn’t it? Its function is to know the reality of anything real?’ ‘Yes.’ ‘And the function of belief, we’re saying, is to entertain beliefs?’ ‘Yes.’ ‘Does it entertain beliefs about the same thing which knowledge knows? Will what is accessible to know ledge and what is accessible to belief be identical? Or is that out of the question?’ ‘It’s ruled out by what we’ve already agreed,’ he said. ‘If different faculties naturally have different fields, and if both [478b] knowledge and belief are faculties, and different faculties 93 Plato, Republic too, as we said, then it follows that it is impossible for what is accessible to knowledge and what is accessible to belief to be identical.’ ‘So if it is reality that is accessible to knowledge, then it is something else, not reality, that is accessible to belief, isn’t it?’ ‘Yes.’ ‘Does it entertain beliefs about what is unreal? Or is it also impossible for that to happen? Think about this: isn’t it the case that someone who is entertaining a belief is bringing his believing mind to bear on something? I mean, is it possible to have a belief, and to be believing nothing?’ ‘That’s impossible.’ ‘In fact, someone who has a belief has some single thing in mind, doesn’t he?’ ‘Yes.’ ‘But the most accurate way to refer to something unreal [478c] would be to say that it is nothing, not that it is a single thing, wouldn’t it?’ ‘Yes.’ ‘Didn’t we find ourselves forced to relate incomprehension to unreality and knowledge to reality?’ ‘That’s right,’ he said. ‘So the field of belief is neither reality nor unreality?’ ‘No.’ ‘Belief can’t be incomprehension or knowledge, then?’ ‘So it seems.’ ‘Well, does it lie beyond their limits? Does it shed more light than knowledge or spread more obscurity than incomprehension?’ ‘It does neither.’ ‘Alternatively, does belief strike you as more opaque than knowledge and more lucid than incomprehension?’ ‘Considerably more,’ he said. [478d] ‘It lies within their limits?’ ‘Yes.’ ‘Then belief must fall between them.’ ‘Absolutely.’ ‘Now, didn’t we say earlier that something which is simultaneously real and unreal (were such a thing to be shown to exist) would fall between the perfectly real and the wholly unreal, and wouldn’t he the field of either knowledge or incomprehension, but of an intermediate (again, if such a thing were shown to exist) between incomprehension and knowledge?’ ‘Right.’ 94 Plato, Republic ‘And now we’ve found that what we call belief is such an intermediate, haven’t we?’ ‘We have.’ [478e] ‘So the only thing left for us to discover, apparently, is whether there’s anything which partakes of both reality and unreality, and cannot he said to be perfectly real or perfectly unreal. If we were to come across such a thing, we’d be fully justified in describing it as the field of belief, on the principle that extremes belong together, and so do intermediates. Do you agree?’ ‘Yes.’ ‘Let’s return, on this basis, to the give and take of [479a] conversation with that fine fellow who doesn’t acknowledge the existence of beauty itself or think that beauty itself has any permanent and unvarying character,5 but takes the plurality of beautiful things as his normthat sightseer who can’t under lily circumstances abide the notion that beauty, morality, and so on are each a single entity. What we’ll say to him is, “My friend, is there one beautiful thing, in this welter of beautiful things, which won’t turn out to be ugly? Is there one moral deed which won’t turn out to be immoral? Is there one just act which won’t turn out to be unjust?”‘ [479b] ‘No, there isn’t,’ he said. ‘It’s inevitable for these things to turn out to be both beautiful and ugly, in a sense, and the same goes for all the other qualities you mentioned in your question.’6 permanent and unvarying character: Plato’s technical usages of the Greek word idea and its cognate eidos are usually nowadays translated ‘Form’ – as in Plato’s famous Theory of Forms. This is unsatisfactory, however: the word ‘form’ is opaque in contexts like ‘the form of beauty’; and it implies physical appearance alone, whereas the Greek word implies ‘what enables us to identify something’, which is far broader than just physical appearance. 5 There is no finally satisfying translation; I use ‘character’ for idea and ‘type’ for eidos. The following definitions of ‘type’ from my dictionary are relevant: ‘a distinguishing mark; a foreshadowing’ an exemplar; a model or pattern; a kind; the general character of a class.’ The philosophical type-token distinction is also useful: in the word ‘aardvark’ there is one type of the letter ‘a’, but three tokens. The words have occurred in Republic before this, the first clearly technical usage: they have most commonly been translated ‘category’ (or synonyms), as at 357c, or ‘appearance’, as at 380d. As often as possible, ‘type’ has been used as a synonym of ‘category’, because that points up the evolutionary background of the technical term: ‘type’ in the technical metaphysical sense is originally a short form for ‘type of thing’ (see especially 435b and 476a, where the familiar sense of the word almost breaks through into the technical sense). The connection between these various senses of the words can easily be seen by thinking about identification: a physical thing’s appearance’ enables us to identify it, and it, is things of a certain ‘type’ or ‘character’ that we put together into a single set and identify as belonging together. 6 in your question: since this is the main point of contrast between particular things and the reality of the types, then Plato is committed to thinking that the type is a kind of super-particular: it really and unalterably is beautiful (or whatever), whereas nothing else is absolutely beautiful (or whatever). This is Plato’s notorious ‘self-predication assumption’ which (as he came to see by the time he wrote Parmenides) may lead to a vicious regress: if the type of beauty is itself beautiful, and if the presence of beauty in anything is to be explained as the presence of a type, then the beauty of the type of beauty itself must be explained by a further type of beauty, and so on. 95 Plato, Republic ‘And there are doubles galore - but they turn out to be halves just as much as doubles, don’t they?’ ‘Yes.’ ‘And do things which are large, small, light, and heavy deserve these attributes any more than they deserve the opposite attributes?’ ‘No, each of them is bound to have both qualities,’ he said. ‘So isn’t it the case, then, that any member of a plurality no more is whatever it is said to he than it is not whatever it is said to be?’ ‘This is like those double entendres one hears at parties,’ he [479c] said, ‘or the riddle children tell about the eunuch and his hitting a bat – they make a riddle by asking what he hit it with and what it was on7 – in the sense that the members of the plurality are also ambiguous: it is impossible to form a stable conception of any of them as either being what it is, or not being what it is, or being both, or being neither.’ ‘How are you going to cope with them, then?’ I asked. ‘Can you find a better place to locate them than between real being and unreality? I mean, they can’t rum out to be more opaque [479d] and unreal than unreality, or more lucid and real than reality.’ ‘True,’ he said. ‘So there we are. We’ve discovered that the welter of things which the masses conventionally regard as beautiful and so on mill around somewhere between unreality and perfect reality.’ ‘Yes, we have.’ ‘But we have a prior agreement that were such a thing to turn up, we’d have to call it the field of belief, not of knowledge, since the realm which occupies some uncertain intermediate point must be accessible to the intermediate faculty.’ ‘Yes, we do.’ [479e] ‘What shall we say about those spectators, then, who can see a plurality of beautiful things, but not beauty itself, and are incapable of following if someone else tries to lead them to it, and who can see many moral actions, but not morality itself. and so on? That they only ever entertain beliefs, and do not know any of the things they believe?’ ‘That’s what we have to say,’ he said. Recent intense study of self-predication has revealed a number of senses in which Plato might have said that F-ness is an F thing’ (to use the convenient jargon); however, most of them are not without their difficulties (Malcolm, Self-Predication; Heinemann). And the only sense that survives (as in the above paragraph) seems absurd. In the famous words of R. E. Allen (in Allen (ed.), Studies in Plato’s Metaphysics, 43), ‘Oddness is not odd; justice is not just; Equality is equal to nothing at all. No one can curl up for a nap in the Divine Bedsteadity; not even God can scratch Doghood behind the Ears.’ It seems that Plato had not thought through all the implications of what he was saying. One must always remember that he does not really have a theory of types: types are introduced from time to time, in different contexts, but they are never expounded and explained. They are a theme, not a theory. Therefore, there seems to me to be little point in asking what exactly Plato meant by statements implying that F-ness is F: if Plato had been interested in the subject, he might have told us. what it was on: the riddle is: ‘A man who was not a man hit a bird which was not a bird with a stone which was not a stone as it was sitting on a twig which was not a twig.’ The solution is: ‘A eunuch hit a bat with a pumice-stone as it was sitting on a reed.’ 7 96 Plato, Republic ‘As for those who can see each of these things in itself, in its permanent and unvarying nature, we’ll say they have knowledge and are not merely entertaining beliefs, won’t we?’ ‘Again, we have to.’ ‘And won’t our position be that they’re devoted to and love [480a] the domain of knowledge, as opposed to the others, who are devoted to and love the domain of belief? I mean, surely we haven’t forgotten our claim that these others love and art spectators of beautiful sounds and colours and so on, but can’t abide the idea that there is such a thing as beauty itself?’8 ‘No, we haven’t forgotten.’ ‘They won’t think us nasty if we refer to them as “lovers of belief” rather than as philosophers, who love knowledge, will they? Are they going to get very cross with us if we say that now?’ ‘Not if they listen to me,’ he replied. ‘It’s not right to get angry at the truth.’ ‘But the term “believers” is inappropriate for those who are devoted to everything that is real: they should be called philosophers, shouldn’t they?’ ‘Absolutely.’ A philosopher’s inherent virtues are displayed. Though they stem from his or her love of knowledge, they coincide with commonly recognized virtues, and are far from incompatible with rulership. [484a] ‘It’s taken a long and thorough discussion, Glaucon,’ I said, and it’s not been easy, but we’ve now demonstrated the difference between philosophers and non-philosophers.’ ‘A short discussion probably wouldn’t have been enough,’ he replied. ‘I suppose you’re right,’ I said. ‘Anyway, I think the conclusion would have been clearer if that had been the only subject we’d had to discuss, and there weren’t plenty of topics left for us to cover if we’re to see the difference between a [484b] moral and an immoral life.’ ‘What’s the next issue for us to look into?’ he asked. ‘The next one’s the one that follows, of course,’ I replied. ‘Given that philosophers are those who are capable of apprehending that which is permanent and unvarying, while those who can’t, those who wander erratically in the midst of plurality and variety, are not lovers of knowledge, which set of people ought to be rulers of a community?’ ‘What would be a sensible answer for us to give?’ he asked. ‘That the position of guardianship should be given to whichever set we find capable of guarding the laws and customs [484c] of a community,’ I said. ‘Right,’ he said. ‘I assume it’s clear whether someone who’s going to guard something should be blind or have good eyesight?’ I said. 8 beauty itself. Plato believes that our usual view of things is unsatisfactory because it makes them no more F (where F is some predicate such as ‘big’) than not-F. He has argued for this, but he merely assumes the next step – that there must therefore be something which is perfectly F. The assumption seems natural to him because the underlying issue is one of identification (see note on 479a): there must be something which is securely F, otherwise I would not have a paradigm to enable me to recognize even unsatisfactorily F things as F. 97 Plato, Republic ‘Of course it is,’ he answered. ‘Well, imagine someone who really lacks the ability to recognize any and every real thing and has no paradigm to shed light for his mind’s eye. He has nothing absolutely authentic to contemplate, as painters do, and use as a reference-point whenever he needs to, and gain a completely accurate picture [484d] of, before establishing human norms of right, morality, and goodness (if establishing is what is required), and before guarding and protecting the norms that have already been established.9 Do you think there’s any difference between is condition and blindness?’ ‘No, there’s hardly any difference at all,’ he said. ‘Is this the type of person you’d prefer us to appoint as guardians? Or shall we appoint those who can recognize every reality, and who not only have just as much practical experience as the others, but are also at least as good as them in every other respect?’10 ‘If they really are at least equal in every other sphere,’ he said, and since they are pre-eminent in the sphere you’ve mentioned, which is just about the most important one there is, then it would be ridiculous to choose anyone else.’ [485a] ‘So what we’d better explain is how a single person can combine both sets of qualities, hadn’t we?’ ‘Yes.’ ‘Well, right at the beginning of this argument we said that the first thing we had to grasp was what it is to he a philosopher. I’m sure that if we reached a satisfactory agreement on that point, we’d also agree that despite being a single person, he can combine both sets of qualities, and that philosophers are the only ones who should rule over communities.’ ‘Let’s start by agreeing that it’s natural for philosophers to [485b] love every field of study which reveals to them something of that reality which is eternal and is not subject to the vicissitudes of generation and destruction.’11 ‘All right.’ 9 established: there is an implied reference back to 412c, where it was argued that the best rulers are the best guardians of a community. The concern of philosophers with paradigms is effectively the main theme of Chapters 9 and 10. 10 practical experience: because philosophers do not live in some other world, even if their concerns sometimes seem other-worldly. It has in fact been assumed so far that philosophic intelligence is practical intelligence, of the kind that might be required for ruling a community (428b-429a; see also 488a-489a). Later, however, when it has been argued that philosophers are really interested in abstract thinking (e.g. 500b), we will find that they have to be forced to gain practical experience (e.g. 539e540a). ‘In Plato’s educational theory, as in his own life, there is a certain wavering between the ideal of action and that of contemplation’ (Barker, 203). vicissitudes of generation and destruction: very literally, ‘and does not wander as a result of coming-to-be and ceasing-to-be’. By 508d, Plato feels he can characterize the whole of the visible world as subject to these processes. Since the things of the visible world do not bear their predicates reliably, Plato is hesitant to say that they are big or beautiful or whatever; he says instead that they come to be or become big etc. for some person in some respect. In shorthand, he talks of the world of ‘becoming’ or ‘coming-to-be’ or ‘generation’. 11 98 Plato, Republic ‘Moreover,’ I said, ‘we can agree that they’re in love with reality as a whole, and that therefore their behaviour is just like that of ambitious people and lovers, as we explained before, in that they won’t willingly give up even minor or worthless parts of it.’12 ‘You’re right,’ he said. ‘The next thing for you to think about is whether there’s a [485c] further feature they must have, if they’re going to live up to our description of them.’ ‘What feature?’ ‘Honesty – the inability consciously to tolerate falsehood, rather than loathing it, and loving truth.’ ‘It makes sense that they should,’ he said. ‘It doesn’t only make sense, my friend: a lover is absolutely bound to love everything which is related and belongs to his beloved.’ ‘Right,’ he said. ‘Well, can you conceive of anything more closely related to knowledge than truth?’ ‘Of course not,’ he replied. ‘Is it possible, then, for love of knowledge and love of [485d] falsehood to be found in the same nature?’ ‘Definitely not.’ ‘Then a genuine lover of knowledge will from his earliest years find nothing more attractive than truth of every kind.’ ‘Indisputably.’ ‘And we know that anyone whose predilection tends strongly in a single direction has correspondingly less desire for other things, like a stream whose flow has been diverted into another channel.’ ‘Of course.’ ‘So when a person’s desires are channelled towards learning and so on, that person is concerned with the pleasure the mind feels of its own accord, and has nothing to do with the pleasures which reach the mind through the agency of the [485e] body, if the person is a genuine philosopher, not a fake one.’13 12 explained before: 474c-475b. The idea that philosophers are intellectual omnivores paves the way for the transition from practical wisdom to theoretical knowledge. 13 not a fake one: this (with an equivalent passage at 588c-589b) is a very important paragraph. It enables us to go some way towards reconciling a conflict, and at the same time to see an important way in which these central chapters of the book deepen Plato’s views on morality. The conflict is … between whether Plato expects the desires/workers to need controlling or to acquiesce in being ruled. The answer is that the more energy is diverted into the activities of the rational mind (the more the philosophers’ role in the community is valued), the less actual heavyhanded control of one’s baser desires (the workers) will be required, and the more the situation is describable as acquiescence. 99 Plato, Republic ‘Inevitably.’ ‘He’ll be self-disciplined, then, and not mercenary, since he’s constitutionally incapable of taking seriously the things which money can buy – at considerable cost-and which cause others to take money seriously.’ ‘Yes.’ [486a] ‘And here’s another point you’d better take into consideration, to help you distinguish a philosophical from a non-philosophical character.’ ‘What?’ ‘You must watch out for the presence of small-mindedness. Nothing stops a mind constantly striving for an overview of the totality of things human and divine more effectively than involvement in petty details.’ ‘Very true,’ he said. ‘When a mind has broadness of vision and contemplates all time and all existence, do you think it can place much importance on human life?’ ‘Impossible,’ he said. [486b] ‘So it won’t find death terrifying either, will it?’ ‘Not at all.’ ‘Then a cowardly and small-minded person is excluded from true philosophy, it seems.’ ‘I agree.’ ‘Well now, take a person who’s restrained and uninterested in money, and who isn’t smallminded or specious or cowardly. ‘Could he possibly drive hard bargains or act immorally?’ ‘No.’ ‘So when you’re trying to see whether or not someone has e philosophical mind, you’ll watch out for whether, from his earliest years, he shows himself to be moral and well mannered, or antisocial and uncouth.’ ‘Yes.’ [486c] ‘And there’s something else you won’t forget to look out for as well, I imagine.’ ‘What?’ ‘Whether he’s quick or slow at learning. I mean, you wouldn’t expect someone to be particularly fond of something it hurt him to do and where slight gains were hard to win, would you?’ ‘I’d never do that.’ ‘What about if he’s incapable of retaining anything he’s learnt? Is there any way he can have room for knowledge, when he’s full of forgetfulness?’ ‘Of course not.’ ‘In the end, don’t you think, after all his thankless toil, he’s bound to loathe both himself and intellectual activity?’ 100 Plato, Republic ‘Yes.’ [487d] ‘So we’d better count forgetfulness as a factor which precludes a mind from being good enough at philosophy. We’d better make a good memory a prerequisite.’ ‘Absolutely.’ ‘Now, isn’t it the case that lack of culture and grace in someone can only lead him to lack a sense of proportion?’ ‘Of course.’ ‘And do you think that truth is closely related to proportion or to its opposite?’ ‘To proportion.’ ‘So we need to look for a mind which, in addition to the qualities we’ve already mentioned, has an inherent sense of proportion and elegance, and which makes a person instinctively inclined towards anything’s essential character.’14 ‘Of course we do.’ [487e] ‘All right. Surely you don’t think that any of the interconnected qualities we’ve mentioned are at all inessential for a competent and complete mental grasp of reality?’ ‘No, they’re absolutely essential,’ he said. ‘Can you find any flaw, then, in an occupation like this, which in order to be competently practised requires the following inherent qualities in a person: a good memory, quickness at learning, broadness of vision, elegance, and love of and affiliation to truth, morality, courage, and self-discipline?’ ‘Not even Momus could criticize this occupation,’ he replied.15 ‘Now, aren’t people who, thanks to their education and their age, have these qualities in full the only ones to whom you would entrust your community?’ 14 essential character: see note on 479a. Since the type of anything is its truest feature, and since proportion and truth are related (in plain terms, a truthful person doesn’t exaggerate, but sees things as they are), then the sequence of thought of this sentence becomes clear. 15 Momus: the personification of criticism. 101 Plato, Republic CHAPTER 9 Socrates professes himself incapable of defining goodness and proposes a simile instead. This is the Simile of the Sun, the first of the three images which Plato uses to convey some of his core views. The Sun consists of an extended analogy between the visible and intelligible realms: just as the sun is the source of light and growth, and is responsible for sight and seeing and is the acme of the visible realm, so goodness is the source of truth and reality, and is responsible for knowledge and knowing, and is the acme of the intelligible realm. Belief, on the other band, is like partial sight. [506d] ‘Socrates, said Glaucon, ‘Please don’t back away from the finishing-line, so to speak. We’d be happy with the kind of description of goodness that you gave of morality, selfdiscipline, and so on.’ ‘So would I, Glaucon,’ I said, ‘very happy. But I’m afraid it’ll be more than I can manage, and that my malformed efforts will make me ridiculous.1 What I suggest, my friends, is that we [506e] forget about trying to define goodness itself for the time being. You see, I don’t at the moment think that our current impulse is enough to take us to where I’d like to see us go. However, I am prepared to talk about something which seems to me to be the child of goodness and to bear a very strong resemblance to it.’ Would you like me to do that? If not, we can just forget it.’ ‘Please do,’ he said. ‘You can settle your account by discussing the father another time.’ [507a] ‘I hope I can make the repayment,’ I said, ‘and you can recover the debt, rather than just the interest, as you are now.2 Anyway, as interest on your account, here’s an account of the child of goodness. But please be careful that I don’t cheat you – not that I intend to – by giving you a counterfeit description of the child.’ ‘We’ll watch out for that as best we can,’ he replied. ‘Just go ahead, please.’ ‘First I want to make sure that we’re not at cross purposes,’ I said, ‘and to remind you of something that came up earlier, though you’ve often heard it on other occasions as well.’ [507b] ‘What?’ he asked. ‘As we talk,’ I said, ‘we mention and differentiate between a lot of beautiful things and a lot of good things and so on we do.’ ‘And we also talk about beauty itself, goodness itself and so on. All the things we refer to as a plurality on those occasions we also conversely count as belonging to a single class by virtue of the fact that they have a single particular character, and we say that the x itself is “what really is”.’ ‘And we say that the first lot is visible rather than intelligible whereas characters are intelligible rather than visible.’ ‘Absolutely.’ [507c] ‘With what aspect of ourselves do we see the things we see?’ more than I can manage: it may also be worth remembering that Plato’s thoughts on goodness were notoriously obscure. He once gave a public lecture on the subject, which was so concerned with mathematics (and arithmology?) that it left the audience baffled and disappointed. 1 interest: the Greek word also means ‘child’ – a debt bears interest as a parent bears a child. But the pun is untranslatable. The pun in the next line is not Plato’s, but is meant to capture the tone of the interchange for an English reader. 2 102 Plato, Republic ‘With our sight, he replied. ‘And we use hearing for the things we hear, and so on for all the other senses and the things we perceive. Yes?’ ‘Of course.’ ‘Well, have you ever stopped to consider’, I asked, ‘how generous the creator of the senses was when he created the domain of seeing and being seen?’ ‘No, not really,’ he said. ‘Look at it this way. Are hearing and sound deficient? Do they need an extra something to make the one hear and the [507d] other be heard – some third thing without which hearing won’t hear and sound won’t be heard?’ ‘No,’ he answered. ‘And in my opinion’, I went on, ‘the same goes for many other domains, if not all: they don’t need anything like this. Or can you point to one that does?’ ‘I can’t,’ he said. ‘But do you realize that sight and the visible realm are deficient?’ ‘How?’ ‘Even if a person’s eyes are capable of sight, and he’s trying to use it, and what he’s trying to look at is coloured, the sight will see nothing and the colours will remain unseen, surely, [507e] unless there is also present an extra third thing which is made specifically for this purpose,’ ‘What is this thing you’re getting at?’ he asked. ‘It’s what we call light,’ I said. ‘You’re right,’ he said. ‘So if light has value, then because it links the sense of sight and the ability to be seen, it is far and away the most valuable link there is.’ ‘Well, it certainly does have value,’ he said. ‘Which of the heavenly gods would you say is responsible for this? Whose light makes it possible for our sight to see and for the things we see to be seen?’ ‘My reply will he no different from what yours or anyone else’s would be,’ he said. ‘I mean, you’re obviously expecting the answer, “the sun”.’ ‘Now, there are certain conclusions to be drawn from comparing sight to this god.’ ‘What?’ ‘Sight and the sun aren’t to be identified: neither the sense [508b] itself nor its location-which we call the eye is the same as the sun.’ ‘True.’ 103 Plato, Republic ‘Nevertheless, there’s no sense-organ which more closely resembles the sun, in my opinion, than the eye.’3 ‘The resemblance is striking.’ ‘Moreover, the eye’s ability to see has been bestowed upon it and channelled into it, as it were, by the sun.’ ‘Yes.’ ‘So the sun is not to he identified with sight, but is responsible for sight and is itself within the visible realm. Right?’ ‘Yes,’ he said. ‘The sun is the child of goodness I was talking about, then,’ I said. ‘It is a counterpart to its father, goodness. As goodness [508c] stands in the intelligible realm to intelligence and the things we know, so in the visible realm the sun stands to sight and the things we see.’ ‘I don’t understand,’ he said. ‘I need more detail, please.’ ‘As you know,’ I explained, ‘when our eyes are directed towards things whose colours are no longer bathed in daylight, but in artificial light instead, then they’re less effective and seem to he virtually blind, as if they didn’t even have the potential for seeing clearly.’ ‘Certainly, he said. [508d] ‘But when they’re directed towards things which are lit up by the sun, then they see clearly and obviously do have that potential.’ ‘Of course.’ ‘Well, here’s how you can think about the mind as well. When its object is something which is lit up by truth and reality, then it has – and obviously has – intelligent awareness and knowledge. However, when its object is permeated with darkness (that is, when its object is something which is subject to generation and decay), then it has beliefs and is less effective, because its beliefs chop and change, and under these circumstances it comes across as devoid of intelligence.’ ‘Yes, it does.’ [508e] ‘Well, what I’m saying is that it’s goodness which gives the things we know their truth and makes it possible for people to have knowledge.4 It is responsible for knowledge than the eye: the eye was commonly regarded as containing a good proportion of fire – it flashes and twinkles. Moreover, since it takes like to see like and we need light to see, then the eye must contain light. 3 4 people to have knowledge: what is the meaning of the assertion that goodness is responsible for truth and knowledge? (Truth means little more than just knowability here: see also 585c.) It cannot be merely that to know a thing is to know in what way it is good, because Plato envisages knowable types of immorality and evil (476a); nevertheless, this does seem to be part of his point – the rulers must be able to relate morality to goodness. But we have also seen that the types are perfect examples (notes on 476e, 479b), so Plato’s general meaning may well be that each type is good in this sense: it is a good example of what it is. (See also the connection at 38od -38iib between being a good case of something and permanence: we know that the types are permanently what they are.) This also makes sense of the idea that they are fully knowable because they fully are what they are. Still, there is the 104 Plato, Republic and truth, and you should think of it as being within the intelligible realm, but you shouldn’t identify it with knowledge and truth, otherwise you’ll he wrong: for all their value, it is even more [509a] valuable. In the other realm, it is right to regard light and sight as resembling the sun, but not to identify either of them with the sun; so in this realm it is right to regard knowledge and truth as resembling goodness, but not to identify either of them with goodness, which should be rated even more highly.’ ‘You’re talking about something of inestimable value,’ he said, ‘if it’s not only the source of knowledge and truth, but is also more valuable than them. I mean, you certainly don’t seem to be identifying it with pleasure!’ ‘How could you even think it?’ I exclaimed. ‘But we can take our analogy even further.’ [509b] ‘How?’ ‘I think you’ll agree that the ability to be seen is not the only gift the sun gives to the things we see. It is also the source of their generation, growth, and nourishment, although it isn’t actually the process of generation.’ ‘Of course it isn’t.’ ‘And it isn’t only the known-ness of the things we know which is conferred upon them by goodness, but also their reality and their being, although goodness isn’t actually the state of being, but surpasses being in majesty and might.’5 [509c] ‘It’s way beyond human comprehension, all right,’ was Glaucon’s quite amusing comment.6 ‘It’s your fault for forcing me to express my views on the subject,’ I replied. ‘Yes, and please don’t stop,’ he said. ‘If you’ve left anything out of your explanation of the simile of the sun, then the least you could do is continue with it.’ ‘There are plenty of omissions, in fact,’ I said. ‘Don’t leave any gaps,’ he said, ‘however small.’ ‘I think I’ll have to leave a lot out,’ I said, ‘but I’ll try to make it as complete as I can at the moment.’ usual equivocation of ‘good’, as meaning ‘morally good’ or ‘beneficial’ or ‘skilful’ or (now) ‘good of its kind’. Note too that knowledge and goodness are also related in Plato’s mind in less metaphysical ways than in this passage. It is only where there is room for improvement that a branch of knowledge is developed, to work for its objects’ improvement. majesty and might: goodness is responsible for the ‘being’ of the types in the same sense that it is responsible for their knowability (note on 508e). Things are knowable as true if they are perfectly and permanently what they are; this is also their being and their reality. The notion that goodness ‘surpasses being’ is hyperbole: it does not mean that we cannot talk of goodness ‘being’ and have to think of it as somehow beyond the intelligible realm of types (otherwise we would have to think of the sun as beyond the visible realm); it just stresses the exalted status of goodness within the intelligible realm. 5 6 quite amusing comment: the joke lies, of course, in whether Glaucon is commenting on the condition of goodness, or on Socrates’ argument. Socrates plays along by responding as if Glaucon had meant the latter alternative. 105 Plato, Republic ‘All right,’ he said. The image of the Line, which now follows, is expressly (509c) supposed to supplement the Sun. |------------------|-----------------------|-----------------------|---------------------------------| A B C D As A stands to B in terms of clarity and opacity, so C stands to D as well. A consists of likenesses, Which are identified by conjecture; B consists of the solid things of the material world, which are identified confidently; C and D consist of the types, which are knowable, but the two sections are distinguished because of a difference in methodology. As B stands to A in terms of truth, so C and D together stand to A and B together. A and B together constitute the visible realm, which is the realm of belief; C and D together constitute the intelligible realm, which is the realm of knowledge. [509d] ‘So bear in mind the two things we’ve been talking about,’ I said, ‘one of which rules over the intelligible realm and its inhabitants, while the other rules over the visible realm – I won’t say over the heavens in case you think I’m playing clever word-games.7 Anyway, do you understand this distinction between visible things and intelligible things?’ ‘Yes.’ ‘Well, picture them as a line cut into two unequal sections and, following the same proportion, subdivide both the section of the visible realm and that of the intelligible realm. Now you can compare the sections in terms of clarity and unclarity. The [509e] first section in the visible realm consists of likenesses, by which [501a] I mean a number of things: shadows, reflections (on the surface of water or on anything else which is inherently compact, smooth, and bright), and so on. Do you see what I’m getting at?’ ‘I do.’ ‘And you should count the other section of the visible realm as consisting of the things whose likenesses are found in the first section: all the flora and fauna there are in the world, and every kind of artefact too.’ ‘All right.’ ‘I wonder whether you’d agree,’ I said, ‘that truth and lack of truth have been the criteria for distinguishing these sections, and that the image stands to the original as the realm of beliefs stands to the realm of knowledge?’8 [510b] ‘Yes,’ he said, ‘I certainly agree.’ ‘Now have a look at how to subdivide the section which belongs to the intelligible realm.’ 7 word-games: However, at Cratylus 396b-c, Plato succumbs to the temptation and derives ouranos (‘heavens’) from horan ano (‘look upwards’). Horan is cognate with horatos, ‘visible’. 8 realm of beliefs: the shift from talk of sense-perception to talk of belief is startling, but not outrageous, given the background of 475e-480a, where again belief and sensible objects were correlated (and where we learnt that ‘belief’ was a portmanteau word for ‘unreliable thinking or apprehension’). Plato appreciates that all identification is due to the mind: the sense-impression is, so to speak, passed on to the mind for identification (see Philebus 38c-39c). 106 Plato, Republic ‘How?’ ‘Like this. If the mind wants to explore the first subdivision, it can do so only by using those former originals as likenesses and by taking things for granted on its journey, which leads it to an end-point, rather than to a starting-point.9 If it wants to explore the second subdivision, however, it takes things for granted in order to travel to a starting-point where nothing needs to be taken for granted, and it has no involvement with likenesses, as before, but makes its approach by means of types alone, in and of themselves.’ ‘I don’t quite understand what you’re saying,’ he said. [510c] You will if I repeat it,’ I said, ‘because this preamble will make it easier to understand. I’m sure you’re aware that practitioners of geometry, arithmetic, and so on take for granted things like numerical oddness and evenness, the geometrical figures, the three kinds of angle, and any other things of that sort which are relevant to a given subject.10 They act as if they know about these things, treat them as basic, and don’t feel any further need to explain them either to themselves or to anyone else, on the grounds that there is nothing unclear [510d] about them. They make them the starting-points for their subsequent investigations, which end after a coherent chain of reasoning at the point they’d set out to reach in their research.’ ‘Yes, I’m certainly well aware of this,’ he said. ‘So you must also he aware that in the course of their discussions they make use of visible forms, despite the fact that they’re not interested in visible forms as such, but in the things of which the visible forms are likenesses: that is, their discussions are concerned with what it is to be a square, and with what it is to be a diagonal (and so on), rather than with [510e] the diagonal (and so on) which occurs in their diagrams. They treat their models and diagrams as 9 originals as likenesses: it is important to notice that here and at 5iiob 5iod-e we are told that things within the material world are within the purview of the mathematical sciences. We already know that things of the material world are the contents of section B of the line: they are also the contents of section C (and note also the necessary equality of sections B and C, given Plato’s instructions for dividing and subdividing the line). Therefore, the Line is not based on a fourfold division of objects: there are three kinds of object – shadows and so on, actual things, and types; and there are four mental states. The Line is merely a convenient tool, to pull together a number of points under the headings of the fourfold division of mental states. These differ in clarity or access to truth, but it should be noted that they do not represent any kind of gradual mental development: no one starts life with his sole objects of perception being reflections in puddles, before moving on to solid objects. a given subject: this proves that ‘taking things for granted’ does not mean quite ‘assuming’, since there is nothing tentative about the existence of odd and even numbers, for instance: it is a given, a fact. Plato is delineating – in a highly condensed fashion – a certain approach to facts, which uses them deductively, to reach conclusions, and does not form them into coherent abstract systems, but takes each fact (or proposition, or concept) as a separate starting-point in a separate argument. This will shortly be contrasted with the approach of dialectic, which refers factual propositions upwards to ever higher principles, until any lingering unclarity in the facts is altogether eliminated: they are ultimately referred to something self-evident, ‘where nothing needs to be taken for granted’, and formed into coherent systems, each part of which may be taken to be true given the self-evident truth of the starting-point. This interpretation, apart from making good sense of the text here (and fitting in with 531dff. and 537eff.), has the advantage of being in accord with Plato’s use of the term ‘dialectic’ in the early dialogues and even in late dialogues, like Sophist, which concentrate on the systems of types. 