Lecture : Truth In Religious Experience (Less realism) Welcome to Saturday. I Hope you’ve found the Colloquium worthwhile so far. I’ve certainly had some fascinating discussions with people and the quality of questions makes me feel that any one of you could be giving this speech in my place. I want to start by just asking a few questions: If someone you met here at the colloquium told you that they’d had a religious experience here at PAC what would you think? What might they mean? Would you believe them? Assuming you were vaguely interested, how would you go about trying to ascertain whether or not there was any truth to the claim? Furthermore, what would be the response of our students to such a claim? It seems to me that many of us would react with incredulity to such a claim, and yet, in my experience, most people, when asked if they believe that there is a spiritual or religious essence to reality, tend to agree that there is. So why do many of us both doubt claims to religious experience whilst at the same time, believe that there is more to life than atoms? Of course I am talking in generalisations here, and I’m not basing this observation on statistical evidence, but this has been my experience so far. In my talk I’m going to try to examine this ambivalence, through the evaluation of claims to religious experience. It is essential at the start, at the risk of being tedious, to try to define some key terms, and then I’ll come on to the evaluation of religious experiences: 1 In the context of my talk I’d like to define experience as “The apprehension of an object, thought or emotion through the senses or mind which involves active participation, whether physical or mental, in an event”. I am trying to say that an experience is not something which a person undergoes as much as something in which the person partakes. There is an interaction between the perceiver and the percept (ie that which is perceived) which naturally involves interpretation and response on a multitude of levels. The key question is whether or not any significant claim to truth can be justified when people claim to have any experience, let alone a religious experience. The strange thing is, that unless there are reasons to doubt people, we generally trust claims to experience made by others, and this is significant. I shall return to this later on, but suffice to say at this stage that we do, as a whole, give great credence to our own experiences and to those which are claimed by others. So what is a religious experience? This is of course going to be a lot harder to define, not least because a definition of religion is problematic anyway, and in fact one of the main points I’m going to make is that language as a whole can only take us so far in describing and defining experiences. I’ll define religious experience as “the apprehension of an object, thought or emotion through the senses or mind which involves active participation in an event, and where the perceiver believes there to be a religious origin to the percept.” Inevitably this is an awkward definition. In essence I’m saying that a religious experience is a claim to a religious experience. Whether or not a claim to such experience is true is the matter in question, but I believe this is a good starting 2 point since it tries to avoid the a priori assumption that either religious experiences are possible, or that they are impossible. So I’m going to start with the claim as the definition and then debate the truth value of such claims. The very ground on which we are discussing Religious experience is based upon our realist or anti-realist persuasions. We have already heard this distinction from other speakers, so I won’t bore you with this again. Suffice to say that I’m approaching the issue of religious experience from the position of a realist since, in my view it is not possible to actually live as an antirealist, and if we are going to be fully human, then we certainly need to live. What I mean by this is that, as a matter of sanity, we cannot live our lives as if all our ideas were merely only coherently true. We can certainly philosophise that this is the case, but I don’t believe we can live as if this were the case. However, having claimed to be a realist I’d like to qualify that, by saying that I believe there to be two key aspects of experience: the internal, subjective part of experience and the external, objective part of experience. These are inextricably and mysteriously linked, but they are not one and the same, or else I would be a solipsist, stuck in the quagmire of my own mind. And that would be a real shame! Thus I believe there to be both a reality to which the external aspect of the experience refers, and also an internal aspect of the experience. The former is that which may or may not correspond to reality, the latter is something which coheres with our internalised response to the external. Thus the realist and anti-realist positions may be seen as more closely linked than we often take them to be. So, to summarise here, for the purpose of evaluating claims to religious experience I am taking these claims to be realist claims, but with these further qualifications in place. 