1 UNIVERSITY OF UTRECHT DEPARTMENT OF GENDER AND ETHNICITY Implementing Radical Feminism into International Law: Feminist Genocidalism and the Yugoslav War (MASTER’S THESIS) Date: August 14, 2010 Supervisor: Dr. Sandra Ponzanesi Student: Milja Spoljar Student Number: 3249255 GEMMA 2008/2010 2 Abstract During the 1990s, the Western legal feminists got highly involved in prosecuting the sexual crimes committed during the War in the former Yugoslavia, demanding justice for the female victims of rape and other violent assaults. In their structural feminist worldview, they found that rape was not merely a tool of belligerent forces, but part of a global war against women. Wishing to implement these structural views into the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, they constructed the “rape-as-genocide” model that could be prosecuted under the definition of genocide found in the 1948 Genocide Convention, and what is more, would satisfy the criteria of persuasiveness relevant for today’s international law. Nevertheless, since international law has states as its basic constituent entities, the “rape-as-genocide” model required from legal feminists to choose a side in the war and name the opposing ethnicities of both the perpetrators and victims. Therefore, in the new feminist structural and universalist view, the rape was directed toward women because they were Muslim or Croatian and perpetrated against them exclusively by Serbian men. This thesis attempts to uncover the surface-level meaning of this and several similar constructions made by legal feminists, working on cases of mass rape perpetrated on the territory of the former Yugoslavia at the beginning of the 1990s. The thesis seeks to explore epistemological (or discursive) conditions that made it possible for these structural feminist ideas to become incorporated into international law, something that prior to the 1990s would not have been epistemically intelligible, let alone supported by the Western liberal system as it was during the 1990s. Finally, the thesis examines the discursive legacy of this feminist legal phenomenon dating from the 1990s. 3 Content CHAPTER 1. - How to become internal to the structure: the secret of feminist legal performance in the Yugoslav War................................................................................................................................... 10 1.1 International law and the wish for transgressing sovereignty .............................................. 11 1.2 International law, human rights and feminism ..................................................................... 21 1.3 Cynthia Ward on MacKinnon and radical feminism .............................................................. 28 1.4 Intersecting international law, radical feminism and war .................................................... 32 CHAPTER 2. - Entering the logic of law: searching for reasons behind the feminist attachment to genocide ................................................................................................................................................ 45 2.1 Validity and persuasiveness of law........................................................................................ 46 2.2 Validity and persuasiveness of two feminist camps.............................................................. 52 2.3 Culturalizing through the law ................................................................................................ 67 CHAPTER 3. - Dedicated to the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia in the Hague ............................................................................................................................................................... 74 3.1 Ethnicizing, culturalizing, “dehumanizing” ............................................................................ 77 3.2 Post scriptum: on the value of feminist legal progress ......................................................... 85 CHAPTER 4. - „Gendercide“ as a legacy of the feminist legal genocidalism: discussing a minoritarian framing of male experience .................................................................................................................. 90 4.1 Gendercide studies and inversion of radical feminism ......................................................... 91 4.2 Staying within technicality of gendercide ............................................................................. 97 4.3 On why gender matters....................................................................................................... 102 Conclusion ........................................................................................................................................... 106 Bibliography and works cited: ............................................................................................................. 110 4 5 Introduction There was something dangerously paradoxical about the title of the 1994 book Mass Rape: the War against Women in Bosnia-Herzegovina, a solid first approach to the topic of genocidal rapes in Bosnia-Herzegovina. Something that seemed suspicious from the very moment I came across this book almost eight years ago. Why are we waging war against “women” (this universalizing category that presupposes the category of “men” as its consolidating and foundational antidote) in Bosnia-Herzegovina (a nation-state entity that is supposed to be defined by its concrete territory and its concrete nationality), when maybe the only institution that could be responsible for the universal “war against women” is the institution of patriarchy? Talking about the war against women in Bosnia-Herzegovina seemed to be made of redundancy, as the totalizing determinism of such a war forecloses the need for any concrete nation-state variables. Moreover, the first part of this peculiar title indubitably reminds us of Mackinnon’s ongoing full-fledged world war between men and women of the world (MacKinnon 2006, 142). Together with the second part, the title is caught in a tautology: it claims that the war is happening somewhere where it has already been happening by the very logic of the totalizing effects of such a war. Accordingly, it finds itself gluing two things that do not need to be glued: in radical feminist theory and its ongoing war of the sexes, gender is a social system that divides power and therefore equals the political system and the state. In such a theory, the power of state and the power of men are one thing, indivisible and impenetrable (MacKinnon 2006, 170). Why, then, BosniaHerzegovina? Why suddenly this universal ongoing battle of the sexes, spurred by misogyny and compounded by the rapes, genital mutilations and assaults of today, in one particular state? 6 My thesis attempts to answer that question and to uncover the surface-level meaning - something I name “discursive actuality” – of similar constructions, theoretical assumptions and ideological propositions made by legal feminists who have been working on the cases of mass rape perpetrated on the territory of the former Yugoslavia during the 1990s. What I am interested in are epistemological (or discursive) conditions that made it possible for these structural feminist ideas to become incorporated into international law. This is even more intriguing given that it is something that prior to the 1990s would not have been epistemically intelligible, let alone supported by the Western liberal system as it was during the 1990s. Therefore, I use the Foucauldian “method” of genealogy in order to provide insights into the mechanisms by which those epistemological factors interacted so that the very idea of “the war against women in Bosnia-Herzegovina” moved beyond epistemic possibility and into discursive actuality. As Foucault would say, the conditions of possibility under investigation are no longer a set of purely epistemic rules, but a power-andknowledge network consisting of all kinds of practices, including the juridical ones that I am discussing in my thesis. Such a network of juridical practices that sustains (and is sustained by) the very possibility of certain feminist constructions, theoretical assumptions and ideological propositions is thus of high importance for my discussion and has pushed me into exploring the jurisdiction of international law. Nevertheless, not being a legal scholar, my intention is not to discuss the law itself, but simply to understand it in order to grasp the logic of legal feminism and its radical feminist aspirations. My main research problem therefore focuses on the following: On the basis of the discursive actuality created around the sexual violence perpetrated during the War in the former Yugoslavia, what can we say about the conditions for implementing a feminist structural worldview into international law over the course of the 1990s? 7 In answering this question, I start by analyzing international law as well as exploring the epistemic alterations that brought about the intersection of law and structural (radical) feminism. I argue that the only way to implement a feminist structural standpoint into international law is to self-consolidate at the expense of other, in this case victims and perpetrators in the Yugoslav War. On the other hand, the second chapter enters the law and explores a peculiar dynamics of contemporary juridical practices and legal definitions in order to better comprehend the alarming feminist legal demands. The third chapter is dedicated solely to the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia and the Kunarac case, the first one intended to focus exclusively on sexual crimes against women, with the ultimate hope of extending the jurisprudence on rape and sexual violence. Finally, the forth chapter discusses the discursive legacy of this feminist legal phenomenon dating from the 1990s. Throughout the thesis, the reader will notice that all my chapters revolve around the notion of West and Western feminism. Instead of claiming that the West is hard to define in all its heterogeneity, I am defining it on the basis of the well protected and blessedly safe Western soil. In terms of its dichotomic relation with the non-Western spaces, this feature of the Western safety is guaranteed through the totalizing presence of the North-Atlantic Treaty Organization (NATO), a political and military alliance that has the military capacity needed to undertake “crises management” operations, alone or in cooperation with other countries and international organizations, and whose goal is to “make sure that we can walk around freely in a safe and secure environment.”1 In this sense, the War in the former Yugoslavia has been a major challenge and a testing area for NATO’s post-Cold War 1 <http://www.nato.int/cps/en/natolive/what_is_nato.htm> 8 expansionist projects. Fifteen years after the war, the former Yugoslav countries, at least Slovenia and partly Croatia, can finally enjoy the privilege and blessing of Western safety; Bosnia-Herzegovina, Macedonia and Serbia (together with Kosovo) are yet to prove how worthy they are to be fully “safe and protected”. This post-Cold War NATO ideology that propagates peace, security and democratic rule of law is a highly complex and multifold one, but in its long-term aspirations it does not differ very much from the totalizing principles of the original East-West divide that had supposedly ended with the fall of the Berlin Wall in 1989. On the contrary, its performance under camouflage of political correctness and human rights makes it hard for the Westerners to acknowledge that the whole picture, something that is called a “global world”, is somewhat different and that this difference is being sustained by our steady belief in the Western superiority: superior technology, higher safety, bigger salaries, respect for human rights, advanced law, top universities and the like. All this, however, is nothing else but a solid infrastructure that can provide for its various experts and condition them to further sustain such an ideology. Sometimes they question, sometimes they criticize, but they never take the system more seriously than it takes itself.2 After all, this is the very condition of both the West and its Western subjects. Legal feminism from the 1990s represents one of those expert “teams” that have been consolidating their status by using others - victims of rapes and perpetrators of sexual violence, plaintiffs and defendants at the ICTY trials – aiming to categorize according to available legal definitions. My interest in their work started few years ago and has been influenced by their mighty feminist propaganda that sought to arouse empathy, but 2 See Zizek's discussion on the Slovenian group Laibach: <http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=1BZl8ScVYvA> 9 condone any questioning of their assumptions. I believed in their expertise, but at the same time felt the possibility of a strong judgment in the case of thinking differently. Being from Croatia did not facilitate my understanding of how powerful of an ideology the feminism can be. I did more or less understand how the system worked, but had immunized feminism from any criticism for the sake of feminist solidarity, this deceptive feeling that works on the principle of exclusion. It was not until I gave myself a chance to go through the inverse process of partial self-immunization from feminism that I finally managed to grasp this legal phenomenon in all its self-righteousness. Subsequently, this led me to the new texts and new authors and brought me to where I am at the moment: a gender studies scholar that thoroughly questions the story about the feminist legal success in the War in the former Yugoslavia. What follows is a very personal narrative “packed up” in a theoretical language. 10 CHAPTER 1. - How to become internal to the structure: the secret of feminist legal performance in the Yugoslav War My first chapter examines the Western feminist legal involvement in the War in the former Yugoslavia over the course of the 1990s. It focuses specifically on the ways of implementing the radical feminist worldviews into the international law through the use of raped Bosnian Muslim (and to a certain extent Croatian3) female bodies, but it does that by offering much broader picture of both international community and law. The first chapter could thus be seen as a somewhat too ambitious project that deals with many different and, at first glance, not directly interconnected issues. However, what this chapter is advising to the reader is to pay close attention to the layers of its structure, inasmuch as they function as an “explicatory” element for understanding the sheer possibility of radical feminist performance within the realm of international law. That is why the chapter starts with the “surface” layer that revolves around the dual paradigm of international law proposed by Gerry Simpson in his text Two Liberalisms (Simpson 2001). This dual paradigm, as we shall see, could be considered an allencompassing theoretical framework that will steadily guide me through my thesis. The chapter then goes beneath this surface by offering Karen Engle’s account of feminist legal performance prior to the 1990s as well as her division on “internal” and “external” feminist internationalism that must be seen in close connection to the Simpson’s model (Engle 1992). The third part, on the other hand, wants to explain the theoretical differences and 3 My main concern will be the „use“ of Bosnian Muslim women, as they have been given incomparably more attention than the Croatian women as far as the feminist legal performance is concerned. One of the reasons for such an attention was a higer number of female victims among this particular ethnicity. 11 similarities between radical and liberal feminism in order to acknowledge both their common tradition and their crucial point of divergence. This is also the preparation for the fourth part where blurring of the boundaries between internal and external - liberal and radical - feminist performance is discussed in details and with the help of various theoretical layers that are truly tangled with each other. Even though the Simpson’s model is still functioning as a somewhat “explicatory” element that is the most external to the overall structure, this does not mean that the feminist legal performance should be understood as a practice thoroughly dependent on the Simpson’s model; on the contrary, feminist legal performance is to be understood as a highly autonomous practice that has very consciously chosen the conformist path of complying with the politics of international law and becoming internal to it. However, being internal to the structure4 is not inherently problematic; it is the fashion of becoming internal that is truly problematic here. What was the fashion of implementing the feminist radical standpoint into the international law is something that I want to discuss in my first chapter. The reader should note that Catherine MacKinnon’s theoretical assumptions are scattered all over the chapter. As a true feminist theologian, as Judith Butler has labeled her (Butler 1991), MacKinnon has influenced the law as nobody had managed before her. She may be continually dismissed as a fundamentalist feminist thinker, but her words and ideas resonate in every legal feminist text that has been written over the course of the 1990s. 1.1 International law and the wish for transgressing sovereignty The international law is the normative expression of the international polity which has states as its basic constituent entities. Other entities, such as individuals, groups and international 4 The terms „structure“ and „system“ will be used as synonyms throughout my thesis. 12 intergovernmental and NGOs, can assert some degree of international personhood for particular purposes, but the state is considered the most complete expression of international legal personality (Charlesworth and Chinkin 2000, 124). The state is, of course, an abstraction, a conception. In relations with other states, a state is represented by another abstraction which is a government. Governments are represented by humans who, as officials, act in a representative capacity, whereas representation is also an abstraction, a conception. International law regards states as independent and autonomous members of the international community. It tends to obliterate the differences between states by considering all states as formally equal, whatever their size, population, geography or wealth. The apparently neutral and value-free definition of a state in international law set out by the Montevideo Convention on Rights and Duties of States in 1933 provides that the state as a person of international law should possess a permanent population, a defined territory, a government and a capacity to enter into relations with other states (Henkin 1995, 13). Such a classical vision of international doctrine of state sovereignty bears an obvious resemblance to the domestic-liberal doctrine of individual liberty. Both characterize the social world in descriptive and normative terms: in terms of the activities of individual agents (“legal subjects”, i.e. citizens and states) that set down the basic conditions within which the relations between these agents should be conducted. Accordingly, both emphasize the liberal qualities of rule of law, autonomy, rights and equality. In his text Two Liberalisms, Gerry Simpson characterizes this traditional view of international law that suggests a dual paradigm for the ordering of individuals - one domestic, the other international - as “Charter liberalism”, insofar as the principles underlying this approach find their highest expression in the text of the UN Charter. The point of this approach is to treat all states equally, to allow them each the same rights 13 afforded to individuals in a liberal society (i.e. domestic jurisdiction, equality, nonintervention) and to, if not celebrate, at least tolerate the diversity produced by these norms. This Charter liberalism, as Simpson argues, is based on a norm of inclusion entwined with a policy of strategic engagement. Undemocratic or illiberal states are admitted into international society so that society might be universalized and those states domesticated. In such a classical vision of liberalism, it is thus the state that has been given ontological priority: state is immune and autonomous, whereas individual human rights are unrecognized. As opposed to this classical view of liberalism (though not in the binary sense, since the two of them share many characteristics), there is another image of what it means to be a liberal. As Simpson explains, “[t]his is liberalism (sometimes characterized as neoliberalism) endowed with a sort of moralistic fervor, a conviction, and at times, an intolerance of the illiberal . . . In various writings about international affairs, Francis Fukuyama’s liberal triumphalism is the starkest example of this liberalism” (Simpson 2001, 539). This is the liberalism of certainty, of what Simpson calls “liberal anti-pluralism”: a liberalism that is more than often exclusive and illiberal in its effects. In international law, this liberal anti-pluralism differs from the Charter liberalism identified above most obviously in its lack of tolerance for non-liberal regimes. The nineteenth century was an era of liberal governance within Western Europe and, at the same time, the one that clearly expressed its civilizational task with reference to the rest of the world. New regimes in Europe became less authoritarian in relation with their own citizens and revolutionary Europe cast aside the old guard of absolutist monarchies. However, at the same time, these liberal states demoted non-liberal societies such as China, Korea, and Japan to the second class status because of a perceived lack of civilization; as Simpson argues, their treatment of non-European civilizations compared rather poorly to 14 those of their illiberal predecessors. In this new international legal community, the emphasis was on law as a reflection of will - particularly individual will - in opposition to the natural law emphasis on the triumph of reason over will.5 The idea of international law as a product of state will was reflected in the willingness of state to “manage” international order, reaching a high point in the counter-revolutionary 1815 “Concert of Europe”6 and its subsequent conferences. However, this should not be perceived as a centralized international legal order; between alliance participants, it was a matter of treaty, and in its impact on other states, it was based on the simple exercise of power - or the dominance of one state will over another - and not on any sense of legal right or obligation. In other words, once the legitimate objectives of statecraft were unleashed from the shared objectives of the ancient régime, they might or might not be revolutionary – but they were now all political, a term that increasingly came to mean whatever is determined by the leaders of a nation to be their objective.7 This can help us to understand how it was possible for the Victorian anti-pluralists to simply divide states into those entities that are entitled to full 5 The idea of a law of nature innate to humanity as a whole was, according to some scholars, synonymous with divine, religious law - the direct divine connection of religious authorities - whereas for others it constituted rules developed from deduction and right reason. In his thirteenth century Summa Theologiae, Thomas Aquinas characterized natural law as the “participation in the eternal law by rational creatures applying right reason” (cited in Mills 2006, 8), in an attempt to reconcile the fact of human law (or at least rational human law) with a concept of universal law. Under this conception, the rules of natural law could be derived through the application of deductive reasoning to accepted principles or axioms. By following the logic of such deductive reasoning, an integral part of the medieval concept of the office of Emperor was that it was his prerogative, based on the power of the sword which was bestowed upon him, to wage war against the internal and external enemies of Christendom. This unified moral/legal order was, with no doubt, a license for military power during the colonization era in 16th and 17th century. Peace of Westphalia of 1648, on the other hand, marked the separation of the law of nations from natural law and is often referred to as the birth of modern international law (Grewe 2000). 6 The Concert of Europe, as developed by the Austrian chancellor Prince von Metternich, drew upon the ideas and the notion of a balance of power in international relations. Its founding members were the United Kingdom, Austrian Empire, Russian Empire and Kingdom of Prussia, the members of the Quadruple Alliance responsible for the downfall of the First French Empire; in time France became established as a fifth member of the concert. 7 For the discussion on the 19th century international law, see Kennedy, Of Law and War (2006): 56-67. 15 sovereign equality (European states), and those possessing some lesser form of sovereignty (unequal sovereigns) (Simpson 2001, 545). By stressing the civilizational task in similar divisions, this Victorian practice can be viewed as a precursor to the homogenous approach of the post-Cold War international world. As Simpson argues, at the same time, some international lawyers, writing in the lateVictorian era, were by now rejecting the idea of international law as a closed system. Many late nineteenth-century writers were keen to present themselves as open-minded and cosmopolitan in comparison with more backward contemporaries. These dual and competing positions of Charter and anti-pluralist liberalists were substantial for the debates at the Versailles Conference in 1919 whose result was, hence, very much unclear. 8 The League of Nations Covenant at Article 1 (2) implied that the League was to be a closed system of like-minded states where a central qualification of membership was to be “selfgovernment”, meaning democratic government. The practice of the League was, nevertheless, a different tale: in the two decades of its existence the organization embraced a more pluralistic and heterogeneous approach to membership with the admission of authoritarian Italy and Bolshevik Russia. It was inevitable, then, that these two conceptions of international organizations would result in a measure of equivocation in the lead-up to the San Francisco Conference in 1945 that entailed drafting of the Charter and a subsequent establishment of the United Nations (UN). As Simpson is reminding us, “Article 1 of the Draft Constitution stated that the new organization would ‘reflect the universal character of the international community’, but Article 1 (2) went on to say that ‘all qualified states . . . shall be members of the International Organization” (Simpson 2001, 551). The Drafting 8 In his Of Law and War, Kennedy is quoting the first Secretary-General of the League of Nations, Harold Nicholson: “We came to Paris confident that the new order was about to be established; we left it convinced that the new order had merely fouled the old” (Kennedy 2006, 74). 16 Subcommittee dealing with the issue of membership rejected the anti-pluralist approach on two potentially contradictory grounds: on the one hand, it was “against referring to a requirement that states have ‘democratic institutions’ on the grounds that ‘this would imply an undue interference with internal arrangements’” (Simpson 2001, 553); on the other hand, the absence of any specific provision to this effect also retained an element of flexibility and elasticity in the main adjective of the Conference, that of the “peace-loving” states. And even though its flexibility was thought to be a positive feature at the time of drafting of the Charter - the adjective itself had not been taken seriously except as a way of reasserting that the UN began as association of the victor states – it later on permitted victor states to incorporate highly intrusive and ideological criteria into their assessment of prospective members (Simpson 2001, 553). Nevertheless, it was universalist, pluralist position that prevailed in the end. As many have argued so far (Allison 1988; Kennedy 2006; Simpson 2001), it is possible to see the Cold War period from 1945 to 1989 as one marked by rejection of standards of civilization, culture and democracy as criteria for membership of the international community: entities meeting certain neutral criteria based on effectiveness and a purely formal promise to comply with international norms were admitted to the system. International community was liberal, then, in the same way that some democracies are said to be liberal; it tolerated highly illiberal elements within its membership.9 The new law became flexible, functional, practical. Even the word “war” was eliminated from the phrase “law of war”, and instead a “law of force” has been put into function. In such a 9 As stated in Simpson’s text, perhaps the most egregious example of this was the continued membership of the Khmer Rouge in the General Assembly long after it had been shown that the organization was implicated in a human rights holocaust and after it had been deposed by the Hun Sen Government with the aid of Vietnamese intervention (Simpson 2001, 557). 