European Education Research Association Annual Conference Dublin: 7-10 September 2005 The final version of this paper was published in: Educational Theory vol 56 no 4 2006 pp 371-386 The practice of higher education: in pursuit of excellence and of equity David Bridges University of East Anglia and Von Hügel Institute, St Edmund’s College, Cambridge INTRODUCTION Higher education is, I suggest, a practice in its own right, though one of which the primary function is to initiate people into a variety of other practices including study, scholarly enquiry and research (each in a variety of forms) but also professional practices (at least I am content to call them such but c.f., for example, MacIntyre and Dunne 2002 and Noddings 2003) associated with medicine, law, teaching etc. It is a practice in its own right in that it is constituted by rule governed and purposive behaviours, values and ideological framing which have some historical continuity and which are shared (to a greater or lesser degree) by communities of practitioners – albeit, as I shall go on to describe, that both the commonality of values and purposes and the historical continuity have been increasingly disrupted. In the course of this paper I shall consider some rather more nuanced analysis of this view of practice, but this rough account will do to start with. As someone engaged in the practice and practices of higher education in the UK and elsewhere, the first thing which strikes me about them is the rapidity and radical nature of the changes which are taking place, not least in response to economic and social agenda demanding wider participation in higher education and the consequent ‘massification’ of higher education. I want, first, to outline some of these changes and then to discuss some issues which they raise both for the very nature of higher education and for considerations of equity in the variety of its contemporary expression. While the account of change I describe here is mainly drawn from recent experience in the UK, the association of the pursuit of wider participation in higher education with its development in diverse forms can be observed in such diverse settings as the United States, where of course it is a long established feature of the higher education scene, and contemporary Ethiopia, which is currently pursuing one of the fastest rates of growth in higher education in the world, albeit from a very small base. . THE CHANGING PRACTICE OF HIGHER EDUCATION Within living experience higher education operated pretty generally in the UK under the following conditions: residence in the physical environment of a university; in the company of a volume of other students; 1 of a broadly similar age (roughly 18-21); with a vigorous social and (broadly) cultural life; for three consecutive terms for three years; some combination of reading, writing, listening to lectures, participation in seminars and tutorials and, where appropriate, laboratory work; engagement with ‘academic’ knowledge in which on the whole abstract concepts were esteemed above concrete practices and critical and creative capacity above routinised skills; with teaching staff who were similarly resident in proximity to the university; who had qualified for their positions through successful scholarly work. Even today universities like Oxford and Cambridge operate under broadly these conditions. In Cambridge students are still required to live within three miles of the University Church of Great St Mary’s and staff within 10 miles and, with only very few exceptions, to study full time. All students and staff have an affiliation with a residential College community (housed in buildings still largely modelled on those historically associated with monastic communities) in which they are encouraged to dine on a regular basis. Terms are rigidly defined and kept, though what was previously referred to as the summer vacation has been re-designated a ‘research period’! There is another side of Cambridge which tends to get less attention. The Institute of Continuing Education (previously and rather revealingly the ‘Extra Mural Board’) actually provides courses for some 15,000 part-time students across the region in which the university is situated, and a recent survey in the University indicated that staff and students committed something of the order of 202,412 hours in one year to voluntary work in the community. Nevertheless, for an ordinary undergraduate or graduate student in Cambridge University the features which have traditionally defined the experience of higher education have very largely been maintained, albeit under increasing pressure for change. However, one only needs to look to two other universities co-located in Cambridge to see how diverse the higher education sector has become. Anglia Polytechnic University has one of its main campuses in the same town as well as another 45 miles away in Chelmsford and some fifteen further education colleges in the East of England ‘delivering’ its degrees as part of its Regional Federation. A high proportion of its students are part time and mature. Many of them take advantage of schemes for the accreditation of prior learning and prior experiential learning which are almost non-existent in Cambridge University. Within a few hundred yards there is the Regional Office of the Open University catering exclusively for distance learners, of which a large number are scattered through the rural and coastal areas of East Anglia in which there is very little opportunity to access conventional campus universities. These examples illustrate what I want to treat a little more systematically – the changing forms of practice of higher education which have challenged all of the characterising, perhaps defining, features of traditional