www.victoria.ac.nz/atp/ Link to this article: http://www.victoria.ac.nz/atp/articles/pdf/Shilliam-2009.pdf Citation: Shilliam, Robbie, “The Enigmatic Figure of the Non-Western Thinker in International Relations”, in AntePodium, Victoria University of Wellington, 2009. The Enigmatic Figure of the non-Western Thinker in International Relations Introduction In one of those cruel, yet revealing, moments of historical fate, the Government of Iran sponsored a meeting in 1998 of the UN General Assembly with the aim of countering the Huntington “clash of civilizations” thesis. 2001 was to be designated the year of a “dialogue of civilizations”. In one of those strange, yet telling, silences in responses to the post-9/11 “war on terror”, the dialogue amongst critical scholars in International Relations (IR) has predominantly centered upon the tensions within one “civilization”, the West, especially with regards to the ambivalent relationship between liberalism, security and freedom in Europe and the USA.1 Post-9/11 debates in IR over the form and content of ethics in world politics lack any sustained consideration of non-Western frameworks that deal with this ethical challenge.2 In fine, discussions of the post 9/11 world in IR show a tendency to ignore or even exclude existing engagements with the ethics of world politics from outside what 1 See, for example, Behnke (2004); Buzan (2006); and the collection of essays edited by Walker (2006). 2 See, for example, two recent forums: “Ethics in World Politics: Cosmopolitanism and Beyond?” Brassett and Bulley (2007); and “A Useful Dialogue? Habermas and International Relations” Diez and Steans (2005). might be called the “Western canon” of thought.3 This marginalization is amplified by the provincialisation of the descriptor “international” as, effectively, the domain of Anglo-American culture.4 And yet, as the call by the then President of Iran, Mohammed Khatami for a “dialogue of civilizations” shows,5 there exist many such engagements. There has, for example, been a sustained debate in Islamic jurisprudence regarding the “law of minorities” where Muslims living in the nonMuslim world can no longer be treated as transients but permanent residents.6 It is notable, to say the least, that this sophisticated and pre-existing discussion of the challenge to Muslims presented by living in a world of cultural plurality has been so under-represented in the IR debate.7 But in truth, the “war on terror” is only the latest historical episode that highlights the impoverished treatment of non-Western thinkers in IR. Exceptions, of course, exist. One is immediately reminded, for example, of the World Order Models Project (WOMP) initiated in the 1960s and charged with interrogating global problems of war and poverty through a cross-cultural perspective.8 Traces of this project still exist in the discipline, especially, for example, in a series of investigations into Islamic, Chinese and Japanese “schools” of thought on world order – past and present. This work is important in that it has highlighted different definitions of categories such as “sovereignty” and the “international” to those deriving from Western traditions of thought, as well as deeper philosophical differences related to the concepts of order, justice and change.9 In addition, intellectuals such as Frantz Fanon, Edward Said and Ashis Nandy, who in varying degrees have been situated both inside and outside the Western Academy have been on occasion used within IR scholarship to interrogate the essentialization of cultural identities.10 In fact, if we take a broader view, we start to glean the spectral presence of a thinking and acting non-Western subject at the very centre of the discipline’s historical development. It should not be forgotten that in the first years of the “American Century” 1949 Western philosophers and political scientists were engaging (often through what we would now consider sophisticated analyses) with the problem of cultural difference in international relations.11 And the so-called “god-father” of American Realpolitik, Hans Morgenthau, believed that, rather than Russian communism, East-Asian independence movements presented the deepest ethical challenge to US foreign policy making.12 Moreover, if the “English School” can be criticized as having built a Eurocentric narrative of the historical rise of international 3 Linklater (2005) typifies the less critical thinking on the subject by claiming that, even though nonWestern communities have in principle the resources to embark on Habermasian-style dialogic politics, Western civilization provides the ideal conditions. 4 See Smith (2002). 5 Khatami (2000). 6 See especially the works of Tariq Ramadan (1999). On the wider project of pursuing Islamic knowledge and eschewing both poles of fundamentalism and secularism see Sulayman (1987); Soroush (2000); and Euben (2002). 7 Exceptions include Hashmi (1998); Mandaville (2001); and Piscatori (2003). 8 See Mendlovitz (1975). 9 On how the classical “sociology” of Ibn Khaldun might speak to contemporary IR theory see Cox (1995); and Pasha (1997). On China see Mitter (2003); Chan (1999); Deng (1998). On Japan see Nakano (2007); Ong (2004); and Jones (2002). 10 Agathangelou and Ling (2004); Jarvis (2001); Persaud (1997); Blaney and Inayatullah (1994). 11 See, for example, Bozeman (1960); Iyer (1965); and Northrop (1949). 