17 community, the political institutions were replaced by a comprehensive constitutional order that fused political and ethical considerations in a common legal vocabulary. Human rights system which existed since the General Assembly of the United Nations proclaimed its Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) on 10 December 1948 did little to change the practice of universal international organizations in their admission policies. So while human rights insisted on adherence to certain values, the practice of international organizations remained pluralistic and there was no serious attempt made to fix human rights obligations to entry requirements into the international community during this Charter liberalist era. These provisions were qualified by Article 2 (7), which says that nothing in the Charter shall authorize the UN to intervene in matters which are essentially within the domestic jurisdiction of any state.10 All of this began to change in the late 1980s with development of norms and practices designed to promote democratic governance. On the normative front, various human rights organs within and outside the UN system articulated new democratic standards. In practice, the UN entered the business of election monitoring through its Electoral Assistance division and started to restore democratic governance through the use of force. In the lead-up to the fall of the Berlin Wall, the era of liberal anti-pluralism was gradually approaching and Western commentaries began to adopt celebratory air in discussing the spread of democracy. During the course of 1990s, a broad trend has been developed towards strengthening the normative status of individual in international law. In his influential book A Philosophy of 10 For a discussion on the post-1945 human rights era, see Michael Freeman, Human Rights Human Rights. An Interdisciplinary Approach (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2002): 32-51. Also, one exception to this Charter liberalist era should be taken into account: it was the UN's response to apartheid in South Africa and white rule in Rhodesia (now Zimbabwe) beginning in 1966 that fist saw a link made between internal state practices and status in the international community. As Simpson argues, here are found the portents of the anti-pluralism that was to flourish in the post-Cold War era (Simpson 2001, 557). 18 International Law, Fernando R. Tesón proposed reexamination of the traditional foundations of international law that is suggesting a dichotomic paradigm for the ordering of individuals: one domestic, the other one international, one private, the other public. As Tesón argues, these “traditional foundations are illiberal and authoritarian because they unduly exalt state power” (Tesón 1998, 1-2). International order thus conceived is incapable of serving as the normative framework for present international relations. “Although it is understandably hard for lawyers to forsake the statist assumptions of classic international legal discourse”, Tesón argues, “new times call for a fresh conceptual and ethical language. A more liberal world needs a more liberal theory of international law” (Tesón 1998, 1). Simpson calls Tesón’s work “the most robust defense of strong liberal anti-pluralism” (Simpson 2001, 563); his “Kantian Theory of International Law” is an explicit rejection of the statism inherent in Charter liberalism and is based on “normative individualism” as opposed to “sovereign equality”. In such a neo-liberalist vision, individual’s democratic and human rights prevail over the state’s claims to territorial integrity or political sovereignty. In juristic terms, one could say that the individual has been transformed into a significant legal player and this in turn transforms the network of legal relations comprising the international legal order. Indeed, as Christopher Harding is reminding us in his Statist Assumptions, Normative Individualism and New Forms of Personality: Evolving a Philosophy of International Law for the Twenty First Century, “it has already been accepted within UN practice that some ‘internal’ human rights violations could be of such nature as to threaten regional peace and stability and thereby justify international (UN authorized) intervention . . . The Security Council has indeed already characterized the internal situation in Kosovo as a threat to the peace in UN Charter terms” (Harding 2001, 117). However, in terms of conventional, UN Charter-based international law, the military action taken by the NATO members against 19 Serbia in 1999 appeared to violate basic norms of non-intervention, having no clear legal justification (for instance, Security Council authorization, or acting in self-defense) under the UN Charter. As Antonio Cassese has argued: “There is no gainsaying that the Charter system has been transgressed, in that a group of states has deliberately resorted to armed action against a sovereign state without authorization to do so by the Security Council” (cited in Simpson 2001, 117). Indeed, there is no gainsaying that the Charter system has been transgressed, but are we heading in a good direction by presupposing that the reason for that lies in illegality of such military action? If the Security Council had authorized such action, would it have turned transgression of the Charter system into something subversive or just?11 In other words, would legality of such transgression necessarily imply justice, and/or is legal system inherently just? In my paper I claim the following: there is nothing either subversive or just about transgressing the Charter system, insofar as such transgression is founded upon the Western neo-liberal and democratic standards that are, themselves, inherently undemocratic and illiberal. As this chapter will try to show, what makes these standards being inherently illiberal and undemocratic is precisely the production and an utter dependence on the “self-consolidating other”.12 Accordingly, both such production and dependence cannot create any possibility for subversion and justice; on the contrary, they are inherently and incessantly violent. Embracing the liberal anti-pluralism through the act of transgression is thus in itself the act of violence: the violence that is invisible and concealed within the language of international law, the violence that is objective or structural, as Zizek would call it, the violence that is, in most of the cases, a non-violent form of perfectly legal 11 12 Instead of using the word “just”, Tesón uses the Kantian „supreme principle of morality“ (Tesón 1998, 4). The problem of the “self-consolidating other” will be discussed in further detail in Part 1.4 of this Chapter. 20 violence.13 What Cassese is arguing above makes sense only in connection with this objective or structural violence. His discourse revolving around legality/illegality of the transgression will always be highly welcomed by the liberal anti-pluralist Western model inasmuch as it presupposes that the problem lies in illegality of certain armed actions, and not in such actions themselves.14 By keeping these actions illegal, the liberal anti-pluralism makes sure that the actual15 violence - a violent form of violence16 - is never an issue for this perfectly legal system; by keeping these actions illegal, the system makes sure that it has nothing to lose, except the illegality of these actions; by keeping these actions illegal, this structurally violent system reproduces itself and at the same time creates its army of quasi-critical conformists whose only goal is to define whether the 1999 bombarding of Belgrade was legal or illegal, whereas, on the other hand, it was the case of actual, if not subjective, violence that managed to kill 200 civilians in only two months.17 13 As Zizek is claiming in an interview named “Divine Violence and Liberated Territories”, first of all, “we have to emphasize that violence is always a structural problem, an ‘objective’ feature of contemporary capitalist societies . . . And we should also remember that violence is not necessarily activity, action. It is not always the case that social functions run by themselves and that it takes a lot of energy, a lot of violence to transform them. To the contrary, it often takes a lot of violence to make sure things stay the way they are. Sometimes, then, the truly violent act is doing nothing, a refusal to act”, interview by Soft Targets (March 14, 2007). <http://www.softtargetsjournal.com/web/zizek.php> 14 A similar problem has been discussed in Brendan O'Neill's article „A 'Legal War' Would Have Been Even Worse“ (March 11, 2008). <http://www.spiked-online.com/index.php/site/article/4860/> 15 An allusion to Gilles Deleuze's concepts of “actual” and “virtual”. According to Deleuze, virtual and actual are both real, but not everything that is virtually contained (immanent) in this world is or becomes actual. 16 Alain Badiou calls it “subjective” violence or the violence with an easily identifiable agent (i.e. NATO military action against Serbia). On the other hand, we get easily fascinated by the “subjective” violence coming from the non-Western world (i.e. identifiable agents such as Karadzic, Osama bin Laden, etc.) 17 But how could we possibly identify the violence coming from the NATO as “subjective”? Who exactly are its agents and aren't they dispersed into thousand little virtual agents? Multilateral organizations such as NATO could never appear as easily identifiable agents of violence, inasmuch as they tend to be classified as the necessary constitutive elements of one legally governed structure or system; accordingly, the violence these agents exercise becomes structural, objective and, therefore, very easily justifiable. This very condition of the Western existence stands in sharp contradiction to the processes of “individuation” of certain personae such as Karadzic, Milosevic, and others. 21 But where is the feminist jurisprudence within this story and what effects the liberal anti-pluralism has had on the feminist legal performance? Since “women have no state, are no state, seek no state” (MacKinnon 2006, 267), as MacKinnon argued, one could assume that legal feminists working within international legal arena have been much more inclined toward the model of liberal anti-pluralism. Indeed, even though feminist jurisprudence has not embraced the normative individualism proposed by Téson - on the contrary, it has been extremely critical about both the “normative” and “individual” aspects in it – it has been sharing with it a strong wish for transgressing sovereignty in the international system. Moreover, both Tesón and feminist jurisprudence have been implicitly claiming that in such transgression, there is something inherently subversive and just. But before I continue further with the implications of these arguments, let me first start with answering on the following questions: which area of international law has been the most accessible and hospitable area for feminist advocates prior to the 1990s? In other words, how did the feminist jurisprudence “look like” under the rule of the Charter system specific to the Cold War? 1.2 International law, human rights and feminism With the conclusion of the Second World War, the UN Charter and the 1948 UDHR began to rework the de jure relationship between state and individual. As stated in Xavier Fellmeth’s text Feminism and International Law: Theory, Methodology, and Substantive Reform, international law no longer solely served whatever elite group is in power to exploit its subjects unhindered by other states (Xavier Fellmeth 2000, 703). It began to recognize and protect individual human rights, the rights of those legal subjects whose access to the international legal system had been previously restricted by the very logic of statist 22 paradigm. By shifting the responsibility for observance of human rights from individual states, the human rights law has penetrated the sovereign system and thus provided the feminist jurisprudence with potential platform for legal action. Hence it is not surprising, as Charlesworth and Chinkin argue, that feminist critiques of rights themselves have been remarkably rare in the literature on international women’s rights (Charlesworth and Chinkin 2000, 210). Human rights offer a framework for a good society and their substantial discourse on justice and rightness can seem very promising for anyone devoted to “peaceloving” discourse. As Wendy Brown has pointed out in addressing the question of the value of rights language for women, “rights are to be suffered as ‘paradoxes’. They are ‘that which we cannot not want’” (cited in Conaghan and Millns 2005, 2). Moreover, when gender is a social and political system that divides power, as MacKinnon has argued together with the liberal feminists (albeit in much more radical fashion), than the acquisition and assertion of rights is by no means the only solution for the domination of women by men and an important feminist tactic. But does this mean that feminist legal scholarship embraces the concept of normative individualism proposed by Tesón in his influential Philosophy of International Law? The international law theory proposed by Téson is founded on the idea of the individual as rational and autonomous. Kantian liberals regard individuals as capable of rational choices, possessed of inherent dignity, and worthy of respect. The liberal states and the members of the liberal alliance are those nation-states with democratically elected officials, where human rights are generally respected. Liberal internationalism assumes a right to democratic governance and holds that a state may not discriminate against individuals, including women. This principle is, of course, a centerpiece of the international law of human rights. Feminist jurisprudence provides very substantial challenges to human 23 rights law as it is institutionally understood. Although it might seem that, since women are human, international law would naturally incorporate women’s rights, women’s rights advocates have suggested that such incorporation cannot be assumed. While some claim that women’s rights are already included in international human rights law, others argue that the international human rights regime will have to change before it can take women into account. In either case, women’s rights discourse is generally positioned at the periphery of human rights discourse, both challenging and defending the dominant human rights model as it attempts to fit its causes into that model. In the arena which is filled with rights enumeration and rights talk, possibilities for conflicts between competing rights ensue.18 Examining how different women’s rights advocates deal with those potential conflicts sheds lights both on international law discourse and on feminist approaches to law. As Engle argues in her text International Human Rights and Feminism: When Discourses Meet, even though the critique of rights has not been launched at human rights law itself, it has not escaped challenge. There are two attacks aimed at law that can be generally detected: first, it is often seen as a Western-conceived and -dominated project that fails to address adequately the concerns of the East and the Third World. While some critics raise a possibility that a Western system of rights cannot accommodate non-Western needs, most believe that the system can rearrange its priorities. Second, and more often, human rights system is attacked for not being expansive enough and is encouraged to take more seriously economic or social rights, or the rights of women or cultural and ethnic minorities (Engle 1992, 519). As Charlesworth et al. argued in their influential text Feminist 18 As Costas Douzinas argues in his Human Rights and Empire, “[t]he more rights we introduce, the greater the pressure to legislate for more, to enforce them better, to turn the person into an infinitive collector of rights, and humanity into an endlessly proliferating mosaic of law“ (Douzinas 2007, 50). 24 Approaches to International Law, international law accords priority to civil and political rights, rights that may have very little to offer women generally, insofar as the major forms of oppression of women operate within the economic, social and cultural realms of human rights. Accordingly, economic, social and cultural rights are traditionally regarded as a lesser form of international right and as much more difficult to implement (Charlesworth et al. 1991, 635). These two sets of critics, of course, are not unrelated. For both sets of critics, whatever deficiencies the law might have can be addressed through expansion, either through new sets of rights or through reordering of the rights that exist. None of the critics believes that taking into account her or his concern will radically disrupt the system (Engle 1992, 519). Since the inception of human rights law, different groups and cause have situated themselves at its margins and challenged it to respond better to more and different types of oppression. Feminists form one of those groups. Through their work, they have not only identified those international legal instruments that include provisions prohibiting sex discrimination, but have also helped establish international legal instruments that pertain specifically to women’s rights. Today there exists multitude of international instruments that affirm women’s rights - in 1986, Natalie Hevener identified twenty-two international documents relating to the status of women19 - but the 1979 Convention on the Elimination 19 For example, the 1929 and 1949 Geneva Conventions, which require combatants to treat women prisoners of war “with all regard due to their sex” and equally to male prisoners in all other respects; the UN Charter, which was the first international instrument to establish women’s full equality and equal right to participate in the United Nations; the 1948 UDHR; the 1949 Convention for the Suppression of the Traffic in Persons and of the Exploitation of the Prostitution of Others; the Fourth Geneva Convention, which forbids the assault, rape, or forced prostitution on women; the 1951 Convention Concerning Equal Remuneration for Men and Women Workers for Work of Equal Value; the 1953 Convention on the Political Rights of Women; the 1957 Convention on the Nationality of Married Women; the 1962 Convention on Consent to Marriage, Minimum Age for Marriage and Registration of Marriages, etc (cited in Xavier Fellmeth 2000, 708-709). 25 of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women (hereinafter “Women’s Convention” or “Convention”) is perhaps the most prominent of all. As of 1999, Women’s Convention has been ratified by over 160 states. Signatories to that convention undertake to eliminate and penalize all practices that have as their purpose or effect discrimination against women in political, social, economic, cultural, and other spheres, including such pernicious practices as trafficking in women and exploitation of prostitution. This commitment applies to preventing discrimination by public officials, private individuals, businesses and organizations. Despite its apparently strong protections,20 Charlesworth et al. dismiss Women’s Convention as an “ambiguous offering”. Moreover, Women’s Convention generally obliges states only to take all appropriate measures to ensure the observance of human rights, but does not set specific mandatory measures or predictable penalties for states that fail to take positive action to implement the Convention. And even though many commentators and activists assume that the quest for rights of women is an important and useful strategy internationally, we should, nevertheless, ask ourselves “whether this task is worth the energy that must be expanded on it. Can the human rights canon usefully respond to women’s concerns across the globe? Are we simply creating new sites for the subtle oppression of women?” (Charlesworth and Chinkin 2000, 210). In her 1992 article that examined in detail much of the literature that has emerged on women’s human rights since 1979, Engle identified three broad approaches taken by women’s human rights advocates: “doctrinalist”, “institutionalist”, and “external critique”. 20 Women's Convention imposes positive obligations on signatories to promote: the full development and advancement of women; cultural and social change to eliminate prejudices and stereotypes; an understanding of maternity and the common responsibility of men and women to raise children; and equal opportunity to participate in the national and international political life of the state. Article 14, for instance, deals with the particular needs of rural women, who often suffer from an oppressive combination of discrimination and disempowerment (cited in Xavier Fellmeth 2000, 710). 26 Each of these three approaches represented a particular feminist approach to law as well as specific approach to human rights discourse. Two approaches, doctrinal and institutional, worked within the field of international human rights and uses language internal to that discourse. Their proponents were, for the most part, liberal feminists who generally believe in the effectiveness of human rights legal doctrine and institutions (Engle 1992, 521). They were advocating women’s rights by interpreting and sometimes criticizing the existing doctrinal and institutional framework. Doctrinalists generally described a specific problem facing women in some or all parts of the world and then showed doctrinally how the problem constituted an international human rights violation. Institutionalists, on the other hand, were critically examining international legal institutions that were created to enforce human rights. They were studying both mainstream human rights institutions and specialized women’s rights institutions to determine whether and how they protected women’s human rights. Engle considers both of these approaches “positivist”, not in the way it is often used in the international law - as mere products of sovereign consent - but to the extent that positivists believe that international law is authoritative and that states are bound by it, particularly those states that have signed or ratified specific documents. Moreover, the positivist nature of both groups evinces a general approach to human rights that sees women’s rights as a normal part of human rights law and discourse, readily assimilable to the human rights model (Engle 1992). Advocates who took a third approach posed what Engle considers external critiques. They approached human rights discourse as feminists, generally radical feminists, who were troubled by the existence of a system that claims to protect the rights of all human being while, systematically and systemically, as MacKinnon would say, excluding one half of the human race. Rather than working within human rights discourse in its current form, external 27 approach critiqued the human rights framework either for being male-defined or –deployed, or for being based on inherently male concepts. These external critics aimed to have what they saw as women’s human rights achieved, regardless of whether those rights existed in positive law. In doing so, they raised difficult questions about whether women’s needs and rights could fit into the existing definition and conception of human rights. Hence they were less likely than internal critics to see women’s rights as assimilable to the human rights model. The views of external critics ranged from those who thought human rights theory would only be fully consistent after it incorporates women’s rights to those who thought human rights theory must change and be reconceptualized in order to address successfully women’s concerns. Thus the primary distinction between the two approaches is that the internal one assumes and acts upon the belief that women’s rights have and can be assimilated to the human rights structure, whereas the external one questions whether assimilation to the structure as it exists is possible. In other words, while internal approach actively operates within the system of international law, the external one develops a metaposition whose main focus is analyzing the flaws that are to be found both in the internal approach and the human rights structure itself. But are there any similarities among these two approaches? And what aspect of radical theory makes this theory truly radical, so that it is doomed to acquire external approach? What follows here is a small digression whose intention is to remind the reader about the unique approach that radical theory has toward women. I use Cynthia Ward’s article Radical Feminist Defense of Individualism, as it both challenges the radical/liberal dichotomy and takes into account the common roots of these different feminist standpoints. 28 1.3 Cynthia Ward on MacKinnon and radical feminism In her text Radical Feminist Defense of Individualism, Ward challenges the assumed link between the gender hierarchy and the rejection of liberalism (Ward 1994-1995). Acknowledging the power of the domination theory as critique, Ward locates radical theory within the liberal tradition and argues that nothing in radical theory blocks the use of liberal strategies to address the problems of male domination. On the contrary, Ward argues, the radical critiques of male domination calls for liberal individualist solutions. In evaluation of radical feminist theory, Ward focuses mainly on MacKinnon’s ideas, as they represent the most fully developed version of the radical feminist approach. For MacKinnon, then, what is “feminine” in the social world is what turns a man on, and what turns a man on is female passivity and subordination – whatever allows him to aggress against her, to invade her, without resistance or even resentment. Thus, MacKinnon reduces society’s conception of “woman” to the female role in sex, and further reduces the role to one of submission and passivity. For radical feminists, these social stereotypes take on political significance because they operate to deprive women of equality in all spheres of life – social, economic, political, and legal. Social rules dictate that women be made sexually available to men, and legal rules help ensure that women’s identities are constructed to fill that desire. But what exactly is the connection between the social idea of the “feminine” and male domination in other spheres? MacKinnon spends very little time defining the concept of male domination; in fact, she proceeds from announcing the gender hierarchy to laying out its results, attempting to demonstrate women’s systematic subordination via descriptions of women’s disadvantaged economic situation, the widespread sexual abuse of them, and the popularity of 29 pornography depicting women being abused or sexually passive and subordinate to men. Nevertheless, Ward argues, feminists of all stripes know of and deplore this abuse, whether or not they agree with MacKinnon’s theoretical approach; its facts are clearly consistent with varying explanations of women’s inequality, from liberal to radical, and cannot alone prove the existence or extent of male domination. Hence it might be helpful to stress out what does not define domination in radical theory. For example, one interpretation of the concept would equate dominance with predominance, but this would be again fully consistent with liberal solutions to women’s inequality. All feminists acknowledge that men have historically filled the vast majority of powerful positions in society, and that statistics in many areas continue to show male predominance. MacKinnon clearly rejects the meaning of domination based on statistics and shows that men dominate women in a second sense of that word: so as to achieve mastery and control over women as a group. This immediately appears to match with radical feminist description of the effects of male dominance on women. Dominating is something men do to women; it is systematized male coercion which constricts women’s development and relegates them to the bottom. In what sense, then, are women coerced to victimhood? While one theme of MacKinnon’s radical theory seems premised on the idea that women’s sexuality is the constant target of men’s control, she ultimately concludes that women lack the power to resist male sexual advances; indeed, MacKinnon states that women are purposely kept in a powerless condition for this purpose. In radical feminist theory, male domination goes beyond the use of power to violate women’s individual autonomy; male power actually destroys the possibility of autonomy and individual selfhood for all women. Here, domination reaches into the very construction of women’s character and personality, creating something analogous to a “false consciousness” under which many 30 women actually voluntarily accept, defend, and even choose roles that help perpetuate the gender hierarchy: women are socially engineered to believe in the naturalness and inevitability of male supremacy. Male dominance thus becomes self-enforcing. This third understanding of male supremacy from externally imposed force to internal compliance by women themselves is central to MacKinnon’s theory. If women are denied independent selves capable of both evaluating and rejecting their situation, this argument loses no persuasiveness when women comply, are successful and even happy members of permanent underclass. Thus, the core of the domination idea is that under a system of male supremacy women are denied opportunity to develop independent selves. Nevertheless, that goal is also central to liberal feminism, which takes the recognition of selfhood and the importance of self-development to be core ideals: liberal reforms are not only consistent with a view of inequality as caused by male domination, Ward argues, but are founded upon such ideas. The classic liberal argument against the gender hierarchy was made by John Stuart Mill in his The Subjection of Women, first published in 1869. Mill’s protest against male dominance contains all the major tenets of radical feminist theory. So what explains this apparently dramatic difference in politics between two visions that share the same central goal - the achievement of selfhood for women? As Ward points out, if there is a difference, it must lie in the concept of selfhood itself. But how can creatures who have been socially constructed to support the system of male supremacy recognize that it does them injustice, or design a new legal regime – a separate feminist view of law and society – that will bring equality to women? 