3 I must also state at the start that by “religious” I am not exclusively referring to Christianity, although much of what I say does refer to Christianity. So, what types of claims to religious experiences have been made? For a very good analysis of this issue I recommend you read Caroline Franks Davis’ book “The evidential force of religious experience” ISBN0198250010. In this book she distinguishes various types of claims to religious experience, but she is careful to point out that the boundaries between these types are neither fixed nor clear-cut, and that many religious experiences are a combination of the following. I shall begin by explaining these types of religious experience and then I’ll spend some time evaluating these different claims to religious experience. But before I do this I want to urge you to start the next term, or the next year with your students looking at four concepts: Proof, Probability, Faith and Reason. This year we did this with every year group from yr 8 to yr 12. I cannot overemphasise the importance of this for your students: They simply must have some grasp of the complexity of interdependence between these concepts. Now, if we are going to facilitate discussion on religious experience with our students then they need to understand the variety of forms of these claims that exist, so here are some types of religious experiences: a) Interpretive experiences: Of course, all experience is interpreted, but here I am referring to experiences which are interpreted from a particular religious framework e.g interpreting an apparent chance meeting, which subsequently transpires to be a life-changing meeting, as being an angel sent from God to help you. 4 b) Quasi-sensory experiences: These are religious experiences “in which the primary element is a physical sensation or whose alleged percept is of a type normally apprehended by one of the five senses”. In this case the percepts might be visions, dreams, voices, pain, heat, being touched. Davis adds to this list the sorts of mental pictures and images in our minds which conjure up sensory experiences such as smells and sounds. c) Revelatory experiences: These are experiences when the perceiver has a sudden conviction, inspiration, revelation, enlightenment, mystical vision, or a flash of insight. St Theresa of Avila writes: “The great inward light seemed to illuminate my thoughts, I experienced a magnificent sensation of arrival. I was filled with joy as though I had just discovered the secret of world peace. I suddenly knew. The odd thing was that I did not know what I knew. From then on I set out to define it”. Notice that the way in which she knew was of a different type to everyday, intellectual knowledge. It is as if it is a self-authenticating experience which needs no external verification because the nature of the experience itself is so compelling. Much of our experiences are like this so why assume that the religious experiences are different? The assumption that perception of religious percepts are of a totally different form needs qualifying rather than assuming. d) Regenerative experiences: These involve the revival of faith, body, mind and/or spirit. E.g a feeling of being recharged with new hope, comfort, joy, peace, security. Sometimes these feelings occur during prayer or meditation, and can involve the perception of being saved by Christ. 5 It is well expressed by the following from The Bhagavad Gita: “Even as the mighty winds rest in the vastness of the ethereal space, all beings have their rest in me. Know thou this truth.” When I think of these experiences I am reminded of Maslow’s concept of self-actualisation or Jung’s concept of the resolution of the self although I am not an expert enough to say that these are clearly one and the same thing. e) Numinous Experiences: Drawing on Kant’s distinction between the noumenon (the thing in itself)and the phenomenon (things as we perceive them), Rudolf Otto best describes the Numinous experience in the following way: a) The experience that the material isn’t as powerful as the spiritual b) Mysterium tremendum: i) Feelings of awe, dread and terror ii) The perception of being overpowered by the numen iii) A feeling of intense energy iv) A sense of the wholly other nature of the ineffable v) A fascination of and attraction to the Numen Also less extreme experiences can be numinous – for example the experience of the sacredness of the world. Numinous experiences are generally dualistic but can slip into mystical oneness too, to which I’ll come later. Think of the story of Moses and the burning bush where Moses hides his face because he was afraid to look at God. Likewise, in the Bhagavad Gita Arjuna describes the following on the battlefield: “ Trembling with awe and wonder, Arjuna bowed his head, and joining his hands in adoration he thus spoke to his God: ‘I see the splendour of an infinite beauty which illumines the whole universe. It is thee! With thy crown and sceptre and 6 circle. How difficult thou art to see! But I see thee: as fire, as the