The time horizon of risky choice: Effects of delayed outcomes

advertisement
1
The time horizon of risky choice: Effects of delayed outcomes
2
3
4
Jonathan J Rolison*1, Vittorio Girotto2, Paolo Legrenzi3 and Yaniv Hanoch4
1
5
2
6
3
7
Queen’s University Belfast, UK
University IUAV of Venice, Italy
University Ca’ Foscari of Venice, Italy
4
8
University of Plymouth, UK
9
10
11
12
13
*Send correspondence to
14
Jonathan Rolison
15
David Keir Building
16
School of Psychology
17
Queen’s University Belfast, UK
18
Belfast, BT7 1NN
19
Northern Ireland, UK
20
E-mail: j.rolison@qub.ac.uk
21
22
KEY WORDS:
23
Risky choice, prospect theory, cumulative prospect theory, time discounting, time delay,
24
intertemporal choice, expected utility theory, preferential choice, time horizon, standard
25
economic theory, watchful waiting
1
26
27
ABSTRACT
28
Studies of risky choice centre on the decision maker’s evaluations of choice options at the
29
neglect of their time horizon. We demonstrate the importance of time horizon for risky choice
30
behavior by manipulating the delay of choice outcomes. Two hundred fifteen participants
31
made hypothetical choices between a sure amount and a lottery, offering either gain or loss
32
prospects. The sure amount, lottery outcome, both, or neither was delayed by one year to
33
investigate effects of time horizon on risky choices. Delaying a lottery outcome with respect
34
to a sure outcome reduced risk taking for gains and increased risk taking for losses by
35
reducing participants’ sensitivity to values and probabilities of outcomes, whereas delaying a
36
sure outcome with respect to a lottery outcome had opposite effects on choices by instead
37
increasing sensitivity to values and probabilities. Our findings demonstrate the importance of
38
time horizon for choices under uncertainty, and highlight a need for further research to
39
investigate effects of time horizon on risky choice behavior.
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
2
51
Imagine finding that your life savings invested in stocks have slumped in value.
52
Your financial advisor informs you of the odds that you might recover your losses
53
in one year from now if you hold onto your investments, but warns that you could
54
stand to lose an even larger amount. Your alternative is to sell your stocks
55
immediately, realising a loss to your savings (Problem 1).
56
57
There are two key aspects of Problem 1 relevant to the study of risky choice. First, the choice
58
options differ in their potential outcomes. Holding onto the stocks avoids a sure loss but
59
exposes the risk of losing an even larger amount. Second, the options differ in their time
60
horizon. Selling the stocks means realising an immediate loss to your savings, whereas
61
holding onto the stocks defers a potential loss to some point in the future.
62
Studies of risky choice centre on the decision maker’s evaluations of choice options
63
at the neglect of their time horizon. The standard economic view proposes that the decision
64
maker, a rational agent, endorses the choice option that yields the maximum expected utility
65
(von Neumann & Morgenstern, 1947; Savage, 1954). A number of findings inconsistent with
66
standard economic theory have led to alternative accounts of risky choice. Among the most
67
influential is cumulative prospect theory (CPT; Kahneman & Tversky, 1979; Tversky &
68
Kahneman, 1992), which proposes that prospects of gains and losses are evaluated separately
69
and in comparison with a reference point, such as current wealth. According to CPT, the
70
magnitude and probabilities of outcomes undergo transformations when the decision maker
71
evaluates choice options, where evaluations depend on subjective perceptions of the values
72
and probabilities of outcomes rather than the objective amounts.
73
A key advance of CPT is the coupling of decision weights for probabilities with
74
diminishing sensitivity to gains and losses, described by a value function. The decision
75
weights cause small probabilities to be overweighted and medium to large probabilities to be
3
76
underweighted. The value function, which is concave for gains and convex for losses, is
77
steeper for losses, displaying loss aversion. As a result, in situations similar to Problem 1,
78
people show a tendency to gamble on a riskier option (e.g. holding onto the depreciated
79
stocks) to avoid a sure loss, even when the safer option has a higher expected value
80
(Kahneman & Tversky, 1979).