12 Morgenthau (1960), 134-137. society, (expanding outward from its post-Catholic European milieu to encompass, after decolonization, the world), it cannot be criticized for having ignored the practical and ethical challenges to this expansion from extra-European political forces.13 Crucially, for the purposes of this article, the enigma of the non-West in IR is not so much created by treating the majority of the earth’s surface as an “arena” or “theatre” in or upon which “international relations” plays out. Rather, the enigma arises from the possibility that this terrain is occupied by subjects who think on the same broad processes of modern world development engaged with by the Western Academy. To clarify the importance of this point it is helpful to briefly travel back in time to the point where many of the modern divisions of the social sciences were established in the Academy. It was in the comparative tradition of knowledge production, developed in the later eighteenth century, that what might be termed non-Western thought was most systematically explored through social-scientific enlightenment idioms.14 Comparative studies developed out of the philological tradition,15 both of which shared a special affinity to Indian studies.16 For example, Artifacts brought back by officials of the East India Company awoke Johann Gottfried von Herder and Friedrich Schlegel to Sanskrit, an empirical linguistic and religious touchstone for future romanticism in German thought.17 But perhaps the most important development in comparative studies was its turn from Philology towards Philosophy. After all, the question of who can “think” and produce valid knowledge of human existence has always been a political one, and was made all the more so when Georg Hegel gave the philosopher a central role in the development and cultivation of the modern self. However, it was Hegel who also narrated the trajectory of this development as moving from the East to the West. It is hard to consider Hegel an ideologue of European colonialism in the directly complicit way that, for example, John Locke was. Nevertheless, Hegel’s grand narrative of world development was, in part, informed by a deep pre-existing current in Enlightenment thought that had already started to draw a temporal division between a modern Western Europe and a non-modern Rest.18 This intellectual privileging of European “being” was contemporaneous to the rise to dominance by certain European powers over existing circuits of world commerce, the accumulation by these powers of overseas colonies, as well as their consolidation of control over the slave trade including the concomitant construction of plantation systems in the Americas. Comparative studies paradoxically posited a universal standard of civilization modeled upon Western Europe, but at the same time denied the colonial relation through which this standard was rising to dominance by treating non-Western cultures and societies as self-referential entities.19 In this sense, the enigmatic character of the non-Western thinker in the Western Academy is a testimony to the influence of the imperial and colonial historical context 13 See for example, Bull (1984); and Gong (1984), esp. ch.4. Although exposure to the Amerindians had already affected European debates on, for example, natural law. 15 Panniker (1988),117. 16 Bilimoria (2003), 342; Halbfass (1985). 17 Davies (1998), 62-74. 18 On Hegel see Inayatullah and Blaney (2007). In general see Fabian (1983). 19 See in general Panikkar (1988); and Krishna (1988). 14 in which the edifice of the modern social sciences was – at the very least partially constructed. And in the spirit of this critique, I would assert that IR is far overdue an explicit and sustained engagement with non-Western thought in order to further expose an “international” masquerading as, overwhelmingly, an Anglo-American province . This engagement might help to retrieve the global, rather than European or Western context within which thought on the “modern experience” has been developed. The retrieval of this context, in turn, might provide deeper insights into the racial, religious, and cultural dimensions of a global modernity shaped so fundamentally by colonialism and Western expansionism, insights that are right now desperately needed for a discipline so closely implicated in Western foreign policy making. In this article I contribute to this retrieval by discussing some of the immediate and urgent challenges that arise from attempting to re-present non-Western thinkers on modernity from within the Western Academy. Firstly, I discuss the dangers – but also the necessity of – constructing a corpus of “non-Western thought”. Secondly, I sketch out the ways in which non-Western thought on modernity challenges standard categorizations and conceptualizations of the “modern” experience. Thirdly, I consider the extent to which critical Western traditions of political thought can act as a substitute for the marginalized voice of the non-Western thinker. I conclude with some provocations regarding the relationship between IR, the Western Academy, and the Postcolonial project. Is the non-Western thinker a valid subject? Any interrogation of non-Western thought must, above all, be aware of the historical tendency for the Western Academy to orientalize the non-Western subject.20 For example, Western intellectuals contributed much to the thesis that the success of the East Asian Tigers in the 1980s was due to the preservation of Confucianism: “Asian values” are, at least to a certain extent, also Western inscribed values. 21 To guard against this Orientalism, we must be aware of the possibility of the complicity of Western influence within what is categorized as non-Western “traditions” of thought. A body of thought only becomes inscribed as “traditional” thought when it is threatened or disturbed by contending bodies of thought. For example, a number of Chinese intellectuals eagerly adopted Western philosophical terminology at the end of the nineteenth century. It was at this point that previous traditions of Chinese thought were retrospectively recognized within the new linguistic idiom and Chinese philosophy ceased to exist as a lived “tradition”.22 Moreover, much non-Western thought comes to us already having internalized the Eurocentric categorization of the non-West as “other”. This “reverse Orientalism”23 is evident, for example, in the “Kyoto” school of philosophy wherein famous intellectuals often sought to give value to the East in the global order by virtue of its negative (spiritual) complementarity to the (rational) enlightenment values of the West.24 Nowhere is the complicity of the West in the production of non-Western political thought more pronounced than in the various doctrines of post-colonial nationalism. Indian nationalism has long been 20 Said (1995). Bell and Chaibong (2003), 2. 