sun, blinding, incomprehensible. Heaven and earth and all ye infinite spaces are filled with thy spirit and before the wonder of thy fearful majesty these three worlds tremble.’” f) Mystical experiences: These are the most difficult experiences to describe. It is here that language most clearly fails to convey the experience. At the heart of the mystical experience is a sense of paradox and a sense that the duality of the world is merely a mental construct, whilst the true reality lies in unity. Here are some aspects of Mystical experience: i) Apprehension of ultimate reality, the pinnacle of the spiritual journey, the closest one can get to seeing reality face to face. Normal experience is seen as a shadow, a cloud, a veil in comparison with the mystical experience. Plato’s analogy of the cave might be seen as expressing this aspect of the mystical experience. ii) A sense of freedom from the limitations of time and space, and a dissolution of the boundary between the self and everything else. Jacob Boehme writes “The soul here saith, I have nothing, for I am utterly stripped and naked; I can do nothing, for I have no manner of power, but am as water poured out; I am nothing, for all that I am is no more than an Image of Being, and only God is to me I AM; and so, sitting down in my own Nothingness, I give glory to the Eternal Being, and will nothing of myself, that so God may will all in me, being unto me my God and All Things”. 7 To the outsider of such experiences this sounds very negative, since there is a focus on the loss of the self, to which humans cling. However, to the mystic the self does not exist in the first place. Rather it is the belief in the self which distances us from the supreme reality. The Zen Buddhist writer D.T Suziki describes it as follows: “The individual shell in which my personality is so solidly encased explodes at the moment of satori (enlightenment). Not necessarily that I get unified with a being greater than myself or absorbed in it, but that my individuality, which I found rigidly held together and definitely kept separate from other individual existences…melts away into something indescribable, something which is of a quite different order from what I am accustomed to.” iii) A sense of oneness. This can be both a sense of oneness in oneself (introvertive(after Stace)), or a sense of oneness between oneself and everything outside of oneself (extrovertive). The latter is described by William Blake’s words “To see a world in a grain of sand, and Heaven in a wild flower”. It is also expressed well by the tat tvam asi (that thou art) of the Upanisads: ‘Whatever they are, whether tiger, lion, wolf, boar, worm, fly, gnat or mosquito, they all become that (the ultimate reality). That which is the subtlest of the subtle, the whole world has it as its self. That is reality. That is the self, and that art thou.” Here the self is understood not in the dualist way we normally understand it but in the unified sense of being which pervades all reality as a unified whole. The oneness can be expressed in terms of a oneness with God or a oneness with the universe. 8 iv) A feeling of bliss or serenity. St Catherine of Genoa wrote “Might but one little drop of what I feel fall into Hell, Hell would be transformed into a Paradise”. Viktor Frankl wrote “For the first time in my life I was able to understand the meaning of the words, ‘The angels are lost in perpetual contemplation of an infinite glory.’” Mystical states of mind sometimes sound indistinguishable from psychosis. Guidance is often needed from a wise person to help the mystic cope with the experience. This of course raises the question as to how to distinguish mystical experiences from psychosis, and I shall return to this point later on. g) I’d like to add to Davis’ list, experiences of the religious. By this I mean the experience of witnessing, whether or not as an outsider, the rituals, buildings, scriptures and people of different religions. In these cases it would be possible to claim, in a very ordinary sense, that one had had a religious experience if one means in this case an experience of a religion rather than of the supreme being or reality behind the religion. This different approach to religious experience is least likely to be refuted by the sceptic, and this is a significant point. If people generally believe others when they say, for example, ‘I had an experience of Islam when I visited the Dome of the Rock’ then why does the sceptic generally disbelieve a person when they say ‘I had an experience of Allah’? This point is taken up by Richard Swinburne to whom I’ll refer to this point later on. DVD of scene from American Beauty, and “unspeakable truths poem”. Discuss with your neighbour whether or not these are examples of religious experience. 