81
There is good reason to believe, however, that time horizon is also involved in risky
82
choice behavior. Time horizon is commonplace in our everyday risky choices. Problem 1
83
illustrates how choice options can differ in their time horizon, such that a delayed outcome
84
might by evaluated differently in comparison to one that yields an immediate result. In the
85
same way that a savings account grows at a fixed rate of interest, standard economic theory
86
assumes that a delayed reward increases in value by fixed proportions as it approaches in
87
time (Fishburn & Rubinstein, 1982). Psychological research, however, has found the
88
subjective value of a delayed reward to increase at proportionally larger amounts as it
89
approaches in time (Green & Myerson, 2004; Kirby & Marakovic, 1996), and as a result,
90
preference for a larger delayed reward can switch to an immediate smaller reward as the
91
delay of the larger reward reduces.
92
Preference reversal for delayed rewards has its parallels in risky choice behavior
93
(Green, Myerson, & Ostaszewski, 1999; Prelec & Loewenstein, 1991; Rachlin, Raineri, &
94
Cross, 1991). As the probability of a gamble increases, initial preference for a larger reward
95
at a lower probability (e.g. a lottery) switches to preference for a smaller sure amount when
96
its riskier alternative increases in probability. This tendency occurs because decision weights
97
applied to probabilistic outcomes cause small probabilities to be overweighted, and medium
98
to large probabilities to be underweighted. Loewenstein and Prelec (1992) identified a
99
number of commonalities between risky and intertemporal choice, and the striking
100
similarity between discounting of probabilistic and temporal rewards has led some theorists
4
101
to propose that a single underlying psychological mechanism is involved (Rachlin et al.,
102
1991; Rachlin, Logue, Gibbon, & Frankel, 1986). Keren and Roelofsma (1995) found that
103
preference reversal was reduced by introducing uncertainty to choice options. When
104
rewards were made probabilistic participants preferred a larger delayed reward even
105
when a smaller reward was immediate. The authors concluded that delay implies
106
uncertainty that a reward may never be received, and as such, that delay and
107
uncertainty are inter-changeable1. The gain/loss asymmetry in risky choice, in which
108
probabilistic gains are discounted more steeply than probabilistic losses, also has its
109
counterpart in preferential choice. While individuals would prefer a larger delayed payment
110
than make an immediate smaller payment, and would prefer a smaller immediate reward than
111
a larger delayed reward, losses are discounted less steeply than gains as a function of delay
112
(Estle, Green, Myerson, & Holt, 2006; Mitchell & Wilson, 2010).
113
Similarities between risky choice and time discounting suggest that the time horizon
114
of uncertain outcomes may influence choice behavior, even though studies of risky and
115
preferential choice have typically studied time delay and uncertainties in isolation (e.g.
116
Green & Myerson, 2004; Green et al. 1999; Tversky & Kahneman, 1992). In the present
117
study, we present participants choices between risky options whilst manipulating the time
118
horizon of outcomes. In some sets, participants choose between a sure gain (or loss) and a
119
lottery gain (or loss) in a similar form to Problem 1, with either the sure amount, lottery
120
outcome, both, or neither delayed. If individuals discount the value of delayed outcomes, then
121
we should expect that time horizon will (a) exacerbate risk taking behavior when a delay is
122
applied to the prospect of a loss, and (b) heighten risk aversion when the prospect of a gain is
123
delayed.
124
125
5
126
METHOD
127
Participants
128
Two hundred fifteen US participants (110 males, 105 females; mean age= 37.06; SD=13.32)
129
recruited via Amazon’s Mechanical Turk completed one of four versions of an online survey
130
designed to measure their choices under risk. The reliability of the participant pool provided
131
by Amazon’s Mechanical Turk has been established by comparisons with other methods of
132
human data collection (Paolacci, Chandler, & Ipeirotis, 2010). The majority of participants
133
indicated either high school (N=62 of 215; 28.8%) or college (N=113 of 215; 52.6%) as their
134
highest educational attainment, and just under half (N=102 of 215; 47.4%) indicated an
135
annual household income above 40,000 US dollars.