31 Although at times MacKinnon seems simply to acknowledge these problems without attempting to resolve them, she is ultimately driven to give some substantive content to its notion of women’s selfhood. She does this in two ways. First, MacKinnon condemns as necessarily male the vision of individual selfhood adopted by liberalism. Whatever women’s selfhood will look like after male domination ends, it won’t be liberal. Second, she attempts to construct a female self out of conscious-raising. In radical feminist view, consciousnessraising is the process through which the contemporary radical feminist analysis of the situation of women has been shaped and shared. As Ward argues, radical feminism gives this method a credit for defining “woman’s self-concept” through an exploration of women’s consciousness, not as individual or subjective ideas, but as collective social being. Two ideas are critical to this theory of consciousness-raising: first, it claims to derive a feminist epistemology from women’s actual experience, from practice, and not from abstract, objective principles of justice. Radical feminists contrast this grassroots, bottom-up approach to the top-down Enlightenment idea which they characterize as beginning from abstract principles about human reality which are then applied to the world in a purportedly gender neutral, but really male-biased, way. Second, they unite grassroots consciousness-raising with group-based reform proposals, insisting that since a woman’s problems are not hers individually but those of women as a whole, they cannot be addressed except as a whole. But this statement deserves exploration, since it seems both obviously true and obviously untrue. Unquestionably, law that treats women unequally as a group – which denies them, as a group, legal rights equal to those of men – should not proceed toward equality by granting rights separately to individual women; such a person-by-person approach would itself violate the equality ideal. To the extent law creates disadvantaged groups by denying them 32 equal rights it must remedy the problem by granting them equal rights, as a group. Once this is done, under liberal theory, women’s group identity dissolves, leaving individuals free to pursue their own goals uninhibited by imposed gendered identities. In this sense, all political and legal reform is group-based, Ward argues. Notions of “collective empowerment” and collective point of view are completely understandable under this interpretation. However, what makes some versions of “groupness” in feminist theory illiberal is not the mere association of, or recognition by groups of women that they have suffered common experiences, but the claim that women are by nature more group-oriented in the sense of being more altruistic and/or relational than men. This view, which explicitly or implicitly subordinates the liberal focus on individual autonomy and rational self-interest, is of course a central tenet of cultural feminism. MacKinnon attacks this vision of the feminine as imposed by male supremacy, but offers no replacement for it. In MacKinnon’s account, consciousness-raising uses a group-based approach to discovery of the truth about women’s situations and reaches collective conclusions about the nature of women under male supremacy. As Ward explains, woman’s collective perspective resulted in the delineation of woman’s self-concept; under male supremacy, that concept is woman as victim. This is, at the same time, the break-up point of radical and liberal theory. 1.4 Intersecting international law, radical feminism and war From late 1991 and throughout 1992 extensive media coverage created widespread pressure for an international legal response to the atrocities committed against women and men in the conflicts accompanying the disintegration of the former Yugoslavia. In particular, sufficient outrage was expressed about the extensive rapes and other violent assaults against women to ensure that they could not be ignored, or discounted as a normal 33 phenomenon of armed conflict. The Security Council’s response to the demands for action was incremental. To collect information on the allegations of war crimes, it established a Commission of Experts to undertake an independent investigation. Following the report of the Commission, the Security Council requested the UN Secretary-General to submit proposals for the establishment of an ad hoc tribunal for the prosecution of war crimes in the former Yugoslavia. The Secretary-General’s Report was adopted in May 1993, and the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY) established. In 1994 events in Rwanda led the Security Council to take similar steps to establish a second ad hoc tribunal to prosecute persons for genocide and other serious violations of international humanitarian law in that country, the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR). In July 1998, a further step was taken by the adoption of a Rome Statute for a permanent International Criminal Court (ICC) by a Diplomatic Conference in Rome. The Rome Statute was the culmination of five years’ work after the completion of a draft text by the International Criminal Law (ICL) in 1994. So where is the 1990s legal feminism in this story? In her text on the work of organized feminism in the formation of new international criminal tribunals over the course of the 1990s, Janet Halley describes their organizational style as overwhelmingly coalitional and resulting in a literary “trace” that is almost devoid of manifest internal conflict. “The consensus that emerged as the feminists’ joint representation of their worldview, argument repertoire, and reform agenda, was not , as one might expect, a median liberal feminist view that split the difference between conservative and leftist feminist ideologies. Instead, the manifest consensus view was an updated radical feminism, strongly committed to a structuralist understanding of male domination and female subordination” (Halley 2009, 2). There was some tension on a few issues between structuralists and liberalists, Halley argues, but was muted by the coalitional 34 style adopted by feminists and compromised usually in the direction of structuralist rule choices.21 Furthermore, Halley argues, the substance of this structuralist feminism vision evolved over the course of the 1990s and changed without producing a literature of internal dissent. The legal agenda started out as a fairly simple commitment to assure that international criminal tribunals expressly and explicitly prohibit rape in war and prosecute it vigorously. “Not to do so was thought to trivialize or even condone rape. But over the course of the decade, the feminists doing this work discovered ways of implementing their structuralist view that rape was not merely a tool of belligerent forces . . . but part of a global war against women” (Halley 2009, 6). As those reforms took shape, a new feminist idea was clarified, one that Halley calls “feminist universalism”. “In this view women are not a particular group of humanity but a universe of their own. In the new feminist universalist worldview, humanitarian law and international criminal law norms relating to armed conflict could be about women” (Halley 2009, 6). In her Are Women Human? And Other International Dialogues, MacKinnon says that to call violence against women a “war", especially in a legal context, is usually dismissed as metaphorical, hyperbolic, and/or rhetorical. Violence against women has not looked like a war in this system in part because states are not seen to wage it, nor does it present armies contending within or across or against or for control or for definition of states. It is not about 21 Halley calls this coalitional style the “Governance Feminism”. The term was developed because it captures the strong resemblance of the new, muscular non-governmental organization (NGO) formations adopted by feminists to the prescription for political engagement with law produced by the “new governance” (NG) school. Amy Cohen describes the project of the NG literature as follows: „[N]ew governance proponents aim to design a wide-scale problem-solving praxis that is both maximally efficient and normatively (democratically) legitimate. They envisage myriad individual stakeholders grouped into 'problem-solving publics' . . . that negotiate about issues of social concern and that openly compare their learning with and against other problem-solving publics. By coordinating and monitoring (but not defining or driving) these horizontal processes from above, moreover, new governance proponents aim to ensure that these local deliberations are inclusive, transparent, justified by a record of demonstrable reason, and progressively evolve towards maximally informed, collaborative, and efficient solutions“ (cited in Halley 2009, 3-4). 35 state power in the usual way. Nor do the sexes look like combatant groups are thought to look. Neither sex is considered to be in uniform. The regularities of their social behavior are not seen as organized, so their conflict looks more chaotic than ordered. The battle of the sexes, MacKinnon argues, simply does not look the way a war is supposed to look (MacKinnon 2006, 261). Nevertheless, talking about the war against women did not seem as a metaphor during the 1990s, as Halley’s text clearly demonstrates. Nor was it a pure rhetorical stance coming from the external critique that Engle was discussing in her text from 1992. On the contrary, Engle’s division on doctrinalist, institutionalist and external critique was a yesteryear story; those with external approach became part of the mainstream, whereas positivists - those who believed that international law was authoritative and that states were bound by it - were pushed on the margins of legal decision-making. In another words, those who considered that the victims of international crimes should be granted some amount of autonomy have been muted by the ones for whom the war-time sexual crime was part of a generic violence against women. But how was it possible that this feminist universalism took over the territory of international feminist jurisprudence? There are several reasons that are crucial here, but before I engage myself into a broader picture, I will start with Puren and Young’s theory of “signifying justice” (Puren and Young 1999) and try to see how it could be applied to the radical and liberal feminist jurisprudence as well as the 1990s feminist legal universalism. As Puren and Young argue in their text Signifying Justice: Law, Culture and the Questions of Feminism, the questions asked by feminism have been associated socially and historically with the question of justice. A fundamental concern in these questions has been the oppression of women: the injury that is suffered under a hierarchical economy of sexual difference. When addressed to law, the questions of feminism have run along two lines, 36 Puren and Young argue. Feminism’s demand for justice is well-known, a justice that would address gender oppression, that might issue from the institutions of law, through legislative change, through the creation of new legal procedures, through the law’s redress of substantive harms and inequalities. But feminism also makes a demand of justice, and this demand is one which precedes the law. The question of the justice which is prior to law – which some might call an ethical question – erupts within law, always returning in the form of injury or trauma. Since the hierarchical economy of sexual difference is predicated upon the oppression of women, gender is always already marked by injury, Puren and Young argue. Law is continually harried by this question of justice; it might not (want to) respond, but the question does not go away. It is continually repeated, ensuring that the repertoire of images in law expands, re-forms, circles, and relocates. According to Puren and Young, feminism has been marked by the tension of keeping in play both its demand for justice and its demand of justice. The substantive exigencies of the demand for justice easily lead to an overlooking of the demand that precedes the law. Reformism, activism and mobilization for change are immediate responses which can address the problem of gender oppression. On the other hand, the demand of justice is a strategy that continually exceeds and yet erupts in law. As a strategy, Puren and Young argue, it addresses a central importance of culture in relating feminism to law. That is, in the relationship between the feminism, law and justice, culture links each to the other. As both of them argue, culture here is to be understood, not as an empirical collection of images, but as a process, or regime of imagination, through which events come to have meaning as texts. Thus the force of law is understood as signifying or textual force (Puren and Young 1999, 3). 37 Prior to the 1990s, the radical feminist demand for justice simply had to be external: in the world consisting of contained systems that cultivated the ideology of Charter liberalism, as Simpson argued, the real field of contestation for radical feminism was to be found within the borders of the West, namely in relation to the liberal feminists whose internal approach to the structure was seen as truly problematic from the point of view of radicals.22 Nevertheless, it was precisely their internal approach that was keeping the radicals from entering the structure and giving the meaning to their externality: if the radicals were to enter the structure, how could they possibly continue arguing for the theory of totalizing oppression of women? Or even better, if liberals were to embrace such theory, how could they argue for the opportunity to develop independent selves? If one is internal to the structure, can one deny women every possibility of self-agency and at the same time actively practice the law? Prior to the 1990s, the boundaries between internal and external liberal and radical - feminist jurisprudence within the Western hemisphere were as sharp as the boundaries between East and West within the Cold War paradigmatic constellation. This can probably explain the radical feminist inclination toward the communist East as well as the fact that they often times wrote the pieces which celebrated the benefits women were seen to receive under communism; indeed, from the perspective of many Western radical feminists during the 1970s and 1980s, access to universal free education, abortion, health and welfare as well as guaranteed employment and maternity leave throughout the region 22 As Engle argues in her text International Human Rights and Feminism: When Discourses Meet, in contrast to other advocates, external critics were concerned less with showing that some right exists in positive law or that some institution has the responsibility to protect women's rights, and more with challenging the entire human rights system – law makers, law enforcers, and advocates – to „wake up“ and accommodate the reality of women's lives (Engle 1992, 576). 38 certainly seemed impressive to a certain extent (Nixon 2001, 211).23 Accordingly, radicals used to believe that the problems with patriarchy were to be partially blamed on those who, by the reasons of their false consciousness, perpetuated the male domination by complying with the stories about autonomy and self-agency. As MacKinnon has implicitly pointed out, “[w]hatever women’s selfhood will look like after male domination ends, it won’t be liberal” (cited in Ward 1994-1995, 886). Hence, such external approach to the structure has not been marked by the tension of keeping in play both its demand for justice and its demand of justice: by acquiring a very explicit meta-position, it was constantly pre-existing the law and it treated the law as a utopian momentum not-yet-ready to be grasped at. Radicals may have been external to the structure, but they were certainly labeled with a signature of justice. They were slowly becoming-justice themselves.24 With the conflicts accompanying the disintegration of the former Yugoslavia at the beginning of the 1990s, this ethical machinery was about to erupt in law. To understand such a profound change, one has to search for the answers within a broader trend that has been developed towards transgressing sovereignty in the post-Cold War international law. As Tesón has argued, new times call for a fresh conceptual and ethical language. A more liberal world needs a more liberal theory of international law. This robust defense of a strong liberal anti-pluralism, as Simpson characterized Tesón’s standpoint, meant an explicit rejection of the statism inherent in Charter liberalism and specific for the Cold War. Hence, the post-Cold War period and its anti-statist paradigm opened up the space for various interventions coming from the human rights movements, particularly the women’s human rights 23 As Shibles argues in her Radical Feminism, Humanism and Women's Studies, anti-capitalism and pro-marxism or socialism were among the basic themes of radicals feminists throughout the 1970s and 80s (Shibles 1989, 35). 24 An allusion to Deleuze and Guattari's concept of Becoming-Animal (Deleuze and Guattari 2009). 39 movement(s) whose roots can be traced back to the 1979 Women’s Convention, but were facilitated in this new period by a broader agenda for “gender mainstreaming” and its transnational aims.25 Adopted as official UN policy within a year of the Beijing conference mandate in 1995, gender mainstreaming has gone global, often bypassing its feminist origins. As Radcliffe et al. argue, mainstreaming gender has become established institutionally through national bodies that, in neo-liberal terms, attempted to provide guidelines on women’s incorporation into the market and new forms of citizenship, thus establishing a basis for “adjustment with a human face” (Radcliffe et al. 2003, 398). For the UN Development Program, a gender mainstreaming policy meant taking account of gender concerns in policy, programs, administrative and financial activities and organizational procedures. Although gender mainstreaming attempted to ensure that gender issues were considered across all sectors of the state and NGOs, “men” tended to remain “unmarked”, so gender was reduced to “women” and in turn unmarked by ethnicity, race and nation (Radcliffe et al. 2003, 398). But if “women” remains unproblematized, as Butler argues in her Disorderly Woman, “it functions no differently than the epistemologically imperialist ‘subject’; the category legislates under the sign of ‘the universal’ its various parochialisms, thereby effecting an exclusion of cultural difference in the very articulation of an ostensibly transcultural commonality” (Butler 1991, 88). The feminist legal universalism organized over the course of 1990s used the category of women as the one that was already marked by injury: in their reactions to the sexual violence perpetrated against women on the territory of former Yugoslavia, women were 25 In their text The Transnationalization of Gender and Reimagining Andean Indigenous Development, Radcliffe et al. argue that their definition of transnationalism owes much to feminist work on globalization, which stresses the complex topographies of political-economic-social and cultural transformations at interconnected scales (the body, the national, and international) that comprise „globalization“ (Radcliffe et al. 2003, 389). 40 seen as already victims, as already rapable, as already raped. The demand of justice that has been continually addressed by radical feminism since the 1970s and 1980s - men as perpetrators, men as capable of raping, men as rapers – erupted in law with no intention of overlooking its crucial structuralist worldview. As Puren and Young argue, law has been continually harried by this demand, but prior to the 1990s, it simply did not want to respond; after all, why responding to such demand, if Charter liberalism was the only possible solution to the Cold War period? Who cares about women if women’s human rights do not serve as a catalyst for Western civilizational solidarity? When during the 1990s standards of civilization, culture and democracy became criteria for membership of the international community, the question of structural oppression of women became important part of international law agenda,26 whereas the extensive rapes perpetrated against women in the War in the former Yugoslavia became a particular “real world” case whose facts revealing the structural oppression of women could be gathered by the international feminist lawyers. As stated at American Association of Law Schools Annual Meeting in 2010, the case of extensive rapes in the Yugoslav War served as an opportunity to test the theory of human rights in the crucible of real world cases.27 Nevertheless, keeping in play both their demand for justice and their demand of justice announced some difficulties for the feminists: since women are not states, as MacKinnon has argued, and international law has states as its basic constituent entities, on behalf of whom will they be intervening? As already mentioned, if the radicals were to enter such structure, how could they possibly argue for the theory of totalizing oppression of 26 Similar phenomenon can be traced in the case of gay movement. As Haritaworn et al. argue in their text Gay Imperialism: Gender and Sexuality Discourse in the ‘War on Terror’, the amnesia at the basis of the sudden assertion of a European tradition of anti-homophobic and anti-sexist core values is less a reflection of progressive gender relations than of regressive race relations and growing Islamophobia (Haritaworn et al. 2008, 72). 27 Liza Velazquez to speak on Kadic v. Karadzic Pro Bono Victory, January 7, 2010. <http://www.paulweiss.com/resources/news/detail.aspx?news=2070> 41 women? Nevertheless, they did manage to enter and subsequently argue for their theory; what would have been unintelligible prior to the 1990s, it has been made into strategic move in the early 1990s and eventually erupted in law in the form of “choosing a side in the war” or “naming the aggressor’s and the victim’s ethnicity”, namely as something that would become known as rape-as-genocide. In the new feminist structural and universalist view, the rape was directed toward women because they were Muslim or Croatian and perpetrated against them exclusively by Serbian men. What exactly are we dealing here with? In her text Feminism, Imperialism and the Mission of International Law, Anne Orford explores the extent to which feminist legal universalism is haunted by the shades of those nineteenth-century European feminists whose role in facilitating the empire was similar to the nowadays feminist sustainment of the liberal anti-pluralism the purpose of which is the promotion of international law and women’s human rights.28 This feminist humanitarian mission presupposes that women from “highly industrialized countries” can gain access to female “native informants” and produce knowledge about victimized women of the Third World. The feminist international legal theory that departs from this role is criticized as unrelated to the real world, insufficiently related to particular cases or unable to deal with the facts on the ground. In this version of the appropriate disciplinary role of feminist theory, as Orford is arguing, the suffering of the Third World Woman becomes the object of knowledge of First World International Lawyers. Feminists, in other words, can take their place as part of a set of human sciences busy establishing the “native” as a self-consolidating other (Orford 2002, 279). This is a direction that may at first glance appear a helpful 28 In her text Liberal Internationalism, Feminism, and the Suppression of Critique: Contemporary Approaches to Global Order in the United States, Engle discusses the Bush administration and the way liberal internationalist discourse and even liberal and radical feminist discourse have been effectively captured by the right. With regard to the Afghanistan War, feminist inclination toward transgression of sovereignty has been, therefore, explicit and continual (Engle 2005a). 42 response to the discovery that the silence of women is one of the foundations of international law. Nevertheless, responding to the silencing of women by simply representing how suffering of the Third World Women is supposed to look like is never a useful respond. Even when initiated with “good intentions”, such a reconstruction work undertaken on the bodies of a specific group of women that are made into the subject of a reconfigured, decolonized Law simply cannot succeed. As Spivak says, “[n]o perspective critical of imperialism can turn the other into a self, because the project of imperialism has always already historically refracted what might have been an incommensurable, discontinuous other into a domesticated other that consolidated the imperialist self” (cited in Orford 2002, 279). What is worse, as Puren and Young argue, in the relationship between the feminism, law and justice, it is the culture that links each to the other; thus the domestication of an incommensurable and discontinuous other happens through the process of (mono)culturalization.29 That in this new feminist structural and universalist view the rape has been directed toward women because they were Muslim (or Croatian) and perpetrated against them exclusively by Serbian men, was the direct effect of a signifying force of law that was consolidating the feminist subjects and their theoretical aspirations by “speaking for” or “representing” the suffering other. In this sense, the former Yugoslavia became a metonymy of the structuralist understanding of women’s oppression under male supremacy. As 29 The term has been used in the text Culturalization of Citizenship in the Netherlands by Tonkens, Hurenkamp, and Duyvendak. In the article, the authors argue that culture has to be taken seriously since - as the example of the Netherlands shows - it has become a hindrance to integration of minorities, not because of its multicultural but due to its monocultural character. In particular, authors argue, some forms of the (mono)culturalization of citizenship risk to reinforce social polarization. The problem of (mono)culturalization will be discussed in further detail in Chapter 2 and Chapter 3 (Tonkens et al. 2008). <http://www.assr.nl/conferences/documents/StaffsempaperTonkens41108.pdf> 43 MacKinnon has argued in one of the most influential feminist texts written after the dissolution of the Cold War, “[i]n this war, the fact of Serbian aggression is beyond question, just as the fact of male aggression against women is beyond question, both here and in everyday life” (MacKinnon 1994, 186). If anybody wished to experience the way radical theory works in practice, the territory of former Yugoslavia was the place to look toward: a place where patriarchy rules, men rape, and women suffer; a big raping stage inhabited by male monsters that made a groundbraking plan to exterminate women with their genitals; a playground for animals with brains, a residence for human animals who think with their penises. A place where the penises literally have brains. As a condensed universum of radical theory turned into practice, Yugoslavia became example of the universal, but hyperintensified male supremacy: this is how the male supremacy looks like when placed outside the Western civilization, as if feminists were telling us. It is generic, it does happen everywhere, but Yugoslavia offers us a chance to see it in the fast-motion. In this sense, “Serbia(ns)” equals “men” and “Bosnia(ns)” equals “women”, but when stepping outside the West, one can actually see - it is visible, it is factual, it is real - how this fascinating phenomenon of becoming-rape-machine30 is played upon women. Rape-as-genocide was a movie spectacle that no international law agenda should have missed. Presented in the fastmotion, this movie about the generic war against women gave something to everybody and finally acknowledged the reappearance of genocide on the European soil. This “feminist legal genocidalism”,31 as I will re-name something that so far in the thesis has been known as 30 See supra note 24. I will use the term proposed by Aleksandar Jokic in his text Genocidalism where he talks about the genocidal use of “genocide”, defined stipulatively as the energetic attributions of genocide in less than clear cases without considering available and convincing opposing evidence and argumentation. Genocidalism is a widespread phenomenon regarding the discourse on international affairs in the advanced, liberal societies of the West, embedding a “normative divide” between the ways of attending to domestic (national) concerns and ways of attending to international issues (Jokic 2003). 31 44 feminist legal universalism, was about to launch its discourse into the world of international law. 45 CHAPTER 2. - Entering the logic of law: searching for reasons behind the feminist attachment to genocide In my previous chapter, I have shown that implementing the feminist structural and universalist worldview into (or making it internal to) the international law can be accomplished only through the use of metonymical and self-consolidating other. In this way, the feminist demand of justice is very much sustaining the Western imperative for transgression of sovereignty that is founded upon the idea of subversion and justice, but is itself inherently violent. As something that precedes the law both in its temporal and nonrelational immanent sense, the feminist demand of justice has been troubling the law, but never succeeded to actually interact with it prior to the 1990s. Then suddenly and smoothly, the international law opened itself up to the feminist demands; it did not really embrace their worldview, but it was certainly ready to listen. The feminists, on the other hand, were ready to cooperate, no matter what the circumstances. In reacting legally to the sexual violence perpetrated against women on the territory of former Yugoslavia, they invented the rape-as-genocide model according to which the rape has been directed toward women because they were Muslim or Croatian and perpetrated against them exclusively by Serbian men. This model has been the product of keeping in play both the feminist demand for and of justice; as such, it has been the product of one dialogue - the feminist dialogue with international law. In this chapter, I would like to “cut to the chase” of the rape-as-genocide model and discuss its compliance with the nowadays international law. In other words, I want to explore the ways in which the rape-as-genocide model is not a reflection of reality, as feminist legal genocidalism was claiming, but a mere reflection of the self-consolidating 46 feminist legal conformism that is serving a thousand little goals of one big and structurally violent system. In this chapter, therefore, I am entering the law and exploring the ways in which various feminist regimes of imagination have been implemented in the law for the sake of keeping in play both the feminist demand of and feminist demand for justice. The initial discussion will be around the concepts of “validity” and “persuasiveness” proposed by David Kennedy, as they offer a somewhat broader and indispensable theoretical framework for understanding the feminist usage of international law. 2.1 Validity and persuasiveness of law In his book Of Law and War, Kennedy discusses the increasing continuity between war and peace, on the one hand, and the continued rhetorical assertion of their distinctiveness, on the other – to understand what makes the wars of our time and place unique (Kennedy 2006). As Kennedy argues, it has become routine to observe the omnipresence of law in both our peacetime culture and in the war. The result has knit war and peace themselves ever close together and made out of warfare a modern legal institution. At the same time, as law has increasingly become the vocabulary for international politics and diplomacy, it has become the rhetoric through which we debate – and assert – the boundaries of warfare, and insist upon the distinction between war and peace or civilian and combatant. Law has built practical as well as the rhetorical bridges between war and peace, and is the stuff of their connection and differentiation. As my previous chapter tried to show in a somewhat different register, a legal institutional process and doctrinal vocabulary for this broad legitimacy of warfare and military tactics had begun to be developed by the start of the 47 twentieth century ,32 but it would only catch on after 1945 with the establishment of the UN when more anti-formal and flexible ideas about law joined hands with a more professional and bureaucratic idea about warfare to make the interrelationship between law and war more pronounced. As Kennedy points out, by the end of the Cold War the international order has been dramatically transformed. The emergence of a global economic and commercial order has amplified the role of background legal regulations and became the strategic terrain for transnational activities of all sorts, such as gender mainstreaming and warfare.33 Sharp boundaries between the political and institutional cultures of the First, Second and Third worlds have dissolved, heightening the significance of the shared legal language of the world’s professional and expert elite, namely lawyers, economists, businessmen, academics, journalists, and the like. In the years after the fall of the Berlin Wall, the humanitarian institutions and professions that call themselves “civil society” quickly became prominent players on the world stage, strengthening the importance of their humanitarian and human rights vocabulary for global political and legal debate. The legacy of successful – and decidedly unsuccessful – partnerships between global humanitarian, diplomatic, and military actors over the last two decades has complicated all of their relationships to an increasingly shared legal vocabulary. As Kennedy argues, although the world’s surface remains organized in territorial nation-states, each, at least in name, absolutely sovereign, the international political system today is a far more complex multilevel game than the rows of equivalent national flags arrayed at UN headquarters would suggest. States and their governments differ dramatically in powers, resources, and independence. There is something audacious 32 See the League of Nations and the debates revolving around the Simpson's model of two liberalisms, Chapter 1, Part 1.1. 