10 107 Plato, Republic likenesses, when these things have likenesses themselves, in fact (that is, shadows and reflections on water); but they’re actually trying to see squares [511a] and so on in themselves, which only thought can see.’11 ‘You’re right,’ he said. ‘So it was objects of this type that I was describing as belonging to the intelligible realm, with the rider that the mind can explore them only by taking things for granted, and that its goal is not a starting-point, because it is incapable of changing direction and rising above the things it is taking for granted. And I went on to say that it used as likenesses those very things which are themselves the originals of a lower order of likenesses, and that relative to the likenesses, the originals command respect and admiration for their distinctness.’ [511b] ‘I see,’ he said. ‘You’re talking about the objects of geometry and related occupations.’ ‘Now, can you see what I mean by the second subdivision of the intelligible realm? It is what reason grasps by itself, thanks to its ability to practise dialectic. 12 When it takes things for granted, it doesn’t treat them as starting-points, but as basic in the strict sense – as platforms and rungs, for example. These serve it until it reaches a point where nothing needs to be taken for granted, and which is the starting-point for everything.13 Once it has grasped this startingpoint, it turns around and by a process of depending on the things which depend from the starting-point, it descends to an end-point. It makes absolutely [511c] no use of anything 11 only thought can see: this paragraph should not be read (as it often is) as criticizing geometers for drawing diagrams: that would be an idiotic criticism. Plato is only pointing out that, despite geometry’s use of diagrams, it is properly seen as concerned with the intelligible realm (this is exactly the point Plato claims in the next paragraph to have made). No criticism is intended: it is just that use of diagrams obscures the mathematical sciences’ true domain. For further examples of this obscuring see 527a-531c (where Plato is critical, because in these cases the scientists themselves have forgotten their true domain). 12 dialectic: dialectic means philosophical discussion (with others or with oneself) whose goal is knowledge and truth. It is the name given to Socrates’ philosophical method, as exemplified particularly in Plato’s early dialogues such as Laches and Charmides. But what has what Plato is saying here (see note on 510c) to do with Socratic practice? It is, in fact, a perfect condensed outline of Socratic dialectic. Socrates asks, for instance, ‘What is courage?’ He is given the reply, ‘Courage is endurance in the face of danger.’ This proposition is then tested by being referred to other propositions. Sooner or later, a supposedly self-evident general proposition is formulated, such as ‘Courage is good.’ In order to prove or disprove ‘Courage is endurance in the face of danger’, then, Socrates only has to test it (and/or its consequences) in the light of the self-evident proposition. If it survives the test, it forms part of a coherent system under the self-evident proposition; if it fails, it is rejected. 13 starting-point for everything. the generality of this kind of statement, and the contrast with the method of mathematics, has led some commentators to believe that Plato means that knowledge of goodness (which it is reasonable to suppose is the most ultimate starting-point possible) enables someone to deduce mathematical truths from it. But this is absurd. We should distinguish between the common properties which all types have (permanence, everlastingness, singleness, etc.) and the peculiar properties which particular types have (circularity is circular, and so on): Plato may mean that the former set of properties are deducible from goodness (see notes on 508e and 509b), but not the latter. 108 Plato, Republic perceptible to the senses: it aims for types by means of types alone, in and of themselves, and it ends its journey with types.’14 ‘I don’t quite understand,’ he said. ‘I mean, you’re talking about crucial matters here, I think. I do understand, however, that you want to mark off that part of the real and intelligible realm – which is before the eyes of anyone who knows how to practise dialectic as more dear than the other part, which is before the eyes of practitioners of the various branches of expertise, as we call them. The latter make the things they take for granted their starting-points, and although they inevitably use thought, not the senses, to observe what they observe, yet because of their failure to ascend to a starting-point-because d their enquiries rely on taking things for granted – you’re saying that they don’t understand these things, even though they are intelligible, when related to a starting-point. I take you to be describing what geometers and so on do as thinking rather than knowing, on the grounds that thinking is the intermediate state between believing and knowing.’ ‘There’s nothing wrong with your understanding,’ I said. ‘And you should appreciate that there are four states of mind, one for each of the four sections. There’s knowledge for the highest section and thought for the second one; and you’d [511c] better assign confidence to the third one and conjecture to the final one.15 You can make an orderly progression out of them, and you should regard them as possessing as much clarity as their objects possess truth.’ ‘I see,’ he said. ‘That’s fine with me. I’ll order them in the way you suggest.’ The final image, the Allegory of the Cave, is the longest and most famous of the three. It is introduced rather abruptly, but is meant to fit in with the preceding two images (517b-c, 532a-d). Further details of the fit are a matter of dispute, although the broad outlines are clear enough. Like all the great images of the world’s greatest literature, Plato’s Cave manages simultaneously to appear transparent and yet unexpectedly rich and surprising. Those readers who believe that philosophy is a dry academic pursuit will be surprised at its presentation here as a pursuit which frees us from a terrible slavery; but for Plato and his peers philosophy is a way of life, not just a course of study. [514a] ‘Next,’ I said, ‘here’s a situation which you can use as an analogy for the human condition – for our education or lack of it. Imagine people living in a cavernous cell down under the ground; at the far end of the cave, a long way off, there’s an entrance open to the outside world. They’ve been there since childhood, with their legs and necks tied up in a way which b keeps them in one place and allows them to look only straight ahead, but not to turn their heads. There’s firelight burning a long way further up the cave behind them, and up the slope between the fire and the prisoners there’s a road, beside which you should imagine a 14 types: why has dialectic as outlined (notes on 510c and 511b) to do with types? Because it relies entirely on abstract statements, and never ‘descends’ to examples like ‘repaying gifts’. It works with propositions like ‘morality is good’, even before checking whether everything we can properly identify as belonging to the class or type of morality is good. 15 to the final one: conjecture is assigned to shadows and reflections because we have to be hesitant before identifying what the likeness is of, and because the details will be far from clear (remember that ancient Greek mirrors were no where near as good as ours!). Confidence is the mental state appropriate for the material world: as 505e shows, it is the state in which I assume unreflectively that I know all there is to know about something. Because the material world is clear to our senses, we do have this confidence. 109 Plato, Republic low wall has been built-like the partition which conjurors place between themselves and their audience and above which they show their tricks.’ ‘All right,’ he said. ‘Imagine also that there are people on the other side of this wall who are carrying all sorts of artefacts. These artefacts, [514c] human statuettes, and animal models carved in stone and wood [515a] and all kinds of materials stick out over the wall; and as you’d expect, some of the people talk as they carry these objects along, while others are silent.’ ‘This is a strange picture you’re painting,’ he said,’ with strange prisoners.’ ‘They’re no different from us,’ I said.16 ‘I mean, in the first place, do you think they’d see anything of themselves and one another except the shadows cast by the fire on to the cave wall directly opposite them?’17 ‘Of course not,’ he said. ‘They’re forced to spend their lives [515b] without moving their heads.’ ‘And what about the objects which were being carried along? Won’t they only see their shadows as well?’ ‘Naturally.’ ‘Now, suppose they were able to talk to one another: don’t you think they’d assume that their words applied to what they saw passing by in front of them?’18 16 no different from us: this statement is unequivocal evidence that the Cave is an allegory. The prisoners are said to be like us, but we do not spend our lives literally gazing at shadows of artefacts. Although there are almost as many interpretations of the relation between the Cave and the Line as there are writers on it, this consideration rules out one common set of interpretations, which tries to find an exact correspondence between the four main objects in the Cave (shadows on the wall, artefacts in the cave, reflections outside the cave, real things outside the cave) and the four divisions of the Line. However, as we have seen, the Line is not a figure for mental development, as the Cave is, and in any case there are only three sets of objects in the Line (see note on 510b). Nor is it at all clear that the Cave settles on four stages: 506a-b alone could be seen as talking of five ‘stages’ outside the cave. In short, it is probably better to see the Cave as illustrating and expanding certain aspects of what has gone before, rather than looking for exact fits. 17 opposite them: the crucial factor for interpreting the Cave is to see that the shadows are cast by things which are themselves effigies of real things. We know from 517b that real things outside the cave stand for types. Therefore the effigies are reflections of types, and the shadows are reflections of reflections of types. (One’s mind jumps to 596aff. and the castigation of artistic products as copies of copies of types; but this is correct only in so far as there is an equivalence of delusion.) But what kinds of things are reflections of reflections of types? They should be things within our everyday experience, since the prisoners symbolize the common human condition. I argue … that in Republic Plato is taking for granted two different kinds of types: one kind (‘bed’, ‘finger’) is perfectly instantiated directly in the physical world, with hardly any need for dispute and doubt about their identification; the other kind (described by incomplete predicates such as ‘big’ and ‘moral’) has to be mediated by our minds, in the sense that we have to think about what objects deserve these predicates. The Cave is concerned (as Plato usually is, but particularly here in the context of determining what knowledge philosopher kings need) with this latter variety: the effigies are my mental impressions or thoughts of morality and so on; the shadows on the wall are moral actions, big rocks, and all the physical things of the world. Thus the bearers of the effigies behind the wall may be the ‘doubles’ of the chained prisoners, or may be the poets, politicians, and so on who have formed the prisoners’ views about morality and similar matters. 110 Plato, Republic ‘They couldn’t think otherwise.’ ‘And what if sound echoed off the prison wall opposite them? When any of the passers-by spoke, don’t you think they’d he bound to assume that the sound came from a passing shadow?’ ‘I’m absolutely certain of it,’ he said. [515c] ‘All in all, then,’ I said, ‘the shadows of artefacts would constitute the only reality people in this situation would recognize.’ ‘That’s absolutely inevitable,’ he agreed. ‘What do you think would happen, then,’ I asked, ‘if they were set free from their bonds and cured of their inanity?19 What would it he like if they found that happening to them? Imagine that one of them has been set free and is suddenly made to stand up, to turn his head and walk and to look towards the firelight.20 It hurts him to do all this and he’s too dazzled to he capable of making out the objects whose shadows [515d] he’d formerly been looking at. And suppose someone tells him that what he’s been seeing all this time has no substance, and that he’s now closer to reality and is seeing more accurately, because of the greater reality of the things in front of his eyes – what do you imagine his reaction would be? And what do you think he’d say if he were shown any of the passing objects and had to respond to being asked what it was? Don’t you think he’d he bewildered and would think that there was, more reality in what he’d been seeing before than in what he was being shown now?’ ‘Far more,’ he said. [515e] ‘And if he were forced to look at the actual firelight, don’t you think it would hurt his eyes? Don’t you think he’d turn away and run back to the things he could make out, and would take the truth of the matter to he that these things are clearer than what he was being shown?’ ‘Yes,’ he agreed. ‘And imagine him being dragged forcibly away from there up the rough, steep slope,’ I went on, ‘without being released until he’s been pulled out into the sunlight. Wouldn’t this treatment [516a] cause him pain and distress? And once he’s reached the sunlight, he wouldn’t be able to see a single one of the things which are currently taken to he real, would he, because his eyes would be overwhelmed by the sun’s beams?’ ‘No, he wouldn’t,’ he answered, ‘not straight away.’ in front of them: in Platonic terms, this shows the extent of the prisoners’ delusion, since our words really refer to types (596a). 19 inanity: the kind of reorientation Plato envisages here is later typified, in an educational curriculum, by the effect of the mathematical sciences (521dff.). But we need not suppose that mathematics is the only thing which can reorient one to break out of the shackles. 18 towards the firelight: we are undoubtedly meant to remember the artificial lights’ Of 508c. On my interpretation of the Cave, the effect of firelight may, in a moral and political context, be convention or the views of others (the bearers of the effigies). Seeing the dependence of one’s cherished views on convention blinds one to things in the sense of 537c-539a: having seen that they were merely conventional, one is tempted to dismiss and despise them, or (the alternative stressed here) to run back to the safety of not challenging them. 20 111 Plato, Republic ‘He wouldn’t be able to see things up on the surface of the earth, I suppose, until he’d got used to his situation. At first, it would be shadows that he could most easily make out, then he’d move on to the reflections of people and so on in water, and later he’d he able to see the actual things themselves.21 Next, he’d feast his eyes on the heavenly bodies and the heavens themselves, which would be easier at night: he’d look at the [516b] light of the stars and the moon, rather than at the sun and sunlight during the daytime.’ ‘Of course.’ ‘And at last, I imagine, he’d be able to discern and feast his eyes on the sun – not the displaced image of the sun in water or elsewhere, but the sun on its own, in its proper place.’22 ‘Yes, he’d inevitably come to that,’ he said. ‘After that, he’d start to think about the sun and he’d deduce that it is the source of the seasons and the yearly cycle, that the whole of the visible realm is its domain, and that in a sense [516c] everything which he and his peers used to see is its responsibility.’ ‘Yes, that would obviously be the next point he’d come to,’ he agreed. ‘Now, if he recalled the cell where he’d originally lived and what passed for knowledge there and his former fellow prisoners, don’t you, think he d feel happy about his own altered circumstances, and sorry for them?’ ‘Definitely.’ ‘Suppose that the prisoners used to assign prestige and credit to one another, in the sense that they rewarded speed at recognizing the shadows as they passed, and the ability to remember which ones normally come earlier and later and at [516d] the same time as which other ones, and expertise at using this as a basis for guessing which ones would arrive next. Do you think our former prisoner would covet these honours and would envy the people who had status and power there, or would he much prefer, as Homer describes it, “being a slave labouring for someone else-someone without property”, and would put up with anything at all, in fact, rather than share their beliefs and their life?’23 [516e] ‘Yes, I think he’d go through anything rather than live that way,’ he said. ‘Here’s something else I’d like your opinion about,’ I said. ‘If he went back underground and sat down again in the same spot, wouldn’t the sudden transition from the sunlight mean that his eyes would be overwhelmed by darkness?’ ‘Certainly,’ he replied. ‘Now, the process of adjustment would be quite long this time, and suppose that before his eyes had settled down and [517a] while he wasn’t seeing well, he had once again to compete against those same old prisoners at identifying those shadows. Wouldn’t he make a fool of 21 in water: the stage of looking at reflections and so on outside the cave does not differ in terms of objects from the stage of looking at the effigies in the cave (compare the identity of objects in sections B and C of the Line – see note on 510b). But it differs in that it is now more difficult for one to return to the safety of convention (see note on 515c). 22 23 in its proper place: the sun in the allegory is, of course, goodness, as it was in the Sun. without property: Odyssey II. 489, also quoted at 386c. 112 Plato, Republic himself? Wouldn’t they say that he’d come back from his upward journey with his eyes ruined, and that it wasn’t even worth trying to go up there? And wouldn’t they – if they could – grab hold of anyone who tried to set them free and take them up there, and kill him?’24 ‘They certainly would,’ he said. ‘Well, my dear Glaucon,’ I said, ‘you should, apply this [517ba] allegory, as a whole, to what we were talking about before. The region which is accessible to sight should be equated with the prison cell, and the firelight there with the light of the sun. And if you think of the upward journey and the sight of things up on the surface of the earth as the mind’s ascent to the intelligible realm, you won’t he wrong – at least, I don’t think you’d be wrong, and it’s my impression that you want to hear. Only God knows if it’s actually true, however. Anyway, it’s my opinion that the last thing to be seen – and it isn’t easy to see [517c] either – in the realm of knowledge is goodness; and the sight of the character of goodness leads one to deduce that it is responsible for everything that is right and fine, whatever the circumstances, and that in the visible realm it is the progenitor of light and of the source of light, and in the intelligible realm it is the source and provider of truth and knowledge. And I also think that the sight of it is a prerequisite for intelligent conduct either of one’s own private affairs or of public business.’ ‘I couldn’t agree more,’ he said. ‘All right, then,’ I said. ‘I wonder if you also agree with me in not finding it strange that people who’ve travelled there don’t want to engage in human business: there’s nowhere else their minds would ever rather be than in the upper region – which is [517d] hardly surprising, if our allegory has got this aspect right as well.’ ‘No, it’s not surprising,’ he agreed. ‘Well, what about this?’ I asked. ‘Imagine someone returning to the human world and all its misery after contemplating the divine realm. Do you think it’s surprising if he seems awkward and ridiculous while he’s still not seeing well, before he’s had time to adjust to the darkness of his situation, and he’s forced into a contest (in a law court or wherever) about the shadows of morality or the statuettes which cast the shadows, and into a [517e] competition whose terms are the conceptions of morality held by people who have never seen morality itself?’ ‘No, that’s not surprising in the slightest,’ he said. [518a] ‘In fact anyone with any sense,’ I said, ‘would remember that the eyes can become confused in two different ways, as a result of two different sets of circumstances: it can happen in the transition from light to darkness, and also in the transition from darkness to light. If he took the same facts into consideration when he also noticed someone’s mind in such a state of confusion that it was incapable of making anything out, his reaction wouldn’t be unthinking ridicule. Instead, he’d try to find out whether this person’s mind was returning from a mode of existence which involves greater lucidity and had been blinded by the unfamiliar darkness, or whether it was moving from relative ignorance to relative lucidity and had been overwhelmed and dazzled by the increased brightness. Once he’d distinguished between the two conditions and modes of [518b] existence, he’d congratulate anyone he found in the second state, and feel sorry for anyone in the first state. If he did choose to laugh 24 and kill him: as Socrates was killed. Cf. the ‘prophecy’ in the Gorgias. 113 Plato, Republic at someone in the second state, his amusement would be less absurd than when laughter is directed at someone returning from the light above.’25 ‘Yes,’ he said, ‘you’re making a lot of sense.’ Since the Cave was expressly introduced as being relevant to education, its immediate educational implications are now drawn out. We all have the capacity for knowledge (in the Platonic sense, not just information), and education should develop that potential But since it requires knowledge of goodness to manage a community web, then those who gain such knowledge have to ‘return to the cave’: paradoxically, those who least want power are the ones who should have it. ‘Now, if this is true,’ I said, ‘we must bear in mind that education is not capable of doing what some people promise. They claim to introduce knowledge into a mind which doesn’t [518c] have it, as if they were introducing sight into eyes which are blind.’26 ‘Yes, they do,’ he said. ‘An implication of what we’re saying at the moment, however,’ I pointed out, ‘is that the capacity for knowledge is present in everyone’s mind. If you can imagine an eye that can turn from darkness to brightness only if the body as a whole turns, then our organ of understanding is like that. Its orientation has to he accompanied by turning the mind as a whole away from the world of becoming, until it becomes capable of bearing the sight of real being and reality at its most bright, which we’re saying is goodness. Yes?’ ‘Yes.’ ‘That’s what education should be,’ I said, ‘the art of orientation. Educators should devise the simplest and most effective methods of turning minds around. It shouldn’t he the art of implanting sight in the organ, but should proceed on the understanding that the organ already has the capacity, but is improperly aligned and isn’t facing the right way.’ ‘I suppose you’re right,’ he said. ‘So although the mental states which are described as good generally seem to resemble good physical states, in the sense [518e] that habituation and training do in fact implant them where they didn’t use to be, yet understanding (as it trims out) is undoubtedly, a property of something which is more divine: it never loses its power, and it is useful and beneficial, or useless [519a] and harmful, depending on its orientation. For example, surely you’ve noticed how the petty minds of those who are acknowledged to be bad, but clever, are sharp-eyed and perceptive enough to gain insights into matters they direct their attention towards. It’s not as if they weren’t sharp-sighted, but their minds are forced to serve evil, and consequently the keener their vision is, the greater the evil they accomplish.’ ‘Yes, I’ve noticed this,’ he said. 25 the light above: because (as Theaetetus 175b-d shows) he finds the antics of those unfamiliar with the upper regions somewhat amusing. 26 which are blind: many commentators have seen here a hint of the famous theory of recollection, according to which all so-called learning is in fact recollection of knowledge acquired before one’s present incarnation. If that is the case, nothing is made of it in Republic. And in Socrates’ next sentence he mentions only the capacity for knowledge, which is quite different from how the theory is presented in Meno and Phaedo. 114 Plato, Republic ‘However,’ I went on, ‘if this aspect of that kind of person is hammered at from an early age, until the inevitable consequences of incarnation have been knocked off it – the [519b] leaden weights, so to speak, which are grafted on to it as a result of eating and similar pleasures and indulgences and which turn the sight of the mind downwards-if it sheds these weights and is reoriented towards the truth, then (and we’re talking about the same organ and the same people) it would see the truth just as clearly as it sees the objects it faces at the moment.’ ‘Yes, that makes sense.’ he said. ‘Well, doesn’t this make sense as well?’ I asked. ‘Or rather, isn’t it an inevitable consequence of what we’ve been saying that uneducated people, who have no experience of truth, [519c] would make incompetent administrators of a community, and that the same goes for people – who are allowed to spend their whole fives educating themselves? The first group would be no good because their lives lack direction: they’ve got no single point of reference to guide them in all their affairs, whether private or public. The second group would be no good because their hearts wouldn’t be in the business: they think they’ve been transported to the Isles of the Blessed even while they’re still alive.’27 ‘True,’ he said. ‘Our job as founders, then,’ I said, ‘is to make sure that the best people come to that fundamental field of study (as we called it earlier): we must have them make the ascent we’ve been talking about and see goodness. And afterwards, once [519d] they’ve been up there and had a good look, we mustn’t let them get away with what they do at the moment.’ ‘Which is what?’ ‘Staying there,’ I replied, ‘and refusing to come back down again to those prisoners, to share their work and their rewards, no matter whether those rewards are trivial or significant.’ ‘But in that case,’ he protested, ‘we’ll be wronging them: we’ll be making the quality of their lives worse and denying them the better life they could be living, won’t we?’ [519e] ‘You’re again forgetting, my friend,’ I said, ‘that the point of legislation is not to make one section of a community better off than the rest, but to engineer this for the community as a whole. Legislators should persuade or compel the members of a community to mesh together, should make every individual [520a] share with his fellows the benefit which he is capable of contributing to the common welfare, and should ensure that the community does contain people with this capacity; and the purpose of all this is not for legislators to leave people to choose their own directions, but for them to use people to bind the community together.’ ‘Yes, you’re right,’ he said. ‘I was forgetting.’ ‘I think you’ll also find, Glaucon,’ I said, ‘that we won’t be wronging any philosophers who arise in our community. Our remarks, as we force them to take care of their fellow citizens and be their guardians, will be perfectly fair. We’ll tell them [520b] that it’s reasonable for philosophers who happen to occur in other communities not to share the work of those communities, since their occurrence was spontaneous, rather than planned by the political system of any of the communities m question, and it’s fair for anything which arises spontaneously and doesn’t owe its nurture to anyone or anything to have no interest in 27 still alive: the Isles of the Blessed were that part of the underworld reserved for people, after their death, who had lived particularly virtuous lives. 115 Plato, Republic repaying anyone for having provided its nourishment. “We’ve bred you, however,” we’ll say, “to act, as it were, as the hive’s leaders and kings, for your own good as well as that of the rest of the community. You’ve received a better and more thorough education than those other philosophers, and you’re more [520c] capable of playing a part in both spheres. So each of you must, when your time comes, descend to where the rest of the community lives, and get used to looking at things in the dark. The point is that once you become acclimatized, you’ll see infinitely better than the others there; your experience of genuine right, morality, and goodness will enable you to identify every one of the images and recognize what it is an image of. And then the administration of our community – ours as well as yours – will be in the hands of people who are awake, as distinct from the norm nowadays of communities being governed by people who shadow-box and fall out with one another in their dreams over who should rule, as if that [520d] were a highly desirable thing to do. No, the truth of the matter is this: the less keen the would-be rulers of a community are to rule, the better and less divided the administration of that community is bound to be, but where the rulers feel the opposite, the administration is bound to be the opposite.’28 ‘Yes,’ he said. ‘And do you think our wards will greet these views of ours with scepticism and will refuse to join in the work of government when their time comes, when they can still spend most of their time living with one another in the untainted realm?’ ‘No, they couldn’t,’ he answered. ‘They’re fair-minded people, and the instructions we’re giving them are fair. However, they’ll undoubtedly approach rulership as an inescapable duty – an attitude which is the opposite of the one held by the people who have power in communities at the moment. ‘You’re right, Glaucon,’ I said. ‘You’ll only have a well [521a] governed community if you can come up with a way of life for your prospective rulers that is preferable to ruling! The point is that this is the only kind of community where the rulers will be genuinely well off (not in material terms, but they’ll possess the wealth which is a prerequisite of happiness – a life of virtue and intelligence), whereas if government falls into the hands of people who are impoverished and starved of any good things of their own, and who expect to wrest some 28 at the moment: Plato never makes completely clear what will induce the philosophers to take up politics: he obscures the issue under the conceit of himself and his fellow interlocutors forcing them to do so. The compulsion is probably a combination of (a) the fact that the rulers have been specifically chosen from among those who feel that their own good and the good of the community as a whole coincide (412cff.), and like everyone else they want to see their own good happen (505d-e); (b) horror at the prospect of worse people than themselves gaining power (347a-d; in the ideal state, however, they themselves will take turns at ruling (540b), so this motivation will be excluded); (c) understanding the importance of debt-repayment (520d-e). Of these, (a) is by far the most important, and it raises the question as to why philosophers should think that their good and that of the community as a whole coincide. Plato has to talk of compulsion now, because he has made contemplation of types seem so attractive that it is unclear why the philosophers should want to end it. This is related to an important issue. He has driven a huge wedge between the philosopher’s experiences and knowledge and everyday life. Yet he is still maintaining that philosophic contemplation is to be of practical benefit to the community. What is the relation between the practical work of reason and its contemplation of unchanging types? Plato does not tell us in so many words, but the gap can be closed to some extent: see the next note. 116 Plato, Republic good for themselves from political office, a well-governed community is an impossibility. I mean, when rulership becomes something to fight for, a domestic and internal war like this destroys not only the perpetrators,’ but also the rest of the community.’ ‘You’re absolutely right,’ he said. [521b] ‘Apart from the philosophical life,’ I said, ‘is there any way of life, in your opinion, which looks down on political office?’29 ‘No, definitely not,’ he answered. ‘In fact, political power should be in the hands of people who aren’t enamoured of it. Otherwise their rivals in love will fight them for it.’ ‘Of course.’ ‘There’s no one you’d rather force to undertake the guarding of your community, then, than those who are experts in the factors which contribute towards the good government of a community, who don’t look to politics for their rewards, and whose life is better than the political life. Agreed?’ ‘Yes,’ he said. Political office: ‘Philosophizing is essential to ruling because it is the activity that is preferable to ruling, and so the activity that the ruler must have available to him if he is to wish not to rule, where wishing not to rule is, paradoxically, what makes it possible for him to rule well. Thus the total task of ruling, properly construed, must include the activity of philosophy, both as a lure from the practical side of actually managing the affairs of the city, and as a source of that knowledge by which the managing is guided. ‘The upshot is that philosophizing is not thought of by Plato as a task somehow additional to that of ruling, but as an essential part of effective ruling’ (White, A Companion to Plato’s Republic, 190). 29 117 Newton, Principia Isaac Newton PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION OF THE PRINCIPIA1 [From H.S. Thayer (ed) Newton’s Philosophy of Nature: Selections from his Writings (New York, 1953)] ince the ancients (as we are told by Pappus2) esteemed the science of mechanics3 of greatest importance in the investigation of natural things, and the moderns, rejecting substantial forms and occult qualities,4 have endeavoured to subject the phenomena of nature to the laws of mathematics, I have in this treatise cultivated mathematics as far as it relates to philosophy. The ancients considered mechanics in a twofold respect: as rational, which proceeds accurately by demonstration, and practical. 5 To practical mechanics all the manual arts belong, from which mechanics took its name. But as artificers do not work with perfect accuracy, it comes to pass that mechanics is so distinguished from geometry that what is perfectly accurate is called geometrical; what is less so is called mechanical. However, the errors are not in the art, but in the artificers. He that works with less accuracy is an imperfect mechanic; and if any could work with perfect accuracy, he would be the most perfect mechanic of all; for the description of right lines and circles, upon which geometry is founded, belongs to mechanics. Geometry does not teach us to draw these lines, but requires them to be drawn; for it requires that the learner should first be taught to describe these accurately before he enters upon geometry,6 then it shows how by these operations problems may be solved. To describe right lines and circles are problems, but not geometrical problems. The solution of these problems is required from mechanics, and by geometry the use of them, when so solved, is shown; and it is the glory of geometry that from those few principles, brought from without, it is able to produce so many things.7 Therefore geometry is founded in mechanical practice and is nothing but that part of universal mechanics which accurately proposes and demonstrates the art of measuring; But since the manual arts are S 1 Written at Cambridge, Trinity College, May 8, 1686, the year of publication of the first edition. Pappus was the author of the Synagoge (“Collection”), the last great treatise of the Alexandrian mathematicians, end of the third century. The Synagoge was a guide to the study of Greek geometry. Many important Greek mathematical results have been preserved for later ages only through the work of Pappus. The Synagoge was written about 320 A.D.; Latin translation, 589. 2 3 science of mechanics = the branch of mathematics concerned with forces and movement. 4 Newton is referring here to the terminology of scholastic (mediaeval) natural philosophy, which was based on Aristotle. Scholasticism explained natural phenomena by appealing to the essential properties of things (substantial forms) and to hidden and unexplained forces (occult qualities). These occult qualities are ridiculed by Moliere, who has a character explain why opium sends you to sleep by saying that it has a vis dormitiva (that is, the power of sending you to sleep). This explains nothing. 5 rational mechanics = a branch of mathematics; practical mechanics = what we might call engineering. Newton is marking the distinction between pure and applied science. 6 describe = draw This is the axiomatic method, discussed last week in connection with Plato: starting with a few basic axioms or principles, the scientist can explain and predict natural phenomena. 