9 Evaluating realist claims of religious experience: In what follows I am going to evaluate realist claims to religious experience, with reference to four key areas: 1.The first of these key areas is that of Conflicting truth claims Along with David Hume, many others have suggested that there is a problem with the conflicting truth claims of different religions. The argument states that if a Hindu perceives Krishna and a Christian perceives the Virgin Mary, these can’t both be true. If one is true then the other must be false since they belong to distinct, mutually exclusive traditions. Furthermore, to equate all religious experience as of coming from the same source is both a misrepresentation of beliefs from within religious traditions and also a pluralist imposition from the outside, laden with its own values and beliefs, which can’t be justified. Counter-arguments to the conflicting truth claims criticism: a) Interpretive religious experiences are, by their description, understood as being interpretations from a certain perspective, so biases are already being acknowledged. Apparently conflicting experiences can be explained with reference to the cultural and religious context in which the experience takes place. Thus a person living in India in 1000BCE is likely to express a religious experience differently to someone living in Mecca today. On the other hand this explanation doesn’t help us with distinguishing real religious experiences from false ones, and therefore interpretive religious experiences are not sufficient evidence in themselves for a reality behind the perceptions. 10 b) Different religious experiences and revelations show an evolving progress towards a greater truth. The understanding that scientific knowledge has evolved over the years can be matched with the understanding that religious knowledge has evolved over the years. With this approach we can argue that we are getting closer to the religious Ultimate Reality just as we are getting closer to scientific truth. The problem with this counter-argument is that it renders all past religious experiences and indeed religions as a whole, only partially true. This is not something that can be accepted by the exclusive Abrahamic faiths for whom their own beliefs are understood to be the final and unalterable truth. Furthermore, conversion experiences imply an exclusivist approach to religious truth-claims, since they rely on the assumption that the ways of looking at the world previous to the religious conversion experience, were erroneous. On the other hand, as a general rule Buddhism and Hinduism are faiths which sit comfortably with a pluralist and evolving journey towards truth. Ultimately where we stand on this issue will largely be conditioned by the religious context in which we are living, including the pluralist and exclusivist positions, and this therefore leads us back to the conclusion that these experiences are not sufficient evidence in themselves for a reality behind the perceptions. c) In terms of Mysticism there are great overlaps between the faiths. All of the faiths have their own tradition of mysticism and often they see it as the apex of the religious journey towards ultimate reality. The aspects of Mystical experience outlined above are found in all religions, including the concept that ultimately, mystical experiences are ineffable and full of paradox. Davis suggests that mystical experiences defy western, Cartesian logic, and that perhaps there is a 11 higher type of ‘mystical logic’ which is not based on a dualistic understanding of the world but on a monistic understanding of the world. From our western Cartesian backgrounds we tend to assume that logic holds the keys to truth, and this needs some justification. We can use logic adequately to assess arguments, but we can’t use logic to determine whether or not logic is the final arbiter of truth. Rather than being further from truth perhaps we are nearer to truth when we point to the limits of language in explaining what we have experienced. This is, after all, what drives so much of our artistic endeavours. The Via negativa is, I believe, a good example of this. The approach of the via negativa is to say what ultimate reality is not (rather than to say what ultimate reality is) so as to avoid making positive claims which, by the limited nature of language, are always insufficient to describe ultimate reality. Thus for Buddhists, Nirvana is said to be the quenching of thirst, the end of greed, hatred and delusion and the annihilation of the self (not to be confused with suicide). Likewise the early thinker known as Pseudo-Dionysius writes : “(The ultimate reality) is not soul, or mind…nor can It be described by the reason or perceived by the understanding, since It is not number, or order, or greatness, or littleness…It is not immoveable nor in motion, or at rest….” You could try this with your students: Get them to describe what God is not (assuming for the time that there is a God). Whilst there are differences in some areas of mysticism, there is also a core of agreement across the board. Take the example of the Trimurti in Hinduism arising from the single ultimate reality of universal spirit called Brahman; The Godhead which lies behind the Christian trinity; and the Three bodies or Rupas of Buddha coming out of a unified Truth-Body (ie truth itself) in Mahayana Buddhism. These may not be the same thing, but the similarities face us with, 12 at the very least, a