MORE ON OBJECTLESS TRANSITIVES AND ERGATIVIZATION PATTERNS IN ENGLISH Submission for a special volume of the journal Constructions, with selected papers of the Construction Grammar conference in Marseille (2004). © Maarten Lemmens Université Lille 3 & CNRS, France In two relatively recent papers, Goldberg (2001, to appear) provides a valuable analysis of transitive constructions without an overt object, as in She contributed to the Leukemia Foundation. Goldberg correctly stresses that this construction, which she terms the Deprofiled Object Construction or DOC for short, has a clear semantic value, pointing out that “[o]mission of the patient argument is possible when the patient argument is construed to be deemphasized in the discourse vis à vis the action” (2001). Clearly, the construction remains transitive as the Patient is still understood even when not overtly expressed. Goldberg further discusses some of the factors that may bring about deemphasizing of the object (repeated or habitual actions, politeness strategies, etc.) as well as some (lexical) factors that prevent object omission. It is especially the latter issue for which the present paper offers a more nuanced, and at the same time more general, alternative. More specifically, while insisting on the semantic impact of the construction, Goldberg relies on the lexical specifications of the individual verb to explain why certain verbs do not sanction the objectless construction. For example, the verb break does not tolerate the DOC all to well: I broke is not an alternate construction to I broke the dishes. Goldberg argues that the Patients of break cannot be omitted without any problem because “[b]ubbles, TVs, breadsticks, and hearts break in very different ways and with very different consequences” (Goldberg 2001). They cannot be omitted indeed, but the argument she offers is incorrect. When one looks at verbs such as cut, kill, or make that do allow the omitted object construction, one notices that the range of Patients that can occur with these verbs is equally varied and they will be cut, killed or made in quite different ways as well. In our approach, we aim to retain the constructional value (we will, consequently, not entirely follow Rice’s (1988) lexical approach) yet at the same time we do not want to claim that lexical issues have no importance. On the contrary, we argue that there is indeed a complex interaction between verbal and constructional meaning, but arguably along different paths than Goldberg suggests. More specifically, we follow Davidse (1999) and Lemmens (1998) who argue for a paradigmatic point of view on the objectless construction. They defend the idea that the grammar of English causative events is governed by two different causative models, the transitive and the ergative, which each impose their own construal on an event. These construals entail different ways in which the participants are engaged in the process, as reflected in the different constructional alternations the paradigms allow. The objectless construction, Davidse and Lemmens point out, is a strictly transitive phenomenon, singling out the conceptual nucleus of the transitive event, the ACTOR-PROCESS constellation. The ergative model, on the other hand, centers around the second participant, the Patient, as illustrated by the hallmark of this paradigm, the non-causative alternation (e.g., Floyd broke the glass vs. The glass broke). The object cannot be omitted in the latter case, as it is the conceptual nucleus of the process. Our cognitive lexico-paradigmatic approach will be evaluated against ample corpus examples for three prototypically ergative verbs: starve, suffocate and break, drawn from the BNC as well as from Internet data (concordances obtained via WebCorp). We show how for the different verbs specific lexical matters do indeed interfere with constructional possibilities, be it in different ways than Goldberg has it. In short, our approach, applied to an elaborate corpus analysis, will provide important nuances to Goldberg’s constructional analysis as well as to Davidse’s paradigmatic account. The data will help us to unravel the intricate and contextually variable interaction between constructional and lexical semantics. References Goldberg. Adele E. 2001. “Patient Arguments of causative verbs can be omitted: the role of information structure in argument distribution,” Language Sciences 34/4-5. 503-524. ———. to appear. “Constructions, Lexical Semantics and the Correspondence Principle: Accounting for Generalizations and Subregularities in the Realization of Arguments”. In: Nomi Erteschik-Shir and Tova Rapoport (éds.). The Syntax of Aspect, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Davidse, Kristin. 1999. Categories of Experiential Grammar. Monographs in Systemic Linguistics X. Nottingham: University of Nottingham. (reprint of Davidse 1991, PhD Thesis, K.U.Leuven). Lemmens, M. 1998. Lexical Perspectives on Transitivity and Ergativity. Causative Constructions in English. Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins. Rice, Sally. 1988. “Unlikely Lexical Entries”. Berkeley Linguistics Society 14.202-212.