higher education. The communities of practice The massification of higher education (as the UK approaches 50% participation rates) has gone alongside and partly been achieved through the bringing into the academy of sectors of professional or quasi professional education and training that fell previously outside it. In the 1970s and 1980s separate teacher training institutions or, more accurately Colleges of Education, were incorporated into the then polytechnics and in some cases universities. At the same time new degree level qualifications were introduced (the BEd) which added an academic gloss to the base of professional training. When in 1992 the Polytechnics were themselves re2 designated as universities, this completed the process of the ‘universitification’ of teacher education. The 1992 universities (in particular) quickly engrossed other educational and training institutions: horticultural and agricultural colleges, colleges of art and design and, then, as a result of further policy decisions, colleges of nursing, occupational and physiotherapy, radiography and pharmacology etc.. The integration of these institutions, their professional practitioners and their professional and educational practice into universities had far reaching implications. The practitioners One consequence was that university had to embrace people who brought to their teaching not so much the fruits of scholarly learning and research but rather the fruits of their experience in working environments. For all the benefits (or otherwise) of the scholarly study of philosophy, sociology and psychology of education, would be teachers needed to learn how to plan lessons and control noisy classrooms, and though academics might in some cases be able to provide such know how it was not easy to combine both requirements and it was quickly clear that practising teachers needed to be brought into partnership with university staff in order to provide effective training. Similarly training for professions allied to medicine (which in some cases expanded to around 20% of the undergraduate teaching of the university), social work and business management required people with recent and continuing experience in the workplace as a resource for students. Universities often laid on these staff the traditional expectations for research and research publication that they had of other academics in the university, but the tension between these demands has often been acute, and many universities have recognised that they are unrealistic. Thus the contemporary academy includes in large numbers people whose expertise lies in the area of professional practice rather than scholarship and whose teaching is based on that expertise and its associated practice (albeit popularly glossed with what Schön conveniently offered in terms of ‘reflective practice’) rather than the more traditional practices of scholarly enquiry and research. With this diversity of practitioners in higher education has come diversity in the conditions of service. Many of those who contribute out of their professional expertise do so from and in their workplaces (see below) and with very little direct contact with the university which they are serving. Many are employed part time and on short term contracts. Similarly their counterparts in research-only posts who live from one externally funded research project to the next can spend years not knowing whether they have a future in a particular institution or not. It is not uncommon for up to a third of academic posts in universities to be of this kind. One of the consequences is of course a high level of mobility between institutions and a reluctance of staff to put down roots and invest in property when their future is so unsure – so they commute, often long distances across the country, and instead of an academic community contained within a tight geographic and social space, you have one widely dispersed and only rarely encountering each other. The temporality of practice The expansion of part-time courses (in evenings, week-ends and summer schools) and the asynchronous periods of teaching and learning required by different forms of professional education and training (not to mention distance learning programmes for which this is a boasted virtue) compound the problem of holding the staff of a higher education institution together as a face to face interactive intellectual community, albeit that modern technology provides altogether more fluent and voluminous opportunities for other sorts of interactions, notably by email. 3 But time gets disrupted in other ways too. Traditional higher education required sustained study and attention even in England where the normal three year undergraduate course was substantially shorter than some of its continental counterparts. But in most UK universities programmes constructed largely within a single subject departments and with progression through a programme under the direction of a relatively stable group of staff has been significantly fragmented by the introduction of modular programmes designed to give students more opportunities to pick and mix their studies and credit frameworks designed to facilitate breaks in the continuity of those studies. Many of these modules were based on semester long commitments, but service driven universities quickly realised that even this was too heavy a commitment for some students, unsure perhaps about their ability to cope, and others engaged in busy working lives. Thus the retail discourse and practice of ‘bite-sized chunks of learning’ and ‘just in time learning’ has come to be applied to the practice of higher education in what has been dubbed ‘the theatre of fast knowledge’ (Besley and Peters 2004 but see also Ritzer 2000). The sites of practice These