7 118 Newton, Principia chiefly employed in the moving of bodies, it happens that geometry is commonly referred to their magnitude, and mechanics to their motion.8 In this sense rational mechanics will be the science of motions resulting from any forces whatsoever and of the forces required to produce any motions, accurately proposed and demonstrated. This part of mechanics, as far as it extended to the five powers which relate to manual arts, was cultivated by the ancients, who considered gravity (it not being a manual power) not otherwise than in moving weights by those powers. But I consider philosophy rather than arts,9 and write not concerning manual but natural powers, and consider chiefly those things which relate to gravity, levity, elastic force, the resistance of fluids, and the like forces, whether attractive or impulsive – and therefore I offer this work as the mathematical principles of philosophy, for the whole burden of philosophy seems to consist in this: from the phenomena of motions to investigate the forces of nature, and then from these forces to demonstrate the other phenomena; and to this end the general propositions in the First and Second Books are directed. In the Third Book I give an example of this in the explication of the System of the World; for by the propositions mathematically demonstrated in the former books, in the third I derive from the celestial phenomena the forces of gravity with which bodies tend to the sun and the several planets. Then from these forces, by other propositions which are also mathematical, I deduce the motions of the planets, the comets, the moon, and the sea. I wish we could derive the rest of the phenomena of Nature by the same kind of reasoning from mechanical principles, for I am induced by many reasons to suspect that they may all depend upon certain forces by which the particles of bodies, by some causes hitherto unknown, are either mutually impelled toward one another and cohere in regular figures, or are repelled and recede from one another. These forces being unknown, philosophers have hitherto attempted the search of Nature in vain; but I hope the principles here laid down will afford some light either to this or some truer method of philosophy. In the publication of this work the most acute and universally learned Mr. Edmund Halley not only assisted me in correcting the errors of the press and preparing the geometrical figures, but it was through his solicitations that it came to be published;10 for when he had obtained of me my demonstrations of the figure of the celestial orbits, he continually pressed me to communicate the same to the Royal Society, who afterward, by their kind encouragement and entreaties, engaged me to think of publishing them. But after I had begun to consider the inequalities of the lunar motions, and had entered upon some other things relating to the laws and measures of gravity and other, forces; and the figures that would be described by bodies attracted according to given laws; and the motion of several bodies moving among themselves; the motion of bodies in resisting mediums; the forces, densities, and motions of mediums; the orbits of the comets, and suchlike, I deferred that publication till I had made a search into those matters and could put forth the whole together. What relates to the lunar motions (being imperfect), I have put all together in the corollaries of Proposition LXVI, to avoid being obliged to propose and distinctly demonstrate the several things there contained in a method more prolix than the subject deserved and interrupt the series of the other propositions. Some things, found out after the rest, I chose to insert in places less suitable, 8 manual arts = engineering and the like Newton’s distinction between ‘philosophy’ and ‘art’ corresponds with the distinction between pure and applied science. He is saying that ancient mechanics (such as the work of Archimedes) was concerned more with engineering applications than understanding the fundamental forces at work. 9 10 Edmund Halley = an eminent astronomer, most famous for identifying the orbit of the comet that bears his name. 119 Newton, Principia rather than change the number of the propositions and the citations. I heartily beg that what I have here done may be read with forbearance and that my labors in a subject so difficult may be examined, not so much with the view to censure, as to remedy their defects. Is. NEWTON Cambridge, Trinity College, May 8, 1686 120 Popper, Conjectures and Refutations Karl R. Popper SCIENCE: CONJECTURES AND REFUTATIONS1 Mr. Turnbull had predicted evil consequences, and was now doing the best in his power to bring about the verification of his own prophecies. ANTHONY TROLLOPE [From Karl Popper, Conjectures and Refutations (Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1963), pp 33-38.] W HEN I received the list of participants in this course and realized that I had been asked to speak to philosophical colleagues I thought after some hesitation and consultation, that you would probably prefer me to speak about those problems which interest me most, and about those developments with which 1 am most intimately acquainted. 1 therefore decided to do what 1 have never done before: to give you a report on my own work in the philosophy of science, since the autumn of 1919 when I first began to grapple with the problem, ‘When should a theory be ranked as scientific?’ or ‘Is there a criterion for the scientific character or status of a theory?’ The problem which troubled me at the time was neither, ‘When is a theory true?,’ nor, ‘When is a theory acceptable?’ My problem was different. I wished to distinguish between science and pseudo-science; knowing very well that science often errs, and that pseudo-science may happen to stumble on the truth. I knew, of course, the most widely accepted answer to my problem: that science is distinguished from pseudo-science - or from ‘metaphysics’ - by its empirical method, which is essentially inductive, proceeding from observation or experiment. But this did not satisfy me. On the contrary, I often formulated my problem as one of distinguishing between a genuinely empirical method and a non-empirical or even a pseudo-empirical method-that is to say, a method which, although it appeals to observation and experiment, nevertheless [34] does not come up to scientific standards. The latter method may be exemplified by astrology, with its stupendous, mass of empirical evidence based on observation-on horoscopes and on biographies. But as it was not the example of astrology which led me to my problem I should perhaps briefly describe the atmosphere in which my problem arose and the examples by which it was stimulated. After the collapse of the Austrian Empire there had been a revolution in Austria: the air was full of revolutionary slogans and ideas, and new and often wild theories. Among the theories which interested me Einstein’s theory of relativity was no doubt by far the most important. Three others were Marx’s theory of history, Freud’s psycho-analysis, and Alfred Adler’s so-called ‘individual psychology’. There was a lot of popular nonsense talked about these theories, and especially about relativity (as still happens even today), but 1 was fortunate in those who introduced me to the study of this theory. We all - the small circle of students to which I belonged - were thrilled with the result of Eddington’s eclipse observations which in 1919 brought the first important confirmation of Einstein’s theory of gravitation. It was a great experience for us, and one which had a lasting influence on my intellectual development. 1 A lecture given at Peterhouse, Cambridge, in Summer 1953, as part of a course, on developments and trends in contemporary British philosophy, organized by the British Council; originally published under the title ‘Philosophy of Science: a Personal Report’ in British Philosophy in Mid-Century, ed. C. A. Mace, 1957. 121 Popper, Conjectures and Refutations The three other theories I have mentioned were also widely discussed among students at that time. I myself happened to come into personal contact with Alfred Adler, and even to cooperate with him in his social work among the children and young people in the workingclass districts of Vienna where he had established social guidance Clinics. It was during the summer of 1919 that I began to feel more and more dissatisfied with these three theories – the Marxist theory of history, psychoanalysis, and individual, psychology; and began to feel dubious about their claims to scientific status. My problem perhaps first took the simple form, ‘What is wrong with Marxism, psycho-analysis, and individual psychology? Why are they so different from physical theories, from Newton’s theory, and especially from the theory of relativity?’ To make this contrast clear I should explain that few of us at the time would. have said that we believed in the truth of Einstein’s theory of gravitation. This shows that it was not my doubting the truth of those other three theories which bothered me, but something else. Yet neither was it that I merely felt mathematical physics to be more exact than the sociological or psychological type of theory. Thus what worried me was neither the problem of truth, at that stage at least, nor the problem of exactness or measurability. It was rather that I felt that these other three theories, though posing as sciences. had in fact more in common with primitive myths than with science; that they resembled astrology rather than astronomy. I found that those of my friends who were admirers of Marx, Freud, and Adler, were impressed by a number of points common to these theories, and especially by their apparent explanatory power. These theories appeared to be able to explain practically everything that happened within the fields to which they referred. The study of any of them seemed to have the effect of an [35] intellectual conversion or revelation, opening your eyes to a new truth hidden, from those not yet initiated. Once your eyes were thus opened you saw confirming instances everywhere: the world was full of verifications of the theory. Whatever happened always confirmed it. Thus its truth appeared manifest; and unbelievers were clearly people who did not want to see the manifest truth; who refused to see it, either because it was against their class interest, or because of their repressions which were still ‘un-analysed’ and crying aloud for treatment. The most characteristic element in this situation seemed to me the incessant stream of confirmations, of observations which ‘verified’ the theories in question; and this point was constantly emphasized by their adherents. A Marxist could not open a newspaper without finding on every page confirming evidence for his interpretation of history; not only in the news, but also in its presentation-which revealed the class bias of the paper-and especially of course in what the paper did not say. The Freudian analysts emphasized that their theories were constantly verified by their ‘clinical observations’. As for Adler, I was much impressed by a personal experience. Once, in 1919, 1 reported to him a case which to me did not seem particularly Adlerian, but which he found no difficulty in analysing in terms of his theory of inferiority feelings, although he had not even seen the child. Slightly shocked, I asked him how he could be so sure. ‘Because of my thousandfold experience,’ he replied; whereupon 1 could not help saying: ‘And with this new case, I suppose, your experience has become thousand-and-one-fold.’ What I had in mind was that his previous observations may not have been much sounder than this new one; that each in its turn had been interpreted in the light of ‘previous experience’, and at the same time counted as additional confirmation. What, I asked myself, did it confirm? No more than that a case could be interpreted in the light of the theory. But this 122 Popper, Conjectures and Refutations meant very little, I reflected, since every conceivable case could be interpreted in the light of Adler’s theory, or equally of Freud’s. I may illustrate this by two very different examples of human behaviour: that of a man who pushes a child into the water with the intention of drowning it; and that of a man who sacrifices his life in an attempt to save the child. Each of these two cases can be explained with equal ease in Freudian and in Adlerian terms. According to Freud the first man suffered from repression (say, of some component of his Oedipus complex), while the second man had achieved sublimation. According to Adler the first man suffered from feelings of inferiority (producing perhaps the need to prove to himself that he dared to commit some crime), and so did the second man (whose need was to prove to himself that he dared to rescue the child). I could not think of any human behaviour which could not be interpreted in terms of either theory. It was precisely this fact-that they always fitted, that they were always confirmed-which in the eyes of their admirers constituted the strongest argument in favour of these theories. It began to dawn on me that this apparent strength was in fact their weakness. With Einstein’s theory the situation was strikingly different. Take one [36] typical instance Einstein’s prediction, just then confirmed by the findings of Eddington’s expedition. Einstein’s gravitational theory had led to the result that light must be attracted by heavy bodies (such as the sun), precisely as material bodies were attracted. As a consequence it could be calculated that light from a distant fixed star whose apparent position was close to the sun would reach the earth from such a direction that the star would seem to be slightly shifted away from the sun; or, in other words, that stars close to the sun would look as if they had moved a little away from the sun, and from one another. This is a thing which cannot normally be observed since such stars are rendered invisible in daytime by the sun’s overwhelming brightness; but during an eclipse it is possible to take photographs of them. If the same constellation is photographed at night one can measure the distances on the two photographs, and cheek the predicted effect. Now the impressive thing about this case is the risk involved in a prediction of this kind. If observation shows that the predicted effect is definitely absent, then the theory is simply refuted. The theory is incompatible with certain possible results of observation - in fact with results which everybody before Einstein would have expected.2 This is quite different from the situation I have previously described, when it turned out that the theories in question were compatible with the most divergent human behaviour, so that it was practically impossible to describe any human behaviour that might not be claimed to be a verification of these theories. These considerations led me in the winter of 1919-20 to conclusions which I may now reformulate as follows: 1) It is easy to obtain confirmations, or verifications, for nearly every theory - if we look for confirmations. 2) Confirmations should count only if they are the result of risky predictions; that is to say, if, unenlightened by the theory in question, we should have expected an event which was incompatible with the theory-an event which would have refuted the theory. 3) Every ‘good’ scientific theory is a prohibition: it forbids certain things to happen. The more a theory forbids, the better it is. 2 This is a slight oversimplification, for about half of the Einstein effect may be derived from the classical theory, provided we assume a ballistic theory of light. 123 Popper, Conjectures and Refutations 4) A theory which is not refutable by any conceivable event is non-scientific. Irrefutability is not a virtue of a theory (as people often think) but a vice. 5) Every genuine test of a theory is an attempt to falsify it, or to refute it. Testability is falsifiability; but there are degrees of testability: some theories are more testable, more exposed to refutation, than others; they take, as it were, greater risks. 6) Confirming evidence should not count except when it is the result of a genuine test of the theory; and I this means that it can be presented as a serious but unsuccessful attempt to falsify the theory. (I now speak in such cases of ‘corroborating evidence’.) 7) Some genuinely testable theories, when found to be false, are still held by their admirers - for example by introducing ad hoc some auxiliary assumption, or by re-interpreting the theory ad hoc in such a way that it escapes refutation. Such a procedure is always possible, but it rescues the theory from refutation only at the price of destroying, or at least lowering, its scientific status. (I later described such a rescuing operation as a ‘conventionalist twist’ or a ‘conventionalist stratagem’.) One can sum up all this by saying that the criterion of the scientific status of a theory is its falsifiability, or refutability, or testability. I may perhaps exemplify this with the help of the various theories so far mentioned. Einstein’s theory of gravitation clearly satisfied the criterion of falsifiability. Even if our measuring instruments at the time did not allow us to pronounce on the results of the tests with complete assurance, there was clearly a possibility of refuting the theory. Astrology did not pass the test. Astrologers were greatly impressed, and misled, by what they believed to be confirming evidence-so much so that they were quite unimpressed by any unfavourable evidence. Moreover, by making their interpretations and prophecies sufficiently vague they were able to explain away anything that might have been a refutation of the theory had the theory and the prophecies been more precise. In order to escape falsification they destroyed the testability of their theory. It is a typical soothsayer’s trick to predict things so vaguely that the predictions can hardly fail: that they become irrefutable. The Marxist theory of history, in spite of the serious efforts of some of its founders and followers, ultimately adopted this soothsaying practice. In some of its earlier formulations (for example in Marx’s analysis of the character of the ‘coining social revolution’) their predictions were testable, and in fact falsified.3 Yet instead of accepting the refutations the followers of Marx re-interpreted both the theory and the evidence in order to make them agree. In this way they rescued the theory from refutation; but they did so at the price of adopting a device which made it irrefutable. They thus gave ‘conventionalist twist’ to the theory; and by this stratagem they destroyed it much advertised claim to scientific status. The two psycho-analytic theories were in a different class. They were simply non-testable, irrefutable. There was no conceivable human behaviour which could contradict them. This does not mean that Freud and Adler were not seeing certain things correctly. I personally do not doubt that much what they say is of considerable importance, and may well play its part one day in a psychological science which is testable. But it does mean that the clinical 3 See, for example, my Open Society and Its Enemies, ch. 15, section iii, and not 13-14. 124 Popper, Conjectures and Refutations observations’ which analysts naively believe confirm their theory cannot do this any more than the daily confirmations which astrologers find [38] in their practice.4 And as for Freud’s epic of the Ego, the Super-ego, and the Id, ‘no substantially stronger claim, to scientificstatus can be made for it than for Homer’s collected stories from Olympus. These theories describe some facts but in the manner of myths. They contain most interesting psychological suggestions, but not in a testable form. At the same time I realized that such myths may be developed, and become testable; that historically speaking all – or very nearly all – scientific theories originate from myths, and that a myth may contain important anticipations of scientific theories. Examples are Empedocles’ theory of evolution by trial and error, or Parmenides’ myth of the unchanging block universe in which nothing ever happens and which, if we add another dimension, becomes Einstein’s block universe (in which, too, nothing ever happens, since everything is, four-dimensionally speaking, determined and laid down from the beginning). I thus felt that if a theory is found to be non-scientific, or ‘metaphysical’ (as we might say), it is not thereby found to be unimportant, or insignificant, or ‘meaningless’, or ‘nonsensical’.5 But it cannot ‘Clinical observations’, like all other observations, are interpretations in the light of theories (see below, sections iv ff.); and for this reason alone they are apt to seem to support those theories in the light of which they were interpreted. But real support can be obtained only from observations undertaken as tests (by ‘attempted refutations’); and for this purpose criteria of refutation have to be laid down beforehand: it must be agreed which observable situations, if actually observed, mean that the theory is refuted. But what kind of clinical responses would refute to the satisfaction of the analyst not merely a particular analytic diagnosis but psycho-analysis itself? And have such criteria ever been discussed or agreed upon by analysts? Is there not, on the contrary, a whole family of analytic concepts, such as ‘ambivalence’ (I do not suggest that there is no such thing as ambivalence), which would make it difficult, if not impossible, to agree upon such criteria? Moreover, how much headway has been made in investigating the question of the extent to which the (conscious or unconscious) expectations and theories held by the analyst influence the clinical responses of the patient? (To say nothing about the conscious attempts to influence the patient by proposing interpretations to him, etc.) Years ago I introduced the term ‘Oedipus effect’ to describe the influence of a theory or expectation or prediction upon the event which it predicts or describes: it will be remembered that the causal chain leading to Oedipus’ parricide was started by the oracle’s prediction of this event. This is a characteristic and recurrent theme of such myths, but one which seems to have failed to attract the interest of the analysts, perhaps not accidentally. (The problem of confirmatory dreams suggested by the analyst is discussed by Freud, for example in Gesammelte Schriften, in, 1925, where he says on p. 314: ‘If anybody asserts that most of the dreams which can be utilized in an analysis ... owe their origin to [the analyst’s] suggestion, then no objection can be made from the point of view of analytic theory. Yet there is nothing in this fact’, he surprisingly adds, ‘which would detract from the reliability of our results.) 