33 See supra note 28 on the connection between the gender mainstreaming and warfare. 48 and terribly misleading, Kennedy argues, about calling them all states and respecting their nominal leaders as “sovereigns”. Even in the most powerful and well-integrated state, power today lies in the capillaries of social and economic life. Governments are no longer – if they ever were – the only or the predominant political actors. Vast networks of citizens, commercial interests, civil organizations, and public officials determine much of what any government, or any president, is able to say or do (Kennedy 2006, 10-14). At the same time, the modern law in war represents a transformation in our sense for what it means to say that something is or is not legal. The classical period - or the period between 1815 and 1919 - favored a professional tendency to think of the legal system as a neutral and external framework for policing the boundaries between legitimate and illegitimate uses of force.34 As Kennedy emphasizes, when legal elites think in this classical register – as they often certainly do – they place the emphasis on the validity of norms. That means that something is legal if it complies with a valid norm. A norm is valid if it was promulgated by the appropriate authority using the authorized legal procedure or if it can be deduced from first principles by recognized professional canons of deduction and interpretation. If the norm is valid, it should simply be followed. As Kennedy argues, in the world of validity, the law is the law and you should follow it because it is valid. However, this idea makes a lot of intuitive sense in a vertical national legal order where there is a court and a police force in the background determining which norms are valid and whether these 34 What is characteristic for this classical period is a sharp legal distinction between war and peace. Each was now a legal status, separated by a declaration, and as a result, the classical jurist paid a great deal of attention to the boundaries between the spheres. Combatants and noncombatants, neutrals and belligerents had different bundles of legal rights and privileges. The battlefield, the territory of belligerency, was legally demarcated. The legal treatises of the period began to place the law of peace and the law of wars in separate volumes. In part, these distinctions aimed to limit the carnage of war by expanding the privileges of civilians and limiting the military privilege to kill. These humanitarian limitations on war were thus part of a broader reorganization of legal thought, sharpening the distinction between the public and the private sphere, hardening private rights and limiting public powers to their respective spheres (Kennedy 2006, 63-66). 49 norms can be enforced. Similarly, it also makes sense in the traditional view of international order that suggests a dual paradigm for the ordering of individuals - one domestic, the other international - that corresponds to the Simpson’s concept of Charter liberalism. However, in the post-Cold War horizontal international legal order where the international norms are being enforced through the decentralized process, the idea of validity makes less sense. In such a “court of public opinion” (Kennedy 2006, 91) or “fantasy government”, 35 as Kennedy calls it, there is no authoritative determiner of the norms and interpretations that are, in fact, valid. That may not be so much of a problem if the rules are clear or where elites agree about what they mean, but once we start foregrounding broad standards like “proportional” or “necessary”36 about which diverse participants in the global political process will disagree, that will be much more complicated. As a result, an alternative way of thinking about the status and enforceability of norms has been developed, and this one emphasizes the persuasiveness, rather than the validity of norms. In this way of thinking, one should follow the norms because one is 35 In his text The International Human Rights Movement: Part of the Problem?, Kennedy discusses how the human rights movement strengthens bad international governance: “[i]nternational governance is often asked to do globally what we fantasize or expect national governments to do locally - allocate stakes, constitute a community, articulate differences and similarities, provide for the common good. The human rights movement, by strengthening the habit of understanding international governance in legal rather than political terms, weakens its ability to perform what we understand domestically to be these political functions. The conflation of the law with the good encourages an understanding of international governance - by those within and without its institutions – which is systematically blind to the bad consequences of its own action” (Kennedy 2002, 122-123). 36 “But it is extremely difficult to see how one might, in fact, weigh and balance civilian deaths against military objectives. The idea of proportionality – or necessity – encourages a kind of strategy, and ethic, by metaphor: the metaphor of weighting and balancing. I have learned that if you ask a military professional precisely how many civilians you can kill to offset how much risk to one of your own men, you won't receive a straight answer. When the Senegalese asked us, we'd say, 'It's a judgment call'. Indeed, at least so far I have been able to ascertain, there is no background exchange rate for civilian life. What you find instead are rules kicking the decision up the chain of command as the number of civilians increases, until the decision moves offstage from military professionals to politicians. Rules transforming weighing and balancing effects into attribution of responsibility“ (Kennedy 2006, 143-144). 50 persuaded one should. As Kennedy argues, ”[y]ou might be persuaded because you believe the norm is valid and think you should follow the valid rules. But you might also be persuaded because you think the rule is wise or ethically compelling. Or because you think it encapsulates best practice. Or because you fear the consequences of not following it. Or for some other reason” (Kennedy 2006, 92). Be that as it may, once elites started thinking about international norms in this way, it was a short step to the idea that a norm was valid law only if it turned out to have been persuasive to relevant political constituencies. Moreover, whether a norm is or is not legal is a function not of its origin or pedigree, but of its effects. Law has an effect when it persuades an audience with political clout that something someone else did, or plans to do, is or is not legitimate. Nevertheless, Kennedy argues, an effort to persuade can be either enhanced, or undermined, by the presentation of the restatement in the rhetoric of validity. If the rules can be shown to be invalid, their persuasiveness may crumble. If presented as ethical standards or as pragmatic methods to achieve a common objective, they may well be more persuasive – though never to an audience that is fully fixated on whether or not the rules are actually valid. The fact that the modern law in war is expressed in the keys of both validity and persuasiveness makes the professional use of its vocabulary by both humanitarian and military professionals a complex challenge. During the early 1990s, the issue how to approach the rapes in the former Yugoslavia agitated feminists throughout the world. Many turned to the international arena and sought diplomatic, if not military, intervention to bring an end to the large-scale rapes in the region and to promptly inform the general public on what was going on in this war. However, once the decision was made to establish the ICTY, the space for feminist legal interventions - or what is called here “demanding for justice” - suddenly opened up in all its vastness and 51 appealing uncertainty. As discussed in the previous chapter, keeping in play both their demand for justice and their demand of justice announced some difficulties for the feminists: since women are not states, as MacKinnon has argued, and international law has states as its basic constituent entities, on behalf of whom will they be intervening? If women were raped on all sides of the war and the feminist goal was to stop all rapes, then how could one choose sides in the conflict? Some feminists did choose a side, seeing the rape by Serbian men as genocidal and therefore attaching some sort of exclusive feature to it. Others disagreed, arguing that such a position would deny the extent to which women were always harmed in war, and were specifically harmed on all sides of the conflict in the former Yugoslavia. As Engle argues in her excellent Feminism and Its Dis(contents): Criminalizing Wartime Rape in Bosnia and Herzegovina, such a position did not deny that rapes were hideous; far from it, those who expressed this view often argued that rapes on all sides might be considered genocidal as well, but because of their effect on women as a group, and not on Bosnian Muslim (and to a certain extent Croatian) women in particular. The divide then seemed to be over whether large-scale rape in any circumstances is genocidal or whether, at least in the former Yugoslavia, genocide could be properly considered to have taken place only on one side (Engle 2005, 785-787). Whereas the later position has already been labeled as feminist legal genocidalism, the later one has been specific to the former Yugoslavian feminists regardless of their Serbian, Croatian or Bosnian Muslim origins. In my paper I name it the “ex-Yugoslavian strategic radicalism”.37 But how valid and persuasive both of these standpoints were and how well the feminists kept in play both their demands for and of justice? Let us first start with the validity feature in order to see what exactly the 37 The meaning of strategic will be explained later on in the text. For the moment, it is important to keep in mind that the ex-Yugoslavian strategic radicalism placed priority on gender, instead of ethnicity component. 52 international law offered to feminists and what each of these feminist camps, as Engle calls them, could offer to the law. 2.2 Validity and persuasiveness of two feminist camps The jurisdiction of the ad hoc Tribunals includes “grave breaches” of the Geneva Conventions,38 crimes against humanity and genocide. The 1993 Report of the SecretaryGeneral recommending the establishment of the ICTY emphasized that the Tribunal should apply those rules of international humanitarian law (IHL) 39 which are beyond doubt part of customary law so that the problem of adherence of some, but not all states to specific conventions does not arise. He concluded that the Geneva Conventions of 1949, the Hague Convention (IV), the Genocide Convention and the Nuremberg Charter were without doubt customary international law.40 To what extent then the IHL covers rape and other violent acts against women? As Charlesworth and Chinkin argue, despite the long history of rape and sexual assault against women during armed conflicts, and evidence offered to tribunals of such offences, they had not figured prominently in either the legal restraints on warfare or directly in judgments of war crime trials. There has long been an understanding of the illegality of violent attacks on non-combatant women; indeed, rape was included in the first recorded war crimes trial in 1474 (Charlesworth and Chinkin 2000). Nevertheless, the first Geneva Convention in 1864 was benefiting those who became hors de combat through the 38 The Geneva Conventions and their Additional Protocols are the principle instruments of IHL and they are often called “the core of international humanitarian law”. 39 Known also as the “law of war” or the “law of armed conflict”. Since grave breaches of the Geneva Conventions are regarded as the most serious violations of IHL, these two concepts – grave breaches of the Geneva Conventions and the IHL - are referring to the same head of jurisdiction applicable to the sexual violence in armed conflict. In this sense, the IHL should be considered an “umbrella term”. 40 A rule is customary if it reflects state practice and when there exists a conviction in the international community that such practice is required as a matter of law. While treaties only bind those States which have ratified them, customary law norms are binding on all States. 53 injury or capture, namely the members of the fighting forces who were invariably men. It was not until 1949 that explicit reference was made to rape and sexual assault in the Fourth Geneva Convention – the first Convention directed at the protection of civilians. However, the obligations were limited: states parties are under an obligation to protect women in international armed conflict “against any attack on their honor, in particular against rape, enforced prostitution, or any form of indecent assault”.41 This provision does not explicitly prohibit the listed offences, but instead presents women as needing protection. It also creates dichotomy between warrior as protector and the woman as the protected, making the use of force seems justified. By designating rape as crime against honor rather than one of violence, as Charlesworth and Chinkin argue, the provision presents women as both male and family property.42 Grave breaches of the Geneva Conventions are made subject to universal jurisdiction exercisable in national courts and thus are regarded as the most serious violations of IHL. However, rape and sexual assault are not explicitly designated grave breaches, but since the category of grave breaches is defined to include acts “willfully causing great suffering or serious injury to body or health”,43 it has been argued that sexual violence falls within this definition (of course, specific inclusion would have foreclosed contrary argument). 41 Fourth Geneva Convention, article 27. <www.icrc.org> For a discussion on these and other articles relevant to the protection of women see Y. Khushalani, Dignity and Honor of Women as Basic and Fundamental Human Rights (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1982): Chapter 5; F. Krill, “The protection of women in international humanitarian law,” in International Review of the Red Cross 249 (November-December 1985): 337. 42 In 1977 two Protocols were adopted to update the Geneva Conventions. Protocol I does not refer to the notion of women's honor, but women continue to be portrayed as the objects of special respect and protection (Protocol I, article 76 states that: “Women shall be the object of special respect and shall be protected in particular against rape, forced prostitution, and any other form of indecent assault.”). Protocol II, article 4(2)(e), applicable in non-international armed conflicts, omits the language of protection and simply prohibits outrages upon personal dignity, in particular humiliating and degrading treatment, rape, enforced prostitution and any form of indecent assault” (cited in Charlesworth and Chinkin 2000, 315). 43 Fourth Geneva Convention, article 147; Statute of the ICTY, article 2(c). <www.icty.org/sections/LegalLibrary/StatuteoftheTribunal> 54 Furthermore, although non-grave breaches may nevertheless constitute war crimes, the legal distinction between grave and other breaches may lead to the latter being perceived as less significant and as not meriting enforcement. The ICC Statute provides that the category of war crimes means grave breaches of the Geneva Conventions and “other serious violations of the laws and customs applicable in international armed conflict”. 44 The definition of “other serious violations” includes the commission of rape, sexual slavery, enforced prostitution, forced pregnancy and enforced sterilization, but adds that “any other form of sexual violence [may also constitute] a grave breach of the Geneva Conventions”.45 As Charlesworth and Chinkin argue, this supports an interpretation of specified grave breaches such as torture or inhuman treatment, willfully causing great suffering, serious injury and unlawful confinement, as including sexual violence. On the other hand, under the Fourth Geneva Convention, the only persons against whom a grave breach can be committed are those who are “in the hands of a Party to the conflict or Occupying Power of which they are not nationals”.46 In the first trial before the ICTY, the Tadic case, the limitations of this defining category were made apparent. In the conflict in Bosnia-Herzegovina, there was no Party to the conflict or Occupying Power of a different nationality to the Bosnian Muslim civilian victims, unless the Bosnian Serbs could be considered as agents of the government of the Federal Republic of Yugoslavia or the Republic of Srpska could be considered a state. Although Tadic was initially acquitted of grave breaches of the Geneva Conventions, the Appeals Chamber reversed this ruling in July 1999 and made a final step toward officially recognizing the Republic of Srpska as a 44 Rome Statute for the ICC, article 8(2)(a) and (b) (cited in Charlesworth and Chinkin 2000, 316). Ibid., article 8(2)(b) and (s). 46 Fourth Geneva Convention, article 4. <www.icrc.org> 45 55 sovereign state.47 From the very beginning of the war, the feminist legal genocidalism was sustaining this official recognition that would eventually facilitate the feminist legal performance: feminists needed one paramilitary fraction of Bosnia and Herzegovina to be a sovereign state inasmuch as they needed international war to be able to facilitate their legal action. Accordingly, they also needed the recognition of distinct nationalities, insofar as without distinct nationalities there is no validity.48 And if the rules of evidence are shown to be invalid, all their persuasiveness would most probably crumble. Nevertheless, relying only on grave breaches of IHL and its focus on civilian population does not place much importance on feminism itself. Since there is no emphasis on gender within the term “civilian” - except as an implicit reference to the female civilian victims - feminists from both clans needed something else to make their standpoint both visible and persuasive. Another possible head of jurisdiction applicable to sexual violence in armed conflict is that of crimes against humanity. Crimes against humanity were defined in the Nuremberg Charter as: 47 In a motion filed with the Tribunal's Trial Chamber in June 1999, Tadic challenged the authority of the Tribunal. One of the grounds on which Tadic challenged the authority was his claim that the Tribunal may only adjudicate war crimes committed in the context of interstate conflicts and that it lacks authority to adjudicate offences committed in the course of civil wars. Claiming that the conflict in Bosnia-Herzegovina, where his alleged crimes occurred, is a civil war, Tadic maintained that the Tribunal could not proceed against him. However, the Appeals Chamber rejected this assertion. Noting that the conflict raging in the former Yugoslavia since 1991 has had both internal and international aspects, the Chamber declined to determine the nature of the conflict at the time and place of Tadic's alleged crimes. Rather, the Chamber concluded that regardless of the type of conflict in which they were committed, it has the authority to adjudicate Tadic's alleged offences which included murder, rape, and torture <http://www.icty.org/sid/7227>. Once again, the international law proved how flexible it is, although by finally recognizing the Republic of Srpska as a sovereign state, it acknowledged the value of “playing it safe”. 48 In her text Rape, Genocide, and Women's Human Rights, MacKinnon says the following thing: „The war against Croatia and Bosnia-Herzegovina, and their partial occupation, is being carried out by Serbian forces in collaboration with the Serbian regime in Belgrade, governing what remains of Yugoslavia. This is an international war. All the state parties have adopted relevant laws of nations that prohibit these acts; they are covered in any case by customary international law and jus cogens“ (MacKinnon 1994, 186). Also, for a discussion on similar matter, see Theodore Meron, “Rape as a Crime under International Humanitarian Law,” in American Journal of International Law 87 (1993): 424-428. 56 Murder, extermination, enslavement, deportation, and other inhuman acts committed against any civilian population before or during the war, or persecutions on political, racial, or religious grounds in execution of or in connection with any crime within the jurisdiction of the Tribunal whether or not in violation of the domestic law of the country where perpetrated.49 The four occupying powers in Germany included rape as a crime against humanity in Control Council Law No. 10,50 but only as constituting part of “other inhuman acts”, thus not deserving its own name as a crime against humanity. The ICTY Statute under Article 5(g), however, specifically includes „rape“ (along with „murder“, „extermination“, „enslavement“, „deportation“, „imprisonment“, „torture“, „persecution on political, racial and religious grounds“ and „other inhumane acts“) as such crimes.51 Vertically,52 as Halley argues in her text Rape at Rome: Feminist Interventions in the Criminalization of Sex-Related Violence in Positive International Criminal Law, the effect of this new legislation is to classify rape as a crime which is a crime against humanity when committed in armed conflict, meaning on the systematic or widespread level. Horizontally, these new rules relieve rape of its retro dignity and honor baggage, and repackage it, in abstracto at least, as a freestanding crime of the same gravity as murder, extermination, enslavement, etc. Rape as rape has entered the pantheon of international humanitarian crimes, but with the proviso that it is punishable only when it is the predicate crime of a crime against humanity (Halley 2009, 6768). Nevertheless, in its consideration of persecution as a crime against humanity, the International Criminal Law (ICL) noted that gender-based persecution could be so designated 49 Charter Annexed to the Agreement for the Establishment of an International Military Tribunal, article 6(c) (cited in Charlesworth and Chinkin 2000, 319). 50 Control Council for Germany, Official Gazette, 31 January 1946 at 50 (cited in T. Meron, see supra note 48). 51 Statute of the ICTY, article 5(g) <www.icty.org/sections/LegalLibrary/StatuteoftheTribunal> 52 The sources of law have both vertical and horizontal dimensions. If rape as a crime against humanity is included only as a constituting part of other inhuman acts, than we can say that, vertically, the crime of rape is not recognized as such, as it does not deserve its own name within the list of crimes against humanity. 57 under article 18(e) - persecution on political, racial, religious or ethnic grounds - but decided instead “to limit the possible grounds for persecution to those contained in existing legal instruments”.53 Similarly, while sex and gender-based54 discrimination might also fall within article 18(f),55 the ICL noted that it might not necessarily amount to a “crime against the peace and security of mankind”56 and again declined to extend the prohibited grounds of institutionalized discrimination to include sex or gender.57 On the other hand, even though the historic association between crimes against humanity and armed conflict was continued in the ICTY Statute, the Appeal Chamber of the ICTY has affirmed that no nexus between crimes against humanity and armed conflict is required by customary international law. In Tadic, the Trial Chamber clarified the concept of crimes against humanity in a number of ways significant for trials of sexual attacks. It held that “a single act by a perpetrator taken 53 Article 18(e) (cited in Charlesworth and Chinkin 2000, 319). More than often, the legal scholars use something that should be called „biological gender“ - gender meaning sex – and has been criticized by Carpenter in her Beyond ‘Gendercide’: Incorporating Gender into Comparative Genocide Studies that will be discussed in Chapter 4. Since in my thesis I am referring to the discursive actuality, my usage of gender in the rest of the text will carry exactly the same meaning. See Chapter 4, Part 4.2 for a discussion on this problematic use of term. 55 Ibid., article 18(f): institutionalized discrimination on racial, ethnic or religious grounds involving the violation of fundamental human rights and freedoms and resulting in seriously disadvantiging a part of the population (cited in Charlesworth and Chinkin 2000, 319). 56 On the complexities of defining crimes against the peace and security of mankind separately from jurisdiction of an international criminal court, see Allain and Jones, „A patchwork of norms: a commentary on the 1996 Draft Code of Crimes against the Peace and Security of Mankind,“ in European Journal of International Law 8 (1997): 100. 57 The ICC Statute does include as a distinct crime against humanity persecution against “any identifiable group or collectivity” on a number of specified grounds including gender. However, the ICC came into being on 1 July 2002 - the date its founding treaty, the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, entered into force and it can only prosecute crimes committed on or after that date. Unlike the International Court of Justice (ICJ), the ICC is legally and functionally independent from the United Nations. However, the Rome Statute grants certain powers to the United Nations Security Council. Article 13 allows the Security Council to refer to the court situations that would not otherwise fall under the court's jurisdiction (as it did in relation to the situation in Darfur, which the court could not otherwise have prosecuted as Sudan is not a state party). Also, the court cooperates with the UN in many different areas, including the exchange of information and logistical support. The court reports to the UN each year on its activities, and some meetings of the Assembly of States Parties are held at UN facilities. The relationship between the court and the UN is governed by a “Relationship Agreement between the International Criminal Court and the United Nations”. 54 58 within the context of a widespread or systematic attack against a civilian population entails individual responsibility and an individual perpetrator need not commit numerous offences to be held liable”.58 This meant that each perpetrator of rape in the context of a mass attack can be held guilty of a crime against humanity. What about the crimes themselves? As already stated above, crimes against humanity under Article 5 of the ICTY Statute require systematic or widespread conduct and can be satisfied by either a state policy or that of non-state forces, including terrorist groups or organizations. Thus it is only where rape reaches the systematic or widespread level required for crimes against humanity that it becomes punishable as an international crime. Whereas rapes on the systematic or widespread level were well-suited for early feminist legal genocidalism, the ex-Yugoslavian strategic radicalism has been strongly supporting the thesis that the rapes in war are frequently sporadic.59 However, as Charlesworth and Chinking argue, the ICC prosecutors should avoid charging rape as a crime against humanity, as it implies that rape is harming humanity and not particularly women as a group (Halley 2009, 72). Indeed, lobbying for this particular head of jurisdiction would certainly miss the point of bringing attention to the feminist demand of justice. Hence, something else was needed; something that would accentuate the intention of destroying women as a particular group and a universe of their own, as Halley calls it. Apart from the grave breaches of the Geneva Conventions as well as crimes against humanity, genocide was the third and final possible head of jurisdiction 58 Prosecutor v. Dusko Tadic, IT-94-IT (May 7, 1997), reprinted in International Legal Martials 36 (1997): 908 (cited in Charlesworth and Chinkin 2000, 320). 