developments, driven by the inclusion of wider spheres of professional training within the curriculum of the university, have also required movement of the sites of practice of higher education outside the physical environment of the university. Learning to teach required practice in teaching in schools. The professions allied to medicine required training in hospital wards and social work training required placements in public service and voluntary organisations. Indeed in recent years professional bodies and national quangos have required higher proportions of professional training in all these sectors to be practically based in the workplace. There are other important policy imperatives which are pushing the sites of practice of higher education further and further from the cloistered, red brick or concrete and glass precincts of the university, which some students may never attend at all. Perhaps the most significant of these from the point of view of issues I shall discuss later is the widening participation agenda aimed at making higher education more accessible to, especially, non-traditional students. One of the ways that universities are responding to this is through outreach programmes – often as in the example already given through partnership with Colleges of Further Education (which have hitherto focussed almost entirely on sub-degree and vocational training programmes) but also in the workplace in cooperation with the human resource development functions of businesses or public sector organisations. More radically, of course, distance learning enables both specialist universities like the Open University but also more traditional universities which are embracing e-learning to bring an experience of higher education onto your kitchen table (or so it is claimed). The stuff of the practice This is a rather inelegant attempt to refer to the learning, the kind of knowledge with which those involved in the university as students researchers or teachers are engaging. It is not for nothing that the student is traditionally said to be ‘reading’ for a degree, for the library, the book and the journal were, and in many contexts remain, the primary resources for a university, its staff and its students. For students, ‘Directors of Studies’ and ‘Supervisors’ (to borrow from the contemporary Cambridge terminology) are of secondary assistance. Moreover the kind of knowledge which these resources dealt in is of a rather specialised kind in which meticulous detail recouped over an extended period of scholarly endeavour competes with and sometimes 4 provides the foundation for sweeping analysis and theory – all of it conducted in the form of disputatious criticism and debate. Whether you are researching and writing or studying, reporting and attempting your own critical analysis, this was and in many parts of the academy is today, the stuff of the practice of higher education. However, contemporary universities embrace a much more varied body of learning. First, as we have seen, the incorporation of professional education and training within the university means that students have to learn to manipulate limbs as well as to study their anatomy; to keep order in classrooms as well as to understand the psychological or moral bases of discipline in an educational setting; to provide a sympathetic ear to psychologically and physically battered clients as well as to understand the social roots of such experience; to absorb cultural and subcultural expectations and develop intuition at a tacit level as well as to be able to write essays which render such understandings explicit. Thus a whole repertoire of practical and applied skills, of interpersonal understanding and empathy, of contextual awareness and sensitivity and of tacit and intuitive understanding has become the stuff of higher education. This is not just the case in the context of professional education and training. New two year ‘Foundation Degrees ‘ in the UK are extending the vocational range of higher education and locating it firmly in the demands of the workplace and the skills required for often very narrowly defined areas of employment like ‘transport logistics’ or ‘e-commerce’. Curricula are planned with employers; delivered in partnership with employers with a substantial element of work-based learning; and designed to meet the needs of employers. Many of the students are indeed in employment and their study may never take them anywhere near a university campus (Mills and Seiffert 2004). In other areas, too, ‘experiential learning’ may constitute up to two thirds of the credits for a degree. At Anglia Polytechnic University, for example, such accreditation has been given for experience of drug rehabilitation as part of a degree in social science and as a holiday life guard towards a degree in sports science (Baty 2003:1). *** I have described briefly some of the ways in which the practice of higher education has changed in particular in the UK over the last twenty years. Though these changes have probably touched all higher education institutions, they have certainly not done so evenly, with the result that the practice of higher education now takes increasingly diverse forms in different institutions as well as within any single institution. The Higher Education Funding Council has indeed positively encouraged ‘mission differentiation’. We have as a result what Smith and Webster describe as: ‘different academics pursuing different knowledges, different teams of researchers combining and recombining to investigate shifting topics, different sorts of students following different courses, with different modes of study and different concerns among themselves, different employment arrangements for different types of staff – difference everywhere in