22 Defoort (2001). 23 Dallmayr (1994), 529. 24 Jones (2003), 143. 21 characterized in the post-colonial literature as a project of European modernity embarked upon by the subaltern intellectual even in resistance to the dominating effects of this modernity.25 And yet doctrines of post-colonial nationalism also remind us that the categorization of West and non-West cannot be easily dismissed by virtue of its (orientalist) constructed nature. For, if a construct, the non-West is nevertheless a construct of concrete historical relations of domination that continue to reverberate and inform in the present lived experiences of Western and non-Western subjects. With this in mind, I would argue that rather than approaching non-Western thought through an either/or approach - that is to say either a distinct body of thought or variations of a universal theme - it must be approached as existing as part of a relation of a process of domination. But how to best approach such a loaded term as domination? We should be especially aware of notions of “cultural imperialism” that presume the colonial encounter to have consisted of a one-way relationship comprising the exploitation of a passive victim.26 As Albert Memmi and Ashis Nandy have insightfully documented, the colonial relation had a negative effect upon the colonizer – and the culture of the “mother country” – as well as upon the colonized.27 If to different extents and with different impacts, both subjects of the colonial relation could nevertheless be considered “victims”. And if this is the case, it follows that so could both colonizer and colonized, again if to different extents and with different impacts, be considered agents of transformation, or at the very least, possessors of agency. Indeed, when browsing the recent historical record it is not possible to explain every non-Western engagement with the West as one of pure and simple domination. For example, Japan did not come under direct (and comparatively brief) Western domination until the end of World War Two, and not until attempting its own Western inspired – if substantively differentiated28 – colonial project in Asia while attempting an entry into Western dominated “international society” (through the League of Nations) as a racial equal. In fact, the Western script of modernity has never simply been written onto a blank paper to be internalized by the non-Western mind. Non-Western intellectuals, rather than assimilate the message, have just as much copied this script (out of command, necessity, pre-emption or inventiveness) into existing narratives for pragmatic, political and ethical purposes other than what the meaning of the script was intended for. Crucially, this means that the act of translation is generative of novel meanings and concepts.29 Vincente Rafael’s work on Spanish attempts to convert the Tagalog of the Philippines to Christianity is instructive in this regard.30 Rafael documents how Latin words formed areas of untranslatability in the Spanish vernacular of prayers and commandments that were taught to the Tagalog who then imbued these words with “inappropriate” indigenous meanings. Submission to the Spanish God could then be performed orally by the Tagalog but minus the meanings of domination that the 25 For example, Chakrabarty (2000), 42; Nandy (1988), xi. Dunch (2002). 27 Nandy (1988); and Memmi (1990) 28 See Beasley (1987), ch.1. 29 See especially Liu (2002). 30 Rafael (1988). 26 Spanish idea of conversion assumed. Neither domination, resistance nor appropriation in toto defined the Tagalog intellectual engagement with Spanish colonialism. Therefore, even having problematized the authenticity of non-Western “traditions” and of both Western and non-Western intellectual representations of the non-West, it is crucial that we do not simply efface non-Western thought as a category. For it is upon this geo-intellectual terrain – by no means an alien world, yet neither a global commons - that many of the deepest engagements and problematizations of modernity have been produced. Effacing the category of the “non-Western thinker” runs the risk of effacing the colonial context of modernity from the construction of “modern” thought, and this runs the risk of lapsing back into a Western provincialism that masquerades as a global experience. In the historical-geographical imaginary, the “West” and “non-West” come to us as inter-linked artifacts already produced by various intellectual attempts to map and chart a passage through a variegated experience of modernity framed through imperial and colonial encounters. We cannot wish these artifacts away in the name of anti-essentialism without effacing the power dynamics of the context that produced them and, what is more, the continued influence of this context upon the present-day world of social-scientific investigation. How do non-Western enigmas challenge standard categorizations of the “modern” condition? The prime assumption of orthodox Western philosophy is that only context free knowledge is universally valid as opposed to context sensitive systems of thought that remain “prejudiced”. This distinction, as always, smuggles in a geo-political and temporal constituency, namely the modern “West” versus the traditional “nonWest”.31 Indeed, much Western thought on modernity – both mainstream and critical – has internalized the Kantian expulsion of religion from practical reason and has hence allowed a prejudice for the secular evident to become a neutral factor in most modern political thought.32 This dichotomy is again historically rooted in a geocultural imaginary most clearly evident in the comparison of “spiritual” Indian “philosophy” with rational Western philosophy.33 Jürgen Habermas’s discourse ethics is perhaps the strongest re-instatement of this separation. Habermas assumes that the problem of pursuing a modern ethical life arises from the loss of the religious basis of moral traditions.34 Yet many colonial routes taken into modernity display none of the “disenchantment” presumed by Habermas. For example, Anthony Bogues has shown how, in the radical Black tradition of thought in the Americas developed to account for slavery and its aftermath, prophesy, redemption and social critique have often been inseparable.35 And both Partha Chatterjee and Dipesh Chakrabarty have explored how British colonialism, by denying the development of a secular “Indian” public sphere, paradoxically led to the cultivation of a “modern” Indian subjectivity imbued with On these issues in general see Larsen (1988). On the terms “context-free” and “context-sensitive” see Ramanujan (1990); and the sympathetic critique of Ramanujan by Dallmayr (1994), 532-538. 