5 The case of astrology, nowadays a typical pseudo-science, may illustrate this point. It was attacked, by Aristotelians and other rationalists, down to Newton’s day, for the wrong reasonfor its now Accepted assertion that the planets had an ‘influence’ upon terrestrial (‘sublunar’) events. In fact Newton’s theory of gravity, and especially the lunar theory of the tides, was historically speaking an offspring of astrological lore. Newt6n, it seems, was most reluctant to adopt a theory which came from the same stable as for example the theory that ‘influenza’ epidemics are due to an astral ‘influence’. And Galileo, no doubt for the same reason, 4 125 Popper, Conjectures and Refutations claim to be backed by empirical evidence in the scientific sense-although it may easily be, in some genetic sense, the ‘result of observation’. (There were a great many other theories of this pre-scientific or pseudo-scientific [38] character, some of them, unfortunately, as influential as the Marx. interpretation of history; for example, the racialist interpretation of history another of those impressive and allexplanatory theories which act upon weak minds like revelations.) Thus the problem which I tried to solve by proposing the criterion of falsifiability was neither a problem of meaningfulness or significance, nor a problem of truth or acceptability. It was the problem of drawing a line (as well as this can be done) between the statements, or systems of statements, of the empirical sciences, and all other statements-whether they are of a religious or of a metaphysical character, or simply pseudo-scientific. Years later – it must have been in 1928 or 1929 – I called this first problem of mine the ‘problem of demarcation’. The criterion of falsifiability is a solution to this problem of demarcation, for it says that statements or systems of statements, in order to be ranked as scientific, must be capable of conflicting with possible, or conceivable, observations. actually rejected the lunar theory of the tides; and his misgivings about Kepler may easily be explained by his misgivings about astrology. 126 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Thomas S. Kuhn THE STRUCTURE OF SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTIONS [Second Edition; University of Chicago Press, 1970] CHAPTER 7: Crisis and the Emergence of Scientific Theories All the discoveries considered in Section VI were causes of or contributors to paradigm change. Furthermore, the changes in which these discoveries were implicated were all destructive as well as constructive. After the discovery had been assimilated, scientists were able to account for a wider range of natural phenomena or to account with greater precision for some of those previously known. But that gain was achieved only by discarding some previously standard beliefs or procedures and, simultaneously, by replacing those components of the previous paradigm with others. Shifts of this sort are. I have argued, associated with all discoveries achieved through normal science, excepting only the unsurprising ones that had been anticipated in all but their details. Discoveries are not, however, the only sources of these destructive-constructive paradigm changes. In this section we shall begin to consider the similar, but usually far larger, shifts that result from the invention of new theories. Having argued already that in the sciences fact and theory, discovery and invention, are not categorically and permanently distinct, we can anticipate overlap between this section and the last. (The impossible suggestion that Priestley first discovered oxygen and Lavoisier then invented it has its attractions. Oxygen has already been encountered as discovery; we shall shortly meet it again as invention.) In taking up the emergence of new theories we shall inevitably extend our understanding of discovery as well. Still, overlap is not identity. The sorts of discoveries considered in the last section were not, at least singly, responsible for such paradigm shifts as the Copernican, Newtonian, chemical, and Einsteinian revolutions. Nor were they responsible for the somewhat smaller, because more exclusively professional, changes in paradigm produced by the wave theory of light, the dynamical theory of heat, or Maxwell’s electromagnetic theory. How can theories like these arise from normal science, an activity even less directed to their pursuit than to that of discoveries? If awareness of anomaly plays a role in the emergence of new sorts of phenomena, it should surprise no one that a similar but more profound awareness is prerequisite to all acceptable changes of theory. On this point historical evidence is, I think, entirely unequivocal. The state of Ptolemaic astronomy was a scandal before Copernicus’ announcement. 1 Galileo’s contributions to the study of motion depended closely upon difficulties discovered in Aristotle’s theory by scholastic critics.2 Newton’s new theory of light and colour originated in the discovery that none of the existing pre-paradigm theories would account for the length of the spectrum, and the wave theory that replaced Newton’s was announced in the midst of growing concern about anomalies in the relation of diffraction and polarization effects to Newton’s theory.3 Thermodynamics was born from the collision of two existing nineteenth1 A. R. Hall, The Scientific Revolution, 1500-1800 (London, 1954), p. 16. Marshall Clagett, The Science of Mechanics in the Middle Ages (Madison, Wis., 1959), Parts II-III. A. Koyré displays a number of medieval elements in Galileo’s thought in his Etudes Galiléennes (Paris, 1939), particularly Vol. I. 3 For Newton, see T. S. Kuhn, ‘Newton’s Optical Papers,’ in Isaac Newton’s Papers and Letters in Natural Philosophy 1958), pp. 27-45. For the prelude to the wave theory, see E.T. Whittaker, A 2 127 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions century physical theories, and quantum mechanics from a variety of difficulties surrounding black-body radiation, specific heats, and the photoelectric effect.4 Furthermore, in all these cases except that of Newton the awareness of anomaly had lasted so long and penetrated so deep that one can appropriately describe the fields affected by it as in a state of growing crisis. Because it demands large-scale paradigm destruction and major shifts in the problems and techniques of normal science, the emergence of new theories is generally preceded by a period of pronounced professional insecurity. As one might expect, that insecurity is generated by the persistent failure of the puzzles of normal science to come out as they should. Failure of existing rules is the prelude to a search for new ones. Look first at a particularly famous case of paradigm change, the emergence of Copernican astronomy. When its predecessor, the Ptolemaic system, was first developed during the last two centuries before Christ and the first two after, it was admirably successful in predicting the changing positions of both stars and planets. No other ancient system had performed so well; for the stars, Ptolemaic astronomy is still widely used today as an engineering approximation; for the planets, Ptolemy’s predictions were as good as Copernicus’. But to be admirably successful is never, for a scientific theory, to be completely successful. With respect both to planetary position and to precession of the equinoxes, predictions made with Ptolemy’s system never quite conformed with the best available observations. Further reduction of those minor discrepancies constituted many of the principal problems of normal astronomical research for many of Ptolemy’s successors, just as a similar attempt to bring celestial observation and Newtonian theory together provided normal research problems for Newton’s eighteenth-century successors. For some time astronomers had every reason to suppose that these attempts would be as successful as those that had led to Ptolemy’s system. Given a particular discrepancy, astronomers were invariably able to eliminate it by making some particular adjustment in Ptolemy’s system of compounded circles. But as time went on, a man looking at the net result of the normal research effort of many astronomers could observe that astronomy’s complexity was increasing far more rapidly than its accuracy and that a discrepancy corrected in one place was likely to show up in another.5 Because the astronomical tradition was repeatedly interrupted from outside and because, in the absence of printing, communication between astronomers was restricted, these difficulties were only slowly recognized. But awareness did come. By the thirteenth century Alfonso X could proclaim that if God had consulted him when creating the universe, he would have received good advice. In the sixteenth century, Copernicus’ co-worker, Domenico da Novara, held that no system so cumbersome and inaccurate as the Ptolemaic had become could possibly be true of nature. And Copernicus himself wrote in the Preface to the De Revolutionibus that the astronomical tradition he inherited had finally created only a monster. By the early sixteenth century an increasing number of Europe’s best astronomers were realizing that the astronomical paradigm was failing in application to its own traditional problems. That recognition was prerequisite to Copernicus’ rejection of the Ptolemaic History of the Theories of Aether and Electricity, I (2nd ed; London, 1951), 94-109; and W. Whewell, History of the Inductive Sciences (rev. ed,; London, 1847), II, 396-466. 4 For thermodynamics, see Silvanus P. Thompson, Life of William Thomson Baron Kelvin of Largs (London, 1910), I, 266-81. For the quantum theory, see Fritz Reiche, The Quantum Theory, trans. H. S. Hatfield and II. L. Brose (London, 1922), chaps. i-ii. 5 L. E. Dreyer, A History of Astronomy from Thales to Kepler (2d ed.; New York, 1953), chaps. xi-xii. 128 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions paradigm and his search for a new one. His famous preface still provides one of the classic descriptions of a crisis state.6 Breakdown of the normal technical puzzle-solving activity is not, of course, the only ingredient of the astronomical crisis that faced Copernicus. An extended treatment would also discuss the social pressure for calendar reform, a pressure that made the puzzle of precession particularly urgent. In addition, a fuller account would consider medieval criticism of Aristotle, the rise of Renaissance Neoplatonism, and other significant historical elements besides. But technical breakdown would still remain the core of the crisis. In a mature science – and astronomy had become that in antiquity – external factors like those cited above are principally significant in determining the timing of breakdown, the ease with which it can be recognized, and the area in which, because it is given particular attention, the breakdown first occurs. Though immensely important, issues of that sort are out of bounds for this essay. If that much is clear in the case of the Copernican revolution, let us turn from it to a second and rather different example, the crisis that preceded the emergence of Lavoisier’s oxygen theory of combustion. In the 1770’s many factors combined to generate a crisis in chemistry, and historians are not altogether agreed about either their nature or their relative importance. But two of them are generally accepted as of first-rate significance the rise of pneumatic chemistry and the question of weight relations. The history of the first begins in the seventeenth century with development of the air pump and its deployment in chemical experimentation. During the following century, using that pump and a number of other pneumatic devices, chemists came increasingly to realize that air must be an active ingredient in chemical reactions. But with a few exceptions – so equivocal that they may not be exceptions at all – chemists continued to believe that air was the only sort of gas. Until 1756, when Joseph Black showed that fixed air (CO2) was consistently distinguishable from normal air, two samples of gas were thought to be distinct only in their impurities.7 After Black’s work the investigation of gases proceeded rapidly, most notably in the hands of Cavendish, Priestley, and Scheele, who together developed a number of new techniques capable of distinguishing one sample of gas from another. All these men, from Black through Scheele, believed in the phlogiston theory and often employed it in their design and interpretation of experiments. Scheele actually first produced oxygen by an elaborate chain of experiments designed to dephlogisticate heat. Yet the net result of their experiments was a variety of gas samples and gas properties so elaborate that the phlogiston theory proved increasingly little able to cope with laboratory experience. Though none of these chemists suggested that the theory should be replaced, they were unable to apply it consistently. By the time Lavoisier began his experiments on airs in the early 1770’s, there were almost as many versions of the phlogiston theory as there were pneumatic chemists.8 That proliferation of versions of a theory is a very usual symptom of crisis. In his preface, Copernicus complained of it as well. The increasing vagueness and decreasing utility of the phlogiston theory for pneumatic chemistry were not, however, the source of the crisis that confronted Lavoisier. He was also much concerned to explain the gain in weight that most bodies experience when burned or 6 T. S. Kuhn, The Copernican Revolution (Cambridge, Mass., 1957), pp. 135-43. J. R. Partington, A Short History of Chemistry (2d ed.; London, 1951), pp. 48-51, 73-85, 90-120. 8 Though their main concern is with a slightly later period, much relevant material is scattered throughout J. R. Partington and Douglas McKie’s ‘Historical Studies on the Phlogiston Theory,’ Annals of Science, II (1937), 361404; III (1938), 1-58, 337-71; and IV (1939), 337-71. 7 129 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions roasted, and that again is a problem with a long prehistory. At least a few Islamic chemists had known that some metals gain weight when roasted. In the seventeenth century several investigators had concluded from this same fact that a roasted metal takes up some ingredient from the atmosphere. But in the seventeenth century that conclusion seemed unnecessary to most chemists. If chemical reactions could alter the volume, colour, and texture of the ingredients, why should they not alter weight as well? Weight was not always taken to be the measure of quantity of matter. Besides, weight-gain on roasting remained an isolated phenomenon. Most natural bodies (e.g., wood) lose weight on roasting as the phlogiston theory was later to say they should. During the eighteenth century, however, these initially adequate responses to the problem of weight-gain became increasingly difficult to maintain. Partly because the balance was increasingly used as a standard chemical tool and partly because the development of pneumatic chemistry made it possible and desirable to retain the gaseous products of reactions, chemists discovered more and more cases in which weight-gain accompanied roasting. Simultaneously, the gradual assimilation of Newton’s gravitational theory led chemists to insist that gain in weight must mean gain in quantity of matter. Those conclusions did not result in rejection of the phlogiston theory, for that theory could be adjusted in many ways. Perhaps phlogiston had negative weight, or perhaps fire particles or something else entered the roasted body as phlogiston left it. There were other explanations besides. But if the problem of weight-gain did not lead to rejection, it did lead to an increasing number of special studies in which this problem bulked large. One of them, “On phlogiston considered as a substance with weight and [analyzed] in terms of the weight changes it produces in bodies with which it unites,” was read to the French Academy early in 1772, the year which closed with Lavoisier’s delivery of his famous sealed note to the Academy’s Secretary. Before that note was written a problem that had been at the edge of the chemist’s consciousness for many years had become an outstanding unsolved puzzle.9 Many different versions of the phlogiston theory were being elaborated to meet it. Like the problems of pneumatic chemistry, those of weight-gain were making it harder and harder to know what the phlogiston theory was. Though still believed and trusted as a working tool, a paradigm of eighteenth-century chemistry was gradually losing its unique status. Increasingly, the research it guided resembled that conducted under the competing schools of the pre-paradigm period, another typical effect of crisis. Consider now, as a third and final example, the late nineteenth century crisis in physics that prepared the way for the emergence of relativity theory. One root of that crisis can be traced to the late seventeenth century when a number of natural philosophers, most notably Leibniz, criticized Newton’s retention of an updated version of the classic conception of absolute space.10 They were very nearly, though never quite, able to show that absolute positions and absolute motions were without any function at all in Newton’s system; and they did succeed in hinting at the considerable aesthetic appeal a fully relativistic conception of space and motion would later come to display. But their critique was purely logical. Like the early Copernicans who criticized Aristotle’s proofs of the earth’s stability, they did not dream that transition to a relativistic system could have observational consequences. At no point did they H. Guerlac, Lavoisier – the Crucial Year (Ithaca, N.Y., 1961). The entire book documents the evolution and first recognition of a crisis. For a clear statement of the situation with respect to Lavoisier, see p. 35. 10 Max Tammer, Concepts of Space: The History of Theories of Space in Physics (Cambridge, Mass., 1954), pp. 114-24. 