136
Design and Materials
137
Participants were presented a choice between a sure amount and a lottery for 115 gambles
138
divided into five gambling sets. Two of the gambling sets presented a choice between a sure
139
gain and a lottery gain of $100 with a low probability (p=.10) for one set and a high
140
probability (p=.90) for the other set. The sure amount increased in increments of $5 for each
141
of 21 gambles from $0 to $100. Two further sets were identical with the exception that the
142
sure amount and lottery referred instead to losses rather than to gains. In a fifth set gain and
143
loss prospects were mixed. Across 31 gambles participants were offered the option of a
144
lottery with a 50% chance of losing $50 and a 50% of gaining an amount, x, that incremented
145
on each gamble in steps of $20 from $0 to $600, and the option of receiving nothing. The
146
five gambling sets were presented in a random order for each participant.
147
Participants were randomly assigned to receive one of four versions of the survey
148
that asked for hypothetical choices between a sure amount (S) and a lottery (L), of which the
149
outcomes were either immediate (I) or delayed (D) by one year. For one group of participants
150
the five gambling sets referred to a sure amount and a lottery outcome that were both
6
151
available immediately (IS:IL; N=49). For a second group, both the sure amount and lottery
152
outcome were delayed by one year (DS:DL; N=55), and for a third and fourth group either
153
the sure amount (DS:IL; N=55) or lottery outcome (IS:DL; N=56) was delayed by one year.
154
Since the survey was administered online, we included an instructional manipulation
155
check developed by Oppenheimer and colleagues (2009) as a final item of the questionnaire.
156
This item identifies unmotivated participants who failed to pay close attention to instructions.
157
The item, which followed the demographic items, explained the importance of carefully
158
reading the study instructions for the experimental manipulations to be effective (see
159
Oppenheimer et al., 2009). The final section of the item requested that participants ignore the
160
first three choice options provided below the statement (which included “never”, “once per
161
week”, “more than once per week”), and instead write “yes” in the text box that followed the
162
choice options, alongside the label “other”. Data from the five participants (of 220
163
participants recruited) who failed to enter “yes” in the text box were not included in the
164
present study, confirming that participants generally were motivated to provide diligent
165
choices on the survey.
166
Procedure
167
We used cumulative prospect theory (CPT) to model participants’ risky choices
168
simultaneously across all five sets of gambles. Details of the CPT model are provided in the
169
Appendix. For each choice made by participants we calculated the probability, L, that they
170
would choose the lottery over the sure amount, S, (or the option of receiving nothing in the
171
mixed prospects set), where
172
173
174
and V equals the subjective expected value of each choice option (Luce, 1959). In Equation 1,
175
 is a consistency parameter that estimates choice consistency, and could range in value from
7
176
0 to 10 (Pachur, Hanoch, & Gummerum, 2010 ; Rieskamp, 2008). A high value for the 
177
parameter would indicate that participants were switching back and forth inconsistently
178
between choice options within gambling sets. We applied the maximum likelihood
179
approach for our model fitting and used the G2 measure to assess the goodness of fit of
180
the CPT model (Rieskamp, 2008), where
181
182
In Equation 2, fiP(L,S) = P(L,S) if the lottery was chosen on choice trial i and 1 - P(L,S)
183
if the sure option was chosen, based on the CPT model parameters. The best fitting CPT
184
parameter values were those that minimized Equation 2, where smaller values of G2
185
indicate better fit. We fitted the CPT model to the data separately for each of the four groups
186
of participants.
