- Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - Epistemic Equality Dr. Boaz Miller Postdoctoral Fellow, The Edmond J. Safra Center for Ethics, Tel Aviv University boaz.miller@gmail.com Dr. Meital Pinto Assistant Professor, Faculty of Law, Carmel Academic Center, Haifa meital.pinto.1@gmail.com Introduction We acquire many of our beliefs from the testimony of others, including experts, and from social institutions, such as science, that are in charge of generating knowledge. Knowledge generation is social in at least three fundamental ways. First, the generation of knowledge depends on an apt division of cognitive labour among researchers (Kitcher 1990). Second, it depends on the existence of justified relations of trust among them (Hardwig 1985). Third, hypotheses must undergo a social process of critical scrutiny and evaluation, as in peer-review, to acquire the status of knowledge (Longino 2002). Because knowledge generation is social in these ways, unequal social power relations may obstruct it. We understand epistemic equality as the solution to such obstructions. Let us distinguish between different possible meanings of “epistemic equality”, and identify the one in which we are interested in this paper. One question epistemic equality may answer is how science may promote society’s becoming more egalitarian and less discriminatory (Kourany 2010), or how it can advance global equality, for example, between the developing and developed worlds (Harding 2002). Other questions it may answer are how society members’ concerns should be equally addressed by science and reflected in its research priorities, and how society members can equally benefit from the products of scientific research (Kitcher 2001). While these are interesting and important questions, and may indirectly relate to the question we address in this paper, the account of epistemic equality we develop in this -1- - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - paper has a different focus. We are concerned with epistemic equality in the context of justification.1 We assume that knowledge production is a social process in an epistemic community, in which claims undergo critical scrutiny, and those claims that successfully survive this scrutiny are communally accepted and certified as knowledge. Unequal social power relations may obstruct this process. For example, the rich and powerful may try to use their power to bring about the communal acceptance of views that suit their interests. They may also try to prevent acceptance by artificially manufacturing uncertainty that prevents the closure of controversies, e.g., tobacco companies’ efforts to impede the scientific acceptance of the harms of smoking (Oreskes & Conway 2010). Epistemic equality of the kind in which we are interested in this paper is designed to prevent such undesirable situations, and aid the smooth and successful generation of knowledge. We regard epistemic equality in the context of justification as addressing a distributive problem. Participation in, and influence over, the knowledge-generating discourse are a limited good that needs to be justly distributed among putative members of an epistemic community. The question our account of epistemic equality answers is how this good should be allocated, such that reliable (justified, trustworthy) knowledge is produced. Put differently, we are interested in a distributive account of equality in an epistemic community designed primarily to achieve the epistemic aim of the successful generation of knowledge. “Knowledge” is used here as a success term that signifies an epistemically privileged form of belief or acceptance that is distinguishable from mere opinion, speculation, or educated guess. 1. Characterizing Epistemic Equality In this section, we characterize epistemic equality in the context of justification qua a scheme of distributive justice. Let us start by examining Longion’s notion of “tempered equality of intellectual authority”, which she suggests as a regulative norm that should govern the knowledge-producing process of critical scrutiny in an epistemic community. The context of discovery refers to the part of research in which hypotheses are raised and explored. It is contrasted with the context of justification, in which hypotheses are tested and accepted or rejected. This distinction is commonly attributed to Reichenbach (1938). 1 -2- - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - Longion’s notion of tempered equality will serve as a springboard for developing our own account. Tempered equality is one of the four norms recommended by Longino’s Critical Contextual Empiricism (Longino 1990, Ch. 4; 2002, Ch. 6). Critical Contextual Empiricism regards objectivity as the aim of inquiry. Longino distinguishes between two meanings of “objectivity”. The first is veridical representation of reality. The second is lack of subjective bias. She argues that the latter is required to achieve the former. She argues that bias enters inquiry by filling the logical gap of underdetermination of theory by evidence. Inquirers make background assumptions that are neither logically necessary nor determined by the evidence, and typically reflect their biases and prejudice. Social norms of critical deliberation are therefore required to expose and eliminate such biases. Such norms grip on the individual inquirer in the sense that they require him to question and publicly defend his assumptions and claims to knowledge. Longino holds that an agreement in an epistemic community amounts to knowledge only if it is reached through a process of critical deliberation and scrutiny that follows four norms: (1) there are public venues of criticism such as professional journals and conferences; (2) there is uptake of criticism – members of the community appropriately respond to the criticism and revise their views accordingly; (3) there are publicly recognized standards of evaluation of theories; (4) there is tempered equality of intellectual authority – intellectual capacity and relevant expertise are the only criteria by which people are given the right to participate in the collective critical discussion, and those with intellectual capacity and relevant expertise do in fact realize their right to participate, regardless of gender, race, etc. The fourth norm is the one we are concerned with. Tempered equality of intellectual authority states that “the social position or economic power of an individual or group in a community ought not determine who or what perspectives are taken seriously in that community” (Longino 2002, 131). Tempered equality inter alia requires diffusion of power, -3- - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - which means giving preference as much as possible to research programs with flat rather than hierarchical power relations. For example, preference should be given to programs that do not require expensive or scarce equipment, to which only select few have access. Similarly, researchers should not be required to have specialized skills, such as extensive mathematical training, more than is actually needed for successfully carrying out their research. Such excessive requirements are a means of exclusion of able researchers, women