32 See Hurd (2004). 33 Krishna (1988). 34 Habermas (1998). 35 Bogues (2003). 31 religious affectivities.36 Moreover, the harmful consequences of attempts to secularize social relations form the core of critical analyses of the modern condition by many Islamic thinkers.37 Religion, however, is not the only “pre-modern” affectivity that has been implicated in the non-Western experience of modernity. Crucially, the modern/pre-modern divide of subjecthood was invariably constructed under colonialism by grouping a whole array of particular cultures and societies under homogenized and racialized identities, for example, “Indian”, “Negro” and, importantly, “White”.38 Attempts to pursue freedom and self-determination by non-white intellectuals have often reflected this “coloring” of the modern experience. Notable, in this respect, is the emergence of pan-Africanism, a political philosophy first cultivated in the Americas that sought to mobilize a putatively homogonous racialized identity, “Black”, in the pursuit of a transnational form of self-determination. Moreover, the identity of a Black political subject necessarily encompassed a humanist element linking colour to colonial domination and socio-economic subordination.39 For example, at the start of the first convention of the Universal Negro Improvement Association in New York in 1920, Marcus Garvey, the famous Jamaican Pan-African leader and political theorist, read out a telegram he had sent to Prime minister Lloyd George: The Negro peoples of the world congratulate you for the splendid statesmanship you have demonstrated in granting to Ireland her internal freedom. The step is a laudable one and we hope you will continue to listen to the cry of the oppressed multitude of your great empire and thus save humanity from the conflicts of war.40 And just as instructive an example is José Martí’s attempt in the late nineteenth century to legitimize an independent Cuba by reference to the miscegenation of its population. Martí posited a mestizo identity as the true modern identity of the Americas against homogenizing ideas such as raza that had been used by certain Creole elites to justify their rule by reference to a “white” European heritage.41 In sum, the fact that personalized attributes could paradoxically form the identity basis for cosmopolitical projects (albeit, as with all cosmopolitanisms, not without serious contradictions) is a fundamental challenge to critical theories that assume only with the globalization of the impersonalized capital relation does there arise the concrete conditions for the possibility of a post-national politics. Neither should the gendered dimension of the categorization of colonial subjects be forgotten. European colonizers in both the Americas and Asia had a tendency to grant the “savage” its own special “nobility” as long as this savage mimicked the martial valor that the colonizers ascribed to themselves. Unfortunately the proof of such nobility was a suicidal urge to throw oneself upon European muskets and maxim guns, and those of the colonized who decided upon a more prudent (and rational!) course of action were assumed to be feminized peoples, passive and weak. The “strategy of survival” that saw, for example, Indian peasants deploying different 36 Chatterjee (1986); Chakrabarty (2000), especially ch.4. See especially Sayyid Qutb in Euben (1997). For a more recent intervention along these general lines see Khatami (2000). 38 Quijano (2000), 220. On becoming “white” see Garner (2007). 39 See Briggs (2005); and Shilliam (2006b). 40 Cited in Hill (1985), 260. 41 Aching (2005). 37 modes of engagement with different social strata, or allowed slaves in the Caribbean to selectively play up to the compliant “quashie” stereotype their masters had of them, was outside of the understanding of the colonizer. 42 The overall point is that the modern distinction between the public sphere of the androgynous citizen and a gendered and affective private life could not coalesce upon a colonial foundation. Rather, the incipient post-colonial nation was itself already (negatively) gendered within the wider sphere of international relations. In sum, “pre-modern” affectivities based upon religion, race and gender were, through various colonial or imperial relations, intimately re-inscribed in contestations over modern subjecthood (and hence in notions of structure, agency, domination and selfdetermination). Therefore it should be expected that non-Western thought on this experience has had to categorize and conceptualize modernity in ways that might, at least by the standards of orthodox Western philosophy and social and political thought, seem “unsophisticated” or even “un-modern”. The point is that non-Western thought cannot be judged as bad copies of originals, or irrational, or nonphilosophical, or non-scientific or non-critical simply for its dependency upon racial, religious and gendered articulations of modern identity at the expense of a purely impersonalized and abstracted sovereign individualism. This stands as a challenge for the Western leftist tradition of political thought just as much as it’s Western liberal counterpart. Is critical Western theory adequate for de-mystifying the non-Western thinker? It would be trite to claim that there are no analytical and ethical engagements with the concept of the “other” within Western traditions of thought.43 Of special importance in this respect are two philosophers who built upon the phenomenological tradition of continental thought (especially Edmund Husserl, and