this postmodern, flexible, accommodating university’ (Smith and Webster, 1997: 104). The huge diversity of the practice of higher education and, hence, of the experience which different students have of higher education raises many issues for policy makers and practitioners of which I want to consider just two in this context. The first, perhaps somewhat conceptual, is the question of whether all that goes on in or under the auspices 5 of a modern university is ‘properly’ regarded as the practice of higher education. The second and more substantive question is whether such diversity of practice meets or undermines the principle of social justice which is often claimed as the basis for this diversification. I shall explain and consider these two issues in the sections which follow. WHAT MIGHT COUNT AS THE PRACTICE OF HIGHER EDUCATION? Unsurprisingly for what is in a sense such a commonplace word, ‘practice’ is used in a number of different ways. Its most commonplace use is perhaps in its application in eg sporting contexts to designate the repeated performance of certain skills with a view to their improvement. Although this use is some way away from the kinds of applications with which I am concerned here – to social practices and communities of practice -- those two ingredients of sustained performance and of activity aimed at improvement are, nevertheless significant features of practice in this sense. I shall probably not be the only contributor to this volume to quote Alisdair MacIntyre’s account of practice as: ‘any coherent and complex form of socially established cooperative human activity through which goods internal to that form of activity are realised in the course of trying to achieve those standards of excellence which are appropriate to, and partially definitive of, that form of activity, with the result that human powers to achieve excellence, and human conceptions of the ends and goods involved, are systematically extended’ (MacIntyre, 1985: 187). In terms of more traditional conceptual analysis, MacIntyre sets three main clusters of conditions for something to count as a practice: (i) (ii) (iii) the requirement for human activity which is socially established, cooperative, coherent and complex. Thus far practice is seemingly morally neutral. Organised crime, street gangs or call centres might claim to be practices in these terms. the requirement for there to be goods internal to that form of activity which are realised through standards of excellence that are partially definitive of that activity. This invokes the notion of internally referenced values or goals , but not any wider moral standards. This might rule out organised crime as a practice (or indeed, as MacIntyre has argued controversially, teaching) on the grounds that these were simply means to ends which lay outside the activity rather than to the realisation of intrinsic goods. The requirement that human powers to achieve excellence, and human conceptions of the ends and goods involved, are systematically extended. This clearly takes the notion of practice into different territory in which, if we are to follow MacIntyre, coherent complex, cooperative and established human activity would not count as practice unless it also contributed to the development of human goodness or virtue. I have a problem about recognising, in particular this third requirement in terms of the ordinary language use of the concept of practice, but MacIntyre himself acknowledges that he is ‘using the word ”practice” in a specially defined way which does not completely agree with current ordinary usage’ (MacIntyre 1985:187). McLaughlin (McLaughlin 2003) helpfully distinguishes two approaches to the notion of practice. The first is the full blown, morally endowed and honorific concept (my words not McLaughlin’s) which 6 MacIntyre offers us. The second is much more empirically approachable, not surprisingly, because it is associated with the work of the ethnographer Etienne Wenger (Wenger 1998). Wenger’s project in examining ‘communities of practice’ is not so much to prescribe or to stipulate definitions of such practices but to investigate them empirically with a view to illuminating how they actually operate, in particular, in the interests of fostering learning. It seems to me that an ethnographic approach to the practice of higher education would be to approach institutions with a certain designation, let’s say ‘Higher Education Institutions’ and then to look for ‘coherent and complex form [or forms] of socially established cooperative human activity’ which seem to characterise their behaviour as well as, perhaps the ‘goods internal to that form of activity’ which are realised through it. It would describe what was going on (and perhaps people’s perceptions of and understandings of what was going on), but would provide no basis for judgement of the kind which suggested that some of these activities were or were not ‘properly’ the functions of higher education. It might, however, provide a basis for an evaluation of the kind which judges people’s experience of the practice against the standards contained in the institutional rhetoric or (pace Wenger) illuminate what features of those practices do or not contribute to the realisation of the goods internal to them. The kind of observations I have made about the changing and diversifying practice of higher education would be of interest in terms of the changing social, value and ideological structures which they reflected but would not raise any problems as to whether the practices were or were not the practices of higher education. By contrast, perhaps, MacIntuyre’s approach to practice might very well raise such questions. If a practice is, by definition, not just a ‘coherent and complex form of socially