strange coincidence. We are reminded of the story of the Blind men and the elephant. Others would want to point to the discrepancies between the mysticisms of the world’s religions, arguing that this common core is a fabrication, based on the preconceived pluralist agenda. And they could be right. But for some the agreements outweigh the disagreements. This is magnified many times when we take into account our biological nature as animals. We are born with what Schopenhauer called the ‘will to life’, and the basic instincts of distinguishing friends from foe. We are born with the dualistic cognitive frameworks which help us to distinguish ourselves from everything around us, to enable us to survive. Furthermore, we are bred into clans and tribes, we are essentially adolescent in our need for peer recognition and the security of a group, and thus we erect barriers between ourselves and other humans. They who are not-me, soon become not-us. And we are glad to know that they are other, and we are even more glad to know that we are right and they are wrong. But stop for a moment and read the scriptures of the great traditions and we find, amongst the rules and rituals, a call for togetherness for people, a commitment to love and fair play. The golden rule. Dig even deeper to the mystical roots of religions and I sense, in so far as I understand, that the divisions fall right away, completely. And this is, in my view, the deepest mystery. And this is as much as can be said, the rest we can only point to, or experience for ourselves. I may of course be entirely mistaken. I may be misrepresenting the religions which do hold exclusive positions. It is difficult if not impossible to find the true religion underneath the traditions and cultures of the world. 13 Indeed if we were to find this truth it would reduce the mystery which is at the heart of religion and which is both wonderful and frustrating! However, perhaps it is a peculiar modern day misconception that mystery implies falsity. I think that many of our students have forgotten their ability to wonder at the world. They, and we, are numbed by entertainment and other drugs and we often ignore the journey towards truth altogether, because being entertained is……….more entertaining. I want my students to be more open to mystery, and I’ve found that this is best done through balancing philosophical debate with stillness and meditation. And I don’t get the right balance often myself! We need to balance these in our own lives to be fully human, by teaching through being full….. of being. We can open our students to the spiritual by being spiritual ourselves, by embodying the virtues, the questing and the spirit we’d like to see in them. And here I mean spiritual rather than being filled with words, humour or entertainment (although these have their place too!). This is our most difficult task, and I almost constantly fall short of the mark myself, but it is the most noble task we can have. Coming back to Mysticism, we can either focus on the disagreements between religious mysticisms or on the similarities. It is difficult to be sure which of these is the greater. My hunch is that the similarities are greater than the differences. Furthermore, I’d argue that to see the world through spiritual eyes is to seek harmony between people, to seek an end to hatred, to encourage love for others and for oneself, and to dismantle the barriers which separate us and which are the cause of so much pain. But maybe I’m wrong. The main thing, I believe, is to continue trying to understand, in the knowledge that we can’t be sure, and to embrace the uncomfortable mystery, whilst trying to wrestle with it at the same time! It seems to me a 14 strange, if not contradictory, thing to claim that we as finite beings can be certain in our understanding of our version of God and truth. I’d rather a path of uncertainty, whilst acknowledging that this path itself could be construed as a form of certainty. That’s why we need to keep searching, and that is why we need to keep our students searching. 2. The second area I want to look at is that of Reductionism If we believe that the universe is nothing but atoms, then all religious experience is to be explained through the physical laws of the universe. We might get there through psychological explanations such as hyper-suggestibility, sense deprivation, mental illness and maladjustment, but the reductionist won’t stop at these explanations, she/he will want to go right down to the laws of physics. That does of course leave consciousness itself: if the universe is essentially matter how does matter become aware of itself? This question is still unfathomable and it is perhaps the last holy grail of the materialist search. Certainly, there are endless articles on the issue of consciousness amongst the scientific community. What I find interesting is that at the limits of our understanding both in science and in religion we use metaphors and analogies to make sense of what we find difficult to put into words. What exactly is anti-matter? How can a photon be a particle and a wave at the same time? Why do