9 130 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions relate their views to any problems that arose when applying Newtonian theory to nature. As a result, their views died with them during the early decades of the eighteenth century to be resurrected only in the last decades of the nineteenth when they lead a very different relation to the practice of physics. The technical problems to which a relativistic philosophy of space was ultimately to be related began to enter normal science with the acceptance of the wave theory of light after about 1815, though they evoked no crisis until the 1890’s. If light is wave motion propagated in a mechanical ether governed by Newton’s Laws, then both celestial observation and terrestrial experiment become potentially capable of detecting drift through the ether. Of the celestial observations, only those of aberration promised sufficient accuracy to provide relevant information, and the detection of ether-drift by aberration measurements therefore became a recognized problem for normal research. Much special equipment was built to resolve it. That equipment, however, detected no observable drift, and the problem was therefore transferred from the experimentalists and observers to the theoreticians. During the central decades of the century Fresnel, Stokes, and others devised numerous articulations of the ether theory designed to explain the failure to observe drift. Each of these articulations assumed that a moving body drags some fraction of the ether with it. And each was sufficiently successful to explain the negative results not only of celestial observation but also of terrestrial experimentation, including the famous experiment of Michelson and Morley.11 There was still no conflict excepting that between the various articulations. In the absence of relevant experimental techniques, that conflict never became acute. The situation changed again only with the gradual acceptance of Maxwell’s electromagnetic theory in the last two decades of the nineteenth century. Maxwell himself was a Newtonian who believed that light and electromagnetism in general were due to variable displacements of the particles of a mechanical ether. His earliest versions of a theory for electricity and magnetism made direct use of hypothetical properties with which he endowed this medium. These were dropped from his final version, but he still believed his electromagnetic theory compatible with some articulation of the Newtonian mechanical view.12 Developing a suitable articulation was a challenge for him and his successors. In practice, however, as has happened again and again in scientific development, the required articulation proved immensely difficult to produce, just as Copernicus’ astronomical proposal, despite the optimism of its author, created an increasing crisis for existing theories of motion, so Maxwell’s theory, despite its Newtonian origin, ultimately produced a crisis for the paradigm from which it had sprung.13 Furthermore, the locus at which that crisis became most acute was provided by the problems we have just been considering, those of motion with respect to the ether. Maxwell’s discussion of the electromagnetic behaviour of bodies in motion had made no reference to ether drag, and it proved very difficult to introduce such drag into his theory. As a result, a whole series of earlier observations designed to detect drift through the ether became anomalous. The years after 1890 therefore witnessed a long series of attempts, both experimental and theoretical, to detect motion with respect to the ether and to work ether drag Joseph Larmor, Aether and Matter ... Including a Discussion of the Influence of the Earth’s Motion on Optical Phenomena (Cambridge, 1900), pp. 6-20, 320-22. 12 R. T. Clazebrook, James Clerk Maxwell and Modem Physics (London, 1896), chap. ix. For Maxwell’s final attitude, see his own book, A Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism (3d ed.; Oxford, 1892), p. 470. 13 For astronomy’s role in the development of mechanics, see Kuhn, op. cit., chap. vii. 11 131 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions into Maxwell’s theory. The former were uniformly unsuccessful, though some analysts thought their results equivocal. The latter produced a number of. promising starts, particularly those of Lorentz and Fitzgerald, but they also disclosed still other puzzles and finally resulted in just that proliferation of competing theories that we have previously found to be the concomitant of crisis.14 It is against that historical setting that Einstein’s special theory of relativity emerged in 1905. These three examples are almost entirely typical. In each case a novel theory emerged only after a pronounced failure in the normal problem-solving activity. Furthermore, except for the case of Copernicus in which factors external to science, played a particularly large role, that breakdown and the proliferation of theories that is its sign occurred no more than a decade or two before the new theory’s enunciation. The novel theory seems a direct response to crisis. Note also, though this may not be quite so typical, that the problems with respect to which breakdown occurred were all of a type that had long been recognized. Previous practice of normal science had given every reason to consider them solved or all but solved, which helps to explain why the sense of failure, when it came, could be so acute. Failure with a new sort of problem is often disappointing but never surprising. Neither problems nor puzzles yield often to the first attack. Finally, these examples share another characteristic that may help to make the case for the role of crisis impressive: the solution to each of them had been at least partially anticipated during a period when there was no crisis in the corresponding science; and in the absence of crisis those anticipations had been ignored. The only complete anticipation is also the most famous, that of Copernicus by Aristarchus in the third century B.C. It is often said that if Creek science had been less deductive and less ridden by dogma, heliocentric astronomy might have begun its development eighteen centuries earlier than it did.15 But that, is to ignore all historical context. When Aristarchus’ suggestion was made, the vastly more reasonable geocentric system had no needs that a heliocentric system might even conceivably have fulfilled. The whole development of Ptolemaic astronomy, both its triumphs and its breakdown, falls in the centuries after Aristarchus’ proposal. Besides, there were no obvious reasons for taking Aristarchus seriously. Even Copernicus’ more elaborate proposal was neither simpler nor more accurate than Ptolemy’s system. Available observational tests, as we shall see more clearly below, provided no basis for a choice between them. Under those circumstances, one of the factors that led astronomers to Copernicus (and one that could not have led them to Aristarchus) was the recognized crisis that had been responsible for innovation in the first place. Ptolemaic astronomy had failed to solve its problems; the time had come to give a competitor a chance. Our other two examples provide no similarly full anticipations. But surely one reason why the theories of combustion by absorption from the atmosphere – theories developed in the seventeenth century by Rey, Hooke, and Mayow – failed to get a sufficient hearing was that they made no contact with a recognized trouble spot in normal scientific practice.16 And the long neglect by eighteenth- and nineteenth-century scientists of Newton’s relativistic critics must largely have been due to a similar failure in confrontation. 14 Whittaker, op. cit., I, 386-410; and II (London, 1953), 27-40. For Aristarchus’ work, see T. L. Heath, Aristarchus of Samos: The Ancient Copernicus (Oxford, 1913), Part II. For an extreme statement of the traditional position about the neglect of Aristarchus’ achievement, see Arthur Koestler, The Sleepwalkers: A History of Man’s Changing Vision of the Universe (London, 1959), p 50. 16 Partington, op. cit., pp. 78-85. 15 132 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Philosophers of science have repeatedly demonstrated that more than one theoretical construction can always be placed upon a given collection of data. History of science indicates that, particularly in the early developmental stages of a new paradigm, it is not even very difficult to invent such alternates. But that invention of alternates is just what scientists seldom undertake except during the pre-paradigm stage of their science’s development and at very special occasions during its subsequent evolution. So long as the tools a paradigm supplies continue to prove capable of solving the problems it defines, science moves fastest and penetrates most deeply through confident employment of those tools. The reason is clear. As in manufacture so in science - retooling is an extravagance to be reserved for the occasion that demands it. The significance of crises is the indication they provide that an occasion for retooling has arrived. 133 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions CHAPTER 13: Progress through Revolutions The preceding pages have carried my schematic description of scientific development as far as it can go in this essay. Nevertheless, they cannot quite provide a conclusion. If this description has at all caught the essential structure of a science’s continuing evolution, it will simultaneously have posed a special problem: Why should the enterprise sketched above move steadily ahead in ways that, say, art, political theory, or philosophy does not? Why is progress a perquisite reserved almost exclusively for the activities we call science? The most usual answers to that question have been denied in the body of this essay. We must conclude it by asking whether substitutes can be found. Notice immediately that part of the question is entirely semantic. To a very great extent the term ‘science’ is reserved for fields that do progress in obvious ways. Nowhere does this show more clearly than in the recurrent debates about whether one or another of the contemporary social sciences is really a science. These debates have parallels in the preparadigm periods of fields that are today unhesitatingly labelled science. Their ostensible issue throughout is a definition of that vexing term. Men argue that psychology, for example, is a science because it possesses such and such characteristics. Others counter that those characteristics are either unnecessary or not sufficient to make a field a science. Often great energy is invested, great passion aroused, and the outsider is at a loss to know why. Can very much depend upon a definition of ‘science’? Can a definition tell a man whether he is a scientist or not? If so, why do not natural scientists or artists worry about the definition of the term? Inevitably one suspects that the issue is more fundamental. Probably questions like the following are really being asked: Why does my field fail to move ahead in the way that, say, physics does? What changes in technique or method or ideology would enable it to do so? These are not, however, questions that could respond to an agreement on definition. Furthermore, if precedent from the natural sciences serves, they will cease to be a source of concern not when a definition is found, but when the groups that now doubt their own status achieve consensus about their past and present accomplishments. It may, for example, be significant that economists argue less about whether their field is a science than do practitioners of some other fields of social science. Is that because economists know what science is? Or is it rather economics about which they agree? That point has a converse that, though no longer simply semantic, may help to display the inextricable connections between our notions of science and of progress. For many centuries, both in antiquity and again in early modem Europe, painting was regarded as the cumulative discipline. During those years the artist’s goal was assumed to be representation. Critics and historians, like Pliny and Vasari, then recorded with veneration the series of inventions from foreshortening through chiaroscuro that had made possible successively more perfect representations of nature.1 But those are also the years, particularly during the Renaissance, when little cleavage was felt between the sciences and the arts. Leonardo was only one of many men who passed freely back and forth between fields that only later became categorically distinct.2 Furthermore, even after that steady exchange had ceased, the term ‘are continued to apply as much to technology and the crafts, which were also seen as progressive) as to painting and sculpture. Only when the latter unequivocally renounced 1 E. H. Gombrich, Art and Illusion: A Study in the Psychology of Pictorial Representation (New York, 1960), pp. 11-12. 2 Ibid., p. 97; and Giorgio de Santillana, ‘The Role of Art in the Scientific Renaissance,’ in Critical Problems in the History of Science, ed. M. Clagett (Madison, Wis., 1959), pp. 33-65. 134 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions representation as their goal and began to learn again from primitive models did the cleavage we now take for granted assume anything like its present depth. And even today, to switch fields once more, part of our difficulty in seeing the profound differences between science and technology must relate to the fact that progress is an obvious attribute of both fields. It can, however, only clarify, not solve, our present difficulty to recognize that we tend to see as science any field in which progress is marked. There remains the problem of understanding why progress should be so noteworthy a characteristic of an enterprise conducted with the techniques and goals this essay has described. That question proves to be several in one, and we shall have to consider each of them separately. In all cases but the last, however, their resolution will depend in part upon an inversion of our normal view of the relation between scientific activity and the community that practices it. We must learn to recognize as causes what have ordinarily been taken to be effects. If we can do that, the phrases ‘scientific progress’ and even ‘scientific objectivity’ may come to seem in part redundant. In fact, one aspect of the redundancy has just been illustrated. Does a field make progress because it is a science, or is it a science because it makes progress? Ask now why an enterprise like normal science should progress, and begin by recalling a few of its most salient characteristics. Normally, the members of a mature scientific community work from a single paradigm or from a closely related set. Very rarely do different scientific communities investigate the same problems. In those exceptional cases the groups hold several major paradigms in common. Viewed from within any single community, however, whether of scientists or of non-scientists, the result of successful creative work is progress. How could it possibly be anything else? We have, for example, just noted that while artists aimed at representation as their goal, both critics and historians chronicled the progress of the apparently united group. Other creative fields display progress of the same sort. The theologian who articulates dogma or the philosopher who refines the Kantian imperatives contributes to progress, if only to that of the group that shares his premises. No creative school recognizes a category of work that is, on the one hand, a creative success, but is not, on the other, an addition to the collective achievement of the group. If we doubt, as many do, that non-scientific fields make progress, that cannot be because individual schools make none. Rather, it must be because there are always competing schools, each of which constantly questions the very foundations of the others. The man who argues that philosophy, for example, has made no progress emphasizes that there are still Aristotelians, not that Aristotelianism has failed to progress. These doubts about progress arise, however, in the sciences too. Throughout the preparadigm period when there is a multiplicity of competing schools, evidence of progress, except within schools, is very hard to find. This is the period described in Section 11 as one during which individuals practice science, but in which the results of their enterprise do not add up to science as we know it. And again, during periods of revolution when the fundamental tenets of a field are once more at issue, doubts are repeatedly expressed about the very possibility of continued progress if one or another of the opposed paradigms is adopted. Those who rejected Newtonianism proclaimed that its reliance upon innate forces would return science to the Dark Ages. Those who opposed Lavoisier’s chemistry held that the rejection of chemical “principles” in favour of laboratory elements was the rejection of achieved chemical explanation by those who would take refuge in a mere name. A similar, though more moderately expressed, feeling seems to underlie the opposition of Einstein, Bohm, and others, to the dominant probabilistic interpretation of quantum mechanics. In short, it is only during periods of normal science that progress seems both obvious and 135 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions assured. During those periods, however, the scientific community could view the fruits of its work in no other way. With respect to normal science then, part of the answer to the problem of progress lies simply in the eye of the beholder. Scientific progress is not different in kind from progress in other fields, but the absence at most times of competing schools that question each other’s aims and standards makes the progress of a normal-scientific community far easier to see. That, however, is only part of the answer and by no means the most important part. We have, for example, already noted that once the reception of a common paradigm has freed the scientific community from the need constantly to re-examine its first principles, the members of that community can concentrate exclusively upon the subtlest and most esoteric of the phenomena that concern It. Inevitably, that does increase both the effectiveness and the efficiency with which the group as a whole solves new problems. Other aspects of professional life in the sciences enhance this very special efficiency still further. Some of these are consequences of the unparalleled insulation of mature scientific communities from the demands of the laity and of everyday life. That insulation has never been complete – we are now discussing matters of degree. Nevertheless, there are no other professional communities in which individual creative work is so exclusively addressed to and evaluated by other members of the profession. The most esoteric of poets or the most abstract of theologians is far more concerned than the scientist with lay approbation of his creative work, though he may be even less concerned with approbation in general. That difference proves consequential. Just because he is working only for an audience of colleagues, an audience that shares his own values and beliefs, the scientist can take a single set of standards for granted. He need not worry about what some other group or school will think and can therefore dispose of one problem and get on to the next more quickly than those who work for a more heterodox group. Even more important, the insulation of the scientific community from society permits the individual scientist to concentrate his attention upon problems that he has good reason to believe he will be able to solve. Unlike the engineer, and many doctors, and most theologians, the scientist need not choose problems because they urgently need solution and without regard for the tools available to solve them. In this respect, also, the contrast between natural scientists and many social scientists proves instructive. The latter often tend, as the former almost never do, to def end their choice of a research problem – e.g., the effects of racial discrimination or the causes of the business cycle – chiefly in terms of the social importance of achieving a solution. Which group would one then expect to solve problems at a more rapid rate? The effects of insulation from the larger society are greatly intensified by another characteristic of the professional scientific community, the nature of its educational initiation. In music, the graphic arts, and literature, the practitioner gains his education by exposure to the works of other artists, principally earlier artists. Textbooks, except compendia of or handbooks to original creations, have only a secondary role. In history, philosophy, and the social sciences, textbook literature has a greater significance. But even in these fields the elementary college course employs parallel readings in original sources, some of them the “classics” of the field, others the contemporary research reports that practitioners write for each other. As a result, the student in any one of these disciplines is constantly made aware of the immense variety of problems that the members of his future group have, in the course of time, attempted to solve. Even more important, he has constantly before him a number of competing and incommensurable solutions to these problems solutions that he must ultimately evaluate for himself. 