established cooperative human activity’ but additionally one through which ‘human powers to achieve excellence, and human conceptions of the ends and goods involved, are systematically extended’ then observable human activity would not even count as a practice unless certain kinds of human excellence were extended. I am not sure how much work such a principle would or would not do in discriminating between the different kinds of higher education which I distinguished earlier. Traditional forms of higher education are pretty clearly linked to certain kinds of human excellence describable in terms of both intellectual virtue and academic capabilities: could the same be said of eg a part time programme in social care or technical engineering with a substantial work and experience based programme? It would perhaps be unusual for the developmental goals of such programmes to be couched in terms of intellectual virtue, but what if they were expressed in terms of higher levels skills in childcare or automotive repair along with eg team working, interpersonal relations, communication skills and relevant IT skills. Might these not legitimately be represented as ‘human conceptions of the ends and goods involved’ which are ‘systematically extended’? There is, however, another condition which MacIntyre makes which it is relevant to apply here. This is especially relevant insofar as some forms of contemporary higher education are defined and interpreted simply in terms of developing skills required, from a student’s point of view, in order to compete successfully for employment and, from an employer’s point of view, to improve their business competitiveness. For MacIntyre any such form of higher education would fall foul of his principle that practice required the pursuit of ‘goods internal to the activity’ ie of something which was perceived as intrinsically worthwhile and not just of instrumental value. It would also fall foul of a second principle: 7 ‘A practice, in the sense intended, is never just a set of technical skills, even when directed towards some unified purpose and even if the exercise of those skills can on occasion be valued or enjoyed for their own sake. What is distinctive about practice is in part the way in which conceptions of the relevant goods and ends which the technical skills serve – and every practice does require the exercise of technical skills – are transformed and enriched by these extensions of human powers and by that regard for its own internal goods which are partially definitive of each particular practice or type of practice’ (MacIntyre 1985: 193) MacIntyre goes on, of course to make a connection between practice defined in this way and the cultivation of virtue, and it seems to me that this is where his analysis offers something important to our consideration of higher education in it diverse forms. Is higher education just about the development of instrumentally useful skills – or is it about initiating people into forms of activity which have intrinsic value and forms of excellence? Is it merely about the development of skills or also about the cultivation of virtues related to the goods which are at the heart of the practice? The conceptual question of whether higher education does or does not satisfy the necessary conditions for it to count as a practice are less important than the substantive question to which it has led us about the kind of activities and the kind of human qualities which it is the proper business of a higher education institution to promote. I don’t want to suggest that diversified forms of contemporary higher education cannot meet these sort of requirements. I do want to suggest that these ought to be one test of their legitimacy as part of the practice of higher education. There is at least one other major substantive issue which is raised by the developments which I have described, and this relates not so much to questions of excellence as to questions of equity. EQUITY IN THE PRACTICE(S) OF HIGHER EDUCATION I have described how the practices of higher education now take on a variety of forms, and how this variety is to be found not just in the differences between, for example, history, science and philosophy as forms and communities of practice within the university but also between the forms of engagement which are involved in higher education itself -including independent distance learning programmes, work based learning, professional training in a hospital or school classroom, e-learning from a base in a local community centre, evening attendance at a local FE College or the cocktail of intellectual curiosity and low gossip at table in a Cambridge College. The practice is hugely diverse and it seems to me fairly safe to predict even in advance of the ethnography that student experience of this practice is hugely diverse. This diversity invites the question: are the variety of practices which are now included under the umbrella of higher education of equal value? It is relevant to observe that at least one of the driving motives for the creation of this diversity has been a principle of equity and social inclusion. The UK Government White Paper on The future of higher education (DfES, 2003), for example, argues: Education must be a force for opportunity and social justice, not for the entrenchment of privilege. We must make certain that the opportunities that higher education brings are available to all those who have the potential to benefit from them, regardless of 8 their background. This is not just about preventing active discrimination; it is about working actively to make sure that potential is recognised and fostered wherever it is found (DfES, 2003: 67). Many of the changes in higher education which I have described have been driven by a desire