Martin Heidegger), namely Hans-Georg Gadamer and Emmanuel Levinas. Gadamer’s work on “philosophical hermeneutics” attempts to make explicit the structure of situatedness from which one already receives meanings of the objects of investigation. Dialogue is key to this process of making visible the “horizon” of experience to the extent that it allows an expansion of this horizon to a point where it might “fuse” with differentially situated horizons of experience.44 Here lies Gadamer’s contribution to an ethics of difference, that is, that there should be no closure of understanding of the self so that the space always exists for understanding the self in terms of an ethical relation to the other.45 Alternatively, Levinas posits a far more radical alterity between the self and the other. Because the other can never be known one cannot make the other into an object of the self. Therefore subjectivity is essentially ethical: the constitution of the self is at the same time a responsibility towards maintaining the integrity of the other.46 Such approaches provide at an abstract level important initial resources with which to situate the Western thinker vis-à-vis the non-Western thinker. And yet it seems as if in both Gadamer and Levinas this “other” is effectively contained within the concrete 42 See Nandy (1988), 107; and Campbell (1985). Good overviews of this literature include Bernstein (1991), ch.3; and Neumann (1999), ch.1. 44 Gadamer (2004), esp. 301-305. 45 For example, Shapcott (1994); and Dallmayr (1996), esp. 41-48. 46 See especially Levinas (1969). For examples of how Levinas has been productively used to problematize the discourse of “geo-politics” see Campbell (1999); and Howitt (2002). 43 history of European civilization. The more “radical” alterity of non-European “others” is treated more as a threat than an opportunity for understanding the European “self”. This bias can be excavated from Gadamer’s writings on translation. His fusion of horizons is, at root, a dialogical engagement between diachronic differences within a given society, especially between past and present meanings of social intercourse. However, Gadamer seems to be far more uncomfortable in dealing with the task of translating between presently existing and differentiated systems of meaning. Ultimately, he contains the threat of synchronous (rather than diachronic) difference by claiming rather offhandedly that the task of translating synchronic differences in meaning “differs only in degrees and not in kind from the general hermeneutical task that any text represents.”47 In a similar vein, David Campbell has outlined the problem that the existence of multiple others presents for Levinas’ ethics. When having to ethically negotiate relations between the one and the many, Levinas organizes this task by asking “who is closest”. The closest seems to be those who have historically shared a common cultural experience… a European experience?48 These examples bring to light a tendency within much “continental” critical thought to effectively bracket the ethical response to the problem of the “other” within European civilization. And this practice in turn creates a tendency to treat the problem of difference as one internal to the modern subject understood as the (Europeanproduced) “sovereign individual”. Once this is assumed, there is no reason why an engagement with non-Western thought should be considered an organic requirement of dealing analytically and ethically with the modern problem of the self/other relation. Instead, there is a tacit assumption that the history and effect of the philosophical tradition of the Western Academy can be critically interrogated by its own internal resources that enable, for example, a deconstruction of monotheism with pantheism,49 universalism with plurality,50 or monologue with dialogue.51 It seems strangely myopic to bracket the archive within European thought considering the colonial context of the production of the enlightened and then modern European “self”. And all the more so, considering the intimate historical relation between the rise in France of “poststructuralist” thought and the pursuit of decolonization. For as both Robert Young and Pal Ahluwalia have noted, the Algerian war of independence formed a crucial part of the political context in which structuralism and then poststructuralism arose as critiques in the French academy. Algeria, more than anything else, revealed the limits of the assimilatory character of the French singular and sovereign subject, the citoyen. One might validly question whether critiques of otherness, difference, irony, mimicry, parody and deconstruction of grand narratives are possible, in large part, because of this evolving post-colonial context.52 After all, seminal intellectuals such as Louis Althusser and Jacques Derrida were born in 47 Gadamer (2004), 387-399, 439-440. However, see Dallmayr (1996), 41-46 for comments on Gadamer’s subsequent development of a more agonistic understanding of the relationship between self and other. 48 Campbell (1999), 37-38. 49 See for example Cox (2000). 50 This is the ethical framework of much of Fred Dallmayr’s influential writing. 51 See for example Guillaume’s (2002) innovative use of Bakhtin. 