we think of atoms as little balls anyway? The answer lies in the fact that science needs analogies to put mathematics into concepts about which we can talk. 15 Although science helps us to explain a great deal, there are also deeply mysterious aspects of the physical world, and hence the use of models. It seems a strange case of double standards to allow these scientific models whilst at the same time refuting religious models. Furthermore, the reductionist materialist might believe that all is physical, but he/she doesn’t behave as if this is true a lot of the time. If reductionism were true then all the meaning in our lives would evaporate, and this is a theory most sane people cannot live by. If reductionism is a belief which is impossible to live then to what extent is it valid? Humans are, in my view, spiritual beings as much as they are biological organisms. Why is this so often assumed to be a dichotomy? Cannot there be many levels to reality? Are we not both animals and also conscious artists? Do we not fall in love and write poems as well as reproduce and kill animals for our survival? Is it not possible that free will, consciousness and even a spiritual level of reality exist, perhaps emerge from the physical universe, or perhaps coexist alongside it? At any rate, most people, despite (and some times because of) the advances of an increasingly materialist and secular outlook in some parts of the world, do still believe in a spiritual quality to the universe. People in some parts of the world have stopped going to church, but the spiritual yearning is still there. Again, what I’m saying is that there need be no dichotomy between spiritual and material ways of seeing the world. The problem is that if reductionism is true and all things are essentially reduced to matter then the idea of reductionism itself is nothing but matter. If this is the case it is difficult to see the relevance of it, since it is matter and nothing more, in fact it is no longer an idea at all. For these reasons we might argue that those who reduce religious experience and all experience through psychology to 16 physics raise just as many questions as they seem to answer. And we should not hesitate to discuss this with our students, and we should greatly encourage discussion with our maths and science departments on this issue. We can know a great deal through science and maths, but we can also know through emotion and the spirit. 3. The third key area is that of Critical realism Critical realists such as Keith Yandell hold that we can use certain criteria to assess truth claims about all experience including religious experience. We might make a list of criteria which we could use to ascertain the validity of a religious experience, and we should visit these with our students to give them some tools for discernment: a) Internal and external consistency: E.g the coherence of the concepts used in the description by the perceiver; the way the experience fits into the pattern of other experiences; consistency with non-religious background knowledge b) The fruits of the experience: e.g good for the perceiver in terms of leading to a life of wisdom, humility, and goodness towards others; tending to building up the community rather than destroy it c) Consistency with other religious doctrines within the same religious tradition d) Being of stable mind: most religious communities distinguish between healthy and neurotic religious experiences. Most claims to religious experience by those with psychotic tendencies cannot be used as evidence for the reality behind the experiences. Whilst many psychotics do claim to have religious experiences they also claim to have non-religious experiences which are also psychotic e.g persecution by imagined others. They also have a tendency towards fragmented thought as a whole. Also, psychotics often claim to have 17 religious experiences which are painful or involve persecution and self harm and this counts against the ‘fruits’ idea above. Psychotics are often terrified of a fragmentation of the self rather than experiencing the uplifting unitary peacefulness of the mystic. In my view, religious experience is neither necessarily a neurosis nor an opiate. Each of these criteria of critical realists might be criticised, in particular some will point out the radically different nature of religious experience to normal sense experience. Furthermore, religious experience often happens after a period of training and this counts against its authenticity. However, flashes of inspiration often occur in scientists after concentrated periods of time at work on a problem. To simply say that it is justified to accept scientific flashes of insight but not to accept religious flashes of insight is to beg the question. In fact all our interpretations of experience are based on layers of mental training. Language, acquisition of knowledge, perception and beliefs are interrelated and all play their part in the way we see the world, but it is a leap from this to saying that they determine what we see. Rather they help to shape it. Alvin Plantinga put forward the idea that religious experiences are, for the believer, ‘properly basic beliefs’ meaning that they are self-evident and do not need any more evidence than other perceptual beliefs which we take to be true in our everyday experiences. But Plantinga acknowledges himself that this is likely to only show that for believers it is reasonable to accept one’s religious experiences, and not that this will be enough evidence to convince the sceptic. 