136 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Contrast this situation with that in at least the contemporary natural sciences. In these fields the student relies mainly on in his third or fourth year of graduate works he textbooks until, begins his own research. Many science curricula do not ask even graduate students to read in works not written specially for students. The few that do assign supplementary reading in research papers and monographs restrict such assignments to the most advanced courses and to materials that take up more or less where the available texts leave off. Until the very last stages in the education of a scientist, textbooks are systematically substituted for the creative scientific literature that made them possible. Given the confidence in their paradigms) which makes this educational technique possible, few scientists would wish to change it. Why, after all, should the student of physics, for example, read the works of Newton, Faraday, Einstein, or Schrödinger, when everything he needs to know about these works is recapitulated in a far briefer, more precise, and more systematic form in a number of up-to-date textbooks? Without wishing to defend the excessive lengths to which this type of education has occasionally been carried, one cannot help but notice that in general it has been immensely effective. Of course, it is a narrow and rigid education, probably more so than any other except perhaps in orthodox theology. But for normal-scientific work, for puzzle-solving within the tradition that the textbooks define, the scientist is almost perfectly equipped. Furthermore, he is well equipped for another task as well-the generation through normal science of significant crises. When they arise, the scientist is not, of course, equally well prepared. Even though prolonged crises are probably reflected in less rigid educational practice, scientific training is not well designed to produce the man who will easily discover a fresh approach. But so long as somebody appears with a new candidate for paradigm-usually a young man or one new to the field-the loss due to rigidity accrues only to the individual. Given a generation in which to effect the change, individual rigidity is compatible with a community that can switch from paradigm to paradigm when the occasion demands. Particularly, it is compatible when that very rigidity provides the community with a sensitive indicator that something has gone wrong. In its normal state, then, a scientific community is an immensely efficient instrument for solving the problems or puzzles that its paradigms define. Furthermore, the result of solving those problems must inevitably be progress. There is no problem here. Seeing that much, however, only highlights the second main part of the problem of progress in the sciences. Let us therefore turn to it and ask about progress through extraordinary science. Why should progress also be the apparently universal concomitant of scientific revolutions? Once again, there is much to be learned by asking what else the result of a revolution could be. Revolutions close with a total victory for one of the two opposing camps. Will that group ever say that the result of its victory has been something less than progress? That would be rather like admitting that they had been wrong and their opponents right. To them, at least, the outcome of revolution must be progress, and they are in an excellent position to make certain that future members of their community will see past history in the same way. Section XI described in detail the techniques by which this is accomplished, and we have just recurred to a closely related aspect of professional scientific life. When it repudiates a past paradigm, a scientific community simultaneously renounces, as a fit subject for professional scrutiny, most of the books and articles in which that paradigm had been embodied. Scientific education makes use of no equivalent for the art museum or the library of classics, and the result is a sometimes drastic distortion in the scientist’s perception of his discipline’s past. More than the practitioners of other creative fields, he comes to see it as leading in a straight 137 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions line to the discipline’s present vantage. In short, he comes to see it as progress. No alternative is available to him while he remains in the field. Inevitably those remarks will suggest that the member of a mature scientific community is, like the typical character of Orwell’s 1984, the victim of a history rewritten by the powers that be. Furthermore, that suggestion is not altogether inappropriate. There are losses as well as gains in scientific revolutions, and scientists tend to be peculiarly blind to the former.3 On the other hand, no explanation of progress through revolutions may stop at this point. To do so would be to imply that in the sciences might makes right, a formulation which would again not be entirely wrong if it did not suppress the nature of the process and of the authority by which the choice between paradigms is made. If authority alone, and particularly if nonprofessional authority, were the arbiter of paradigm debates, the outcome of those debates might still be revolution, but it would not be scientific revolution. The very existence of science depends upon vesting the power to choose between paradigms in the members of a special kind of community. Just how special that community must he if science is to survive and grow may be indicated by the very tenuousness of humanity’s hold on the scientific enterprise. Every civilization of which we have records has possessed a technology, an art, a religion, a political system, laws, and so on. In many cases those facets of civilization have been as developed as our own. But only the civilizations that descend from Hellenic Greece have possessed more than the most rudimentary science. The bulk of scientific knowledge is a product of Europe in the last four centuries. No other place and time has supported the very special communities from which scientific productivity comes. What are the essential characteristics of these communities? Obviously, they need vastly more study. In this area only the most tentative generalizations are possible. Nevertheless, a number of requisites for membership in a professional scientific group must already be strikingly clear. The scientist must, for example, be concerned to solve problems about the behaviour of nature. In addition, though his concern with nature may be global in its extent, the problems on which he works must be problems of detail. More important, the solutions that satisfy him may not be merely personal but must instead be accepted as solutions by many. The group that shares them may not, however, be drawn at random from society as a whole, but is rather the well-defined community of the scientist’s professional compeers. One of the strongest, if still unwritten, rules of scientific life is the prohibition of appeals to heads of state or to the populace at large in matters scientific. Recognition of the existence of a uniquely competent professional group and acceptance of its role as the exclusive arbiter of professional achievement has further implications. The group’s members, as individuals and by virtue of their shared training and experience, must be seen as the sole possessors of the rules of the game or of some equivalent basis for unequivocal judgments. To doubt that they shared some such basis for evaluations would be to admit the existence of incompatible standards of scientific achievement. That admission would inevitably raise the question whether truth in the sciences can be one. This small list of characteristics common to scientific communities has been drawn entirely from the practice of normal science, and it should have been. That is the activity for which the scientist is ordinarily trained. Note, however, that despite its small size the list is already 3 Historians of science often encounter this blindness in a particularly striking form. The group of students who come to them from the sciences is very often the most rewarding group they teach. But it is also usually the most frustrating at the start. Because science students “know the right answers,” it is particularly difficult to make them analyse an older science in its own terms. 138 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions sufficient to set such communities apart from all other professional groups. And note, in addition, that despite its source in normal science the list accounts for many special features of the group’s response during revolutions and particularly during paradigm debates. We have already observed that a group of this sort must see a paradigm change as progress. Now we may recognize that the perception is, in important respects, self-fulfilling. The scientific community is a supremely efficient instrument for maximizing the number and precision of the problem solved through paradigm change. Because the unit of scientific achievement is the solved problem and because the group knows well which problems have already been solved, few scientists will easily be persuaded to adopt a viewpoint that again opens to question many problems that had previously been solved. Nature itself must first under mine professional security by making prior achievements seem problematic. Furthermore, even when that has occurred and a new candidate for paradigm has been evoked, scientists will be reluctant to embrace it unless convinced that two all-important conditions are being met. First, the new candidate must seem to resolve some outstanding and generally recognized problem that can be met in no other way. Second, the new paradigm must promise to preserve a relatively large part of the concrete problem-solving ability that has accrued to science through its predecessors. Novelty for its own sake is not a desideratum in the sciences as it is in so many other creative fields. As a result, though new paradigms seldom or never possess all the capabilities of their predecessors, they usually preserve a great deal of the most concrete parts of past achievement and they always permit additional concrete problem-solutions besides. To say this much is not to suggest that the ability to solve problems is either the unique or an unequivocal basis for paradigm choice. We have already noted many reasons why there can be no criterion of that sort. But it does suggest that a community of scientific specialists will do all that it can to ensure the continuing growth of the assembled data that it can treat with precision and detail. In the process the community will sustain losses. Often some old problems must be banished. Frequently, in addition, revolution narrows the scope of the community’s professional concerns, increases the extent of its specialization, and attenuates its communication with other groups, both scientific and lay. Though science surely grows in depth, it may not grow in breadth as well. If it does so, that breadth is manifest mainly in the proliferation of scientific specialties, not in the scope of any single specialty alone. Yet despite these and other losses to the individual communities, the nature of such communities provides a virtual guarantee that both the list of problems solved by science and the precision of individual problem-solutions will grow and grow. At least, the nature of the community provides such a guarantee if there is any way at all in which it can be provided. What better criterion than the decision of the scientific group could there be? These last paragraphs point the directions in which I believe a more refined solution of the problem of progress in the sciences must be sought. Perhaps they indicate that scientific progress is not quite what we had taken it to be. But they simultaneously show that a sort of progress will inevitably characterize the scientific enterprise so long as such an enterprise survives. In the sciences there need not be progress of another sort. We may, to be more precise, have to relinquish the notion, explicit or implicit, that changes of paradigm carry scientists and those learn from them closer and closer to the truth. It is now time to notice that until the last very few pages the term ‘truth’ had entered this essay only in a quotation from Francis Bacon. And even in those pages it entered only as a source for the scientist’s conviction that incompatible rules for doing science cannot coexist except during revolutions when the profession’s main task is to eliminate all sets but one. The 139 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions developmental process described in this essay has been a process of evolution from primitive beginnings-a process whose successive stages are characterized by an increasingly detailed and refined understanding of nature. But nothing that has been or will be said makes it a process of evolution toward anything. Inevitably that lacuna will have disturbed many readers. We are all deeply accustomed to seeing science as the one enterprise that draws constantly nearer to some goal set by nature in advance. But need there be any such goal? Can we not account for both science’s existence and its success in terms of evolution from the community’s state of knowledge at any given time? Does it really help to imagine that there is some one full, objective, true account of nature and that the proper measure of scientific achievement is the extent to which it brings us closer to that ultimate goal? If we can learn to substitute evolution-from-what-we-do-know for evolution-toward-what-we-wish-to-now, a number of vexing problems may vanish in the process. Somewhere in this maze, for example, must lie the problem of induction. I cannot yet specify in any detail the consequences of this alternate view of scientific advance. But it helps to recognize that the conceptual transposition here recommended is very close to one that the West undertook just a century ago. It is particularly helpful because in both cases the main obstacle to transposition is the same. When Darwin first published his theory of evolution by natural selection in 1859, what most bothered many professionals was neither the notion of species change nor the possible descent of man from apes. The evidence pointing to evolution, including the evolution of man, had been accumulating for decades, and the idea of evolution had been suggested and widely disseminated before. Though evolution, as such, did encounter resistance, particularly from some religious groups, it was by no means the greatest of the difficulties the Darwinians faced. That difficulty stemmed from an idea that was more nearly Darwin’s own. All the well-known pre-Darwinian evolutionary theories – those of Lamarck, Chambers, Spencer, and the German Naturphilosophen – had taken evolution to be a goal-directed process. The ‘Idea’ of man and of the contemporary flora and fauna was thought to have been present from the first creation of life, perhaps in the mind of God. That idea or plan had provided the direction and the guiding force to the entire evolutionary process. Each new stage of evolutionary development was a more perfect realization of a plan that had been present from the start.4 For many men the abolition of that teleological kind of evolution was the most significant and least palatable of Darwin’s suggestions.5 The Origin of Species recognized no goal set either by God or nature. Instead, natural selection, operating in the given environment and with the actual organisms presently at hand, was responsible for the gradual but steady emergence of more elaborate, further articulated, and vastly more specialized organisms. Even such marvellously adapted organs as the eye and hand of man-organs whose design had previously provided powerful arguments for the existence of a supreme artificer and an advance plan-were products of a process that moved steadily from primitive beginnings but toward no goal. The belief that natural selection, resulting from mere competition between organisms for survival, could have produced man together with the higher animals and plants was the most difficult and disturbing aspect of Darwin’s theory. What could ‘evolution,’ Loren Eiseley, Darwin’s Century: Evolution and the Men Who Discovered It (New York, 1958), chaps. ii, iv-v. 5 For a particularly acute account of one prominent Darwinian’s struggle with this problem, see A. Hunter Dupree, Asa Gray, 1810-1888 (Cambridge, Mass., 1959), pp. 295-306, 355-83. 4 140 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions ‘development,’ and ‘progress’ mean in the absence of a specified goal? To many people, such terms suddenly seemed self-contradictory. The analogy that relates the evolution of organisms to the evolution of scientific ideas can easily be pushed too far. But with respect to the issues of this closing section it is very nearly perfect. The process described in Section XII as the resolution of revolutions is the selection by conflict within the scientific community of the fittest way to practice future science. The net result of a sequence of such revolutionary selections, separated by periods of normal research, is the wonderfully adapted set of instruments we call modern scientific knowledge. Successive stages in that developmental process are marked by an increase in articulation and specialization. And the entire process may have occurred, as we now suppose biological evolution did, without benefit of a set goal, a permanent fixed scientific truth, of which each stage in the development of scientific knowledge is a better exemplar. Anyone who has followed the argument this far will nevertheless feel the need to ask why the evolutionary process should work. What must nature, including man, be like in order that science be possible at all? Why should scientific communities be able to reach a firm consensus unattainable in other fields? Why should consensus endure across one paradigm change after another? And why should paradigm change invariably produce an instrument more perfect in any sense than those known before? From one point of view those questions, excepting the first, have already been answered. But from another they are as open as they were when this essay began. It is not only the scientific community that must be special. The world of which that community is a part must also possess quite special characteristics, and we are no closer than we were at the start to knowing what these must be. That problem – What must the world be like in order that man may know it? – was not, however, created by this essay. On the contrary, it is as old as science itself, and it remains unanswered. But it need not be answered in this place. Any conception of nature compatible with the growth of science by proof is compatible with the evolutionary view of science developed here. Since this view is also compatible with close observation of scientific life, there are strong arguments for employing it in attempts to solve the host of problems that still remain. 141