59 Nikolic-Ristanovic's Women, Violence and War: Wartime Victimization of Refugees in the Balkans published in 2000 can be considered a good reference point for understanding the ex-Yugoslavian strategic radicalism. Among other things, Nikolic-Ristanovic argues that “[a]lthough the point has frequently been made that the Statute of the Hague Tribunal represents progress in the field of female rights, a more detailed analysis reveals that rape is explicitly treated as a crime against humanity (Article 5) only when it is systematic and widespread, or, in other words, when it occurs as a part of ethnic cleansing” (Nikolic-Ristanovic 2000, 79). 59 applicable to the sexual violence in armed conflict. Besides the possible validity feature of persecuting sexual crimes as genocidal crimes, such a choice would certainly persuade the audience that the war against women led on the territory of former Yugoslavia is something exceptional in our history. As Kennedy argues, “[o]ften, the trouble begins when humanitarians speaking the language of external virtue hit the problem of exceptions – what if it were Hitler, what if there were genocide, what if they were raping your mother?” (Kennedy 2006, 108). But what was the generally accepted legal definition of genocide? The generally accepted legal definition of genocide comes from the Genocide Convention: Genocide means any of the following acts committed with intent to destroy, in whole or in part, a national, ethnical, racial or religious group, as such: ï‚· Killing members of the group; ï‚· Causing serious bodily or mental harm to members of the group; ï‚· Deliberately inflicting on the group conditions of life calculated to bring about its physical destruction in whole or in part; ï‚· Imposing measures intended to prevent births within the group; ï‚· Forcibly transferring children of the group to another group. 60 As Engle argues, this definition was ultimately relied upon and accepted as governing the jurisprudence of both the ICTY and the ICTR, and most arguments for treating rape of Bosnian Muslims as genocide conform with this definition. Although this definition covers sterilization and forced termination of pregnancy, sexual violence does not appear to fall within the legal notion of genocide. Nevertheless, it has been argued that where rape has 60 Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide, article 2. <http://www.preventgenocide.org/law/convention/text.htm> 60 been carried out on a massive and systematic basis with the intent of destroying the victims’ family and community life, of cleansing an area of all other ethnicities by causing mass flight and the birth of children with the rapists’ blood, it becomes genocidal. In reviewing the indictments against the Bosnian Serbs, Radovan Karadzic and Ratko Mladic, a Trial Chamber of the ICTY invited the prosecution to broaden the scope of its characterization of genocide, suggesting that: “The systematic rape of women . . . is in some cases intended to transmit a new ethnic identity to the child. In other case humiliation and terror serve to dismember the group”.61 This characterization is further supported by the phenomenon of forced detention of women, first for impregnation and subsequently to prevent abortion. Nevertheless, this legal characterization of genocide was a decisive moment for splitting of two feminist camps: whereas the ex-Yugoslavian radical feminism realized that what was at stake under this particular head of jurisdiction was exactly “choosing a side in the war” or “naming the perpetrator”, the feminist legal genocidalism pursued with the legal persecution and decided to focus mainly on one enemy and one victim: the Bosnian Serb men and Bosnian Muslim women. After all, it was the only possible way for keeping in play both their radical feminist and legal demands. Mass Rape: the War against Women in Bosnia-Herzegovina (1994) was a solid first approach to the topic of genocidal rapes in Bosnia-Herzegovina that made its political stance very clear in Roy Gutman’s introductory text: “Rape occurs in nearly every war, but in this one it has played a unique role” (Gutman 1994, X).62 Roy Gutman, the former European correspondent for the American Newsday was covering the War in the former Yugoslavia and was the first one to expose an alleged 61 See Preliminary Statement, Kadic v. Karadzic, Civil Action No. 43, CN 1163, United States District Court, Southern District of New York; Kadic v. Karadzic 70 F. 2d 232 (1995). 62 The very title of this book - The War against Women in Bosnia-Hezegovina – is by far the best example of Yugoslavia becoming a metonymy of the structuralist understanding of women’s oppression under male supremacy. 61 network of rape camps where mostly Bosnian Muslim women have been held for days, weeks, or months and systematically raped by Bosnian Serbs. Gutman's coverage won him much international acclaim, as well as a slew of journalistic awards, including the Pulitzer Prize for International Reporting in 1993.63 What is more astonishing here, Gutman was named one of the "50 visionaries who are changing your world" by the Utne Reader in November-December 2008.64 In his introductory text to Mass Rape, Gutman makes a parallel with “a pattern of criminality that easily recalls the Third Reich: . . . [h]ow is one to explain the sudden reappearance of genocide on European soil less than half a century after the Nazi Holocaust and after three generations of Europeans and Americans have come of age accepting the motto ‘never again’?” (Gutman 1994, XII). Gutman’s use of Holocaust analogy was extremely well accepted by legal academic feminist elite. Although the book 63 Castigating the press for "journalistic crimes" committed during its reporting on the Balkans wars of the 1990s, retired New York Times reporter David Binder claims the 1993 Pulitzer Prize for International Reporting awarded to Roy Gutman "should, in all fairness and honesty, be revoked". Binder was speaking at a press conference for the release of a new book criticizing the war reporting and wrote the foreword to the book by Peter Brock, titled Media Cleansing: Dirty Reporting, Journalism and Tragedy in Yugoslavia. In his book, Brock faults Newsday's Roy Gutman for being unduly influenced by government propagandists including one source who operated under four different aliases. Gutman was criticized for not exercising enough scrutiny before repeating allegations of atrocities and statistics of the dead and tortured. Gutman won his Pulitzer partly for "electrifying stories about 'concentration camps'", notes Brock, who criticizes the reporter for the prominence of "hearsay" and "double hearsay" in his stories, as well as gratuitous use of the language of the Nazi Holocaust. Furthermore, Gutman's first five stories about the alleged Omarska concentration camp in Bosnia were actually filed from Zagreb, in Croatia, Brock complains. It was Gutman's sixth story on the subject that finally carried an Omarska dateline, Brock wrote, and that was after the prison had been shut down. Both Binder and Brock accuse the press of falling into "pack journalism" and playing the role of "co-belligerent." The reliance on Croat and Bosnian Muslim propaganda resulted in distorted reporting that exaggerated the Serb role in the three-sided conflict and ignored ethnic cleansing of Serbs, according to Binder and Brock. Brock went so far as to say the $3,000 Pulitzer Prize money awarded to Burns and Gutman was "blood money". To read more of this article, see: Sherrie Gossett, “Former NY Times Reporter: 93 Pulitzer Should Be Revoked” (March 22, 2006) <http://www.spinwatch.org/-news-by-category-mainmenu-9/157-us-politics/2734-formerny-times-reporter-93-pulitzer-should-be-revoked>. For a similar discussion, see Herman and Peterson, „The Dismantling of Yugoslavia. A Study in Humanitarian Intervention (and a Western Liberal-Left Intellectual and Moral Collapse),” in Monthly Review 59(5) (2007). 64 This is what Utne Reader says about this heroic figure: „Atrocities easily pass unseen. If people notice, it’s because someone made a ruckus loud enough to pierce media static and social malaise . . . While such work tempts despair, the men’s commitment to truth-telling remains unshaken”. <http://www.utne.com/2008-11-13/50-Visionaries-Who-Are-Changing-Your-World.aspx> 62 itself is an utter conceptual chaos – its editor Alexandra Stiglmayer gathered in it certain texts that do not comply with the theory of genocidal rapes,65 but has proudly put Gutman’s text as an introductory and thus the only one worth mentioning on the book cover - it (once again) launched into academic space possibly the two most important and influential MacKinnon’s texts over the course of the 1990s: her Turning Rape into Pornography: Postmodern Genocide66 and Rape, Genocide, and Women’s Human Rights. In her first text, one of her major arguments was that pornography, which “saturated the former Yugoslavia” (MacKinnon 1994, 77), was one of the by-products of, but more importantly, one of the causes of sexual violence in the Yugoslav War. There she had also announced her thesis upon which she elaborated more thoroughly in her second text: “[y]et the world has never seen sex used this consciously, this cynically, this elaborately, this openly, this systematically, with this degree of technological and psychological sophistication, as a means of destroying a whole people” (MacKinnon 1994, 75); according to MacKinnon, the Serbs make the Nazis efforts look comparatively primitive (MacKinnon 65 In her Mass Rape, Stiglmayer also published the texts by Susan Brownmiller who claimed that "Balkan women, whatever their ethnic and religious background, and in whatever fighting zone they happen to find themselves, have been thrust against their will into another identity. They are victims of rape in war.“ (Brownmiller 1994, 180) and by Rhonda Copelon who argued that "to emphasize as unparalleled the horror of genocidal rape is factually dubious and risks rendering rape invisible once again . . . Women are targets not simply because they 'belong to' the enemy . . . They are targets because they too are the enemy; . . . because rape embodies male domination and female subordination“ (Copelon 1994, 198-207). For MacKinnnon, on the other hand, feminists who refused to see the rapes as genocide were involved in a cover-up. Indeed, she claimed that her view was in direct response to a feminist version of the cover-up, which she saw as "useful to the perpetrators because it seems to acknowledge the atrocities - which are hard to deny (although they do that too) - and appears to occupy the ground on which women have effectively aroused outrage against them. But its function is to exonerate the rapists and to deflect intervention“ (MacKinnon 1994, 189). However, „when rape-as-genocide advocates began to make their case with regard to the former Yugoslavia, what was meant by genocide received surprisingly little explicit attention“ (Engle 2005, 788). In the beginning of the 1990s, the term was used in numerous ways and the most important thing was to publish and to be heard. Stiglmayer's Mass Rape is the best example of this initial confusion over the concept of genocidal rapes and it proves that the editor herself did not really understand what kind of ideas she is propagating in her book. 66 Turning Rape into Pornography: Postmodern Genocide was originally published in Ms. 24 (July-August, 1993). 63 1994, 80).67 MacKinnon’s second text focused completely on her rape-as-genocide concept and expressed her indignation over the fact that the rapes in the War in the former Yugoslavia are “grasped in either their ethnic or religious particularity, as attacks on culture, meaning men, or in their sex specificity, meaning as attacks on women” (MacKinnon 1994, 188). Rape-as-genocide was supposed to cover both its gender and ethnic components, but more importantly, it was expressed in the keys of both validity and persuasiveness. If these rapes were to everyday rape what the Holocaust was to everyday anti-Semitism, as MacKinnon was arguing, then something alarmingly dangerous was happening on the territory of the former Yugoslavia, something that deserved the following consideration: What if Karadžić was Hitler? What if the Republic of Srpska was new Nazi Germany?68 As Butler argues in her Precarious Life: the Power of Violence and Mourning, “[w]hen analogies are offered, they presuppose the separability of the terms that are compared. But any analogy also assumes a common ground for comparability, and in this case the analogy functions to a certain degree by functioning metonymically” (Butler 2006, 72). Accordingly, Bosnian Muslim women stood as a symbol of universal female victim just as the Jews in the 67 A sophisticated Serbian rape-machine on the territory of Yugoslavia at the beginning of the 1990s? Not very likely, as the Croatian feminist Vesna Kesic argued in her response to MacKinnon’s text published in Ms.; see Vesna Kesic, “A Response to Catherine MacKinnon’s Article”, in Hastings Women’s Law Journal 267, no. 5 (1994); see also from the same author: “Muslim Women, Croatian Women, Serbian Women, Albanian Women,” in Balkan as Metaphor. Between Globalization and Fragmentation, edited by Dusan I. Bjelic and Obrad Savic (MIT Press, 2002). 68 In the interview conducted by the Bosnian organization Women of Srebrenica, the 1992-1993 president of the UN Security Council Diego E. Arria says that back then, the other members of the Security Council considered the Serbian army as the one that had defeated Hitler in the Second World War. They also considered Serbs to be some sort of “supermen”, Arria claims, whose power was incomparably bigger than the power of UN; interview by Meliha Pihura, Esad Krcic and Belma Pekmezovic, in Bilten Srebrenice, Year 7, no. 36 (February 2006) <http://www.srebrenica.ba/?link=bilteni&b=7#br36>. Of course, throughout the whole interview, Arria blames everybody else for the failures of international community with regards to Srebrenica and the Yugoslav War in general: other Security Council members, the European Union, the UN SecretaryGeneral, etc., but this well-known tactic of shifting the blame on others is a common phenomenon in the postYugoslav War international politics. With the nowadays blurring of legal categories of perpetrators and victims, war and peace, combatants and noncombatants, international and internal, nothing is easier than to relativize certain actions taken by the UN. 64 Second World War stand as a symbol of universal and timeless experience of Jewish suffering. Not surprisingly, such a politicized vision of sexual atrocities committed on the territory of former Yugoslavia was very much opposed by the ex-Yugoslavian strategic radicalism. But why do I insist to call them strategic? In her paper on a dynamic that took place in the interplay between local women’s organizations in post-war Bosnia-Herzegovina and the Western-dominated international community of donors and officials, Elissa Helms has shown to what extent the gender discourses coming from the Western donors were frequently “nation-ed” (Helms, 2003: 1). Even when women’s organizations strived to focus only on women’s issues, donor pressures oblige them to integrate ethnic concerns - towards ethnic reconciliation and communication - into their rhetoric and activities. This can be seen readily in the case of the Bosnian Medica Zenica, a self-proclaimed antinationalist, feminist women’s NGO funded by Western and UN donors. Medica began during the war by providing medical and psychological therapy to women survivors of wartime rape and other traumas and has continued in the post-war period by aiding women survivors of domestic violence. Its public outreach section Infoteka maintained close contacts with other women’s organizations that worked on sexual violence issues, including several women’s NGOs in the Republic of Srpska, the Croatian Zagreb Women’s Lobby and Serbian's Women in Black. During and after the War in the former Yugoslavia, these important feminist organizations consciously worked at ethnic cooperation through what one activist called “strategic avoidance” (stratesko zaobilazenje) of sensitive “ethnic” topics (Helms 2003). In other words, they attempted to address ethnic divisions by playing down their importance and playing up gender in its place. This enabled the feminist organizations to build trusting, cross-ethnic working relationships of the kind that Western donors seemed to be promoting. Moreover, in the early 1990s, the ex-Yugoslavian strategic 65 radicalism developed an analysis that relied on the framework proposed by Nira Yuval-Davis and Floya Anthias,69 according to which women tend to participate in nationalist and state practices as the biological regenerators of the nation, as reproducers of the boundaries of ethnic groups, as central participants in the ideological reproduction of the collectivity and as transmitters of its culture; namely, as passive receivers of various nation-state appellative functions. In this sense, the ex-Yugoslavian feminists were strategically relying upon one theory that permitted them to refrain themselves from the nation-state principles and actively create a universe of their own. Naming such standpoint “strategic” is thus meant to accentuate exactly such feminist efforts to keep alive something that in the midst of the politics of instrumentalization of victims suddenly disappeared: a feminist ethics of care “grounded in the principles of women’s solidarity, independence and self-help“ (Batinic 2001, 8-9).70 Accordingly, the genocidal aspect of the rapes proposed by the ex-Yugoslavian strategic radicalism was such in a truly radical feminist sense: it was the patriarchal and sexist essence of the nation-state ideology that was responsible for the War in the former Yugoslavia, and its victims were primarily women.71 As such, this genocidal aspect could not and did not aim at complying with the legal definition of genocide. Its emphasis on gender (and not ethnicity) and on sporadic (and not necessarily systematic or widespread) rapes was not well suited for the ICTY whose jurisdiction includes grave breaches of the Geneva 69 Nira Yuval-Davis and Floya Anthias, Woman-Nation-State (Palgrave Macmillan: London, 1989). As Batinic argues in her text Feminism, Nationalism, and War: The ‘Yugoslav Case’ in Feminist Texts, “[i]n December 1992, several women activists from various feminist and pacifist organizations in Croatia (including the Antiwar Campaign - Croatia and Zagreb Women’s Lobby), founded the Center for Women War Victims, ‘grounded in the principles of women’s solidarity, independence and self-help’, and offered support for rape victims and refugee women regardless of their nationality“ (Batinic 2001, 8-9). 71 I certainly do not wish to imply that such a standpoint is not problematic in itself, but as it is not my primary concern in the thesis, I will leave this discussion for later in the future. 70 66 Conventions, crimes against humanity and genocide. Furthermore, this particular genocidal aspect was far from “historical opportunity” that MacKinnon saw in these rapes;72 on the contrary, it became an obstacle for those who wished to perform juridically. At the June 1993 UN Human Rights Conference in Vienna, MacKinnon going public with her hostility to Serbian feminists made the following comment in response to a question posed by Belgrade feminist Nadezda Cvetkovic : “If you are in opposition to the regime in Serbia, why aren’t you already dead?” (Batinic 2001, 11). By that time, MacKinnon had already started to cooperate closely with the second branch of Croatian feminists, the one that Batinic in her Feminism, Nationalism, and War: The ‘Yugoslav Case’ in Feminist Texts calls “patriotic”. “Patriotic” groups in Croatia and Bosnia and Herzegovina argued that “mass rapes under orders of the Serbian-occupied territories of Bosnia-Herzegovina and Croatia are part of a Serbian policy of genocide against non-Serbs. That means that non-Serbian women - most prominently Muslims and Croatians – are not only tortured by rape as are all other women, but are being raped as a part of a Serbian policy of ‘ethnic cleansing’ on the basis of their sex and ethnicity both; most of these rapes end in murder. And this is not happening to all women“ (cited in Batinic 2001, 7). Furthermore, according to Croatian patriotic feminists, all Serbian women, including feminists, are “women of the group committing genocide” and therefore, Croatian and Muslim women’s groups could not participate in the same projects with them. What is more, at the time of writing this manifesto, these patriotic branches from both Croatia and Bosnia-Herzegovina were already in the midst of preparations for their lawsuit brought by 72 MacKinnon says at the end of her manifesto Rape, Genocide, and Women's Human Rights: „The genocidal rapes of this war present the world with a historic opportunity: that this becomes the time and place, and these the women, when the world recognizes that violence against women violates human rights. That when a woman is raped, the humanity of a human being is recognized to be violated. When the world says never again – not in war, not in peace . and this time means it“ (MacKinnon 1994, 195). 67 MacKinnon and the NOW Legal Defense and Education Fund from New York.73 But let us now explore the regimes of imagination that resulted from the substantive exigencies of the feminist demand for justice, as these tend to be most intimately connected with both validity and persuasiveness of a law. 2.3 Culturalizing through the law While discussing the genocidal aspect of the rapes proposed by the feminist legal genocidalism, the following question should be answered: in which possible ways did the injuries of rape-as-genocide model erupt in the law and eventually managed to comply with various definitions of genocide coming from the Genocide Conventions. As Engle has pointed out, one particularly strong and largely unchallenged belief was “rape as social ostracism” 74 that, according to the Genocide Convention, destroys “in whole or in part”. The other strong and unchallenged belief seemed to be that, if Muslim egg were inseminated with a Serbian sperm, a Serbian child would ensue; this particular belief was known as the “rape as forced 73 The March 1993 lawsuit brought by MacKinnon and the NOW Legal Defense and Education Fund focused specifically on crimes against women and sought to redress for the alleged human rights violations pursuant to the Alien Tort Claims Act (ATCA), the chief means by which a foreigner may recover in United States federal courts for torture or other violations of international human rights norms. In addition to compensatory and punitive damages, the complaint sought injunctive relief for personal injury due to genocidal acts of rape, forced pregnancy, enforced prostitution, torture, extrajudicial killing and other violations of international and domestic law. On the other hand, since in this New York trial the Republic of Srpska was for the first time recognized internationally as a sovereign state - a conditio sine qua non for acting internationally – the trial had set up the basis for intervening within international arena in general and the ICTY in particular. For a discussion on MacKinnon’s trial, see Michele Brandt, “Doe v. Karadzic: Redressing Non-State Acts of Gender-Specific Abuse under the Alien Tort Statute,” in Minnesota Law Review 79(6) (June 1995): 1413-1447. See supra notes 47 and 61. 74 For the discussion on rape as social ostracism, see Adrienne Kalosieh, „Consent to Genocide?: the ICTY's Improper Use of the Consent Paradigm to Prosecute Genocidal Rape in Foca,“ in Women's Rights Law Reporter 24 (2003): 121-135. 68 impregnation” (Engle 2005).75 Here we should go back to what Puren and Young stated in their text, namely that the question of justice addresses a central importance of culture in relating feminism to law; that is, the question of justice continually asked by feminism shows how injury is constituted by a process of representation or regime of imagination.76 Pointing to the first regime of imagination, that of “social ostracism” as the effect of the rapes, discerned something unique in the rapes of Bosnian Muslim women that would distinguish them from rapes of women on other sides of the war. As Engle explains, the sense of uniqueness relied on problematic beliefs about the special trauma caused by the rape of a Muslim woman because of the likely response of her Muslim family and community. This particular regime of imagination, as Puren and Young call it, can be traced back to Stiglmayer’s Mass Rape where it was already initiated in Gutman’s introductory text: Women of childbearing age were the primary targets. In the conservative society in which the Muslims of rural Bosnia grew up, women traditionally remain chaste until marriage. Rape is a trauma with far-reaching consequences for these victims, who have well-founded fears of rejection and ostracism and of lives without marriage or children. In this regard the pattern of the rapes of unmarried women of childbearing age fulfils another definition of genocide – the attempt to block procreation of the group. Yet so many cases have come to light of women of sixty and girls under twelve being raped, gang-raped, often in front of their relatives, that genocide seems too dry a description of unrefined savagery (Gutman 1994, X). Under this interpretation, the rapes become genocidal because they are aimed at destroying the group by splitting it – by turning Muslim communities against the women who are raped. Pinning the effects on Muslim culture and religion, the argument relies on the assumption both that such effects are intended by the Serbian rapists and that they have occurred and 75 For the discussion on rape as forced impregnation, see Charli Carpenter, “Surfacing Children: Limitations of Genocidal Rape Discourse,” Human Rights Quarterly 22 (2000): 428-477; Siobhan K. Fisher, “Occupation of the Womb: Forced Impregnation as Genocide,” Duke Law Journal 46(1) (October 1996): 91-133. 76 See the Chapter 1, Part 1.4. 69 will continue to occur. Of course, genocide requires intent only, but the argument often uses presumed effects to impute intent. That the Muslim communities might respond differently from the ways suggested by this stereotype, even with acceptance, is not considered at all. After all, Muslim rural society is supposed to be conservative and patriarchal, as Roy Gutman, the big Bosnian Muslim expert77 has straightforwardly pointed out in his text. The second regime of imagination already implied within the above quotation from Gutman’s text was “rape as forced impregnation”. This particular representational sequence was aiming at complying with the definition of genocide and was simultaneously reproducing brutal stereotypes about the Bosnian Muslims. As I argued in my previous chapter, the domestication of an incommensurable and discontinuous other happens through the process of (mono)culturalization where culture of the other is a coherent and more or less fixed whole to be uncovered by, in this case, feminist legal experts. As Engle points out, those who argued that forced impregnation constituted genocide not only insisted that the purpose of the rapes was to produce children, but they also pointed to the ways that women were detained to ensure that they in fact brought the children produced by the rapes to terms (Engle 2005). At first, however, the forced impregnation argument seems counterintuitive: if children resulted from rapes, there would be more, not fewer, offspring of Bosnian Muslims. But Western imagination assumed that any children born as a result of such a union would be Serbian, not Muslim (of course, given that women might have additional children, this alone would not ensure the destruction of a people; even were the intended effect to produce more Serbian children, it would not necessarily be to destroy all Muslim children). Others, on the other hand, relied heavily on the Islamic and Muslim law 77 As Halley argues in her text Rape at Rome, whereas the outside forces exert political pressure, the inside players have expertise (Halley 2009, 34). 