4. My fourth key area is that of the problem of the Ineffable 18 If Ultimate reality is so ineffable (not possible to describe in words), we surely can’t talk about it at all, and if this is the case then we can’t argue for its existence any more than we can argue against it. This is where faith comes in. Faith is (as John Hick put it) the ‘seeing-as’ and ‘experiencing-as’. It is the way in which we view the world despite our limits of understanding. In Buddhism the analogy is used of a finger pointing to the moon, where we shouldn’t focus on the finger (dogma, doctrine) but on the moon itself. Perhaps getting too hung up on words is like looking at the finger and not the moon. On the other hand some would say that describing religious experience as indescribable is a cop out! I wonder what you think. Religious experience is not the only experience which we find difficult to put into words. What of love and beauty, what of the smell of coffee? These too are ineffable. Aquinas’ analogies of proportion and attribution are useful here: we can talk of love because we can experience love in our lives from other humans, but this is a shadow when compared with the love of God for us. Hence God’s love is ineffable but we can still experience it. For Buber, a main characteristic of religious experience was of relationship. For Buber experience of God is an I-thou, personal relationship analogous to our relationships with other humans, but different in quality. This is distinct from an I-it relationship which we might have with an object. As such it is necessarily ineffable since all relationships we have with each other are ultimately impossible to describe fully. It’s a matter of degree, and hence proportion, as Aquinas pointed out. In our restless and overloaded lives it is difficult to have time to stop and rest. It is difficult to find time for quietness and stillness, but I believe that it is at these times that the greatest 19 spiritual insights often arise. Sitting still surrounded by natural beauty, meditation through prayer, studying the scriptures, chanting, breathing and visualisations are all very useful tools for bringing an antidote to all these words. I am well aware of the irony of my saying this to you today, and so I propose, as a brief break from my words, for us to sit silently for a minute. (Thumbs exercise). This is an exercise which I find most useful with my students as a way into silence and stillness. Writer’s week vs St.Peter’s Cathedral Now, I’m afraid I need to carry on with my talk…. 5. The fifth area I want to touch on briefly is the Problem of Classical Theism The Classical Theist concept of God faces many problems, to which believers consider that there are answers. These include the problem of evil, the problem of a bodiless God acting in a world limited by time and space, the paradoxes of God being transcendent and immanent, timeless and everlasting, personal and impersonal and so forth. I don’t want to even begin to analyse these today, but they do of course provide further debate. If we were able to show logically that God is an ontological a priori impossibility then we might, if we are sticking to logic, have disproved God’s existence. This has not been done adequately, as far as I am aware, nor do I believe that it will be done and as such there is, in my mind, at least the possibility that God exists. If this is so then there is, at least a possibility that religious experiences are sometimes really true. Nonetheless the tensions inherent in the God of classical theism are too great for some, like Don Cuppitt, who have let go of this view altogether. I imagine that these tensions are the ones you might be exploring with your students in 20 philosophy of religion classes. The students will certainly have a view on these issues. I simply leave you a question: What sence can we make of the concept of God? 6. Finally I want to look at Cumulative arguments Both the arguments for and against religious experience are strongest when put together cumulatively. The final conclusion is a matter of evidence leading to faith, and Richard Swinburne makes a valuable contribution to this debate. He argues from the principles of credulity and testimony. The principle of credulity states that in the absence of the following we should believe our own perceptions, including religious experiences: a) The conditions of the experience leading generally to unreliable claims b) The subject being generally unreliable c) The percept not being present d) The alleged percept being present, but not a cause of the subject’s experience. The Principle of credulity only shows that Religious Experience is, in some instances, probable, not certain. In