in particular, and they give undue decision-making power to those who possess these skills (Longino 1995, 389). The idea behind tempered equality is preventing situations of underdetermination in which there are several theories that can accommodate the same evidence, but some of them are not seriously considered because their proponents are socially disempowered. For example, when both cultural and biological explanations are suggested to explain differences in intelligence tests scores between men and women, but only biological theories are considered because female proponents of the cultural theories are dismissed due to gender bias. Longino’s notion of tempered equality is admittedly underdeveloped and sketchy. Let us, then, try to more fully characterize it (2002, 133-134). How are we to understand tempered equality qua a conception of equality? A common distinction exists between formal and substantive equality. Formal equality may be broken down into two requirements, universality and impartiality. Universality requires that the distributive rule apply to everybody. Impartiality requires that all individuals be treated impartially. Formal equality is not equated with justice. For example, a principle that states that all blonde-hair persons should be made rulers satisfies the formal requirement, but is not just. A substantive principle of equality is one that demands that people be treated equally in certain respects that are substantive to their life (Temkin 2001, 29). Aristotelian equality is associated with the maxim of “treat like cases alike”, originally attributed to Plato. Some interpret this maxim as merely committed to formal equality, namely, to universality and impartiality (e.g., Gosepath 2011, §2.1), while others interpret it substantively (e.g., Berlin 1955-56). According to the substantive interpretation, -4- - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - which will be endorsed in this paper, Aristotelian equality makes a substantive demand on the rule of distribution, which is that the similarity condition that the rule evokes should establish a rational relation between the properties by which similarity or relative similarity between individuals is determined and the amount or relative amount of the good each individual deserves. That is, the rule of distribution cannot distinguish between individuals on an arbitrary basis, which does not draw a rational connection between the individuals’ entitling properties and the nature of the good. This requirement seems inline with Aristotle’s own words: “everyone agrees that justice in distribution must be in accordance with some kind of merit, but not everyone means the same by merit” (Aristotle 2000, 1131a). As we will see in Section Error! Reference source not found., however, defining the merit for epistemic equality is not a trivial matter. A second distinction that is relevant to characterizing tempered equality is between simple and complex equality. Simple models of equality identify one encompassing aspect in people’s lives to which all other aspects are reducible, and devise general rules for just distribution of goods with respect to that aspect. For instance, if overall welfare is the encompassing aspect, a distribution of goods is just if it satisfies the different preferences of different people with regard to their welfare. By contrast, complex equality models deny the existence of such one encompassing aspect. They identify different inconvertible currencies for different aspects of people’s lives (Miller 1995). The idea of complex equality comes from Walzer’s (1983) theory of “spheres of justice” which divides people’s lives into spheres that represent different aspects in life such as education, health, and career. In every sphere, a different criterion of distribution governs. Walzer argues that society should reduce the effect of dominant goods from one sphere over other spheres. In this way, social and distributive justice is achieved because individuals are considered only by relevant criteria. As mentioned above, tempered equality states that the social position or economic power of an individual or group in a community ought not to determine who or what perspectives are taken seriously in that community. This classifies tempered equality as a form of complex equality. That is, tempered equality recognizes the epistemic domain as a -5- - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - distinctive distributive sphere, governed by its own distributive criterion, and aims at eliminating the influence of other spheres on it. The characterization of epistemic equality as complex equality is important. Walzer stresses that in complex equality, genuine equality cannot be achieved merely by implementing a just rule of distribution within each sphere. Rather, separating the spheres and preventing the influence of dominant goods from one sphere on other spheres is as important. In the case of epistemic equality, even if we formulate a just distribution rule, e.g., relevant expertise, it is not enough that participation in and influence over the knowledge-generating discussion are allocated according to it. It is also required, for example, that the poor and other members of disempowered groups be able to acquire such relevant expertise in the first place, namely, that they get proper education, the opportunity to pursue an academic career, etc. Otherwise, they will not be adequately represented at the stage the knowledge-generating discussion, even if it is governed by a just distribution rule, and their potential epistemic imports will not contribute to the epistemic products of the knowledge-generating community. While in this paper we focus on the internal rule of distribution that should govern the epistemic sphere, we acknowledge that merely implementing it within the epistemic sphere is insufficient for realizing genuine epistemic equality. Rather, epistemic equality must be part of a systematic correction of other social inequalities, purporting to minimize the influence of dominant goods in different spheres on each other. In this section, we examined Longino’s tempered equality of intellectual authority in order to identify the characteristics of epistemic equality in the context of justification qua a model of equality. Our characterization reveals that tempered equality is form of complex equality, which defines the epistemic domain as a distinct distributive sphere, in which the distributed good is participation in, and influence over, the knowledge-generating discourse in an epistemic community. Within this sphere, this good is distributed according to the principle of Aristotelian equality, in its substantive form, where the distributive criterion is relevant expertise in the issues under discussion.2 2 Rolin (2009) argues that stakeholders regarding issues under discussion may legitimately participate in -6- - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - As mentioned, Longino’s account of tempered equality of intellectual authority is admittedly underdeveloped. If an account of epistemic equality in the context of justification is to cut ice, we need one of two things. We either need a clear formulation of what the distributive criterion of “relevant expertise” means, and how it applies to different scenarios. Call this “the top-down approach”. Alternatively, drawing on empirical experience in successful and unsuccessful cases of knowledge production, we may devise a workable method for realizing or approximately realizing the rationales of epistemic equality in different scenarios without having a clear formulation of the distributive criterion. Call this “the bottom-up approach”. In the next section, we argue that the topdown approach is difficult and ultimately futile both conceptually and practically. 