to make what might be regarded as the traditional content of higher education accessible to people who, for one reason or another, have not been able to access one of the traditional sites of higher education. The creation of the Open University in the UK was a clear example of this ambition. The OU took great pains to ensure that the academic character and quality of its curriculum stood comparison with that of any long established university even if in its approach to entry requirements and to its teaching it was highly innovative. Similarly the validation and accreditation requirements imposed by established universities on partner further education colleges involved in the delivery of their curriculum, were intended to demonstrate that a degree awarded by the university represented the same, whether study had been part-time in an FE college or full time on a university campus. Thus, one interpretation of the requirements of equity within the widening participation agenda is that the intellectual practice(s) into which students are initiated are of the same kind, even if the social and pedagogic practices through which this initiation takes place are different. This aspiration raises its own questions. Can one really separate the two? The retail metaphors of ‘delivery’ and ‘product’ which abound in contemporary higher education make such separation sound easy. Clearly ‘products’ can find the customer to whom they are destined by post, by electronic communication or in the back of a van. Your new washing machine is not transformed by the form of its delivery (except perhaps for a few dents and scratches!) But is the same true of the practices with which higher education institutions seek to engage their students? How important is face to face interaction with fellow students and with people who have dedicated their whole lives to particular areas of scholarship to initiation into the practice(s) of higher education? How important to higher learning is the social presence in an academic community? How is intellectual virtue represented and cultivated through ‘bite-sized chunks of learning’? How much of what is important about a traditional campus based university is passed on through the informal curriculum rather than the official one – and how much of this is lost or sustained through eg the course intranet café? What do differences in ethos between, for example, a university and a further education college make to the experience of study in these different environments? All of these questions seem to me to invite empirical investigation. For the moment I simply want to make the point that it may not be possible to change the practice of teaching and learning in higher education – the sites, the temporality, the communities of practice -- without also having some impact on the quality of the intellectual practices (of science, medicine, philosophy, literary criticism etc) into which students are being initiated. It is possible that the changes in teaching and learning are beneficial ones in terms of the kind of educational experience provided. I have heard it plausibly argued that FE colleges can provide a more secure and supportive learning environment for some students than can universities, which were, for example, particularly slow to adapt to the needs of disabled students. Whatever the benefit or disbenefit, the probability is that they will be different in some important respects. So, one aspiration underlying the diversification of higher education provides for different practices in teaching and learning (suited to the different requirements of different learners) linked with access to the traditional academic and professional practices of the university. It is, nevertheless, not surprising that a second part of the equity agenda with respect to higher education in the UK is to ensure that students from all backgrounds have access to sites and communities of higher education practice – notably to Oxbridge and ‘the elite 9 Russell Group’ of universities – which are widely perceived as offering particular benefit to students which lie in the formal and informal learning experience and not just in terms of the (commonly unspecified) learning outcomes of the curriculum. There is, however, a third and more radical project underlying the changing practice of higher education which has to do with the stuff – the knowledge, skills, personal qualities and their embededness in social practice – which is at the very heart of the institution and to giving equal value in institutions of higher education to practices which previously had little or no place in that environment: the practices of teaching, social work, and professions allied to medicine and the modes of knowing -- often tacit, contextually sensitive, local – which Gibbon and others have labelled mode 2 knowledge (Gibbons et al 1004); work based learning; experiential learning, team working, presentational and communication skills. So what has happened is that kinds of knowledge which are valued, in particular, in working lives, have been brought into the sphere of higher education, accredited, validated and honoured with the award of a degree, albeit, usually, when mixed with an element of more traditional academic learning. Different motives lie behind these developments. Some of them are to do with an economic analysis of the requirements of the labour market and/or the stated requirements of employers for people equipped with practical and social skills and not just the narrow range of capacities developed in a traditional higher education. This has little to do with equity and a lot to do with the need for a differentiated labour market. Some of them are driven by evidence that many of the people whom government is trying to draw into