187
188
RESULTS
For the gain and loss sets we calculated the amount of the sure option that was equivalent to
189
participants’ preference for the lottery. These certainty equivalents (CEs) measure risk taking
190
attitudes and are determined by the mid-point between gambles where a participant switches
191
from preferring the sure amount to the lottery for loss sets, or vice versa for gain sets2. The
192
mean group CEs are provided in Figure 1. The expected value of the lottery for each set
193
is indicated by the dotted horizontal line. Observing Figure 1, when the expected value
194
of the lottery was a $10 gain participants switched from the lottery to the sure amount
195
at $21.94, and when the expected value of the lottery was a $90 loss participants
196
switched from the sure amount to the lottery at $70.66, exhibiting risk seeking behavior
197
for low-probability gains and high-probability losses (Figure 1). In contrast, when the
198
expected value of the lottery a $90 gain participants switched from the lottery to the
199
sure amount at $65.25, and when the expected value of the lottery was a $10 loss
8
200
participants switched from the sure amount to the lottery at $19.30, exhibiting risk
201
averse behavior for high-probability gains and low-probability losses (Figure 1). Thus,
202
participants displayed the four-fold pattern predicted by prospect theory (Kahneman,
203
2011; Tversky & Kahneman, 1992), and this was the case for all four groups (Figure 1).
204
We conducted a four way mixed analysis of variance (ANOVA) on participants’
205
CEs, including the time horizon of the sure outcome (immediate, delayed) and lottery
206
outcome (immediate, delayed) as between subjects factors, and the domain (gain, loss)
207
and probability (low probability, high probability) of outcomes as repeated measures.
208
We reversed the negative values for the CEs in the loss sets in our ANOVA in order to
209
make group comparisons between the gain and loss sets. The certainty equivalent of the
210
lottery was significantly higher in participants’ choices when the lottery outcome was
211
likely (M=67.96) than when it was unlikely (M=20.62), F(1,155)=748.82, p<.001, but did
212
not differ between gain and loss sets (gains, M=43.60; losses, M=44.98), F(1,155)=0.73,
213
p=.394. However, the domain and probability of outcomes interacted, F(1,155)=10.99,
214
p=.001. Follow-up ANOVA’s, conducted separately for low and high probability sets,
215
revealed that the certainty equivalent of the lottery was higher for potential losses
216
(M=70.66) than for potential gains (M=65.25) when the lottery outcome was likely,
217
F(1,174)=7.20, p=.008, but not when the lottery outcome was unlikely (gains, M=21.94;
218
losses, M=19.30), F(1,179)=0.88, p=.348. This indicates that participants were more risk
219
seeking for likely losses than they were risk averse for likely gains.
220
Time horizon affected participants’ risky choices. The certainty equivalent of
221
the lottery was reduced by delaying its outcome (immediate, M=49.94; delayed,
222
M=39.06), F(1,155)=31.67, p<.001, and was increased by delaying the sure amount
223
(immediate, M=37.91; delayed, M=51.09), F(1,155)=41.37, p<.001. The time horizon of
224
the lottery outcome interacted with choice domain, F(1,155)=7.91, p=.006. Follow-up
9
225
ANOVAs, conducted separately for the gain and loss sets, confirmed that the certainty
226
equivalent of the lottery was reduced by delaying its outcome for both gain sets,
227
F(1,185)=29.99, p<.001, and loss sets, F(1,168)=8.39, p=.004. However, follow-up
228
ANOVAs, conducted separately for immediate and delayed lottery outcomes, revealed a
229
significant difference between gain and loss sets for the delayed lottery outcome,
230
F(1,86)=9.66, p=.003, but not immediate lottery outcome, F(1,69)=1.36, p=.248,
231
indicating that delaying the lottery outcome had a greater effect on gains (immediate,
232
M=51.23; delayed, M=36.39) than on losses (immediate, M=48.65; delayed, M=41.74).