2. Against the Top-Down Approach In the previous section, we characterized epistemic equality in the context of justification as a complex substantive Aristotelian equality in which participation in, and influence over, a knowledge-generating discourse in an epistemic community is allocated to individuals based on the criterion of their relevant expertise in the subject matter. In this section, we examine how a practicable definition of relevant expertise may be formulated, and we argue that its prospects are grim. Recall that Aristotelian equality requires that the distributive criterion establish a rational relation between an individual’s entitling property and the nature of the distributed good. For example, allocating seats in a bus according to skin colour does not satisfy the rationality requirement, because it fails to draw a rational connection between the two. By contrast, relevant expertise does satisfy the requirement because there is a rational connection between it and participation in, and influence over, a knowledgegenerating discourse. The rationale is that people with relevant expertise would make a the knowledge-generation discourse in the epistemic community in addition to experts, and that Longino’s Critical Contextual Empiricism can accommodate their participation. In addition, according to Douglas (2009), epistemic standards for theory acceptance may be legitimately influenced by people’s stakes regarding the risks associated with possible errors. It follows that being a stakeholder in addition to an expert may be a relevant criterion for participating in the communal critical discussion. We acknowledge that this may add complexity to our account, but we leave it out of our account within the scope of this paper. -7- - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - positive contribution to, and influence over, the knowledge-generating discourse in the domain of their expertise. A natural way to go is formulating the relevant expertise criterion in terms of a person’s having relevant credentials, such as education, publications, and awards. As we will argue in this section, however, this way faces many difficulties and ultimately leads to a dead end. The first problem with this suggestion is epistemic. It is often unknown or disputed who the relevant experts are. When the subject at hand has not been extensively researched, it is unclear who the experts are, who can actually produce knowledge about it, especially when putative experts from different domains make competing claims to expertise. In addition, in complex matters, expertise is required to determine who the experts are, which leads to regress. Second, formulating relevant expertise in terms of credentials leads to exclusion of alternative forms of expertise, and perpetuates the social status quo, which is not necessarily just or desirable. A case study that is commonly mentioned in this context is Wynne’s (1996) study of the Cumbrian sheep-farmers affair. In 1986, following the Chernobyl disaster in Russia, high nuclear radiation levels were measured in sheep in the Lake District of Cumbria, England. The sheep were grown by local Cumbrian farmers, and played a central role in the economy of the area. Drawing on models of radioactive decay, government scientists confidently attributed the radiation to fallout from Chernobyl. Their claims encountered scepticism, however, because the alleged Chernobyl fallout just happened to concentrate in the area surrounding a local nuclear facility, in which a major nuclear disaster had taken place thirty years before (Wynne 1996, 21-24). The failure of credited expertise in this case was evident. While the scientists first confidently predicted that radiation levels would drop within three weeks, after which the sheep could be slaughtered and sold, the radiation levels stayed high for years. Only later was it realized that the radiologists wrongly extrapolated from models of the behaviour of caesium in clay soil to the local peaty soil, in which it behaved differently. Time and time again, scientists’ predictions proved false, which did not undermine their confidence. In addition, scientists’ experiments for measuring the levels of radiation in sheep failed, -8- - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - because they ignored local farmers’ criticism of their design that did not take into account sheep grazing patters. Last, scientists gave the farmers useless advice, which ignored farmers’ local knowledge about possible and impossible farming practices (Wynne 1996, 25-36). Wynne argues that the failure of scientific expertise in this case was not due to mere scientists’ arrogance. Rather, it goes at the heart of the constitutive norms of modern science. We may therefore draw general lessons from it. The first scientific norm that Wynne identifies is artificial standardization of variations, and extrapolation from idealized models, which caused scientists to err by ignoring relevant local variations in the physical environment and farms. The second scientific norm is prediction and control, which engendered in scientists’ exaggerated sense of certainty. These norms conflicted with farmers’ epistemic norms of local variability, adaptation, and intrinsic lack of control (Wynne 1996, 37-38). Trying to identify experts by characters, such as academic education and official accreditation, then, leads to marginalizing uncredited experts, such as the farmers, whose expertise stems from relevant life experience or alternative training. Uncredited experts offer a viewpoint that supplements the scientific viewpoint and is sometimes superior to it. It is important to remember that credited experts usually already enjoy greater epistemic authority and social power than uncredited experts, who are usually already excluded and marginalized. Thus, formulating the relevant expertise criterion in terms of credited expertise may give more power to those who already have it, pulling the rug under the very point of epistemic equality. It might be objected that Wynne’s study does not expose problematic constitutive norms of modern science, but merely depicts a case of bad science, namely, science that fails to live up to its own standard. According to this objection, good scientists ought to have taken into consideration farmers’ local knowledge and admit their own uncertainty rather than disguise it. Thus, we simply need to formulate the relevant expertise criterion in terms of credited experts who are also good scientists. This objection fails, however, for two reasons. -9- - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - First, Wynne’s study