70 where a child's ethnicity is determined by that of the father. In this narrative, forced impregnation thus functioned to create Serbian babies who, by populating otherwise Muslim territory, would effectively take it over. Rather than forcibly moving the population, Serbs would change the Muslim population by ensuring that the next generation was composed of Serbs. Another way that forced impregnation was seen to comply with the definition of genocide was by evidencing intent to prevent births within a group. In this sense, the pregnancies themselves served directly in a genocidal capacity because they interfered with the reproduction of the victimized group: „When reproduction is used to proliferate members of one group and simultaneously to prevent the reproduction of members of another, it is a form of destruction” (cited in Engle 2005, 794). Advocates using this definition of genocide argued that, when a Muslim woman was forced to carry a child (or fetus) that resulted from a Serbian rape, her womb was occupied by the enemy, making her incapable of conceiving and bearing a child of her own ethnicity. Such a position goes beyond the claim that a child born of such a rape is Serbian. It suggests that the child is explicitly not Muslim and that the child is not her mother’s own child. What is more, as Engle points out, there is nothing about the coercive nature of rape that leads these advocates to their conclusion. “If a Serbian sperm implanted in a Muslim egg creates a Serbian child, lack of consent is not necessary to this outcome. Thus, all children born of such a union, consensual or not, would not be Muslim” (Engle 2005, 794). These views were extremely problematic insofar as they largely exaggerated the extent to which women were denied abortions and forced to give birth, and because they took for granted that children or wouldbe children born of rapes are or would be Serbian. As Engle argues, in the overdetermination of the children as Serbian, feminist legal genocidalism refused to see any possibilities for 71 women impregnated by Serbian men or for Islamic communities to refuse the genetic and religious assumptions about the children that were expressed by at least some of the Serbian rapists. In fact, feminist legal genocidalism often reinforced and perpetuated such assumptions, turning a blind eye to the history of the region, which itself demonstrates that such a result is more than evitable. Not only were children of mixed marriages abundant before the war – in fact, it would be hard for me to name anybody among my personal exYugoslavian acquaintances not having some sort of “mixed” background – but during and after the war it was more common for the religious leaders to encourage women to raise the children as Muslim. As Engle points out, some religious Muslim leaders apparently felt less constrained by Islamic law than some of the feminists. Prior to the war, Bosnia and Herzegovina was a place where interpersonal relationships between people of various groups were common. Although numbers are difficult to come by, it is estimated that up to one-third of the marriages were “mixed”, primarily among members of what would nowadays be considered different ethnic groups. Religious identity in the Bosnian context has always had an ethnic aspect, since a person usually inherits her or his religious identity from his parents and, above all, from the father who passes on his surname to his children and thus establishes a child’s ethnic identity, a phenomenon that, after all, carries a universal geo-cultural attributes. For all religions in Bosnia-Herzegovina, the lines were passed down through the fathers, but in a very few cases for the reasons of religious doctrine. Rather, the last name is how one tended to be identified as Muslim, Catholic, or Orthodox – or Muslim, Croatian, or Serbian. That identity category was traditionally organized on the basis of religion does not mean that individuals actively practiced the religions with which they were identified. However, even though the majority of Bosnians were not religious, it was often the religious aspect of being Muslim or 72 Croatian that returned to the forefront during and after the war. Feminist legal genocidalism often reinforced this equation of religion and ethnicity, as they treated all Bosnian Muslim as religious and as leading lives guided by Islamic law – a serious prejudice that the Western hemisphere does not seem to be tackling, inasmuch as it helps sustaining the Western solidarity. As Engle argues, claiming that the rape of Muslim women in Bosnia-Herzegovina was genocidal because it caused social ostracism - by perpetuating statements about Muslim women such as “being soiled and unmarriageable” - can in fact be traced back to an influential article written in 1993 by Adrien Wing and Sylke Merchán, Rape, Ethnicity, and Culture: Spirit Injury from Bosnia to Black America. While this article deals with rapes of Bosnian Muslim women, most of its discussion about the concept of honor and its effect on family cohesion for Muslim is not specific to Bosnia-Herzegovina. Moreover, the account it offers of Islam is relatively fundamentalist, and not applicable to much of that territory.78 Nevertheless, the academics, they know and they are the experts. And apparently they can publish whatever they want. Although, as we shall see, the ICTY jurisprudence has not taken the road of focusing on forced impregnation, both feminist legal genocidalism and the ICTY further entrenched understandings of essentialized ethnic identity, and conflated religious and ethnic identity in ways that defy the history of the treatment of both in Bosnia-Herzegovina. The concepts of validity and persuasiveness that Kennedy is discussing in his book Of War and Law have 78 As Wing and Merchán argue, „though brief, the foregoing delineation of Islamic religion and culture illustrates the differential treatment of men women that can exist in Muslim society. It should come as no surprise that under these deeply held Islamic and cultural precepts, the Serb-instigated, systematic rape of Muslim women constitutes not merely a physical injury but a spiritual injury on the very culture of the Bosnian Muslims. The removal of purity, chastity, and virginity from the unmarried rape victims literally makes them unmarriageable, and brings shame and disgrace to the entire family group. The violation perpetrated upon married women makes it impossible for many of them to stay in their marriages“ (Wing and Merchán 1993, 2324). 73 been, therefore, taken utterly professionally by the feminists who were preparing themselves for the legal performance at the ICTY. What is striking while reading the texts similar to those published in Stiglmayer’s Mass Rape is exactly this level of legal consciousness expressed by the authors such as Gutman and MacKinnon. These texts are always the products of a very strictly defined adjustment to the rules of law and their assertiveness is reinforced by the legal vocabulary shared among various world’s professional and expert elite, namely lawyers, economists, businessmen, academics, journalists, and the like. In this case, Gutman has played a function of the Balkan connoisseur and his successful journalist expedition to the territory of the former Yugoslavia has made him the authority within the Western utopian field of the “Balkan studies”. That he forged close relations with the Croatian war crime criminals, such as Ante Gotovina,79 and maintained direct correspondence with the U.S. State Department while paying his visits to the former Yugoslavia is something that the feminists impatient to devour the legal territory were not interested in tackling upon. On the contrary, they also began their quest for the female victims that would help them bring this long-awaited justice to the patriarchal world. 79 “Roy Gutman: Granatiranje Knina nije bilo prekomjerno, a HV nije odgovoran za protjerivanje Srba”, interview with Roy Gutman by Nacional, no. 3 (June 17, 2003). <http://www.nacional.hr/clanak/10622/roy-gutman-granatiranje-knina-nije-bilo-prekomjerno-a-hv-nijeodgovoran-za-protjerivanje-srba> 74 CHAPTER 3. - Dedicated to the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia in the Hague In my second chapter I tried to show that the only way to perform in a legally legitimate way is to satisfy the criteria of both validity and persuasiveness and that an effort to persuade an “audience” can sometimes be enhanced and other times undermined by the rhetoric of validity. The reason that the feminist legal genocidalism chose to concentrate its efforts on genocide instead of other two applicable jurisdictions – grave breaches and crimes against humanity - was the very possibility of meeting both of these criteria when it comes to rapeas-genocide model. Besides possible validity feature of persecuting sexual crimes as genocidal crimes, such a choice would certainly persuade an audience that the war against women led on the territory of the former Yugoslavia is something exceptional in our history. On the other hand, the ex-Yugoslavian radical feminism led politics different from the one which sought to name the perpetrator and choose a side in the war for the sake of jurisdictional validity and persuasiveness: whereas the feminist legal genocidalism decided to focus mainly on one enemy and one victim – the Bosnian Serb men and Bosnian Muslim women - the ex-Yugoslavian radical feminism considered the “patriarchal essence” of nation-state ideology to be responsible for the War in the former Yugoslavia and named women the primary victims of patriarchy. This was, at the same time, a decisive moment for splitting of two feminist camps - the ex-Yugoslavian radical feminism could not and did not aim at complying with legal definition of genocide nor any other legal definition whatsoever; the feminist legal genocidalism, on the other hand, pursued with legal persecution and 75 started to adjust the case of sexual violence perpetuated in the Yugoslav War to what the international law was offering. My third chapter is dedicated solely to the ICTY, this huge UN machinery that during the 1990s have been producing very dualist reactions among the former Yugoslav population. In the Yugoslav countries that had just recently gone through a war (in one way or the other), one could be either pro or against the Tribunal. And while the right-wingers were very much opposed to it, the left-wingers were very much opposed to such an opposition. This, in turn, resulted in numerous “crimes” committed against the complexity of ICTY-related topics: since the question of dealing with consequences of war has been oversaturated with various political aspirations, there was nobody who could afford herself to develop truly critical thinking about the Tribunal. During the 1990s in Croatia, the Tribunal stood as a sort of savior from the post-war nationalist projects. Fifteen years later, this dichotomy has been very much deconstructed and new approaches to the ICTY have been built. In my third chapter, I intend to offer one of these approaches. My initial intention is to discuss the first significant ICTY case concerning the sexual crimes against women in the War in the former Yugoslavia – the Kunarac case – and then to proceed with a text written by Kirsten Campbell that discusses the gendered pattern of legal proceedings at the ICTY and reveals the way in which the ICTY has finally responded to the feminist legal demands. Among other things, this text is meant to depict a peculiar dynamics that both the ICTY and feminist legal genocidalism have been creating together, a dynamics that reminds me of the 1990s in Croatia: if one is to participate in the legal system, can one afford herself developing truly critical thinking about the Tribunal? But before I proceed with the Hague case, let me first say a few words about the ICTY official webpage as a primary source for discussing the Kunarac case. 76 Even though there is an open access to the ICTY legal documents, many researchers tend to rely mostly on a secondary source - the feminist interpretations of a primary source in their analyses of rapes committed on the territory of former Yugoslavia. One of the reasons for that is an immense amount of various legal documents (Indictments; Transcripts; Trial Chamber Decisions, Orders, Judgments; Appeal Chamber Decisions, Orders, Judgments; President’s Decisions, Orders, etc.80) that the ICTY is offering to a researcher; thus browsing through the documents of only one particular ICTY case would simply be time-consuming. Another thing is the fact that most of the cases dealing with sexual violence have already been analyzed numerous times by feminist researchers and that more than often those who embark on such research would consider a secondary source to be more “functional” than a primary one: it simply offers reliable (technical) information about a particular case and, what is more, it offers the safe haven of ready-made opinions. As a result, a primary source is somewhat neglected and the opinions on various ICTY issues are very much uniformed. Although instead of analyzing the ICTY cases themselves, I have been discussing the epistemic mechanisms which brought about such a particular discursive actuality, I believe that making a direct link with something that is supposed to be the final “destination” of every single feminist publication from the early 1990s - the trial itself – is indispensable for “getting the whole picture”. Hence in my next part I intend to work with transcripts and various legal documents in the Kunarac trial and hopefully disclose the case of systematic ethnicization and culturalization of both the defendants and plaintiffs on the part of the ICTY. 80 See http://www.icty.org/case/kunarac/4 for an example of the Kunarac case. 77 3.1 Ethnicizing, culturalizing, “dehumanizing” One of the most apparent manifestations of feminist aspirations can be found in the pattern of prosecutions by the ICTY's Office of the Prosecutor. The Office successfully prosecuted rapes alleged to have been committed on all sides but, at the same time, concentrated its efforts on a case that viewed the rapes as systematically aimed at Bosnian Muslims. The ICTY has handed down three judgments that make up its jurisprudence on rape. In the first, Celebici, the ICTY found rape to constitute torture and thus a grave breach; the case was brought against Bosnian Muslim defendants for raping Serbian women. That the defendants were Muslim is rarely mentioned but seems significant in the context of the debate between the two feminist camps. Through this prosecution, the ICTY signaled that all rapes committed on all sides violated international law. This view was reinforced by the second successful rape prosecution, Furundzija, in which the defendants were Croats, not Serbs. However, it was not until Kunarac - the case involving the municipality of Foca - that Serbian men were convicted for raping Bosnian Muslim women. The Kunarac case was designed to do two things. First, it was intended to focus exclusively on sexual crimes against women, with the ultimate hope of extending the jurisprudence on rape and sexual violence. When the indictment was issued, the front page of the New York Times quoted a court spokesman, who called it a „landmark indictment because it focuses exclusively on sexual assaults, without including any other charges . . . There is no precedent for this. It is of major legal significance because it illustrates the court's strategy to focus on gender-related crimes and give them their proper place in the prosecution of war crime“ (cited in Engle 2005, 798). Second, the case was meant to bring attention to the systematic detention and rape of Bosnian Muslim women. In the end, the ICTY handed down convictions for rape and enslavement as crimes against humanity. Thus, even without a finding of genocide, the ICTY 78 indicated that the rapes of Bosnian Muslim women were different from the rapes of Serbian and Croatian women: only the former were found to be systematic. Before I start with the analysis, it is necessary to give some brief outline of the Kunarac case as presented by the Trial Chamber. In April 1992, the city and municipality of Foca were overtaken by Serb forces. Muslims living in Foca and the surrounding area were attacked, expelled from the region, and/or detained, with women, children and some older men taken to detention centers at the local high school and sports hall. Prior to the war in Bosnia-Herzegovina, fifty-two per cent of the 40 513 inhabitants of the Foca Municipality were Muslim. After the conflict, approximately ten Muslims remained. For the Muslims detained in Foca, conditions were extreme. The facilities were unhygienic, little food was available, and the prisoners were subject to beatings and, in the case of women and girls, repeated rapes. It is this latter development that concerns the judgment in Kunarac. Serb soldiers routinely raped the women and girls kept at the local school and sports hall. The three defendants were involved, in different capacities, with those rapes as well as with the removal of a group of women and girls, most of them ranging in age from twelve to twenty, from these centers to local houses/apartments, where they were raped by the defendants and other soldiers. Some of these women were detained for several months and were subject to constant rapes, taken as the “property” of the individual defendants, and made to do housework, cleaning and cooking. After a period of time, some of these women/girls, including a twelveyear-old, were then sold to other soldiers. The twelve-year-old girl was never seen again. The three defendants - Kunarac, Kovac and Vukovic - were charged under the Statute of the Yugoslav Tribunal with various criminal offences. As already stated in the second 79 chapter, the Yugoslav Tribunal has authority, from the UN Security Council, to prosecute violations of the laws of war, grave breaches of the Geneva Conventions, crimes against humanity, and genocide committed within the territory of the former Yugoslavia. The Tribunal’s Statute – its constituting document – outlines the types of acts considered “criminal” for the purposes of the Tribunal. It was drafted to reflect only the most settled areas of IHL, and to include, to the extent that this allowed, provisions that would cover crimes committed under a policy of “ethnic cleansing”.81 According to Doris Buss in her text Prosecuting Mass Rapes, the Statute is a curious balancing act between a conservative and reactive reading of international humanitarian law, and an innovative document, seeking to open up a new era of international adjudication of war crimes. The result is a complex set of rules that aims to elaborate and condemn systematic persecution of groups within a juridical system focused on the individual acts of individual defendants against specific members of the civilian population. Another result is that indictments, such as those in Kunarac, are lengthy and perplex, referring to individual acts and patterns of activity, and laying charges under multiple headings (Buss 2002, 93). In the context of Kunarac, the defendants were charged with rape as a crime against humanity (Article 5 (g) of the ICTY Statute) and as a violation of the laws of war (Article 3), and rape as torture, constituting both a crime against humanity (Article 5 (h)) and a violation of the laws of war (Article 3). In addition, the defendants were charged with enslavement as a crime against humanity (Article 5 (c)) and with outrages upon personal dignity (Article 3). In most cases, the multiple charges of rape (as a crime against humanity and as a violation of the laws of war) and torture (also as a crime against humanity and as a violation of the laws of war) are made in respect of the 81 The term ethnic cleansing is not to be confused with genocide. Simply put, ethnic cleansing is similar to forced deportation or “population transfer” whereas genocide is the intentional murder of part or all of a particular ethnic, religious, or national group. 80 same incident. The multiple charges are significant here, insofar as they constitute the recognition that wartime rape occurs in different contexts, for different reasons, with various impacts. Nevertheless, many aspects of the Kunarac case remain truly problematic here and the overall outcome does not seem as promising as it has been advertised by the feminist legal genocidalism. First and foremost, when it comes to genocidal aspect of wartime rape, the ICTY has never specifically drawn a connection between rape and genocide or ethnic cleansing. Although in Kunarac the judgments themselves contain some references to ethnic cleansing, the Appeals Chamber included in its findings that “the campaign was successful in its aim of ‘cleansing’ the Foca area of non-Serbs”.82 Therefore, the aim of cleansing is primarily connected with ethnicity, whereas the gender aspect emerges as soon as the discussion starts to revolve around various tools of destroying a certain ethnic group. As stated by the Trial Chamber, “the rapes against the Muslim women were one of the many ways in which the Serbs could assert their superiority and victory over the Muslims”.83 Moreover, the Trial Chamber described the attacks on the population as follows: After months of captivity, many women were expelled or exchanged. Some men spent as much as two years and a half in detention for no reason other than their being Muslims . . . Almost all the remaining Muslim men and women from all three municipalities were 82 Prosecutor v. Kunarac, Appeals Chamber, No. IT-96-23 & IT-96-23/1-T, para. 3 (June 12,2002) [hereinafter Kunarac]. 83 Kunarac, Trial Chamber, para. 583 (February 22, 2001). The prosecutor describes the rape in the following way: „Rape is only one of the constituent ingredients in the widespread or systematic attack“, Trial Transcript (May 30, 2000): 4179. However, this opinion was expressed only after Judge Hunt had warned the prosecution that “[a]rticle 5 does not require you to prove that the rapes were widespread; it only requires you to prove that the armed conflict against the civilian population was widespread. The evidence that you or Mr. Kuo suggested was going to be available from this witness’ evidence seemed to be an attempt to establish that the rapes were widespread”, Trial Transcript (May 30, 2000): 4178. Thus at the very beginning of the Kunarac trial, Judge Hunt made a clear statement that any attempt to give priority to gender - and not ethnicity - of the victim would immediately be interrupted by the Trial Chamber. 81 arrested, rounded up, separated and imprisoned or detained at several detention centers . . . in accordance with a recurring pattern. Some of them were killed, raped or severely beaten. The sole reason for this treatment of the civilians was their Muslim ethnicity.84 After this, one can easily conclude that we are far away from the rape-as-genocide model where rape is a highly planned and coordinated strategy aimed against women as both gender and ethnic group. Moreover, the Trial Chamber in its judgment in the proceedings against the accused explicitly rejects the presupposition that systematic rape could have been employed as a weapon of war in itself. As Judge Mumba claims: [t]he trial against the three accused has sometimes been called the “rape camp case”, an example of the systematic rape of women of another ethnicity being used as a weapon of the war. It is to some extent misleading to say that systematic rape was employed against as a weapon of war. This could be understood to mean a kind of concerted approach or an order given to the Bosnian Serb armed forces to rape Muslim women as part of their combat activities in the wider meaning. There is no sufficient evidence for such a finding before the Trial Chamber.85 Furthermore, since the ICTY has not found rape to constitute genocide, it would seemingly never have considered the issue of forced impregnation, as a means either to produce Serbian babies or to prevent births of Muslim children. As Engle points out in her text Feminism and its (Dis)Contents, by continuing to pay some credence to the arguments embedded in the rape-as-genocide claims, the ICTY has, nevertheless, alluded the possibility that forced impregnation might have been part of an anti-Muslim campaign. In the Kunarac indictment, for instance, there were references to a victim being told that she would bear 84 Kunarac, Trial Chamber, para. 577 (February 22, 2001). It is also worth noticing what the prosecution argued in its opening statement:”It will become clear that what happened to the Muslim women of Foca and surrounding area occurred purely because of their ethnicity or religion and because they were women”, Trial Transcript (March 20, 2000): 303. In this sentence, one can sense a strong influence of the feminist legal genocidalism that has been thoroughly mitigated in the course of a trial (see supra note 83). 85 Kunarac, Trial Transcript (February 22, 2001): 6558-6559 [judgment delivered by the Trial Chamber]. 82 Serbian children: “At Hotel Zelengora, FWS-48 was placed in a separate room and Dragoljub Kunarac and Zoran Vukovic, a local military commander, raped her . . . Both perpetrators told her that she would now give birth to Serb babies”.86 What is “interesting” here is that the Trial Chamber interpreted comments by the accused suggesting such an intent as evidence that the women were raped because they were Muslim rather than, as the accused had argued, out of a sexual urge or some other similar motivations: “The treatment reserved by Dragoljub Kunarac for his victims was motivated by their being Muslims, as is evidenced by the occasion when the accused told women, that they would give birth to Serb babies, or that they should ‘enjoy being fucked by a Serb’”.87 I agree with Engle when she claims that it is strength, rather than a weakness, of the ICTY’s jurisprudence that it has not taken the road of focusing on rape-as-genocide model, even though it has still done everything what was in its power to emphasize the ethnic component of both the victims and perpetrators. In the end, gender had little to do with determining the outcome of the ICTY judgments and basically served a purpose of fixating the general image of ethnic bigotry in the former Yugoslavia. However, I would like to proceed with something that concerns me even more when reconsidering the possible jurisdictions of the ad hoc Tribunals: the prosecution of rapes as a crime against humanity and, in addition, outrages upon personal dignity. If we take into account that the rape-asgenocide model has been about rape directed toward women because they were Muslim or Croatian - thus equally encompassing gender and ethnic aspect – then the ICTY decision in Kunarac to prosecute rapes (primarily) as a crime against humanity is almost painfully missing the point. On the other hand, prosecuting rapes as a crime against humanity has 86 87 Kunarac, Third Ameneded Indictment (Kunarac and Kovac), para. 6.1 (November 8, 1999). Kunarac, Trial Chamber, para. 654 (February 22, 2001). 83 definitely drawn attention to the systematic side of attacks on Muslim population and has led the rape-as-genocide camp to more or less embrace these prosecution rules. In this sense, the lack of emphasis on gendered crimes has been “compensated” by a constant recurrence to a widespread and systematic nature of sexual violence. What concerns me here, though, is a very strong suggestion that the victim was made un-human by the very act of a crime: This is the case about the women and girls, some as young as 12 or 15 years old, who endured unimaginable horrors as their worlds collapsed around them. Before their very eyes, their family members were killed and their homes were destroyed. They were then brutalized, sexually assaulted, and dehumanized by their captors, including the three accused who sit before you today. This is a case about justice and international laws that seek to proscribe the atrocities committed during armed conflict. In this trial, you will see the human face of the atrocities, both of the perpetrator and the victims.88 This opening statement of the Prosecution case against Kunarac, Kovac and Vukovic revolves around the problem that Jenny Edkins has analyzed in her text Humanitarianism, Humanity, Human (Edkins 2003): do we want to repeat the totalitarian impulse and deny the humanity of those who find themselves enduring unimaginable horrors of concentration camps and/or enslavement? In her text, Edkins starts with Primo Levi’s memoir of his experiences in Auschwitz-Monowitz that “takes us to a world where simple distinctions between human and non-human no longer make sense; a world where people die for no reason except that a guard has decided to kill them; a world where there are no comrades in adversity but an endless ‘grey zone’ where many are implicated in the evil that is taking place and all are contaminated by it” (Edkins 2003, 253). As Levi is pointing out in his book, in the universe of 88 Kunarac, Trial Transcript (March 20, 2000): 293-294 [prosecution opening statement]. 84 the concentration camp, most prisoners are stripped of all dignity and lose even their will to survive. In one sense, they become non-human; they no longer care whether they live or die and their only interest is in food and shelter. However, not everyone in the camp is brought to this state. Some manage to retain their human dignity through various strategies or through luck: they become camp officials, or they steal from fellow inmates, or they obtain privileges that mean they have more to eat or less strenuous work to perform. It is the “survivors” who are drawn mainly from this group and they are the ones that bear witness to the camps.89 A question that Agamben has named “Levi’s paradox” is the following one: “In this context, is it more human to retain one’s dignity, one’s ‘humanity’, or to lose it?” (cited in Edkins 2003, 257).90 Even though I am not trying to search for direct analogies - is the concentration camp really similar to the alleged rape camps in and around the town of Foca?; were the power relations really brought to their paradoxical auto-abolition as in the case of Nazi concentration camps where the subject/object relations strived toward a complete dichotomization and subsequently ceased to exist?; how similar are the perpetrator/victim constellations in both of these cases?; etc. – it is true that ever since the General Assembly of the UN proclaimed its UDHR on 10 December 1948, the international law has been vehemently promoting the idea of “human dignity” allegedly lost in the midst of everyday life in the Nazi concentration camps. To claim that the victims in Kunarac trial have gone 89 90 Levi Primo, If This is A Man and The Truce (London: Abacus, 1979) (cited in Edkins 2003, 253). Consider a deplorable account of human dignity in the text Gendercide and Humiliation in Honor and Human Rights Societies published in Journal of Genocide Research 4(1) (2002): 137-155. The author of this text, Evelin Gerda Linder, is the founding president of an emerging interdisciplinary field of „Human Dignity and Humiliation Studies“ that aim to “increase our understanding of the negative consequences of humiliation and generate support of alternative approaches that promote human dignity”. <http://www.humiliationstudies.org/education/education.php> 85 through the process of dehumanization, as the Prosecution claimed in their opening statement, is to position the raped body within the non-human sphere of zoe and to make this body have its final destination amongst those who are stripped of their political voice. 91 However, such a paranoid approach towards “human”, where one is defined through the negation of one’s bare life, suffers from the highly normative assumptions that are placing this very same (meta)human ideal at the center of our cosmos. If to be raped is to be nonhuman, as the prosecution claimed in their opening statement, then we should ask ourselves how much effort the humanity must be putting into continual re-establishment of negation in order to be able to define itself through such negativity. In this context, isn’t the act of rape a matter of human indispensability and the act of suicide the only chance to retain humanity of those who are raped?92 3.2 Post scriptum: on the value of feminist legal progress In her text The Gender of Transitional Justice: Law, Sexual Violence and the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia, Kirsten Campbell analyses how legal norms and practices instantiate and reiterate, rather than transform, existing hierarchical gender 91 In his Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, Agamben confirms the kinds of arguments initiated by Foucault when he claims that „the entry of zoe into the sphere of the polis – the politization of bare life as such – constitutes the decisive event of modernity and signals a radical transformation of the political-philosophical categories of classical thought“ (Agamben 1998, 4). He continues by claiming that the Western politics has not succeeded in constructing the link between zoe and bios, between voice and language, that would have healed the fracture. Bare life remains included in politics in the form of exception, that is as something that is included solely through an exclusion. 