233
In the mixed prospects set participants were offered the option of a lottery with
234
a 50% chance of losing $50 and a 50% of gaining an amount, x, that incremented on
235
each gamble, and the option of receiving nothing. All four groups indicated an amount
236
that was significantly greater than $50 (IS:IL, M=154.13, t(45)=4.55, p<.001; DS:DL,
237
M=125.10, t(50)=3.83, p<.001; IS:DL, M=146.40, t(49)=3.85, p<.001; DS:IL, M=139.80,
238
t(49)=4.81, p<.001), displaying loss aversion for mixed prospects. A two-way
239
independent ANOVA conducted on participants’ CEs for the mixed prospects lottery,
240
including the time horizon of the sure outcome (immediate, delayed)3 and lottery
241
outcome (immediate, delayed) as between subjects factors, revealed that the amount of x
242
at which point participants found the lottery equally attractive to the option of receiving
243
nothing was unaffected by delaying the sure outcome, F(1,193)=0.68, p=.412, or lottery
244
outcome, F(1,193)=0.27, p=.606, and there were no significant interactions.
245
Provided in Table 1 are the best fitting cumulative prospect theory (CPT) parameter
246
values for each group. In order to make comparisons between groups, we held one of the
247
parameters constant for each between-group comparison in a second round of model fitting.
248
The reduction in model fit that result from constraining a parameter indicates differences
249
between the two groups on the respective parameter, and can be tested for significance using
10
250
the chi-square statistic (Table 1). This analysis revealed that time horizon affected
251
participants’ risk taking behavior by increasing their sensitivity to changes in the payoffs (α
252
and β parameters) and changes in the probabilities (γ and δ parameters) of gains and losses
253
when the sure outcome was delayed, and by decreasing their sensitivity to changes in payoffs
254
and probabilities of gains and losses when the lottery was delayed (Table 1). This pattern is
255
illustrated in Figure 2, which plots the probability that the lottery is chosen over the sure
256
amount based on the best fitting CPT parameter values for each group. Delaying the sure
257
amount made the lottery a more attractive option when the prospect was a potential gain, but
258
reduced its appeal when it presented a potential loss (Figure 2).
259
The effects of delaying a sure outcome on participants’ choices did not mirror
260
effects of delaying its riskier lottery alternative. Figure 2 suggests that delaying the prospect
261
of a sure gain (or loss) had a greater effect on participants’ preferences for the lottery than did
262
delaying the prospect of a lottery gain (or loss). To test this, we compared the ∆G2 values for
263
each parameter—the reduction in model fit between groups when a parameter is held
264
constant—for when a sure outcome was delayed with the ∆G2 values when the lottery was
265
delayed. These comparisons revealed that delaying the sure outcome had a greater impact on
266
increasing participants’ sensitivity to changes in payoffs (gains, χ2(1)=.61.17, p<.001; losses,
267
χ2(1)=.122.47, p<.001) and probabilities (gains, χ2(1)=.86.21, p<.001; losses, χ2(1)=.12.15,
268
p<.001) of outcomes than delaying the lottery outcome reduced them. Waiting for a sure loss
269
rather than risk losing more immediately on a lottery was a more attractive option to
270
participants than paying the sure amount now rather than wait for the outcome of the lottery
271
(Figure 2).
272
DISCUSSION
273
Despite similarities between risky choice and time discounting, studies of choice behavior
274
have typically studied the uncertainty and time horizon of choice options in isolation
11
275
(e.g. Green & Myerson, 2004; Green et al. 1999; Tversky & Kahneman, 1992). We found
276
presently that the time horizon of prospects influenced participants’ evaluations of choice
277
options. Delaying a lottery outcome with respect to a sure outcome reduced risk taking for
278
gains and increased risk taking for losses by reducing participants’ sensitivity to values and
279
probabilities of prospects, whereas delaying a sure outcome with respect to a lottery outcome
280
had opposite effects on risky choice by increasing sensitivity to the values and probabilities
281
of outcomes. This innocuous sounding result has important consequences for theoretical
282
accounts of risky choice.