is not an isolated case. There are other cases that lend themselves to similar analysis, which suggests that this may well be an epistemic failure typical of science. For example, Suryanarayanan and Kleinman (2013) have conducted an ethnographic research of the ongoing debate about the honeybee colony collapse disorder. Since 2005, there has been an unexplained phenomenon of massive collapse and die-off of honeybee colonies. In the US, there has been a dispute between commercial beekeepers on the one hand, and scientists and regulators on the other hand. Commercial beekeepers claim, based on their experience and knowledge of the fixed and changing conditions in their environment, that the growing use of certain pesticides (neonicotinoids) is a major factor responsible for the disorder. Yet scientists reject this claim, because they have not managed to conclusively prove it using standardized methods of experimental design (yet the experiments do not rule out the beekeepers’ hypothesis either, and some are suggestive of it). Similarly to Wynne, Suryanarayanan and Kleinman analyze this case as an epistemic failure of the constitutive norms of modern science. They argue that standardized experimental methods are too rigid to accommodate as relevant evidence the beekeepers’ testimonies, which draw on on their actual real-time experience and observations. They further argue that standardized experimental methods that try to isolate and control single causes do not manage to cope with the complex beekeeping reality on the ground, in which multiple causes exist and interact. Last, they argue that the scientific preference for avoiding false positives over avoiding false negatives in illegitimate in this context, and sets the epistemic bar too high for the beekeepers to meet. Moreover, inequality in social status between the scientists and beekeepers is responsible for the fact the scientists are the ones who are taken by the regulator as authoritative on the subject. In our view, to the extent that Suryanarayanan and Kleinman’s analysis is correct, this is an epistemic failure that epistemic equality should be able to correct. The mere fact that the beekeeper’s evidence fails to meet pre-existing institutionalized epistemic norms does not in itself constitute a legitimate reason for scientists to dismiss the beekeepers’ testimony as relevant evidence and exclude it from the knowledge-generating discourse. - 10 - - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - The second reason the above objection fails is that it in fact acknowledges that good science needs to take into account non-scientific perspectives. Thus, a criterion of inclusion for epistemic equality needs to allow uncredited experts to participate in and influence the knowledge-generating discourse. But we see no reason not to include uncredited experts as equals, rather than as informants to the scientists, who are not allowed to participate in the knowledge generating processes themselves. So far we reviewed two problems with the top-down approach – the epistemic problem of identifying the right experts in a non-question begging way, and the problem that cashing out a relevant expertise criterion in terms of relevant credentials – the most seemingly promising way to go – leads to marginalizing uncredited experts, who are already in a socially inferior status with respect to credited experts. We now move to discussing the third problem with the top-down approach, which is a principled conceptual problem that stems from the inherently dual nature of expertise as both cognitive and social. The attempt to formulate a distribution criterion in terms of relevant expertise presupposes that relevant expertise can be formulated in purely cognitive terms, such that it can be used as a criterion for the allocation of a social good. But expertise is inherently both social and cognitive. Expertise is intrinsically a social status that entails social privileges and powers to those that have it. Thus, in a society in which putative experts already have more (or less) social power than they deserve, appealing to expertise as a distributive criterion for implementing epistemic equality would just perpetuate the existing inequalities. Expertise is inherently social in two ways. First, as Fuller (2006) argues, experts are socially recognized as cognitive authorities in their domain of expertise, which is, by its very nature, esoteric and inaccessible to lay people. But such recognition ipso facto also gives experts special autonomy that entails privileges. Experts have the exclusive power to define their domain of expertise, and the problems they can and cannot address. Experts have the power to decide on the resources they need if their services are to be used. And strikingly, when experts’ solutions fail, experts are the ones that decide the causes of failure and have the power to blame and assign responsibility! Fuller compares experts to magicians who get - 11 - - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - to decide how the stage is set and what the audience gets to see and not to see if it wants to enjoy their tricks. Turner (2003, Ch. 2) argues that this dual nature of expertise – both cognitive and social – poses a difficulty to liberal commitment to equality and state neutrality. The state mandates experts to decide what counts as factual, thus they de facto have the privilege to decide what is beyond the scope of political discussion. I do not want to overstate the case and argue that expertise cannot be subject to political legitimation or public criticism. As Turner argues, while the public usually lacks the epistemic competence to directly evaluate scientific evidence, it can and does evaluate the technological outcomes of science, for example, in medicine and physics, and legitimates them. Turner argues that the state should adopt only those fields that have gone through such a process of political legitimation. Yet, that expertise may in some cases undergo a process of political legitimated by the lay public does not alleviate the problem of using expertise as a distributive criterion for epistemic equality, as it does not show how the social in expertise can be separated from, or reduced to, the cognitive. Second, expertise is social because knowledge and belief are social. As Mill (1993, 86) writes, a person’s beliefs are a product of “his party, his sect, his church, his class of society […] his own country or his own age”. Feminist epistemologists add that because certain perspectives are often inseparable from certain social identities, even in open and critical settings, there is a limit to people’s ability to transcend their original background and free themselves of their biases and prejudice. This is why Longino (2002, 132) argues that the absence of women and ethnic minorities from a scientific consensus, even if not intentional, constitutes a serious cognitive flaw, which reduces the community's critical resources. Yet, at the same time, Longino’s norm of tempered equality requires that factors such as social and ethnic background should not be taken into account when allocating the good of participation in and influence over the knowledge-generating discussion of the