higher education under the widening participation programme are not attracted to conventional academic programmes and want something more directly applicable to work and perhaps accessible in combination with paid work. (See eg research carried out recently on the life and life-style aspirations of young people who had opted out of higher education: Watts and Bridges 2004). An equity driven ambition to include such people in higher education, on this analysis, requires higher education to adapt its offer to meet their requirements. A third set of motives invokes a different principle of equity. This has to do with affirming the value of knowledge (and linked practices) other than the traditional academic ones – even if, ironically, the mechanism for achieving this is to provide a validation which draws its authority from its association with this tradition. The crunch issue which is raised by these last two projects is, again, whether these different kinds of knowledge and the associated practices which have now found their ways into higher education are really of equal value. Has justice at last been done to the young person who is studying ‘Sports and Leisure’ with two thirds of her credits being awarded for prior experience working in a sports and leisure centre and a programme designed with and substantially taught be local employers – or another doing a two year Foundation Degree on Child Care while working as a classroom assistant in a local primary school and a large component of the course based on assessment of practical competence in the classroom? Or has the principle of equity been betrayed? How does one begin to answer this question (and in this context I can do no more than begin)? One response is to run with the subjective choices of the students. These are after all adult people or very nearly so. Most of them have 11 to 13 years of educational experience behind them. They have their own views on the goods which they wish to pursue in their lives and the routes which will enable them to do so. The choice may be surrounded by ‘advice and guidance’ issues (Is this really what they are interested in? Are they being 10 realistic about their own abilities? Are they being under-ambitious? Will what they have chosen to study really enable them to do what they want to do afterwards? etc). If they themselves choose let’s call them the mode 2 practices for their experience of higher education, then perhaps that indicates their value -- and the principle of equity is saved. There is of course the underlying risk of adaptive preference being at work ( I discuss this more fully in Bridges 2005) but for current purposes I will discount this and go along with the principle of preference autonomy succinctly expressed by Harsanyi as ‘in deciding what is good and bad for a given individual, the ultimate criterion can only be his own wants and his own preferences’ (Harsanyi 1982: 55). On this principle, the fact that higher education institutions provides students with opportunities to engage in different kinds of practice as part of their higher education experience could be a proper response to the students’ own different priorities and demands and thus shows that they are being treated with equal regard. But is there any more objective standpoint from which we might argue and conclude differently? Suppose, for example, that we could demonstrate that let’s call them the mode 1 practices of higher education were actually more personally empowering than the mode 2; that the articulate, critical, analytic, synoptic and synthetic capacities (supposedly) associated with traditional academic learning actually enable people to think for themselves; to spot public deceit and spin and reveal it for what it is; to understand things in their wider context; to absorb large amounts of information and make sense of it for themselves and others; to see pathways through complex decisions and debates – and to do all of this in ways which mode 2 knowledge does not make possible. Might we not then start to wonder whether the substitution of mode 2 for mode 1 in the practice of higher education was really to offer something which was different but of significantly unequal value? A debate around the higher education curriculum in the United States found the left wing Stephen Aronowitz and the right wing Allan Bloom in a remarkable consensus around the importance of the ‘Great Books’ tradition in higher education. But while for Bloom these were to be admired for their Truth and Beauty, what Aronowitz saw in the Western canon was ‘a legacy of power, both epistemologically and ontologically’ (Weiner 2001: 39). ‘My approach’ writes Aronowitz, ‘does not assume the superiority of the conventional over the alternative or oppositional canon, only its power’ (Aronowitz 2001: 169). Though in the case of ‘work based learning’ there is of course hardly an alternative canon, let alone one which will provide the ‘basis for any critique and transvaluation’ which Aronowitz is looking for (ibid). So do we have an objective basis for esteeming some knowledge and its relationship with practice above other kinds of knowledge on graounds of its greater power? One of the problems about this argument is that the notions of power and the fashionable ‘empowerment’ do not have much purchase in the abstract. People are not just generally ‘empowered’: they are empowered to do certain kinds of things and to pursue certain kinds of lives. So what kind of knowledge counts as empowering depends on what kinds of things people want to be able to do. There is a long history of eg university programmes designed to enable people to teach, to practice medicine, nursing, engineering or other professional work which have been regarded as insufficiently empowering (in terms of enabling them to lead the lives they wanted to live) precisely because they have focussed too narrowly on academic knowledge at the expense of practical knowledge and skills, contextual awareness and interpersonal understanding. But for others, the traditional academic practices of a university may indeed be exactly what they wish to engage in either as a life sufficient unto itself or because of what they see these practices as enabling them to do, to be or to become. 