Some Points on Plato, Aristotle, and Rhetoric [These represent my reflections, responses, and opinions.] Plato and Dialectic – a method for moving through disciplined discourse toward an acknowledged, if not ever fully embraceable truth. -- a way of using careful examination of assumptions/propositions in relationship to authoritative moral principles, in order to expose and refute falsehood, propose and reveal a direction toward truth (a behavioral commitment, a way of acting), and the process, through guided dialogue, to teach/persuade a person to make recognize the need for that commitment and to make it. -- the interactive exchange between a patient philosopher/teacher and an engaged but still uninformed and unformed student—it leads, gradually, through the self-conscious guidance of the teacher, to the student’s awareness of, appreciation for, acceptance of, and commitment to a movement to truth. -- the dialectic demonstrates ways of understanding the meaning of that which can be claimed but cannot be directly sensed, the transcendent meaning behind the experience of truth’s shadows in the material world. -- the expression and demonstration of loving intimacy of spirit (not body) between the loving teacher and the beloved student, and the embrace of love as a path to truth by the student through the recognition and acceptance of love’s transcendent and transformative power. -- Plato prefers the direct oral discourse of dialectic, between two individuals or among a small group, because he repeatedly demonstrates that love is essential to truth, and devotion to truth is essential to love, and that both must emerge from the psychological intimacy of that interpersonal dialogue represented in the writings. -- we might theorize that Plato rejects “rhetoric” that is public speaking, not “rhetoric” that is interpersonal discourse, because the public speaking is about manipulation and control of a group or crowd, not about the shared awakening to the love of truth between a teacher and student. -- Plato’s sense of what would be a “true rhetoric” is an intimate discourse of teaching through which both teacher and student come closer to active love of truth. -- Plato’s rejection of “public rhetoric” seems more a matter that it is neither necessarily loving nor necessarily truth seeking, merely seeking resolution of issues and consensus on action. 1 -- dialectic is the rhetoric of love, where love is the ongoing commitment to seek the truth and to share with others the seeking of that truth—it is the loving verbal dance of truthseeking. Aristotle – Logic, Dialectic, and Rhetoric – draws on the Platonic/Socratic tradition, but extends it as a more formal Method. -- Aristotle’s philosophical oeuvre represents a wide range of subjects, both fundamental/general and specific and topical. -- at the heart of his philosophical system is the Organon (can be called the “instrument” or perhaps the “method”) – an elaborate, analytical, hierarchical system for determining what we can know and how we know it —taken as a whole, the Organon is a systematic logic that allows for the development and expression of true statements. -- the Organon comprises the following: Categories, On Interpretation, Prior Analytics, Posterior Analytics, Topics, and Sophistical Refutations—the first three of these represent the foundational principles and procedures of deductive logic, establishing the categories of reasoning, the terms of reasoning, and the procedures of reasoning (almost like a linguistics study—how terms can be placed into groups, and how the groups can be used to propose statements about the relationship between and among groups, between and among terms, and between and among terms and groups (to some extent, we have so embedded this kind of logical processing in our language, our institutions, and our overall culture that it seems almost a given, an outgrowth of nature itself, but it is all the result of intellectual endeavor by Aristotle, his students and followers, and generations of philosophers who worked as disciples of the Aristotelian philosophy). -- at the heart of the whole Organon, especially at the heart of the first half, is the syllogism—the basic method for making statements about the true relationships between and among things and categories of things -- the Posterior Analytics deals with induction, though it also depends on deduction as well – drawing on the rather nebulous and perhaps transcendent concept of “nous” (a kind of a priori knowledge, or a kind of natural potential of the mind to perceive first principles), one can establish a basis for observation, analysis, and deduction that, in concert, demonstrate what can be established as real and true. -- in the Posterior Analytics, demonstration is revealed as a deduction that produces knowledge (in a sense, a kind of applied logic that is deployed in response to experience and observation, resulting in authoritative statements about reality—i.e., knowledge, and in this case, an early form of authoritative “scientific” knowledge. 2 -- the Posterior Analytics and the procedures of demonstration are what, for Aristotle, constitute a “scientific method,” and the technique of the “demonstration” is the means by which scientific knowledge is established—how we know what is. -- at the heart of Aristotle’s sense of “science” is a knowledge of causes—the cause why something is, that this cause is definitive, and that it cannot be otherwise. -- Aristotle deals with four aspects of causality—the Material Cause, the Formal Cause, the Efficient Cause, and the Final Cause— The Material Cause is that out of which something comes (its material nature and substance). The Formal Cause is the shape the thing takes. The Efficient Cause is that which is the primary source of something’s condition (e.g., what shapes the material into the form). The Final Cause is the “telos” or the reason or end for which something exists. -- additionally, Aristotle is concerned that the analysis of causality yield a sense of what are “necessary” and “sufficient” causes of something— The “necessary” cause – if A is necessary for B, then the mere presence of B, indicates the presence of A (but the presence of A does not, of itself, indicate the presence of B). The “sufficient cause – if A is a sufficient cause of B, then the mere presence of A does indicate the presence of B (but the presence of B does not, of itself, indicate the presence of A because B can be brought about by another cause, say C). -- Dialectic in Aristotle relates both to the methods of discovering premises or propositions from which a conclusion follows and also to the methods for discovering premises which will be accepted by an audience – in the service of logic and science, dialectic is more often than not a method of challenging and refuting premises—dialectic also works in areas of greater certainty or authority than rhetoric, but less certainty or authority than demonstration—in a way, it is a middle ground between demonstration and rhetoric. -- Rhetoric, for Aristotle, is parallel to dialectic, using similar methodologies and procedures, but in the service of areas that are not so much authoritatively proved as agreed upon through consensus – rhetoric is also a matter of understanding what premises can lead to what conclusions, but in a context influenced by both the character of the speaker and by the states of mind of the listeners, and so it is much more in the realm of the probabilistic than in the realm of the demonstrable. [ Note: The notes on Aristotle are derived from my own reading and study, in part, and also from a variety of prior courses from times gone by. To review, I found a useful online source on Aristotle’s logic -- http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-logic/] 3