92 Those who are raped are often said to be living on the threshold of life and death which, in turn, makes them incapable of “owning” themselves and their own lives: how to own a life that is excluded from bios and, as such, cannot constitute any kind of human sacrifice as, for instance, in the case of a soldier dying for his country? On the other hand, claiming that being raped is a fate worse than death makes these victims incapable of dying as well: how to die if you are not really alive and if you are somewhere in between – on the threshold of life and death? This topic will be discussed in further detail in Chapter 4, Part 4.1. 86 relations (Campbell 2007). Her text is extremely valuable insofar as her case study provides a much needed statistical analysis of the ICTY gendered pattern. As Campbell has analyzed, there have been 17 cases of sexual violence out of a total 35 completed cases heard by the ICTY and the indictments specify the gender of the victim in all but three cases. Out of a total of 17 cases, seven cases include counts of sexual violence solely against female victims, three against male victims and four involving both male and female victims. This basically means that over 40 percent (7 out of 17) of the total number of these cases include charges in which men are the victims of sexual violence. A similar pattern emerges if we consider counts93 rather than cases. Of a total of 476 counts, 108 involve sexual violence, that is, approximately 20 percent of all counts. Of these sexual violence counts, 64 involve offences against women; 31 against men; 5 against both men and women; with 8 unspecified. What is important to add here, the majority of the counts involving sexual violence against women were brought in the case of Kunarac; if the Kunarac is excluded, then there is an equal distribution of male and female sexual violence offences in other cases. As Campbell continues, the same is with the cases involving explicit rape charges, in which 19 (83 percent) involve offences against women, and four (17 percent) offences against men. However, with Kunarac excluded, again there is a roughly equal distribution, with four rape charges involving male and three charges female victims (Campbell 2007, 422-423). As Campbell argues, the high number of cases and counts involving sexual violence against male victims is unexpected for two reasons. First, prosecutions of these cases are in clear contrast to the general lack of visibility of male sexual assault in the Yugoslavian 93 In Criminal Procedure, count is one of several parts or charges of an indictment, each accusing the defendant of a different offense. 87 conflict; both in terms of media coverage and in comparison to the institutional and legal focus upon sexual violence against women. Second, a high proportion of counts of male sexual assault are surprising given the generally agreed predominance of sexual violence against female victims in the conflict. Estimated number of female victims of sexual violence in Yugoslavia range from 12 000 to 50 000.94 Nevertheless, the gendered pattern of legal practices in these legal proceedings reveals the overrepresentation of prosecuted incidences of sexual violence against men, where that overrepresentation is defined in terms of comparable incidences of female sexual assault in the conflict. If it is agreed that incidences of male sexual assault form a comparably small proportion of total sexual assaults, then it is reasonable to expect that the proportion of male and female victims before the ICTY would reflect this. However, approximately 40 percent of the cases, and 30 percent of the counts involve sexual violence in which men are victims. If the Kunarac case is excluded, then there is an equal distribution of male and female sexual violence offences in other cases. These proportions, as Campbell concludes, do not reflect the generally agreed differential scale of gendered assaults (Campbell 2007, 424). Even though the ICTY has been constantly propagating a feminist-friendly approach, its gendered pattern of legal proceedings tells us that there is nothing decisively feminist about it. Such an obvious discrepancy between institutional/media focus upon sexual violence against women and gendered pattern of legal proceedings that reflects no exceptionality of female suffering in the Yugoslavian conflict is quite characteristic for liberal 94 Exact numbers of female victims were difficult to establish for two reasons, as Campbell notes. First, the investigations faced not only the general challenges encountered when researching sexual violence, but the additional difficulty of doing so in the midst of an armed conflict. Second, as claims and counter-claims of sexual violence became part of the Yugoslavian conflict, these estimates themselves became the subject of “wars of interpretation” that I have been discussing (though quite indirectly) in my previous chapters (Campbell 2007). 88 anti-pluralist system and its totalitarian tiptoeing, as some would call it. Though having allowed for the rape-as-genocide model to be brought into focus and to move forward,95 the system is not showing any real interest in prosecuting the crimes. On the other hand, having been offered a nutritive substance that has been feeding it and moving it forward, the legal feminism seems to be ignorant about the long-term effects that such a substance is producing in the feminist body. The body does move forward, but is at the same time sabotaged from within by the very same substance that has been feeding it; eventually, with no doubt, this body will implode. What needs to be pointed out, though, is a particular feminist stance that such a perplexing behavior of the system is systematically producing within the feminist legal circles, a stance that can tell us a story about the domestication of legal feminists from around the globe, though specifically those coming from the West. This domestication is manifested in the following way: whenever there is an attempt to criticize the ICTY jurisdiction, this attempt is immediately weakened by a simple reminder that it was no other institution but the ICTY itself that has pioneered accountability for sexual violence against women in armed conflict. In other words, in almost every feminist text that discusses this topic, first there is a bow to legal and, consequently, feminist legal progress, and then a bow is usually followed by a critique that is overwhelmingly saturated with excuses for having decided to do such a critique in the first place. Hence, feminists who write these texts often express their guilt for being insufficiently grateful to the system; after all, as legal progressives, they tend to regard the many successes of the feminist legal work as perfectly benign, if not as precious examples of humanitarian progress. On the other hand, that there is hardly any feminist legal text that fails to accentuate that famous 95 The system simply has to allow for similar concepts, as it is dependent on the feminism that functions as a “witness” to the system’s will to assist and encourage the similar liberal aspirations. 89 progress can certainly tell us a great deal about both our steady belief in it and our incapability to grasp the system in all its paradoxical complexity. For if the ICTY – this huge machinery that is representing the system – is deliberately using the inexact numbers of female victims and/or failing to actually prosecute the crimes, how valuable this manifest progress can actually be?96 96 At the very end of this chapter, consider the following paragraph from Buss’ paper: “In Kunarac, for example, the decision runs to over 300 pages and contains masses of evidence and testimony on the experience of women raped and abused while in detention. In evaluating this evidence, the Tribunal details individual acts of abuse, noting times, places, supporting evidence. On a number of indictments, the Tribunal rules that there is insufficient evidence, or the indictment has not been properly drawn, to sustain a conviction. The result is bizarre. After reading pages and pages of witness evidence about the existence of what are, in effect, ‘rape camps’, the Tribunal then dismisses individual charges of rape for lack of evidence. Arguably, within a strict reading of criminal evidence and international law, the Tribunal is ‘right’ in its conclusion, but the very process of analysis feels particularly ill suited to the task of accounting for, and reconciling the experiences of these women. What lesson do we take away from a Tribunal that can, on the one hand, find evidence of rape camps, and yet find that individual women are not to be believed in their accounts of rape and violence at those same camps? In this respect, the Yugoslav Tribunal reproduces many of the same problematic aspects of ‘the rape trial’ found in Western domestic legal systems. Does this mean that feminists and others should not seek to use this system to prosecute rape and sexual violence? Certainly not. But it does raise additional questions about the war crimes tribunal as a mechanism of reconciliation and resolution in a post-conflict situation“ (Buss 2002, 98-99 [italics mine]). 90 CHAPTER 4. - „Gendercide“ as a legacy of the feminist legal genocidalism: discussing a minoritarian framing of male experience 97 My third chapter was an attempt to bring out just a “few words" from the Kunarac case and, as such, it functioned as a sort of digression from my main attempt to situate the feminist legal genocidalism within the discursive production of knowledge about the War in exYugoslavia. Nevertheless, I have discussed one case that has done a lot in terms of fastening the ethnic relations in the former Yugoslavia as well as creating a clear picture about who is the perpetrator and who the victim. Moreover, with this case, I tried to reanimate an important issue I had already raised in my previous chapters, the issue of ethnicitzation and/or culturalization. In the post scriptum part of my chapter, I wanted to depict a peculiar dynamics that both the ICTY and feminist legal genocidalism have been creating together, a dynamics of “mutual symbiosis” in which the legal feminism has been feeding itself on the illusion of legal progress. In this chapter, I am returning to my original plot, although this time I will be discussing the post-1990s discursive legacy of feminist legal genocidalism: where can we find the traces of it and what possible shapes does the genocidalist discourse carry nowadays? As Aleksandar Jokic argues in his text Genocidalism, such genocidalist activity abounds among journalists, activists, politicians, but its saddest and perhaps most dangerous form resides in (what poses as) academic scholarship; for academics are, by way of their training, uniquely positioned to provide credence to this malignant intellectual attitude and the pursuits that genocidalism represents. Moreover, they have the skills and prestige, as Jokic continues, needed to successfully package propaganda to appear as 97 The second part of the title is taken from the title of the text written by Adam Jones (see Jones 2000a). 91 scholarship, emotions as good reasons, dogmatic belief as well supported claims, and prejudice, bigotry, and even racism as respectable viewpoints. They can turn lies into truth (or “truth”), fiction into fact, sick imagination into historical events, total ideological blindness into insights of a visionary, and, last but not least, they can turn apologia into veritable art form (Jokic 2003, 256-257). Feminist legal genocidalism is one of those “scholarships” whose epistemic arrogance resulted in accusatory texts in which asking for evidence itself may have been a sign of vile character deserving the strongest condemnation. In fact, this has been the essence of genocidalism, Jokic argues; much is in the mode of presentation, the pose of expertise, and the appearance of revealing gruesome discoveries are much more important than the content and how one could support it (Jokic 2003, 269). In this chapter, I want to draw attention to the remnants of this feminist self-righteousness of the 1990s within academia and talk about the cases where the rape-as-genocide model has found a cozy sanctuary and fertile ground for its entirely irresponsible reproduction. 4.1 Gendercide studies and inversion of radical feminism While reading the academic texts on the War in the former Yugoslavia I found that the term “gendercide”, first coined by Mary Ann Warren in her 1985 book Gendercide: the Implications of Sex Selection, has been gaining more and more attention in academic circles. In his article Gendercide and Genocide published in 2000, Adam Jones sought to revitalize the term and to place such acts of gendercide in comparative and global-historical perspective. He argues that gendercide, inclusively defined as gender-selective mass killing, is a frequent and often defining feature of human conflict, and perhaps of human social organization, extending back to antiquity. Besides, gendercide is a regular, even ubiquitous feature of contemporary politico-military conflicts worldwide, Jones observes. In his article, 92 Jones argues that gendercide – particularly when targeting males – has attracted virtually no attention at the level of scholarship or public policy. As such, it can be classified as one of the great “taboo” subjects of the contemporary age. Nonetheless, it is remarkable how regularly one comes across references in literature on modern mass killing, to staggering demographic disproportions of adult males vs. adult females – that is, a wildly skewed underrepresentation of adult men (Jones 2000, 187). As Jones argues, non-combatant men have been and continue to be the most frequent targets of mass killing and genocidal slaughter, as well as a host of lesser atrocities and abuses. Unlike their armed brethren, these men have no means of defending themselves, and can be detained and exterminated by the thousands or millions. The gender of mass killing, moreover, likely extends beyond the age range specified. Elderly males are probably more prone than elderly women to be caught up in the “maelstrom” of war; and modern warfare, with its relentless press-ganging and criminality, extends ever further down the age ladder in the hunt for child soldiers and street thugs - overwhelmingly boys (Jones 2000, 192). Jones' article has swiftly generated a body of genocide research that specifically focuses on gender-selectivity98 in patterns of mass killings, with an emphasis on genocide: the March 2002 issue of the Journal of Genocide Research is devoted entirely to the topic. The articles in this special issue cut at the problem of gender-selective killing from a variety of directions, but all share two interrelated commonalities. First, they focus on the practice of targeting members of one or another sex as a crucial site around which gender dynamics manifests in the practice of genocidal atrocity. Second, they seek to balance the feminist emphasis on women’s human rights with analysis of the extent to which males are targeted 98 As in the case of legal feminists, these authors use something that should be called „biological gender“. This problem will be discussed in further detail in Part 4.2. 93 on the basis of gender. Nevertheless, these two things are highly interrelated: that this time it is the males who are victimized through some sort of de-neutralization99 of the male gender is a direct, but non-acknowledged consequence of the feminist legal genocidalism that used to excessively emphasize women’s suffering and systematically disregard the multiplicity100 of roles that men played in the Yugoslavian War. Quite naturally, though, there is no explicit remark of the fact that “gendercide studies” should primarily be understood as a competitive response to the 1990s feminist legal performance. Instead, what we are offered is a constant recurrence to the political correctness toward feminist scholarship behind which one is able to sense a high level of irritation with everything that has been done within academic circles regarding the rape-as-genocide model on the territory of the former Yugoslavia.101 The most striking feature of this project is that the authors of this special issue (indirectly) dismiss as non-genocidal anything that does not include death as the final outcome of genocidal activities. This is why their concern over the rapes committed on the territory of Yugoslavia is nothing compared to the one displayed with regards to Rwandan context where the death of the victim was a common outcome. 99 This idea is discussed in further detail in Holter's A Theory of Gendercide: „When Russian leaders left 118 men aboard a sunken submarine to die in the Barents Sea in August, 2000, by not calling for international help until it was too late, there was no reference to gender. Yet the event concerned men, and not only as incidental male individuals . . . The gender system appeared as something neutral, peripheral, as it often does in male contexts (Holter 2002, 14-15). 100 In these war, men were not only the perpetrators, but also the victims; they were not only the soldiers, but also the civilians. 101 Consider, for instance, the following paragraph written by Jones in his text on the Rwandan genocide: “[i]n recent years, the phenomenon of the mass rape of women in ethnic and other conflicts has attracted a flood of attention from feminist scholars. The inquiry, which arguably began with Susan Brownmiller’s discussion of mass rapes in East Pakistan/Bangladesh during the genocide of 1971 was substantially deepened with the onset of the wars in the former Yugoslavia and the rape of tens of thousands of women, mostly Bosnian Muslims assaulted by Serbian regular and irregular forces. The rapes of Rwandan Tutsi women were on a vastly greater scale than in the former Yugoslavia. Both in their murderous dimension—with rape frequently followed by killing, either immediately or after a period of forced sexual servitude—and in the element of savage mutilation, they bear comparison only with the genocidal rampage of the Japanese army in Nanjing in 1937– 1938“ (Jones 2002, 80-81 [italics mine]). 94 Once again, as in the case of MacKinnon and her clash with Serbian feminists, the other has to die in order to fit into somebody’s theoretical frame (the living dead appears as a somewhat too complicated conception): The manner in which women are targeted in genocidal slaughters may also amount to gendercide. There is no doubt that the term should be applied to all cases of mass rape followed by murder. In certain historical circumstances—including relatively recent ones (Bangladesh, Nanking, Berlin)—women have been targeted en masse for combined rape and killing, or raping to death. This must surely rank among the most excruciating deaths known to humankind, and much the same “culling” process may be evident as in the case of genderselective mass killings of men. In the contemporary era, a further deadly element has been added to the mix: AIDS (Jones 2000, 192). What such an approach could possibly challenge is the common feminist presumption that rape is the worst possible fate for a woman and, thus, living your life at the threshold of life and death can be much worse than simply being dead.102 Nevertheless, this is not what these authors are trying to say. In their account, the death has the value of something which is concrete, which is numbered and which is more traceable than the rapes themselves, very often leaving no visible scars on the female bodies. On the other hand, drawing attention to the suffering of civilian men during the armed conflict is not worth criticizing per se, but when presented as part of this comparative measurement - which gender actually suffers more? – it starts to reveal a competitive (male) strategy that uses the (female) other in order to prove that women are capable of being political and/or genocidal human beings who can 102 This is exactly what Janet Halley is challenging in her text Rape in Berlin where she claims that “[t]he superior badness of rape can background other bad things: to import the idea that ‘rape is a fate worse than death’ into the setting of armed conflict - for example, to declare that the panoramic violence of the Yugoslav conflict was a ‘war against women’- is to background the death that armed conflict brings to people generally, and specifically to the death it brings to men” (Halley 2008, 80). 95 perform as active agents of rapes and slaughter. This inversed, Bizarro103 version of radical feminism where listing the names of female architects of the Rwandan genocide104 should serve a positive purpose of the de-victimization of female gender goes as far as to claim that the large-scale human rights violations are not directed only against women qua women, but in the similar vein against men qua men, with “the variables of minority ethnicity, social class, and age [being] separated from gender for analytical purposes“ (Jones 2000a): in the conflict in Kosovo, for instance, the entire Serbian state juggernaut, the armed forces, the police, the paramilitaries, the militias, all aligned in their efforts to root out and punish ethnic Albanian men, simply because they were men, writes David Buchanan, one of the authors of the March 2002 special issue, in his text Gendercide and Human Rights (Buchanan 2002, 98). But why repeat something as lame as universal gender dichotomy? And why appropriate the same theoretical skeleton that is the main target of this critique? What is actually hiding behind this unfortunate account of gendercide presented by Jones et al. that wants to distinguish between the oppression of men and the oppression of other marginalized groups? 103 The Bizarro World (also known as Htrae) is a fictional planet in the American comics universe. Introduced in the early 1960s, Htrae is a cube-shaped planet, home to Bizarro and his companions, all of whom were initially Bizarro versions of Superman, Lois Lane and their children. In the Bizarro world of "Htrae" ("Earth" spelled backwards), society is ruled by the Bizarro Code which states "Us do opposite of all Earthly things! Us hate beauty! Us love ugliness! Is big crime to make anything perfect on Bizarro World!". Later, the mayor appoints Bizarro No. 1 to investigate a crime, "Because you are stupider than the entire Bizarro police force put together"; this is, however, intended and taken as a great compliment. If we apply this concept to the gendercide studies, it is obvious that in their universe everything is functioning exactly in the opposite way: men are victims, women are perpetrators, but what is more, this reversed situation is intended to be taken as a great compliment by the feminist scholars. While the concept of Bizarro World may have a certain charm within pop culture - it uses the famous technique of defamiliarization (ostranenie) - when applied within genocide studies, it is an oversimplified, not to mention a dangerous, concept. 104 In his text Gender and Genocide in Rwanda, Jones goes as far as to actually name the most notorious cases of female génocidaires: Pauline Nyiramasuhuko, Rose Karushara, Odette Nyirabagenzi, Athanasie Mukabatana and sister Julienne Kizito (Jones 2002, 83-84). For a discussion on the “subjective” violence or the violence with an easily identifiable agent, see supra note 16 and 17. 96 What seems to be the case here is a theoretically unsophisticated and almost childish reaction to both the feminist legal genocidalism and (radical) feminist theory in general, although this time disguised under the banner of political correctness that cowardly sustains something which it considers as theoretically inferior. As already stated above, the problem is not criticizing something that deserves to be criticized; the problem is the manner in which this critique is performed: gendercide studies seem to be offering us some sort of “payoff” against radical feminist theory by using the bodies of those who inhabit the Third World and who are insufficiently significant to be holding the copyrights to their miserable genocidal lives. As such, they are becoming actors in a movie that is supposed to teach us about all the mistakes that radical feminism has committed so far. If one can speculate that in the Rwandan genocide “a greater proportion of women than men participated voluntarily in the killings” (Jones 2002, 83), how could one possibly bestow any credibility to the radical feminist theory?; if one could have seen Odette Nyirabagenzi, “the terror of Rugenge”, sending her militia in pursuit of the Tutsi men of Rugenge, being physically present on every occasion when men were massacred and taking an active part in selecting the men who were to die (Jones 2002, 83), would one still be able to hold opinion with those who claim that women are less villain, more victim-like and more rapable? The theatrical stage has been set up again, but this time in the Bizzaro fashion in which naming the genocidal figures such as Odette Nyirabagenzi is functioning as an important approval of the post-radical and/or post-structural feminist theory, inasmuch as it sustains their primary principle that there is nothing fixed and definitive about anyone’s identity. In other words, claiming that women are even more ferocious than men should be understood as a compliment, as it finally elevates women from the status of victims and caretakers.105 And indeed, the most 105 Consider these sentences from Jones' text on the Rwandan genocide: „Nonetheless, the prominence of 97 influential response to this conceptual fraud written by Charli Carpenter has not been impregnated with any kind of “anger” over the fact that women are capable, more than often to a higher extent than men, of genocidal behavior; after all, why such anger in the midst of this enlightened era of post-dichotomic and post-radical thinking that allows for all sorts of gender identities? However, although her reaction paper is a very important attempt to clarify Jones’ confusion over the difference between varieties of sex and gender, Carpenter misses the point once she introduces broader political implications of the gendercide framework. 4.2 Staying within technicality of gendercide In her text Beyond ‘Gendercide’: Incorporating Gender into Comparative Genocide Studies, Carpenter argues that the problem with the concept of gendercide is that it confuses biological sex and social gender (Carpenter 2002). In the original article, Carpenter argues, Jones defines gendercide as “gender-selective mass killing” and specifically claims that gender can be defined primarily, if not exclusively, in terms of biological sex. Carpenter, on the other hand, disagrees and instead uses the term “sex-specific massacre” to describe what Jones has labeled gendercide. According to Carpenter, there are scholarly and political implications of the term gendercide that need to be distinguished here: whereas political implications of this term carry with them certain advantages, the scholarly ones need to be improved. On the one hand, Carpenter argues, gender is defined as bodies, as in genderselective human rights violations. On the other hand, gender is defined as ideas, as in masculinization of the enemy: not as brute facts of human biology, but as social facts such as genocidal women may have a certain predictive value, one that is profoundly relevant to the current debate over women, peace, and conflict . . . One must ask, in fact, whether 'the Rwanda test' does not substantially refute the equation of women and peace that has dominated much of the aforementioned debate“ (Jones 2002, 84). For a discussion on various human rights tests, see supra note 25 chapter 1). 98 ideologies, norms and intersubjective ascriptive characteristics. This not only makes for terribly confusing scholarship replete with analytical inconsistencies, enabling Jones, for example, to make the extraordinary statement that since Jews of both sexes had died, gender was far from a dominant consideration in the Holocaust; it also renders scholars incapable of distinguishing varieties of sex (biological and performative) and varieties of gender (structural and individual) to say nothing about capturing the interplay between them or identifying pressure points where political leverage could be brought to bear to create change, Carpenter argues (Carpenter 2002). Recalling the sex/gender distinction enables us to establish cases where gender is the cause and sex-specific outcomes the effect, but it also helps us distinguish between different gendered causes of sex-specific outcomes, Carpenter argues. When it comes to sex-specific massacre, as Carpenter calls Jones’ gendercide, gender can operate indirectly, as a “cultural schema” which channels men and women into separate spaces where they are at risk of different types of harm; or directly, as a “conscious ideology” of actors who may use sex as a proxy variable for socially constructed attributes - something that MacKinnon herself was proposing in her rape-as-genocide model, albeit her understanding of gender was identical to the one Jones uses in his gendercide model. As Carpenter continues, a pre-existing gender structure can generate sex-specific outcomes without any gender-selectivity on the part of particular policy-makers. If in any particular case we wish to explain sex-specific killing, one hypothesis is that men are disproportionately killed just because men happen to occupy the particular social roles that perpetrators consider threatening. If the target is not “adult males” but is “everyone in the military and political elite” (institutions which just happen to be male-dominated), then men will die more frequently. To use the converse example, where villages are attacked indiscriminately, women, children, and the elderly are often the 99 primary casualties because many adult males have either been conscripted, killed or have fled. In such cases, Carpenter claims, it is not that women and children are being targeted as such, but they simply happen to occupy the targeted location in greater numbers. Although gender ideology on the part of the perpetrators is irrelevant in these cases, it is still true that gender, as a pre-existing cultural system that has created sex-disproportionality in social institutions, has played a role in generating these outcomes.106 On the other hand, where gender ideology is the key factor, Carpenter argues, men may be specifically targeted because of perpetrators’ conscious beliefs regarding ascriptive characteristics of men. This was clearly the case in the Rwandan genocide, where even small boys were killed for fear that they would grow up to be RPF107 soldiers, while their sisters were spared as chattel for the Hutu militias. As Carpenter argues, this can be a deliberate and self-reflexive act. Thus killing may not be merely sex-specific, where men happen to be killed because of the social roles they inhabit, but sex-selective as well: men of a group are consciously selected, because of the assumption that they may possibly inhabit those roles, now or in the future. Gender structure, as Carpenter argues, may create sex-specific outcomes regardless of conscious thought on the part of the actors; on the other hand, gender ideology operates consciously in the decision-making process of those actors themselves. As she continues to argue, these too can be mutually reinforcing. However, gender ideologies can become robust even where gender structure has changed. In the U.S., for instance, the movement of women into previously male-dominated institutions such as the military has arguably done little to immediately change the masculinism of these institutional cultures. Even if women in a particular ethnic conflict are equally well armed 106 If it was not for a gender role in generating these outcomes, there would not be so many cases of rapes within armed conflicts in the first place. 