epistemic community. That is, for Longino, the distributive criterion for tempered equality is purely cognitive. In Longino’s account, then, there is a conflict between two opposing rationales, one that - 12 - - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - requires that members’ social background be taken into consideration and one that requires that they be ignored. This tension stems exactly from the dual – social and cognitive – nature of expertise. It may be argued that this tension may be resolved if we regard the first condition of social diversity as a condition of inclusion in the communal discussion, and the second criterion of relevant expertise as a condition for participation in, and influence over it. That is, social diversity is a preliminary condition of membership in the epistemic community, and once the community is constructed, relevant expertise is the procedural condition for considering the different members’ views once the knowledge-generating discussion takes off. But this reply seems incompatible with Longino’s account. If, as Longino argues, social backgrounds are of genuine epistemic import, what is the point in including minority members with different social backgrounds in the communal discussion only to disregards their views later because they may lack sufficient relevant expertise? The inherently dual nature of expertise leads us to the last problem with relevant expertise as a distributive criterion for epistemic equality. Even if we assume, for the sake of the argument, that the relevant expertise distributive criterion is formulated such that the correct experts are identified, there is no guarantee that they will use their powers for the good. The fact that experts can positively influence the knowledge-generating processes does not necessarily mean that they will actually do so. Privileges that experts have qua experts can be misused. For example, Beatty (2006, 55-64) discusses the U.S. National Academy of Sciences report entitled The Biological Effects of Atomic Radiation (1956). This was a consensus statement drafted by leading geneticists, which masked major disagreements within them about the safe ranges of atomic radiation. Rather than making their disagreements public, the experts decided to artificially agree on wide safe radiation ranges that had no sound scientific rationale. This was for two reasons. First, geneticists worried that if they did not present a unified front, physicists would claim expertise on questions of radiation safety. Second, they shared a conviction that the public could not cope well with scientific uncertainty. As Beatty (2006, 53-6) notes, a group of experts may have various reasons to misuse their power in such a way. The experts may - 13 - - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - paternalistically decide it is better for the public that they speak in one voice; they might worry that their social status might be undermined if disagreements among them became public; they may wish to gain material support; etc. This is, of course, just one example of the many ways experts may misuse their powers. There are more. Pharmaceutical companies are accused of giving clinicians implicit and explicit economic incentives to skew results (Brown 2004). In an anonymous survey for Nature among practicing scientists, 15.5(!) percent of surveyed scientists admit to “changing the design, methodology or results of a study in response to pressure from a funding source” (Martinson et al. 2005, 737). The questionable phenomenon of “ghostwriting” of published papers is also becoming more common (Sismondo 2009). The commercialization and corruption of research have reached such an extent that Marcia Angell, a Harvard medical researcher and former editor-in-chief of the New England Journal of Medicine, argues – among other senior researchers – that much or even most of our clinical medical research may no longer be trusted (Angell 2009). To conclude this section, the top-down approach, i.e., trying to formulate a distributive criterion for epistemic equality in terms of relevant expertise that should be applicable to different distributive scenarios, leads to a dead end. In the next section, we present the bottom-up approach, and argue that it offers the best solution for realizing the aims of epistemic equality. 3. In Favour of the Bottom-Up Approach In the previous section we argued against the top-down approach, which tries to develop in the abstract a distributive criterion for epistemic equality, and apply it to different cases. In this section, we argue that the alterative bottom-up approach is both workable, and better realizes the political and epistemic aims of epistemic equality. What is the bottom-up approach? It is simple. The bottom-up approach requires that we examine the particular characteristics of a given case and similar cases like it, identify relevant group that are likely to be otherwise underrepresented, excluded, marginalized, or dismissed, and make sure that they participate in the knowledge-generating discussion and - 14 - - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - are able to influence it as equals. Instead of trying to formulate a substantive criterion of relevant expertise in order to implement epistemic equality, the bottom-up approach simply makes sure that there is active participation of members of disempowered groups, such as women and minority members, who have seemingly relevant interests in the matter at hand, without worrying too much whether they possess relevant expertise or not. As a general heuristic, looking for members of vulnerable groups, such as lower classes, and ethnic, gender, and national minorities is a good way to start. More precisely, the bottom-up approach can be expressed as the satisfaction of two requirements: (1) all accredited experts with seemingly relevant expertise equality participate in and influence the knowledge-generating discourse, regardless of the prestige and status of their institution; (2) relevant stake holders with seemingly relevant experience-based or alternative expertise equally participate in the discourse. For example, in the above-discussed cases, the sheep farmers and beekeepers should be identified and included as equals in the knowledge-generating process. Or when drafting a document such as the DSM, patients and not just psychiatrists should have the ability to participate and influence the outcome. How does the bottom up approach realize the moral and political aims of epistemic equality? Equality is the opposite concept of discrimination. Therefore, delving into the moral harm of discrimination is useful for explaining how the bottom up approach realizes the moral and political aims of epistemic equality. As we have seen, Aristotelian equality requires that a distributive criterion be based on a rational connection between the individual’s entitling property and the nature of the good. When a distributive criterion between individuals is not based on such a rational connection, it is arbitrary in the sense that it ignores the individuals' specific needs, capacities and prospects. It denies them the equal concern and respect they deserve as human beings (Dworkin 1977, 272-273). An