52 Young (2001); Ahluwalia (2005). Algeria and spent formative years there. And in his adult life, Michel Foucault spent an important sojourn in Tunisia.53 The “continental” tradition cannot be judged lacking solely on the grounds of its colonial lacuna. And neither should one claim – tritely - that it is impossible to critically interrogate non-Western thought and non-Western experience through the conceptual frameworks of authors such as Foucault and Derrida.54 Rather, the fundamental point is that critical “continental” thought tends to obfuscate perhaps the foundational geo-cultural and geo-political context of modern knowledge production itself – colonial domination (and the threat thereof). And shorn of this context, the use of critical continental thought to interrogate the “other” tends to produce a “concept” driven research agenda rather than a “problem” driven one leading to an abstract engagement with the universal modern condition (albeit interrogated concretely through the European condition).55 This perhaps is the deep context within which critical responses to the “war on terror” in IR can so easily but enigmatically evade a non-Western perspective on this war. In making this argument I am not claiming that we should allow the European “self” to go un-interrogated. Rather, armed with this appreciation of the colonial context of the production of the “other” we might better recognize the impact upon – and tainting of – ‘enlightened’ Europe by its own various colonial ventures.56 The point is that an engagement with the terrain of non-Western thought does not need to be an exercise in provincialism, any less than an engagement with “continental” thought has to be. But that such an engagement has, so far, received woefully inadequate attention must be understood as itself part of the effect of Eurocentrism. For Eurocentrism is most evident in the unspoken assumption that we do not need to attempt to travel to the intellectual terrain of the non-West and interrogate its archive of thought in order to problematize the modern experience. It is not just that the non-Western thinker must be added into the existing archive of the Western Academy, but rather, that an engagement with the non-Western thinker might be necessary in order to reveal the boundedness of this Academy and thus open the way for more salient explorations of the making of modern world order. The enigma as a political challenge for the Western Academy We should remember that – Anglo-American debates aside - it is not only Realpolitik or Liberal Internationalism that have been the dominant worldviews informing policy making discourse in the making of modern world order. Just as important – among both elites and masses - have been, non-Western discourses of e.g. Islamic Jurisprudence, Leninism, Maoism, Dependencia, the Kyoto School, Pan-Africanism, Negritude, Third Worldism and Satyagraha. Therefore, the potential pay-off for IR from investigations that grapple with the enigma of the non-Western subject as thinker rather than as object is a retrieval of the global, rather than narrowly European or Western context within which thought on the “modern experience” has been 53 We might add to this context the increasing influence of Maoism as an alternative form of radical political organization to the Parti communiste français. For Althusser’s engagement with Maoism see Elliot (2006). 54 See, respectively, the postcolonial work of Said and Spivak. 55 Cf. Diez and Steans (2005), 138; and Neumann (1999), 28. See also Grosfoguel (2007). 56 See especially Nandy (1988). developed. Global here means, effectively, the colonial and imperial dimension of this experience. Crucially, the retrieval of this context might provide deeper insights into the racial, religious, and cultural dimensions of a global modernity, insights that are badly needed at the start of the twentieth century for a discipline so intimately associated with the corridors of Western power. All well and good. But why should it be necessary to turn in the first place to the IR discipline if postcolonial concerns have been readily addressed in other disciplines, such as History and Literature? One might alternatively ask, why not IR? For in the separation of disciplines in the modern Western Academy, it is not Literature, Sociology, History, Economics, Anthropology or even Politics, but this peculiarly “late” discipline,57 IR, that holds the singular and specific mandate to investigate not simply comparisons between differently constituted societies and cultures, but the nature of political plurality itself, in other words, that space that is in-between but also links and co-constitutes societies and cultures. That there has been such institutional resistance – or perhaps complacency is a better word – regarding the pursuit of postcolonial (or decolonial) problems in IR (even amongst postcolonial intellectuals) might tell us something about the wider historical institutional culpability of the Western Academy in (post-)colonial relations of domination. In this the spirit of this critique, I shall conclude by offering two provocations, one to the IR discipline in particular, and one to the Postcolonial project more generally. The first provocation is this: before the formalisation of the IR discipline in the Western Academy the problem of a world of plurality was engaged with either through comparative studies (that effectively obfuscated the colonial or imperial link between different societies by methodologically presenting them as particular selfreferential entities) or civilisational discourses (that effaced the problem of difference under a universalising Europe). The dominant approach before the 1990s within International Relations was to consider humanity fractured into a world of particular self-referential states organised, by analogy to the “state of nature” argument, through the principle of anarchy. Notions of a globalised (or globalising) world that became fashionable among critical intellectuals in the discipline after the 1990s effectively posit that difference has now become internalised within one universalised (or universalising) and Western dominated system of order.58 Plus ça change..? The second provocation: the Western Academy and those intellectuals critical or otherwise who inhabit it remain implicated in a disciplining of non-Western experience until IR is made to travel to the terrain of non-Western thought. For what is at stake here is not simply a reform of one of the most conservative disciplines in the Western Academy (conservative because so organically linked to the defense of state power). Rather, what is at stake is a radical critique of the conservative nature of the Western Academy as a whole. This conservatism, now more so than ever, is rooted in the patrol and surveillance of disciplinary separations. As an effect of this, foreign policy analysis, diplomacy and statecraft have been hived off into a peculiar discipline called International Relations (which is, moreover, often treated as a subdiscipline of Political Science) to be artificially separated from issues of history, literature, sociology, philosophy and non-western politics. Therefore, focusing the 57 David Davies endowed the first Woodrow Wilson chair in International Relations at the University College of Wales in 1919. 