Department of Linguistics University of Cambridge Academic year 2010/2011 Dr. Luna Filipović Li2 Paper Lecture 2 Meaning Relations I. Meaning in Major Linguistic Approaches (a very short historical reminder) a) Structuralism (European: de Saussure; American: Bloomfield; Sense is created between words, not in isolation; syntagmatic and paradigmatic relations) b) Generativism (Meaning is generated from a universal deep structure into language-specific surface structures; generative syntax and generative semantics) c) Cognitivism (not a unified approach; explores the dynamics between language and other cognitive structures; Pinker’s language instinct vs. Fodor’s modularity vs. Levinson’s biocultural symbiosis) d) Typological approaches to language will be tackled separately in Lecture4. II. Traditional view of meaning relations: sense relations a) synonymy (e.g. glasses/spectacles) b) antonymy (e.g. old/new) c) homonymy(e.g.light1/light2);homography(bow1/bow2); homophony(tail/tale) d) polysemy (e.g. foot of the mountain) e) metonymy (e.g. Kant is hard to understand.) f) metaphor (e.g. Richard is a wolf.) g) hyponymy (fruit/apple) III. Theoretical approaches to word meaning and meaning relations a) CA (traditional: crunching lexical items down to basic meaning components; no hierarchy of components; however, components are not necessarily more basic than the whole item: kill vs. cause to be not alive) b) Field theory (lexemes are of the same word class and their meanings have something in common; e.g. furniture, colour, etc.) c) Prototype Theory (prototypes are ‘better members’; graded membership in a category; If robin is a prototype bird, what is a prototype of robin?; makes more sense to assume that the prototype is an abstract case defined by a concept that fixes certain features and leaves others open; however: flexible category boundaries suggest inherent vagueness, which is not a negative quality!) d) Semantic Primitives (Wierzbicka’s NSM – Natural Semantic Metalanguage; set of primitives and syntax for their combination; a semantic primitive is indefinable and universal; X feels envy=sometimes a person thinks something like this: something good happened to this other person, it did not happen to me, I want things like this to happen to me, because of this, this person feels something bad, X feels something like this) IV. Recent developments (in cognitively-oriented theories) a) Jackendoff’s universals (1995, 1997, 2003) THING, PLACE, DIRECTION, EVENT, MANNER, PATH, AMOUNT E-language (“real world”) vs. I-language (“projected world”) 1. A tiger has stripes (true or false? Does not matter because it is of no concern for the understanding what the sentence means.) 2. The lamp is standing on the floor. [THING] occupies [PLACE] 3. The dog went into the room. [Event GO ([Thing DOG], [Path TO ([Place IN ([Thing ROOM])])])] (Jackendoff 1995: 183) Central hypothesis: The grammatical aspects of language make reference only to Conceptual Structure (CS), not to Spatial Structure (SpS) and that nothing in grammar depends on, for example, detailed shapes of objects (Jackendoff 2003). However, some examples to the contrary can be found, such as languages that have classifier systems that depend on coarse object shapes (e.g. the Japanese classifier hon which is used for skinny objects. Furthermore, empirical studies do indeed exist and they provide evidence that there is a persistent reliance on lexicalized language-specific concepts even in tasks that are not explicitly linguistic (cf. Levinson 2003a, 2003b; Lucy 1992; Lucy and Gaskins 2003). For example, Lucy (1992) explained how Yukatek Mayan speakers classify objects according to material rather than to shape as preferred by English speakers as a consequence of categories of grammatical number and of numeral classifiers available in that language. b) Levinson’s (2003a, b) Neo-Whorfian proposal IN spatial scene is not a universal Shape discriminations: Karuk postposition ‘though a tube’, Nishga locative proclitics encoding ‘on something horizontal’ (Levinson 2003a). Some locative verbs make contrastive pairs based on shape, as in the Tzeltal contrast between ‘be in a hemispherical container’ and ‘be in a cylindrical container’ (cf. Brown 1994). IN cannot be a universal concept and should not be annotated as such. Japanese conflates OVER and ON, Tzeltal has just one preposition to cover the scenes of OVER, UNDER, ON, IN and THROUGH, while some languages have no adpositions at all (Jaminjung or Arrernte). Yélî Dnye has two IN concepts (i.e. forms dedicated to containment) and six forms to cover the semantic space subsumed by the English ON or ABOVE (Levinson 