example of such a discriminatory practice is a “separate but equal” education policy, which - 15 - - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - distinguishes between individuals based on skin colour, although there is no rational connection between it and the good of education. By contrast, in many cases in which the distributive criterion establishes a rational or seemingly rational connection between the entitling property and the distributed good, we find it permissible. For example, we think that it is legitimate to accord citizens’ right to vote according to age. This is in spite of the fact that such a distribution criterion is based on a stereotype, i.e., a generalization with regard to individuals that bear the same property. The stereotype in this case connects the voting age with certain properties we think are required for voting such as mature judgment. We know that this is an approximation – there are people under the voting age that possess the properties required for voting, and there are some over it that do not. That is, we know that using this stereotype as a criterion for distribution does not allow individuals to demonstrate that they do not fall within this stereotype (Schauer 2003, 120). We know that like all other stereotypes, it limits individuals' freedom and autonomy by enforcing an image on them, which they personally did not create, and prevents them from presenting themselves as they wish in public (Réaume 2003, 673; Moreau 2004, 298-303). We find the use of such stereotypes permissible, although they limit autonomy, because we cannot afford, do not want to, or simply cannot in principle make an individualized investigation into each individuals’ properties. We thus find the stereotype a good enough approximation. But not all cases are like this. As we will later explain, there are cases in which a criterion identifies a rational or seemingly rational relation between an entitling property and the distributed good, but it still amounts to unjust discrimination because it significantly harms not only individuals’ autonomy but also, and more importantly, their dignity. Note that merely harming individuals’ autonomy is not sufficient for a distinction to amount to wrongful discrimination. In the voting case, the autonomy of individuals under the voting age who possess all the capacities required for voting is harmed because they are not allowed to realize these capacities by voting, while others, who also possess them, are allowed to vote. Nevertheless, this distinction is considered permissible. - 16 - - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - In what follows, we examine two views about when a use of a serotype harms dignity and therefore amounts to a morally wrong discrimination. (Recall that wrongful discrimination is the opposite of equality.) According the first view, the use of a stereotype is wrong when the stereotype is unreliable. According to the second view, the use of a stereotype is wrong when the stereotype is demeaning. We will side with the second view, and argue that the bottom up approach is consistent with it. Fricker (2007, 17-29) discusses the use of stereotypes for evaluating the credibility of a speaker’s testimony. She notes that we regularly rely on stereotypes to evaluate speakers’ credibility and trust their testimony accordingly. She coins the term “testimonial injustice” to denote cases in which a hearer assigns a speaker less credibility than she deserves because of biases; for example, when a hearer does not trust a woman because he takes women to be incapable of rational reasoning. In such a case, there is an epistemic harm – the hearer is denied knowledge or justified belief, and if such biases are systematic, the dissemination of knowledge in society is obstructed. In addition, there is a moral harm to the speaker. The speaker’s autonomy and dignity are harmed. We can apply Fricker’s analysis to using a stereotype as a distributive criterion for epistemic equality as well. Yet, according to Fricker, not all cases in which stereotypes are used amount to testimonial injustice. When the stereotype is not prejudicial, but rather reliable, the hearer is not culpable for using it, even if he makes a wrong credibility assessment, hence he does not harm the speaker. For example, if a hearer responsibly judges a speaker to be untrustworthy owing to the fact that the speaker avoids looking her in the eye, frequently looks askance, and pauses self-consciously in mid-sentence as if to work out his story, then she is not culpable, even if the speaker is in fact not a liar, but rather very shy. The shy speaker is just a victim of bad luck, and so is the honest used-car salesman who is not trusted by his customers because they hold an otherwise reliable stereotypes about usedcars salesmen’s honesty (Fricker 2007, 41-42). In Fricker’s view, then, the epistemic and moral aims of epistemic justice overlap. If we apply the same analysis to epistemic equality, then the stereotype on which the distribution criterion is based should be reliable. Moreover, the cases that realize the - 17 - - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - epistemic and moral (or political) aims of epistemic equality overlap. If this analysis is correct, however, then we are back to square one. This is because we must formulate a distribution criterion for epistemic equality that reliably connects an individual’s entitling property and his capacity to generate knowledge. As we have seen in the previous section, this approach leads to a dead end. In our view, however, the epistemic and the moral do not coincide in epistemic injustice in the way Fricker argues. Consider the following case. In most Westren countries, blood donations from men who have sex with men are refused.3 Health regulators, including the FDA, justify this policy by claiming that there is a reliable statistical correlation between homosexuality and HIV infection, which increases the risk of contaminating the donation. Opponents of this practice dispute the correlation and argue that it is based on bad scientific reasoning. In particular, it is argued that the distinction should not be between men who have sex with men and men who do not, but between persons who have only one sexual partner or none over an extended period of time, and those who frequently exchange partners (Culhane 2005). Suppose, however, for the sake of the argument that the statistics connecting homosexuality and HIV infections are reliable, then from an epistemic perspectives, according to Fricker, their use is permissible and does not amount to epistemic injustice. Nevertheless, intuitively, the use of the gay stereotype in this case is offensive regardless of the reliability of the statistics. This means that the connection that Fricker wants to draw between epistemic reliability and justice breaks down. What is the rationale for a legitimate use of stereotypes that can explain this intuition? Hellman provides an account of a specific kind of stereotypes that are not legitimate, even when they are reliable from an epistemic point of view. According to Hellman (2008, Ch.2), the use of a reliable stereotype as a criterion for distribution of goods amounts to a wrongful discrimination when the stereotype is demeaning. A demeaning stereotype is oppressive, degrading, subordinating, or regards a person as subhuman. The exact meaning of what is demeaning is contextual. It depends on the conventions and For an overview of the policy in different countries, and the controversies around it, see http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Gay_male_blood_donor_controversy. 