11 We are brought back, then, to the point that different people choose different forms of life and therefore, sensibly, forms of education which will prepare them for these forms of life and to the difficulty of providing objective grounds for giving higher value to one over another. As John White pointed out in discussing this very issue: ‘One may, of course, reject the pluralism in all this i.e. the view that different individuals may have different ways of life and are none the worse for that. One may hold that there is a particular way of life which everyone should follow, thus translating a personal ideal into a moral imperative. This seems wholly arbitrary. Gulfs have existed since the beginning of civilisation between one preferred way of life and another: no-one has succeeded in producing a “knock down” argument that eliminates all rivals’ (ibid 44-45). If we have no basis for demonstrating that (at least among the sort of options we are discussing here) one is superior to another, then, presumably, there are no grounds either for suggesting that forms of higher education practice which provide an effective preparation for or initiation into these different forms of life are of different value, even if they are of different character. Nor are there, therefore, any grounds for suggesting that higher education practices constructed around this variety of ways of life offend against the principle of equity, provided that (taking into account relevant differences) they are all equally accessible to people wishing to engage in them. I am conscious that this is a peremptory treatment of a huge debate. My real concern, however, is not so much to present a conclusion to the debate as to bring the debate into the discussion of contemporary higher education policy. The diversification of practice which characterises contemporary higher education lies justified at least in part by considerations of inclusiveness, equity and equal valuing. But are we being persuaded to treat as equal practices and, more particularly, forms of knowledge which are actually unequal – in power, in value, in terms of the forms of life in which they enable us to participate, in terms of the forms of human excellence which they allow us to develop? Are we observing (and this is where my own argument seems to lead) a genuinely emancipatory project or, as I still uneasily suspect, simply another subtle exercise of those processes which ensure the reproduction of social inequalities under the guise of their eradication? It would be useful to know. REFERENCES Aronowitz,S., (2000) The knowledge factory: dismantling the corporate university and creating true higher learning, Boston, Beacon Press. Baty, P. (2003) ‘QAA warning over degree shortcuts, Times Higher Education Supplement, 29th August 2003, page1. Besley,T. and Peters,M. (2004) Performative epistemologies: the theatre of fast knowledge, paper presented to the Annual Conference of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain, Oxford, 2nd-4th April. 12 Bridges, D (2005) Widening participation in higher education: ‘the philosopher and the bricklayer’ revisited. Paper presented to the Annual Conference of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britian, Oxford, 1st-3rd April. Gibbons,M., Limoges,C., Nowotny,H., Scwatrzman,S., Scott,P. and Trow,M. (1994) The new production of knowledge: the dynamics of science and research in contemporary societies, London, Sage. Harsanyi, J.C. (1982) ‘Morality and theory of rational behaviour’ in A.Sen and B.Williams (Eds.) Utilitarianism and beyond, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. MacIntyre, A.C. (1981) After virtue, London, Duckworth. MacIntyre,A.C. and Dunne,J. (2002) ‘Alasdair MacIntyre on education: in dialogue with Joseph Dunne’ Journal of Philosophy of Education, 36:1 (pp1-19). McLaughlin, T.H. (2003) ‘Teaching as a practice and a community of practice: the limits of commonality and the demands of diversity’ Journal of Philosophy of Education vol. 37 no. 2: 339-352. Noddings,N. (2003) ‘Is teaching a practice? Journal of Philosophy of Education, 37:2, pp 241251). Ritzer,G. (2000) The MacDonaldization of society, New Century Edition, Thousand Oaks, California: Pine Forge Press. Seiffert, M. and Mills,R. (2004) The development of Foundation Degrees in the East of England, Cambridge, Association of Universities in the East of England and Foundation Degree Forward. Smith,A. and Webster,F. (1997) ‘Conclusion: an affirming flame’ in A. Smith and F. Webster (Eds.) The postmodern university? Contested visions of higher education in society: London, Open University Press. Watts, M. and Bridges, D. (2004) Whose aspirations? What achievement? An investigation of the life and lifestyle aspirations of 16-19 year olds outside the formal system of education, Cambridge, Association of Universities in the East of England. Weiner, E.J.(2001) Concretizing possibility through a pedagogy/politics of critical engagement: a radical alternative for the future of higher education’ Educational Researcher 30:2 (pp 37-39) Wenger, E. (1998) Communities of practice: Learning, meaning and identity, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. White, J.P. (1973) Towards a compulsory curriculum, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul. 13