2006). Basically “no agreement as to what constitutes an IN spatial scene, a spatial relation of containment or any other basic topological relation”. There are vanishingly few universals of language in the direct sense that all languages exhibit them” (Evans and Levinson 2009: 429) V. What the make of the universal vs. language-specific dynamics? Jackendoff’s Conceptual Structure Hypothesis proposes a single universal level of mental representations (Jackendoff 1995). What follows directly from this isomorphism between the semantic and the conceptual level of representation is that if languages differ in crucial aspects of lexicalization in a cognitive domain (e.g. space), then so does the corresponding conceptualization of relations within that domain. This is certainly not something that Jackendoff advocates, but it is a possible consequence of such an isomorphism between the two levels of representation. In essence, the role of semantics as a language-specific intermediate level is something that is of no consequence for conceptualization, which is universal. Levinson (2003a) and Levinson and Wilkins (2006) argue that the ways in which languages organise spatial notions are based on atomic concepts such as contact, vertical relation, adhesion, containment, not molar (complex) concepts like ON or IN. Simple conflation of semantics and conceptual structure is not defensible, but if we assume a kind of partial isomorphism, decompositional theories can explain how it is possible to learn a language by building up complex constructs from more elementary concepts. However, it need not be an either-or issue and Levinson argues along these lines that there are two levels of representation: decompositional and noncompositional. See Filipović (in press) for more details And remember: Habitual processing happens on the molar level (Levinson 2003a,b) References (with Advanced Reading in bold): Bohnemeyer, J and Stolz, C. 2006. Spatial reference in Yukatek Maya: A survey. In S. C. Levinson and D. Wilkins (eds.), (pp. 273-310). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bowerman, M. and Choi, S. 2003. Space under construction: Language-specific spatial categorization in first language acquisition. In D. Gentner and S. GoldinMeadow (eds.), Language in Mind (pp. 387-427). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Brown, P. 1994. The INs and ONs of Tzeltal locative expressions: The semantics of static descriptions of location. Linguistics 32: 743-790. Evans, N. and Levinson, S. C. 2009. The myth of language universals: Language diversity and its importance for cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32(5): 429-492. Filipović, L. (in press) Spatial reference in discourse. In Jaszczolt, K. and Allan, K. (Eds.) Handbook of Pragmatics. Cambridge: CUP. Jackendoff, R. 1995. Semantics and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press Jackendoff, R. 1997. The Architecture of the Language Faculty. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Jackendoff, R. 2003. Foundations of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Levinson, S.C. 2003a. Space in Language and Cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Levinson, S. C. 2003b. Language and Mind: Let’s get the issues straight! In D. Gentner and S. Goldin-Meadow (eds.), Language in Mind (pp. 25-45). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Levinson, S. C. 2006. The language of space in Ye´lıˆ Dnye. In Levinson, S.C. and Wilkins, D. (eds.), (pp. 157-205). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Levinson, S.C. and Wilkins, D. 2006. Towards a semantic typology of spatial description. In Levinson, S.C. and Wilkins, D. (eds.), (pp. 512-552). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Levinson, S.C. and Wilkins, D. (eds.) 2006. Grammars of Space. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lucy, J. 1992. Language Diversity and Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lucy, J. and Gaskins, S. 2003. Interaction of language type and referent type in the development of nonverbal communication. In D. Gentner and S. Goldin-Meadow (eds.), Language in Mind (pp. 465-492). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Vandeliose, C. 2003. Containment, support and linguistic relativity. In H. Cuykens, R. Dirven and J. Taylor (eds.), Cognitive Approaches to Lexical Semantics (pp. 393-425). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Vandeliose, C. 2006. Are there spatial prepositions? In M. Hickman and S. Robert (eds.), Space in Languages: Linguistic Systems and Cognitive Categories (pp. 149-154). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.