3 - 18 - - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - perceptions in a given culture and its history. It is also usually associated with vulnerable groups in society, such as women, blacks, and gays, who have historically been victims of persecution or exclusion. More specifically, Hellman argues that a stereotype is demeaning when it meets three conditions. First, the stereotype at hand has been used in the past as a criterion for distributions of goods between individuals. Second, the individuals who are the object of this stereotype are identified as belonging to vulnerable groups in society, such as women, blacks and gays. Third, the stereotype conveys a message that is culturally interpreted in the specific society at hand as negative. Stereotypes that meet these three conditions are demeaning, even when they are epistemically reliable, because they perpetuate the inferior social status of vulnerable groups that are marked by these stereotypes. Let us take the example of profiling ethnic and racial minorities in airports in order to illustrate Hellman's argument. Let us also assume, for the sake of the argument, that the stereotype, according to which ethnic and racial minorities are more likely to be terrorists than other groups, is epistemically reliable. This stereotype is still demeaning because it has been often used in the past to distinguish between individuals, the ethnic groups that are associated with it are vulnerable groups in terms of their inferior social status in general society, and most importantly, the stereotype carries a negative message that associates ethnic minorities with terrorism. Because demeaning stereotypes are especially harmful in terms of harming individuals' autonomy and dignity, they are wrongful. In the blood-donation case, because gay man are members of a vulnerable and historically persecuted minority group, a distinction based on a stereotype according to which they are diseased is demeaning, hence morally wrong. An nice upshot of this rationale is that what naturally follows from it is that the bottom up approach realizes the moral and political aims of epistemic equality. This is because the bottom up approach starts by identifying the vulnerable groups that are usually marginalized and excluded, and makes sure that their members participate in the communal discourse as equals. Thus, it is especially designed to prevent demeaning discrimination. - 19 - - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - So far we argued that the bottom up approach realizes the political and moral aims of epistemic equality. But in the case of epistemic equality, as opposed to other models of political equality, the moral and political aims are secondary to the epistemic aim, which is the generation of knowledge, where knowledge is an epistemically prestigious form of belief or acceptance, distinguishable from mere opinion, theory, or guess. Does the bottom up approach realize the epistemic aim of epistemic equality? We will now argue that it does. Most common definitions of knowledge in philosophy are based on some variant of a conception of knowledge as justified true belief. We may use this definition to formulate two desiderata from communal acceptance to count as knowledge. First, it must be true.4 Second, when true, it must not be just accidentally true or true by mere luck.5 As we will now argue, the bottom up approach satisfies both desiderata. Let us start with truth. The bottom up approach increases social diversity among inquires, and makes sure that positions associated with members of relevant weak groups, which would otherwise be marginalized or overlooked, would get proper consideration. If one of these views is in fact the truth, the bottom up approach increases the chances that it will be accepted by the epistemic community and be certified as knowledge. Miller (2013) argues that social diversity is an important epistemic desideratum, independently of evidential support for theory that the epistemic community agrees on and eventually certifies as knowledge. That is, even if a theory on which there is an agreement in an epistemic community enjoys seemingly strong evidential support, we would still want the agreement to be socially diverse. To illustrate this point, Miller (2013, 1312) uses the following thought experiment. Suppose you discover that a scientific consensus exists that passive smoking does not raise the chances of lung cancer. Suppose this consensus exhibits apparent consilience of evidence. Studies of different types support this conclusion: Epidemiological studies show no significant correlation between passive smoking and lung cancer, structural-analysis Or be in another robust semantic relation with reality or observable phenomenon such as approximate truth or empirical adequacy. 5 See Miller (2013) for a more detailed discussion of the conditions an agreement in a community should satisfy to count as group knowledge. 4 - 20 - - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - studies suggest that cigarette smoke undergoes some chemical reaction in the open air that reduces its carcinogenic effects, etc. Suppose further these studies do not seem to be based on some common problematic background assumptions. This consensus, so the objection goes, is knowledge based. Suppose you later discover that all these studies were supported or partly supported directly or indirectly by tobacco companies. Is knowledge still the best explanation of the consensus? Not any more. Regardless of what you thought of the consensus and the evidence before, they now become suspect. A better explanation of the consensus may be that the tobacco industry is responsible for bringing it about. For example, it may have given leading researchers incentives to produce evidence that supports its interests, and this evidence convinced other members of the scientific community who formed a consensus. Diversity also helps an agreement satisfy the non-accidentality desideratum. A central problem in theory choice is a failure to conceive of alternative explanations. Hence if for a putatively successful theory T, it very easily could have been the case that had we thought of an alternative T*,we would not have accepted T, then if T is true, we are lucky to have accepted it. Social diversity increases the number of alternatives we consider, and hence we can be more confident that if T is true, it is not merely luckily true. It might be objected that the bottom up approach is not workable, because members of vulnerable groups do not always have the relevant expertise and background knowledge required for participating in the knowledge-generating discussion. This objection is problematic for three reasons. First, there are many cases in which the marginalized views come from within the scientific community, and they are dismissed due to gender and other social biases.6 Second, this objection trades on a narrow notion of expertise. It presupposes that expertise is credited expertise. If we widen the notion to include non-credited expertise, as in the Cumbrian sheep-farmers case, then members of relevant vulnerable groups do possess expertise, and it is up to the credited and non-credited experts alike to learn each others’ terminology and methods. Third, expertise can be acquired. A case of For gender bias in the biological sciences in the 19 th and 20th century see Okruhlik (1998); and for gender bias in science since the Enlightenment see Bowler & Morus (2005) at 487-510. 