58 On this point about globalisation see Hobson (2007) Postcolonial critique upon IR is a requisite for the adequate pursuit of the Postcolonial project itself. Indeed, there might be something unusual about the immediacy of IR’s relationship to foreign policy that could shed novel light on issues of Postcolonial critique, a light that might be more diffused in the mediated relationship that e.g. History and Literature enjoy with the corridors of power. Bibliography Aching, G. 2005. Against ‘Library-Shelf Races’: José Martí’s Critique of Excessive Imitation. In Geomodernisms – Race, Modernism, Modernity edited by Doyle, L. and Winkiel, L. Bloomington: Indiana University Press: pp Agathangelou, A.M. and Ling, L.M.H. 2004. Power, Borders, Security, Wealth: Lessons of Violence and Desire from September 11. International Studies Quarterly 48: 517-538 Ahluwalia, P. 2005. Out of Africa: Post-Structuralism’s Colonial Roots. Postcolonial Studies 8 (2): 137-154 Beasley, W.G. 1987. Japanese Imperialism 1894-1945. Oxford: Clarendon Press Behnke, A. 2004. Terrorising the Political: 9/11 Within the Context of The Globalization of Violence. Millennium 33 (2): 279-312 Bell, D.A. and Chaibong, H. 2003. Introduction: The Contemporary Relevance of Confucianism. In Confucianism for the Modern World, edited by Bell, D.A. and Chaibong, H. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 1-28 Bernstein, R.J. 1991. The New Constellation: The Ethical-Political Horizons of Modernity/Postmodernity. Cambridge: Polity Press Bilimoria, P. 2003. What is the ‘Subaltern’ of the Comparative Philosophy of Religion? Philosophy East and West 53 (3): 340-366 Blaney, D. and Inayatullah, N. 1994. Prelude to a Conversation of Cultures in International Society? Todorov and Nandy on the Possibility of Dialogue. Alternatives 19 (1): 23-51 Bogues, A. 2003. Black Heretics, Black Prophets: Radical Political Intellectuals. London: Routledge Bozeman, A.B. 1960. Politics and Culture in International History. Princeton University Press: Princeton Brassett, J. and Bulley, D. 2007. Ethics in World Politics: Cosmopolitanism and Beyond? (eds) International Politics 44 (1): 1-149 Briggs, C.L. 2005. Genealogies of Race and Culture and the Failure of Vernacular Cosmopolitanisms: Rereading Franz Boas and W.E.B. Du Bois. Public Culture 17 (1):75-100 Bull, H. 1984. The Revolt Against the West. In The Expansion of International Society, edited by Bull.H & Watson, A. Oxford: Clarendon Press: 217-228 Buzan, B. 2006. Will the ‘Global War on Terrorism’ Be the New Cold War? International Affairs 82 (6): 1101-1118 Campbell, D. 1999. The Deterritorialization of Responsibility: Levinas, Derrida, and Ethics After the End of Philosophy. In Moral Spaces: Rethinking Ethics and World Politics, edited by Campbell, D. and Shapiro, M.J. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 29-56 Campbell, H. 1985. Rasta and Resistance: From Marcus Garvey to Walter Rodney. Dar es Salaam: Tanzania Publishing House Chakrabarty, D. 2000. Provincializing Europe – Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference. Oxford: Princeton University Press Chan, G. 1999. Chinese Perspectives on International Relations: A Framework for Analysis (London: Macmillan) Chatterjee, P. 1986. Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative Discourse? London: Zed Books Cox, R. 1995. Towards a Posthegemonic Conceputalization of World Order: Reflections on the Relevancy of Ibn Khaldun. In Approaches to World Order edited by Cox, R. and Sinclair, T. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press): 144-173 Cox, R. 2000. Thinking About Civilisations. Review of International Studies 26: 217234 Dallmayr, F. 1994. Western Though and Indian Thought: Comments on Ramanujan. Philosophy East and West 44 (3): 527-542 Dallmayr, F. 1996. Beyond Orientalism: Essays on Cross-Cultural Encounter. Albany: SUNY Press Davies, A.M. 1998. History of Linguistics Vol.4. London: Longman Defoort, C. 2001. Is There Such a Thing as Chinese Philosophy? Arguments of an Implicit Debate. Philosophy East and West 51 (3): 393-413 Deng, Y. 1998. The Chinese Conception of National Interests in International Relations. The China Quarterly 154: 308-329 Diez, T. and Steans, J. 2005. A Useful Dialogue? Habermas and International Relations. (eds) Review of International Studies 31 (1): 127-209 Dunch, R. 2002. Beyond Cultural Imperialism: Cultural Theory, Christian Missions, and Global Modernity. History and Theory 41: 301-325 Elliot, G. 2006. The Detour of Theory. Leiden: Brill Euben, R.L. 1997. Comparative Political Theory: An Islamic Fundamentalist Critique of Rationalism. Journal of Politics 59 (1): 28-55 Euben, R.L. 2002. Contingent Borders, Syncretic Perspectives: Globalization, Political Theory and Islamizing Knowledge. International Studies Review 4 (1): 23-48 Fabian, J. 1983. Time and the Other: How Anthropology Makes its Object. New York: Columbia University Press Gadamer, H. 2004. Truth and Method. London: Continuum Impacts Garner, S. 2007. Atlantic Crossing: Whiteness as a Transatlantic Experience. Atlantic Studies 4 (1): 117-132 Gong, G. 1984. The Standard of ‘Civilization’ in International Society. Oxford: Clarendon Press Grosfoguel, R. 2007. The Epistemic Decolonial Turn: Beyond Political-Economy Paradigms. Cultural Studies 21 (2-3): 211-223 Guillaume, X. 2002. Foreign Policy and the Politics of Alterity: a Dialogical Understanding of International Relations. Millennium 31 (1): 1-26 Habermas, J. 1998. “A Genealogical Analysis of the Cognitive Content of Morality”, in The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory, edited by Cronin, C. and De Greiff, P. Cambridge MA: MIT Press: 3-46 Halbfass, W. 1985. India and the Comparative Method. Philosophy East and West 35 (1): 3-15 Hashmi, S.H. 1998. Islamic Ethics in International Society. In International Society: Diverse Ethical Perspectives (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998): 215-236 Hill, R.A. The Marcus Garvey and Universal Negro Improvement Association papers Vol.4 (university of California Press, 1985) Hobson, J.M. 2007. Is critical theory always for the white West and for Western imperialism? Beyond Westphalia towards a post-racist critical IR. Review of International Studies 33: 91–116 Hurd, E.S. 2004. The Political Authority of Secularism in International Relations. European Journal of International Relations 10 (2): 235-262 Inayatullah, N. and Blaney, D. 2007. "Shed No Tears: Wealth, Race, and Death in Hegel’s Necro-Philosophy," Paper presented at the International Studies Association conference in Chicago, Illinois. Iyer, R.H. (ed). 