107 RPF stands for the Rwandan Patriotic Front. 100 and likely to serve in rebel armies, the perception that it is the men who are combatants may result in sex-selective atrocity, and gender-motivated interventions by third parties under the assumption that “women and children” are innocent and vulnerable. In this sense, Carpenter has clarified something that for radical feminists and gendercide scholars did not have any importance. As Jones argues in his response to Carpenter’s text, the fact that the blurring of sex and gender is common in colloquial usage, as well as in much international discourse pertaining to women, might be regarded as conceptual laziness (sic), but it might also reflect the difficulty of distinguishing, in an analytically rigorous way, between biological sex and culturally-constructed gender (Jones 2003, 141). Nevertheless, in discussions on large scale human rights violations, the sex/gender distinction can be a crucial element for understanding the elements which led to either widespread rapes of women or mass scale killings of men. As Carpenter says, “’gender matters’ is no longer by itself a novel argument. The question is, ‘how, precisely?’” (Carpenter 2002, 85). Beyond this fuzzy conceptualization, Carpenter claims that the key problem with the gendercide concept is the manner in which it has been equated with genocide. This is due to a false analogy in Warren’s book and the misappropriation of her concept by Jones. In her path-breaking book, Warren writes that genocide is defined as the deliberate extermination of a race of people. By analogy, gendercide would be deliberate exterminations of persons of a particular sex. As Carpenter argues in her text, the Oxford dictionary defines genocide as extermination of a race, not just of some persons of that race. If any attack on mere persons of a particular race were genocide, regardless of the reason or the connectedness to a policy to destroy the whole group as such, then any racial killing would be genocidal, Carpenter claims; likewise, to be genocidal, attacks on men or on women must be connected to an intent to destroy men as a group or women as a group in order to be analogous to racial or 101 ethnic genocides. However, neither women nor men constitute a group that, as a whole, has been targeted for extermination of another group (members of the opposite sex); nor have sex-selective or sex-related atrocities generally been directed against men or women as such - by defining their otherness on the basis of their sex. According to Carpenter, it seems that this is the key factor that would justify Jones’ emphasis on biological sex as a basis for extermination in his reworked genocide definition. Nevertheless, this is not borne out in most of the cases the gendercide literature cites. Were there a case of women or men targeted because of their femaleness or maleness, as part of an attempt to wipe out women as women or men as men, in whole or in substantial part, that would be genocide, Carpenter concludes. It would be wrong to say that, technically speaking, Carpenter’s account of genocide and/or gendercide is incorrect: in a strictly technical sense, Jones’ elaboration on gendercide is purely fictional, inasmuch as destroying the opposite sex as a group has been running only through the lesbian SF literature or through a certain misogynist or misandrist imaginary scattered all over the planet. Nevertheless, what Carpenter does not seem to be acknowledging is that the classical radical feminist thought is as temporal as any other philosophical or political ideology that has once been actualized, fixated and made “available” to both historical and immanent temporality. In other words, radical feminist thought as we know it from the 1970s has been consumed in time and history, reformulated within the new international constellations and appropriated by the system of liberal antipluralism; it is still present, but endowed with a new reality and new institutionalized purpose. That is why to say, as Carpenter does, that “[s]ince technology could well provide the means of enacting a true genocide against either men or women as such on this basis, it is important not to dilute the concept of genocide against a sex by applying it to cases . . . 102 that are of a fundamentally different character” (Carpenter 2002, 87) is to stay within a spaceless and timeless technicality of the term “gendercide” and to entirely miss the point while claiming that any such political implications of this term could possibly carry some theoretical heaviness at this very moment in time and history. Therefore, Carpenter’s elaboration on the potential and true gendercide - or “genocide against a sex”, as she calls it - that would sometime in the future finally manage to correspond to the definition of genocide found in either the Oxford dictionary or the Genocide Convention is both lacking understanding of the dynamics of contemporaneous international politics and revealing one thoroughly alarming academic unwillingness to enter more deeply into the meaning of Jones’ and similar genocidalist propositions. Carpenter has made a valuable input by clarifying the sex/gender distinction, but has generally misunderstood the importance of mechanisms by which certain discursive factors interacted so that the very idea of gendercide moved beyond epistemic possibility and into something which is called discursive actuality. It is true that saying that “gender matters” is no longer by itself a novel argument; however, the question is not “how, precisely?”, but “why, precisely?” it matters? 4.3 On why gender matters Once again, it is necessary to make reference to the metonymical representation of the nonWestern world that functions here as an indicator of universal gender relations: by using gender as their primary theoretical tool in explaining the motivations behind genocidal events such as those in Rwanda or Bosnia, a certain part of Western academia is first and foremost depoliticizing the historico-political aspirations that led to such tragic outcomes in these countries. Moreover, by using these specific locations as metonymical representations of generic gender relations, they are at the same time distancing themselves as Western 103 subjects from the rapes and slaughters of the non-Western world. As in the case of MacKinnon’s rape-as-genocide model, gender equals ethnicity – Rwandan, Bosnian, Serbian… or any other non-Western ethnicity for that matter. In this sense, gender matters because it is a powerful tool for discussing the universal, but pointing to the particular. Consequently, the universal ceases to be universal and becomes condensed within particular, whereas everything that stays outside this condensed space functions as a neutral, post-gendered space that is, quite logically, impossible to associate with the particular. As such, everything that is outside this condensed space of particular is implicitly defined as fait accompli – it is resolved, it is advanced and it is -post. But let me put this in a less abstract way by introducing the case of the Rwandan genocide with the following questions: don’t we all feel the distance of space and time while reading about 800, 000 people being killed within the period of 100 days? And don’t we all consider it impossible for something like this to happen on the well protected and blessedly safe Western soil? Why do we use something as universal as male/female relations? Are we really that naïve as to think that the Rwandan genocide can be analyzed through such universal lenses? The only possible conclusion we would be able to come up with when discussing the Rwandan genocide through the universal lenses is that we simply cannot associate any aspect of our gender identities with the mass killings, rapes and slaughters perpetuated during the Rwandan genocide. Even if “[w]omen joke among each other about a world where there were no men” (Carpenter 2002, 87), as Carpenter notes, discussing the recruitment of women whose sole purpose would be the extermination of the whole (or part of) male Western population means inhabiting one thoroughly ungrounded theoretical position that Carpenter is inhabiting in her paper. As all of us are very much aware, genocide 104 of any kind does not happen in the West;108 this is the essence of the West defined by the West, sustained by the West, and controlled by the West. Therefore, encountering such an analysis would undoubtedly create the very feeling of estrangement from the genocidal events in Rwanda and help us conclude that we have nothing to do with these hardly intelligible male and female identities. This is exactly the moment when the universal ceases to be universal and becomes condensed within the particular territory of Rwanda. Also, this is the moment when everything that stays outside this condensed space - our everyday experience of well protected and blessedly safe Western soil - can easily be defined as fait accompli: if we have learned so far to cohabitate peacefully as men and women and to go through our lives without wishing to harm each other on such massive scale, then our very own experience can prove us that this battle of the sexes has been pretty much resolved in our case; if we have learned so far how to restrain ourselves from taking advantages of the opposite gender, then we simply must be advanced in one way or the other; if the gender dichotomy does not seem to be troubling us as nearly as it troubles those living outside the West, then we are simply ready for labeling our gender relations as –post.109 So why does gender matter? Gender matters because it helps to conceal all possible circumstances that 108 The fact that the genocide did happen in the West during the Second World War is the sole reason the West is re-affirming its civilizational supremacy through nazification of others and de-nazification of the West itself. What the West really needs is a complete historical dissociation from the concept of genocide, as the major obstacle to re-affirm its civilizational superiority has always been the Nazi Holocaust; the concept of “biological gender”, on the other hand, can run this process of dissociation and re-affirmation more smoothly. And indeed, in his text Jones is making a sort of genocide hierarchy and claiming that the Rwandan genocide, solely by reason of its gendered pattern, is simply without historical precedent: “The gendering of genocide in Rwanda bears comparison with many of the worst atrocities of the twentieth century. In the Armenian and Jewish genocides; the annihilation of Soviet prisoners of war during World War II; the massive slaughters in East Pakistan/Bangladesh and Indonesia; and the gendercides in Bosnia and Kosovo, a pattern of initial targeting of males is inescapably evident. The role of anti-male gendercide as a 'tripwire' or 'onset phase' of genocide should be one of the most powerful analytical weapons of anyone seeking to predict, confront, and end genocides. However, the Rwandan genocide, as we have seen, cannot be integrated into this framework without qualification: the elderly, children, and women were all swept up in the slaughter from its very first hours, though much less systematically than adult and adolescent males“ (Jones 2002, 87). 109 The same goes for the category of post-human that I consider extremely problematic and, briefly speaking, oriented towards a very subtle, but intense apologia of the technological progress. As Jokic argues in his text Genocidalism, academics can turn apologia into veritable art form (Jokic 2003). 105 brought about the events such as those in Rwanda. It matters because it strategically dehistoricizes our reality and makes the Western safety look natural and timeless. It matters because it gives the impression that the Western linear advancement does not carry the historico-political reasons for being advanced in the first place. Using spaceless and timeless gender means sustaining one ideology whose roots can be traced back to MacKinnon’s pamphletic texts from the beginning of the 1990s, but whose tentacles are hard to denounce in their overwhelming Deleuzian kind of virtuality. 106 Conclusion Ideas do not die. Not that they survive simply as archaisms. At a given moment they may reach a scientific stage, and then lose that status or emigrate to other sciences. Their application and status, even their form and content, may change: yet they retain something essential throughout the process, across the displacement, in the distribution of a new domain. Ideas are always reusable, because they have been usable before, but in the most varied of actual modes (Deleuze and Guattari 2009, 235). Although it may seem the radical feminist idea is a yesteryear's story, my assumption is that it has changed its form and content and actualized itself in various modes everywhere around us. Even the Sex and the City, one of the most popular shows ever, has been carrying the intensities and potentials of the radical thought, though this time within new domains of the so-called late capitalism and its pop culture. Though some would never connect it with MacKinnon’s remarks on the totalizing patriarchal structure, this show is thoroughly based upon the idea that women are inherent victims of social rules that constantly condition their utter vulnerability to men’s sexual desires. Such a displacement of a certain idea – from MacKinnon all the way to Sex and the City - can be perplexing and difficult to grasp, but its mere change of form and content should not prevent us from acknowledging its intensively radical re-usage. Regardless of its promotion of independent and emancipated womanhood, Sex and the City is essentially drawn from the radical feminist thought. Exactly the same process has happened in the case of radical feminist thought when it entered the realm of international law. In this sense, my thesis attempted to reveal that this “uneasy alliance” between radical feminism and international law is such only because we have presupposed 107 in advance that these various actual modes cannot contain the plurality of supposedly incompatible ideas. Radical feminism and international law do go together, but their alliance is conditioned by circumstances other than those from the 1970s and 1980s. On the other hand, this alliance is a symptom of one moment in time and history when a dominant system embraced the radical thought instead of dismissing it as a mere female blubbering. Therefore, the fact that such an alliance has actualized its existence within manifest discursive practices should be an excellent starting point for discussing a certain discursive (or epistemic) regime. In this particular one, it is very much accepted to use metonymical representations of the non-Western spaces in order to achieve legal goals and secure the conditions for legal prosecutions. As I have argued in my thesis, this practice is overwhelmingly present in areas other than the legal feminism, but it is in legal feminism that it has found its most intensive reproduction. These legal texts typically begin with big numbers and unfortunate facts about the violence perpetrated against women, but are usually accompanied by an enumeration of “distant” countries where such violence is “condensed” and is happening in fast motion. Subsequently, the category of gender - in all its biological meaning – merges with the notion of ethnicity and encourages the distancing from these unintelligible human forms and their intense becoming-gender-ethnicity. As Vali Nasr, Senior Advisor from the U.S. State Department, has argued at the BBC World Debate from Brussels Forum, in order to start a dialogue with them, we must first bring the Western kind of “space and time” to these countries.110 The way they are killing and raping each other is simply too condensed and way too fast for us. 110 BBC World Debate – Afghanistan: A Winnable War?, BBC World (March 26, 2010). 108 What I have discussed in my thesis has not been a product of reading certain texts where this information can be obtained, but a product of “sensing” the practices that install the “regime of sayability”: what is sayable is what is written within the controlling and paranoid practices of a certain regime. In this sense, the regime of sayability has been directing me towards assumptions which very often lack a straightforward relation to some of the texts, but are a result of my constant digging out and digging deeper into the soul of the regime, as Foucault writes in his Discipline and Punish. By detecting the cooperation between legal feminist genocidalism and the anti-pluralist liberal system I have been, at the same time, detecting the maladies of the Western soul that nurtures itself on the myths about the Balkan irremediable bellicosity. As stated by EurActive Network, the “EU's main objective for the Western Balkans region (South East Europe) is to create a situation where military conflict is unthinkable – expanding to the region the area of peace, stability, prosperity and freedom, established over the last fifty years in the European Union”.111 But if peace is expandable and follows the linear line of historical temporality, where was the Balkan region fifty years ago when the West was preparing itself for a major destruction? Was it on the other side of this linearity, ahead of the West, more civilized and peace-minded? By claiming what it claims, isn’t the West unconsciously acknowledging that the epicenter of the war and destruction lies exactly in the West, at the center of the European Union in Brussels or at the UN headquarters in New York? Nevertheless, by criticizing this structurally violent system, do we really want to apply such a childish Bizzaro theory of inverse relations that Jones has applied in the case of gender relations? And do we 111 “EU-Western Balkan Relations”, EurActive Network (14 December, 2007) [italics mine]. http://www.euractiv.com/en/enlargement/eu-western-balkans-relations-linksdossier-188295 109 really want to imply that the West should accept its destructive nature as a compliment, as it finally elevates it from this thoroughly traumatized status of innocent viewer of the fast motion movies coming from the non-Western counties? This is exactly what the terrorism has been doing so far: warning the West that its complicity in the nowadays wars and violence is way more serious than the West has been capable of imagining. However, terrorists have been doing this by spreading hatred towards the West and killing innocent people that, according to them, are never innocent and never only standbyers. A theory critical of the West must find alternatives to spreading violence and wishing for the “death” of the West. Instead, it should be capable of claiming that that which has been actualized is always a product of immense virtuality of possible interrelations and that the idea of the Serbian rape-machine is always already in us, disguised under the name of radical feminism, hiding beneath the frustrations of not-yet achieved equality, and floating in the air of sorrow over the unacknowledged, but ever-present fact that justice will never be achievable through the rule of law. Using the other to consolidate one’s inherently destabilized subjectivity should never be the answer. 110 Bibliography and works cited: Agamben, Giorgio. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998. Allison, Roy. The Soviet Union and the Strategy of Non-Alignment in the Third World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988. Arria, Diego E. Interview by Meliha Pihura, Esad Krcic and Belma Pekmezovic. Bilten Srebrenice, Year 7(36) (February 2006). <http://www.srebrenica.ba/?link=bilteni&b=7#br36> BBC World Debate – „Afghanistan: A Winnable War?.“ BBC World (March 26, 2010). Batinic, Jelena. “Feminism, Nationalism, and War: The ‘Yugoslav Case’ in Feminist Texts.“ Journal of International Women's Studies, 3(1)(2001): 2–23. Brownmiller, Susan. “Making Female Bodies the Battlefield.” In Mass Rape: the War against Women in Bosnia-Herzegovina. ed. A. Stiglmayer. Lincoln and London University of Nebraska Press, 1994. Buchanan, David. “Gendercide and Human Rights.” Journal of Genocide Research, 4(1) (2002): 95-108. Buss, Doris. “Prosecuting Mass Rape: Prosecutor v. Dragoljub Kunarac, Radomir Kovac and Zoran Vukovic.” Feminist Legal Studies, 10 (2002): 91-99. Butler, Judith. “Disorderly Woman.” Transition, 53 (1991): 86-95. ------------------. Precarious Life. The Powers of Mourning and Violence. London: Verso, 2006. Campbell, Kirsten. “The Gender of Transitional Justice: Law, Sexual Violence and the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia.” The International Journal of Transitional Justice, 1 (2007): 411-432. 111 Carpenter, Charli R. “Beyond ‘Gendercide’: Incorporating Gender into Comparative Genocide Studies.” The International Journal of Human Rights, 6(4) (Winter 2002): 77-101. Charlesworth, Hilary and Christine Chinkin. The Boundaries of International Law. Manchester: Manchester University Press, 2000. Charlesworth, Hilary, Christine Chinkin, and Shelley Wright. “Feminist Approaches to International Law.” The American Journal of International Law, 85(4) (October 1991): 613645. Conaghan, Joanne and Susan Millns. “Special Issue: Gender, Sexuality and Human Rights.” Feminist Legal Studies, 13 (2005): 1-14. Copelon, Rhonda. “Surfacing Gender: Reconceptualizing Crimes against Women in Time of War.” In Mass Rape: the War against Women in Bosnia-Herzegovina. ed. A. Stiglmayer. Lincoln and London: University of Nebraska Press, 1994. Deleuze, Gilles, and Félix Guattari. A Thousand Plateaus. Capitalism and Schizophrenia. London: Continuum, 2009. Douzinas, Costas. Human Rights and Empire. The Political Philosophy of Cosmopolitanism. Abingdon, New York: Routledge-Cavendish, 2007. Edkins, Jenny. “Humanitarianism, Humanity, Human.” Journal of Human Rights, 2(2) (June 2003): 253-258. Engle, Karen. “Feminism and Its (Dis)contents: Criminalizing Wartime Rape in Bosnia and Herzegovina.“ The American Journal of International Law, 99(4) (October 2005): 778-816. -----------------. “International Human Rights and Feminism: When Discourses Meet.” Michigan Journal of International Law, 13 (1992): 517-611. 112 ----------------. “Liberal Internationalism, Feminism, and the Suppression of Critique: Contemporary Approaches to Global Order in the United States.” Harvard International Law Journal, 46(2) (Summer 2005a): 427-439. “EU-Western Balkan Relations.” EurActive Network (14 December, 2007). <http://www.euractiv.com/en/enlargement/eu-western-balkans-relations-linksdossier188295> Gossett, Sherrie. “Former NY Times Reporter: 93 Pulitzer Should Be Revoked.” March 22, 2006. <http://www.spinwatch.org/-news-by-category-mainmenu-9/157-us-politics/2734- former-ny-times-reporter-93-pulitzer-should-be-revoked> Grewe, Wilhelm G. The Epochs of International Law. New York: de Gruyter, 2000. Gutman, Roy. “Roy Gutman: Granatiranje Knina nije bilo prekomjerno, a HV nije odgovoran za protjerivanje Srba.” Interview by Nacional, 3 (June 17, 2003). <http://www.nacional.hr/clanak/10622/roy-gutman-granatiranje-knina-nije-biloprekomjerno-a-hv-nije-odgovoran-za-protjerivanje-srba> Halley, Janet. “Rape at Rome: Feminist Interventions in the Criminalization of Sex-Related Violence in Positive International Criminal Law.” Michigan Journal of International Law, 30(1) (2009). ----------------. “Rape in Berlin: Reconsidering the Criminalisation of Rape in the International Law of Armed Conflict.” Melbourne Journal of International Law, 9(1) (May 2008): 78-125. Harding, Christopher. “Statist Assumptions, Normative Individualism and New Forms of Personality: Evolving a Philosophy of International Law for the Twenty First Century.” NonState Actors and International Law, 1(2) (2001): 107-125. Haritaworn, Jin, Tamsila Tauqir, and Esra Erdem. „Gay Imperialism: Gender and Sexuality Discourse in the 'War on Terror'.“ In Out of Place: Interrogating Silences in Queerness/Raciality. ed. A. Kuntsman and E. Miyake. York, UK: Raw Nerve Books, 2008. 113 Helms, E. “The ‘Nation-ing’ of Gender? Donor Policies, Islam, and Women’s NGOs in PostWar Bosnia-Herzegovina.” Anthropology of East Europe Review, 21(2) (2003). Henkin, Louis. International Law: Politics and Values. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1995. Holter, Oystein Gullvag. “A Theory of Gendercide.” Journal of Genocide Research, 4(1) (2002): 11-38. Jokic, Aleksandar. “Genocidalism.” The Journal of Ethics, 8 (2004): 251-297. Jones, Adam. “Gender and Genocide in Rwanda.” Journal of Genocide Research, 4(1) (2002): 65-94. ---------------. “Gendercide and Genocide.” Journal of Genocide Research, 2(2) (2000): 185211. ----------------. “Gendercide: a Response to Carpenter.” The International Journal of Human Rights, 7(1) (Spring 2003): 141-147. ---------------. “Of Rights and Men: Towards a Minoritarian Framing of Male Experience.” Journal of Human Rights, 1(3) (2000a): 387-403. Kennedy, David. Of War and Law. New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 2006. Kennedy, David. “The International Human Rights Movement: Part of the Problem?.“ Harvard Human Rights Journal, 15 (Spring 2002). MacKinnon, Catherine A. Are Women Human? And Other International Dialogues. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2006. ----------------------------------. “Rape, Genocide, and Women’s Human Rights.” In Mass Rape: the War against Women in Bosnia-Herzegovina. ed. A. Stiglmayer. Lincoln and London: University of Nebraska Press, 1994. 114 ----------------------------------. “Turning Rape into Pornography: Postmodern Genocide.” In Mass Rape: the War against Women in Bosnia-Herzegovina. ed. A. Stiglmayer. Lincoln and London: University of Nebraska Press, 1994. Mills, Alex. “The Private History of International Law.” International and Comparative Law Quarterly, 55(1) (2006): 1-51. Nikolic-Ristanovic, Vesna. Women, Violence and War: Wartime Victimization of Refugees in the Balkans. Budapest: Central European University, 2000. Nixon, Nicola. “Cinderella’s Suspicions: Feminism in the Shadow of the Cold War.” Australian Feminist Studies, 16(35) (2001): 209-223. O'Neill, Brendan. „A 'Legal War' Would Have Been Even Worse.“ March 11, 2008. <http://www.spiked-online.com/index.php/site/article/4860/> Orford, Anne. “Feminism, Imperialism and the Mission of International Law.” Nordic Journal of International Law, 71 (2002): 275-297. Puren, Nina, and Alison Young. “Signifying Justice: Law, Culture and the Questions of Feminism.” Australian Feminist Law Journal, 13 (1999): 3-13. Radcliffe, Sarah A., Nina Laurie, and Robert Andolina. “The Transnationalization of Gender and Reimagining Andean Indigenous Development.” Signs, 29(2) (2003): 387-416. Shibles, Warren. “Radical Feminism, Humanism and Women’s Studies.” Innovative Higher Education, 14(1) (Fall-Winter 1989): 35-47. Simpson, Gerry. “Two Liberalisms.” European Journal of International Law, 12(3) (2001): 537571. Tesón, Fernando R. A Philosophy of International Law. Oxford: Westview Press, 1998. Tonkens, Evelien, Menno Hurenkamp, and Jan Willem Duyvendak. Culturalization of Citizenship in the Netherlands, 2008. 115 <http://www.assr.nl/conferences/documents/StaffsempaperTonkens41108.pdf> Ward, Cynthia V. “Radical Feminist Defense of Individualism.” Northwestern University Law Review, 89(3) (1994-1995): 871-900. Wing, Adrien K. and Sylke Merchán. “Rape, Ethnicity, and Culture: Spirit Injury from Bosnia to Black America.” Columbia Human Rights Review, 25(1) (Fall 1993). Xavier Fellmeth, Aaron. “Feminism and International Law: Theory, Methodology, and Substantive Reform.” Human Rights Quarterly, 22 (2000): 658-733. Yuval-Davis, Nira and Floya Anthias. Woman-Nation-State. Palgrave Macmillan: London, 1989. Zizek, Slavoj. “Divine Violence and Liberated Territories.” Interview by Soft Targets. Los Angeles, March 14, 2007. <http://www.softtargetsjournal.com/web/zizek.php>. Legal sources websites (accessed 01-04-2010): CRIMES AGAINST HUMANITY: http://avalon.law.yale.edu/imt/imtconst.asp GENEVA CONVENTIONS: http://www.icrc.org/web/eng/siteeng0.nsf/html/genevaconventions#a1 GENOCIDE CONVENTIONS, 9 DECEMBER, 1948: http://www.icrc.org/ihl.nsf/385ec082b509e76c41256739003e636d/a2ec826e5d083098c125641e00 40690d?OpenDocument ICC: http://www.icc-cpi.int/menus/icc ICTY: http://www.icty.org/ ICTY STATUTE: http://www.icty.org/sections/LegalLibrary/StatuteoftheTribunal IHL: http://www.icrc.org/eng/ihl THE KUNARAC CASE: http://www.icty.org/cases/party/712/4 116