many if not most cases Swinburne is happy to concede that religious experience is unfounded, but he thinks that in some cases it is founded by the absence of evidence to the contrary. Swinburne’s second principle, the principle of testimony, comes out of the principle of credulity: we can’t test everything, so in general we should believe the testimony of others in the absence of evidence which might count towards disbelief. This is generally the case: when people tell us they’ve experienced something we generally believe them. 21 Thus if we put the principle of testimony and credulity together there will be some cases in which it is justifiable to believe that a real religious experience has taken place. And here I don’t just mean a claim to religious experience, but that a reality lies behind the experience, to which the experience refers. Assuming his principles of credulity and testimony, Swinburne goes on to argue for God’s existence. He argues that if the evidence for God’s existence was very low then this might count against God, but this is not the case (since there is at least some evidence for God e.g design, cosmos, ontology) and therefore belief in God is more probable than belief in his non-existence. So he combines the principles of credulity and testimony to arrive at the conclusion that sometimes when a claim is made to religious experience this is more likely to be true than to be false. The principle of credulity implies that the sceptic has a more difficult task than the theist. Criticisms of Swinburne: i) ii) iii) Swinburne is Christocentric, and doesn’t take account of the diversity of Religious experiences Conflicting truth claims between religions exist eg Buddhism and Christianity. If he is right it counts against truth claims of other religions. Most experiences work with Swinburne’s criteria but to place experience of God beside other experiences and to apply the same criteria for judging perception and testimony is to make a categorical mistake. On the other hand this criticism itself begs the question: why assume the categories are so dissimilar? Furthermore, this criticism seems to have beneath it the assumption that really the only reality is the material, and this is as we have seen questionable, and impossible to justify without reference to faith in the materialist world view. In other words it is a circular argument. 22 iv) Finally, he argues that our starting point should be credulity not scepticism, and this is dubious, as Descartes would want to argue if he were here. Davis points out that what one considers sufficient evidence will depend on the circumstance. ‘seeing a rabbit in the field’ is different to ‘seeing the Risen Christ’. She goes on to write that challenges to a perceptual experience may be overcome in two ways: If the challenge is defeated, or if the challenge is outweighed by other evidence in favour of the validity of the experience. In other words if there is cumulative evidence which weighs heavier for the reality of the perceived religious experience, then it is reasonable to believe in the reality of the experience. If on the other hand the cumulative evidence against the experience is greater than that for the experience then it is more reasonable to disbelieve. Of course the problem lies in determining which side of the argument has the stronger case. Anthony Flew described the leaky bucket argument, in which he criticised the cumulative case for God by saying that many arguments each with flaws do not lead to a good argument overall, in the same way that a series of leaky buckets put inside each other still leaks. However, if Flew is right about the short comings of the cumulative argument in favour of religious experience, there must also be shortcomings in any cumulative case against religious experience too. So what is my conclusion? I don’t pretend to have all the answers, but I hope that I’ve at least stimulated some debate today. My overall conclusion is that when we claim to have a religious experience there are 23 some indicators to which we can refer to test this claim, albeit imperfectly. Thus a claim to religious experience is not just a fantasy, but a claim to a true reality beyond that experience. The experience itself is a signifier and a pointer towards something else, something mysterious. This experience is impossible to communicate perfectly, and so too are other experiences we’ve had, but this mystery is a cause for creativity, and the claim to truth is no less valid. And this means that religious experience is not off limits in the classroom, since acknowledging mystery is at the heart of the religious journey. It is this epistemic distance, this cloud of unknowing which I feel allows for faith and for the spiritual journey towards understanding. We will all have experiences on the way which are part of this journey, I for my part find music, meditation and the natural world to be the best catalysts for religious experience, you no doubt have your own preferred ways or perhaps you think there is no spiritual reality. Either way I wish you well on your onward journey. Any questions? 24