1965. The Glass Curtain Between Asia and Europe. London: Oxford University Press Jarvis, D.S. 2001. Beyond International Relations: Edward Said and the World. In Still an American Social Science? Towards Diversity in International Thought, edited by Crawford, M.A. SUNY Press: New York: 349-367 Jones, C.S. 2002. If Not a Clash, Then What? Huntington, Nishida Kitarô and the Politics of Civilizations. International Relations of the Asia-Pacific 2: 223-243 Jones, C.S. 2003. Interman and the ‘Inter’ in International Relations: Watsuji Tetsurô and the Ethics of the Inbetween. Global Society 17 (2): 135-150 Khatami, M. 2000. Roundtable: Dialogue Among Civilizations. http://www.unesco.org/dialogue/en/khatami.htm Krishna, D. 1988. Comparative Philosophy: What It Is and What It Ought to Be”. In Interpreting Across Boundaries: New Essays in Comparative Philosophy, edited by Larson, G.J. and Deutsch, E. Princeton: Princeton University Press: 71-83 Larson, G.J. 1988. Introduction: The Age-Old Distinction Between the Same and the Other. In Interpreting Across Boundaries: New Essays in Comparative Philosophy, edited by Larson, G.J. and Deutsch, E. Princeton: Princeton University Press: 3-18 Linklater, A. 2005. Dialogic Politics and the Civilising Process. Review of International Studies 31 (1): 141-154 Liu, L. 2002. The Problem of Language in Cross-Cultural Studies. In Comparative Political Culture in the Age of Globalization: An Introductory Anthology, edited by Jung, H.Y. Boulder: Lexington Books: 305-357 Mandaville, P. 2001. Transnational Muslim Politics: Reimagining the Umma. London: Routledge Memmi, A. 1990. The Colonizer and the Colonized. London: Earthscan Mendlovitz, S.H. 1975. Introduction. In On the Creation of a Just World Order, edited by Mendlovitz, S.H. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company: vii-xviii Mitter, R. 2003. An Uneasy Engagement: Chinese Ideas of Global Order and Justice in Historical Perspective. In Order and Justice in International Relations, edited by Foot, R., Gaddis, J. and Hurrell, A. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 207-235 Morgenthau, H.J. 1960. The Purpose of American Politics. New York: Alfred A. Knopf Nakano, R. 2007. ‘Pre-History’ of International Relations in Japan: Yanaihara Tadao’s Dual Perspective of Empire. Millennium 35 (2): 301-319 Nandy, A. 1988. The Intimate Enemy: Loss and Recovery of Self Under Colonialism. New Delhi: Oxford University Press Neumann, I.B. 1999. Uses of the Other: ‘The East’ in European Identity Formation. Minneapolis: Minnesota Press Northrop, F.S.C. (ed). 1949. Ideological Differences and World Order: Studies in the Philosophy and Science of the World’s Cultures. New Haven: Yale University Press Ong, G. 2004. Building an IR Theory with ‘Japanese Characteristics’: Nishida Kitaro and ‘Emptyness’. Millennium 33 (1): 35-58 Panikkar, R. 1988. What is Comparative Philosophy Comparing? In Interpreting Across Boundaries: New Essays in Comparative Philosophy, edited by Larson, G.J. and Deutsch, E. Princeton: Princeton University Press: 116-136 Pasha, M.K. 1997. Ibn Khaldun and World Order. In Innovation and Transformation in International Studies (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press): 56-70 Persaud, R. 1997. Frantz Fanon, Race and World Order. In Innovation and Transformation in International Studies, edited by Gill, S. & Mittelman, J.H. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 170-184 Piscatori, J. 2003. Order, Justice and Global Islam. In Order and Justice in International Relations, edited by Foot, R., Gaddis, J. and Hurrell, A. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 262-286 Quijano, A. 2000. Coloniality of Power and Eurocentrism in Latin America. International Sociology 15 (2): 215-232 Ramadan, T. 1999. To Be a European Muslim: A Study of Islamic Sources in the European Context. Islamic Foundation: Leicester Ramanujan, A.K. 1990. Is There an Indian Way of Thinking? An Informal Essay. In India Through Hindu Categories, edited by Marriot, M. London: Sage: 41-58 Rafael, V.L. 1988. Contracting Colonialism – Translation and Christian Conversion in Tagalog Society Under Early Spanish Rule. London: Cornell University Press Said, E. Orientalism. 1995. London: Penguin Shapcott, R. 1994. Conversation and Coexistence: Gadamer and the Interpretation of International Society. Millennium 23 (1): 57-83 Shilliam, R. 2006b. What about Marcus Garvey? Race and the Transformation of Sovereignty Debate. Review of International Studies 32 (3): 379-400 Soroush, A. 2000. Tolerance and Governance: A Discourse on Religion and Democracy. In Reason, Freedom and Democracy in Islam: Essential Writings of ´Abdolkarim Soroush, edited by Sadri, M. and Sadri, A. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 156-170 Sulayman, A. 1987. Toward an Islamic Theory of International Relations: New Directions for Islamic Methodology and Thought. Herndon: International Institute for Islamic Thought Todorov, T. 1999. The Conquest of America: The Question of the Other. University of Oklahoma Press Walker, R.B.J. (ed). 2006. Special Section: Theorizing the Liberty-Security Relation: Sovereignty, Liberalism and Exceptionalism. Security Dialogue 37 (1): 7-82 Young, R. 2001. Postcolonialism: an Historical Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell