LOL AC Practical thought can be centered on a conception of the ought as grounded in the notion of the proper function of a being or on abstract morality. Elizabeth Anscombe explains, The terms “should” or “ought” or “needs” relate to good and bad: e.g. machinery needs oil, or should or ought to be oiled, in that running without oil is bad for it, or it runs badly without oil. According to this conception, of course, "should" and "ought" are not used in a special "moral" sense when one says that a man should not bilk. (In Aristotle's sense of the term "moral" [ήθικός], they are being used in connection with a moral subject matter: namely that of human passions and [non_technical] actions.) But they have now acquired a special so_called "moral" sense-_i.e. a sense in which they imply some absolute verdict (like one of guilty/not guilty on a man) on what is described in the "ought" sentences used in certain types of context: not merely the contexts that Aristotle would call "moral"_-passions and actions_-but also some of the contexts that he would call "intellectual." The ordinary (and quite indispensable) terms "should," "needs," "ought," "must"_-acquired this special sense by being equated in the relevant contexts with "is obliged," or "is bound," or "is required to," in the sense in which one can be obliged or bound by law, or something can be required by law. The functional ought makes reference to the characteristic activity of a thing under its natural conditions. A thing can deviate from its characteristic function by becoming impaired i.e. as we can say that a good watch and a bad watch are distinguished by how effectively they keep time. Deducing norms from functional character is necessary because (1) the only coherent use of the word “good” is attributive i.e. in the sense of a good car or a good watch; there is no content to the idea of something being good all on its own whereas reference to the purpose of the thing yields content, (2) If the functional view is wrong there will be no justifiable inference from factual premises to oughts, so all ought premises would have to be warranted by other oughts, and norms would have no foundation, (3) if we could talk about “good” in the abstract we would be able to coherently infer from “x is a good car” that “x is a good” and “x is a car” but it makes no sense to talk about x being “a good”. Since the object of the resolution is the criminal justice system this means that saying what the system ought to do can only be done with reference to the purpose of the system. The criminal justice system is an artifact rather than a naturally occurring being meaning that its functional ought makes no reference to practical norms generally because it is possible to create artifacts that serve exclusively bad purposes. One can say that a poison ought to kill someone when used even if killing is immoral because the function for which poison is created is to kill. The criminal justice system is individuated by (a) the fact that belongs to the US and (b) the fact that it has whatever constitutive role it plays in the governmental structure because if it were defined by relevant law governing it then we would say that the US has a new justice system every time the law changed. Functional aspects of other governmental institutions do not bear on the resolution because the criminal justice system is a sub unit of the government on the whole so norms applicable to the whole do not apply to the part for instance the function of the heart is to pump blood but the function of the body on the whole is not to pump blood meaning that functional arguments related to other aspects of government do not apply to the resolution. Appeals courts are a different functional unit of the government because the power to determine who is guilty is distinct from the power to determine where the law lies. Rawls explains the constitutive character of punishment: One might say, however, that the utilitarian view is more fundamental since it applies to a more fundamental office, for the judge carries out the legislator's will so far as he can determine it. Once the legislator decides to have laws and to assign penalties for their violation (as things are there must be both the law and the penalty) an institution is set up which involves a retributive conception of particular cases. It is part of the concept of the criminal law as a system of rules that the application and enforcement of these rules in particular cases should be justifiable by arguments of a retributive character. The decision whether or not to use law rather than some other mechanism of social control, and the decision as to what laws to have and what penalties to assign, may be settled by utilitarian arguments; but if one decides to have laws then one has decided on something whose working in particular cases is retributive in form. The application of non-retributive considerations to actions taken by the criminal justice system turns the system into a mechanism of promoting some end other than applying the law. The basic requirement of retributive acts in legal terms is mens rea or psychological dimension of the crime for the system to serve its purpose then laws must be applied in accordance with the relevant mens rea – this means laying down the relevant sentence given the degree to which the guilty is culpable so my standard is application of mens rea categories that track differences in responsibility. I contend that application of the diminished capacity defense, when relevant, to juveniles satisfies the requirements of mens rea practice while juvenile sentencing does not. Juvenile jurisprudence absolves the accused of criminal liability as though they were completely non-culpable. Michele Cotton writes, It may now be difficult to believe, but at one time the juvenile justice system was willing to explicitly denominate itself as "deterministic." Justice White remarked that while "the criminal law proceeds on the theory that defendants have a will and are responsible for their actions[,] ... . for the most part, the juvenile justice system rests on more deterministic assumptions." Thus, "reprehensible acts by juveniles are not deemed the consequence of mature and malevolent choice but of environmental pressures (or lack of them) or of other forces beyond their control.” Similarly, one federal court described juvenile justice's rehabilitative ideal as "rooted in a determinist view of young people" that sees them as "essentially products of their environments and so not yet responsible for their own acts." Along the same lines, the Nevada Supreme Court explained that “the juvenile court from its inception in Illinois in 1899 until approximately the middle of this century was a child-centered institution based on theories taken from the positive school of criminology and especially on the deterministic principle that youthful law violators are not morally or criminally responsible for their behavior but, rather, are victims of their environment.”1 The assumption that juveniles are fully non-culpable assimilates them to a mens rea category with the criminally insane, which is palpably wrongheaded. Rational action is the power of acting for reasons, and this power is not absent just because someone can act for bad reasons. Even young children are obviously capable of rationalizing decisions. Gerry Maher 1 writes, In my view the assimilation of the infant and the insane is misleading. It tries to squeeze into the age-based defense the same justification as that used for insanity, namely that the person accused of an offense is completely lacking in practical rationality. But this does not seem as obviously true of children as it is for the mentally disordered. Children of a certain age (and often of a young age) can give reasons for doing what they do. distorted in the same way as those provided by the mentally disordered (“fairies told me to do it”), but Sometimes these reasons seem usually children explain actions in terms of coherent reasons which make (some) sense of the world around us. Rather the point is that as adults we judge that children have a defective or incomplete capacity to consistently apply or act out their motivations or J.D. NYU Law School PhD Brandeis. “A FOOLISH CONSISTENCY: KEEPING DETERMINISM OUT OF THE CRIMINAL LAW” 15 B.U. Pub. Int. L.J. 1. 1 reasons for acting. Children, even at a relatively early age (in other words when they proceed beyond infancy), have the capacity for rational action.2 Apart from the criminally insane, irrationality sufficient to defeat culpability is not present in persons – deprivations of culpability are scalar in character. David Brink 1 writes, Normative competence can be compromised in various ways that the law recognizes. The insane and the severely mentally retarded lack normative competence and, as a result, are not responsible. But normative competence is not an all or nothing matter, and there is good reason to suppose that immaturity involves a form of reduced or diminished normative competence. Normative competence involves the cognitive ability to discriminate right from wrong but also the affective and conative abilities to regulate one’s emotions, appetites, and actions in accordance with this normative knowledge. the ability to refrain from acting on one’s good-independent desires that is necessary to being guided by one’s good-dependent desires. One central ingredient in normative competence is impulse control – All of these capacities appear to be scalar insofar as they can be possessed to different degrees. The gradual development of this competence is what marks normal normative progress through childhood and adolescence to maturity.3 Emotional volatility, susceptibility to peer pressure, and the ongoing development of the structure of the frontal lobes hamper the application of capacities for practical self-management but do not undercut agency wholesale. No one doubts that juveniles have the capacity to act for reasons and with foresight. Failure to accommodate scalar variation in culpability leads to sentencing inconsistent with mens rea. David Brink 2 writes, Older mature adolescents will often be significantly, if not fully, normatively competent. So they can be largely, if not fully, responsible for committing heinous crimes. Under the traditional juvenile sentencing rules that require juvenile sentences to expire by the age of majority, such offenders are unlikely to receive sentences commensurate with their wrongdoing. Indeed, there is a puzzle for the traditional juvenile sentencing system that the older and more responsible the offender the less time is he eligible to serve for his crimes.4 Criminal code currently incorporates the notion of scalar culpability under the partial responsibility 2 Queen's Counsel and Professor of Law at University of Edinburgh. “Age and Criminal Responsibility”. OSU Journal of Criminal Law Vol. 2:493. 3 Professor of Law and Philosophy at UC San Diego. “Immaturity, Normative Competence, and Juvenile Transfer: How (Not) to Punish Minors for Major Crimes.” Texas Law Review Vol. 82 2004. 4 Brink. defense. Stephen Morse 1 explains, Partial responsibility is a form of lesser legal insanity: The defendant is claiming that, as a result of mental abnormality, he is not fully responsible for the crime proven against him. Even if the technical elements of an offense are satisfied, the defendant is less culpable and should be convicted of a lesser crime, or, at least, should be punished less severely.5 The basis of distinction here is scalar. Morse 2 continues, The rationales for holding a defendant partially responsible and for excusing him by reason of insanity differ only in degree. The preconditions for moral and legal responsibility are, inter alia, that the actor is reasonably rational and in control of his actions. Actors, such as small children, who lack reasonable cognitive or volitional capacity through no fault of their own may be dangerous, but are not considered fully responsible as moral agents. This basic intuition about the way cognitive and volitional capacity relate to responsibility is tracked by the insanity defense tests, which all focus on the actor's irrationality (e.g., lacks substantial capacity to appreciate the criminality of his actions) and/or lack of self-control (e.g., lacks substantial capacity to conform his actions to the requirements of law). Although the law draws a bright line for legal responsibility, human cognitive and volitional capacities and behaviors are clearly distributed along a very lengthy continuum of competence. All legally sane defendants will not be equally rational or equally in possession of self-control at the time of the prohibited act. When a legally sane defendant has impaired rationality or self-control because of mental abnormality -- a cause he is allegedly unable to control -- an argument for some form of lessened responsibility arises.6 So wherever there is evidence that a given juvenile has diminished agency the common law justifies appeal to a partial responsibility defense to downgrade the severity of the crime or sentence. My argument is not that all juveniles have legitimate grounds for a partial responsibility defense but rather that if youth is correlated with diminishing grounds then the adult legal system already incorporates the proper remedy. Even if most juveniles have these features to ascribe them to the whole class is to commit a probabilistic fallacy. Probabilities are systemic properties that are not held by individuals – if there are five red marbles in a bag of ten, the probability that any marble drawn will be red is .5, but this doesn’t mean that the probability that any particular marble will be .5 – it will or won't be red so the probability will be 0 or 1. Similarly juveniles may be more likely to have culpability mitigating traits but that doesn't license a categorical distinction on that basis. The diminished responsibility defense recognizes this fact. 5 Professor of Law at USC. “Undiminished Confusion in Diminished Capacity.” 75 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 1984. 6 Professor of Law at USC. “Undiminished Confusion in Diminished Capacity.” 75 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 1984. The assimilation of juveniles to this framework makes sense of the exact manner in which they are less culpable. Gerry Maher 2 writes, Accordingly if there is an analogy to be used here it is between children and the category of persons formerly known as psychopaths. Both have the capacity for engaging in rational action but both, for very different reasons, find it difficult to apply it in a consistent way. The criminal responsibility of the psychopath is, to put it mildly, controversial, even more so than that of persons who are more definitely mentally disordered. Yet even if the analogy is weak, there is an interesting consequence. A dominant (but far from exclusive) view about psychopaths is that they are not completely lacking in criminal responsibility. Their responsibility for their conduct is incomplete. As a consequence, although the psychopathic criminal may be liable to conviction, his condition has relevance at the punishment (or disposal) stage of the criminal justice system. In my view much the same holds in respect of children. On this basis children are responsible agents, but their responsibility is in some way defective or incomplete. Some writers have described this situation by using the Scots law term “diminished responsibility.”7 This application has an established role in common law jurisprudence. Franklin Zimring writes, To consider immaturity as a species of diminished responsibility has some historic precedent but little analytic pedigree. Children below seven were at common law not responsible for criminal acts by reason of incapacity, while those between seven and fourteen were the subject of special inquiries with respect to capacity.8 7 Queen's Counsel and Professor of Law at University of Edinburgh. “Age and Criminal Responsibility”. OSU Journal of Criminal Law Vol. 2:493. 8 Professor of Law at UC Berkeley. “ Toward a Jurisprudence of Youth Violence.” 24 Crime & Just. 477 1998.