6 - 21 - - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome - acquired expertise by lay people, which is commonly considered a successful case in which non-scientists have made a significant positive epistemic contribution to scientific research, is the case of AIDS activists (Epstein 2004). In this case, members of a grassroots group of activists, who strongly opposed FDA drug-testing protocols for AIDS, which they took to be much too cumbersome and slow, managed by political activism to integrate in the FDA committees and significantly change the testing protocols and drug approval standards (cf. Brister 2012). While this case has unique characteristics, which distinguish it, for example, from the unsuccessful sheep-farmers case, it shows that when the conditions are favourable enough, expertise can be acquired. Conslusion In this paper we proposed an account of epistemic equality in the context of justification, namely, an account of how participation in, and influence over a knowledge-generating discourse in an epistemic community should be justly distributed among putative members of an epistemic community such that knowledge is eventually produced. We examined two possible ways to go. The first devises a distributive criterion and applies it to individual members. We argued that this approach is both unworkable and suffers from an inherent conceptual internal tension. By contrast, the straightforward way of simply increasing relevant diversity in the epistemic community and making sure that the views of members of weak groups are given proper consideration is both easy to implement, and realizes the aims epistemic equality is designed to achieve. References Angell, Marcia. 2009. Drug Companies and Doctors: A Story of Corruption. The New York Review of Books 56(1): 8-13. Aristotle. 2000. Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Roger Crisp. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Beatty, John. 2006. Masking Disagreement among Experts. Episteme 3(1): 52-67 Berlin, Isaiah. 1955-56. Equality. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56: 301-326. Bowler, Peter J. & Iwan R. Morus. 2005. Making Modern Science: A Historical Survey. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. - 22 - - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome Brister, Evelyn. 2012. Distributing Epistemic Authority: Refining Norton’s Pragmatist Approach to Environmental Decision-Making. Contemporary Pragmatism 9(1): 185203. Brown, James R. 2004. Money, Method and Medical Research. Episteme 1(1): 49-59. Culhane, John G. 2005. Bad Science, Worse Policy: The Exclusion of Gay Males from Donor Pools. Saint Louis University Public Law Review 24: 129-148. Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc. 1993. 509 U.S. 579. Douglas, Heather. 2009. Science, Policy, and the Value-Free Ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. Dworkin, Ronald. 1977. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Epstein, Steve. 2004. Democracy, Expertise, and Activism for AIDS Treatment. In Emerging Illnesses and Society: Negotiating the Public Health Agenda, ed. Randall M. Packard, Peter J. Brown, Ruth L. Berkelman, and Howard Frumkin, 102-120. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Fuller, Steve. 2006. The Constitutively Social Character of Expertise. In The Philosophy of Expertise, eds. Evan Selinger & Robert P. Crease, 342-356. New York: Columbia University Press. Gosepath, Stefan. 2011. Equality. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/equality. Harding, Sandra. 2002. Must the Advance of Science Advance Global Inequality? The International Studies Review 4(2): 87-105. Hardwig, John. 1985. Epistemic Dependence. The Journal of Philosophy 82(7): 335-349. Hellman, Deborah. 2008. When Is Discrimination Wrong? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Kitcher, Philip. 1990. The Division of Cognitive Labor. The Journal of Philosophy 87(1): 5-22. Kitcher, Philip. 2001. Science, Truth, and Democracy. New York: Oxford University Press. Kourany, Janet A. 2010. Philosophy of Science after Feminism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Longino, Helen. 1990. Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Longino, Helen. 1995. Gender, Politics, and the Theoretical Virtues. Synthese 104(3): 383397. Longino, Helen. 2002. The Fate of Knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Martinson, Brian C., Melissa S. Anderson & Raymond de Vries. 2005. Scientists Behaving Badly. Nature 435(9): 737-738. - 23 - - Work in Progress. Comments are Welcome Miller, Boaz. 2013. When Is Consensus Knowledge Based? Distinguishing Shared Knowledge from Mere Agreement. Synthese 190(7): 1293-1316. Miller, David. 1995. Complex Equality. In Pluralism, Justice, and Equality, eds. David Miller & Michael Walzer, 198-226. New York: Oxford University Press. Moreau, Sophia R. 2004. The Wrongs of Unequal Treatment. University of Toronto Law Journal 54(3): 291-326. Okruhlik, Kathleen. 1998. Gender and the Biological Sciences. In Philosophy of Science: The Central Issues, eds. M. Curd and J. A. Cover, 192-208. New York: Norton. Oreskes, Naomi & Erik M. Conway. 2010. Merchants of Doubt: How a Handful of Scientists Obscured the Truth on Issues from Tobacco Smoke to Global Warming. New York: Bloomsbury. Réaume, Denise G. 2003. Discrimination and Dignity. Louisiana Law Review 63: 645-695. Reichenbach, Hans. 1938. On Probability and Induction. Philosophy of Science 5(1): 21-45. Rolin, Kristina. 2009. Scientific Knowledge: A Stakeholder Theory. In The Social Sciences and Democracy, ed. Jeroen van Bouwel, 62-82. New York : Palgrave Macmillan. Sismondo, Sergio. 2009. Ghosts in the Machine: Publication Planning in the Medical Sciences. Social Studies of Science 39(2): 171-198. Suryanarayanan, Sainath and Daniel Lee Kleinman. 2012. Be(e)coming Experts: The Controversy over Insecticides in the Honey Bee Colony Collapse Disorder. Social Studies of Science 43(2) 215-240. Temkin, Larry S. 2001. Inequality: A Complex, Individualistic, and Comparative Notion. Philosophical Issues 11: 327-353. Turner, Stephen P. 2003. Liberal Democracy 3.0: Civil Society in an Age of Experts. London: Sage. Walzer, Michael. 1983. Spheres of Justice. New York: Basic Books. Wynne, Brian. 1996. Misunderstood Misunderstandings: Social Identities and the Public Uptake of Science. In Misunderstanding Science? The Public Reconstruction of Science and Technology, eds. Alan Irwin & Brian Wynne, 19-46. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. - 24 -