283
Problem 1 presented a choice between selling depreciated stocks at an immediate
284
loss, and gambling on the prospect that the loss might be recovered, if the stocks are invested
285
for a longer term. Our results suggest that delaying the outcome of a riskier option (holding
286
onto depreciated stocks) could elicit extreme risk taking behavior. We found that participants
287
were more willing to bet on a gamble to avoid a sure loss when the outcome of the gamble
288
was deferred to the future. Thus, studies of risky choice using standard economic theory (von
289
Neumann & Morgenstern, 1947) and CPT (Tversky & Kahneman, 1992) may underestimate
290
risk seeking behavior for losses and underestimate risk aversion for gains by neglecting the
291
time horizon of prospects.
292
Participants displayed the four-fold pattern predicted by CPT, exhibiting risk
293
seeking behavior for low-probability gains and high-probability losses, and risk averse
294
behavior for low-probability losses and high-probability gains (Figure 1). Effects of time
295
horizon on risky choice behavior varied as a function of both the domain and
296
probabilities of outcomes (Figure 2). Participants showed a preference for a lottery win
297
over a smaller sure amount when the lottery outcome was unlikely, and this was
298
especially the case when the sure outcome was delayed (Figures 1 and 2). When a lottery
299
win was likely participants showed a preference for a smaller sure amount, but this
12
300
preference was almost entirely eliminated by delaying the sure amount. When the
301
lottery offered an unlikely loss participants preferred to lose a smaller amount with
302
certainty, which was heightened by delaying the sure loss. Instead, preference for a
303
lottery loss over a certain loss when the lottery outcome was likely was almost entirely
304
eliminated by delaying sure loss (Figure 1). These findings imply that effects of time
305
horizon depend on both the likelihood of outcomes and whether they refer to potential
306
gains or to potential losses.
307
Our current results suggest that time horizon is a key to risky choice behavior by
308
altering people’s evaluations of risky options. Preference reversal for delayed and
309
probabilistic rewards (Prelec & Loewenstein, 1991), and the gain/loss asymmetry observed
310
for preferential and risky choice (Mitchell & Wilson, 2010), has led some theorists to propose
311
that a single underlying mechanism is involved in discounting of probabilistic and temporal
312
rewards (Rachlin et al., 1991). Our results provide a demonstration that time horizon should
313
be integrated into models of risky choice behavior.
314
Time horizon has important implications for real-world risky choice. Radical
315
prostatectomy is a recommendation made by health care professionals for men diagnosed
316
with early prostate cancer (Wilt et al., 2012). ‘Watchful waiting’ is an alternative to
317
aggressive treatment that involves monitoring cancer growth, but implies a longer time
318
horizon. Potential costs and benefits of watchful waiting over immediate treatment has
319
received much recent attention, both in the medical literature (Wilt et al., 2012) and media
320
reports (Parker-Pope, 2012). Time horizon is likely an important aspect of both patients’
321
decisions about treatment and physicians’ recommendations. In the financial domain, time
322
horizon is important for investment strategy. Individuals who have shorter investment time
323
horizons (e.g. saving for a mortgage down-payment) are encouraged by financial advisors to
324
invest less aggressively, and it is recommended that older adults be prudent in their
13
325
investments, for a loss to savings in later life could take many years to recover (Bernard,
326
2012). Recent studies report increased aversion to financial risk taking in older age (Rolison,
327
Hanoch, & Wood, 2012), and future research may seek to understand how time discounting
328
factors in financial risk taking of older adults who have shorter life time horizons than
329
younger individuals.
330
Time horizon is also central to policy making and may be a key to the climate
331
change debate. Some policy makers advocate a “wait-and-see” strategy for dealing with
332
climate change (Yohe, Andronova, & Schlesinger, 2004), and despite strong
333
recommendations by the scientific community for immediate action, long term negative
334
consequences of climate change are low on the list of concerns for the US general public
335
(Dunlap & Saad, 2001). As illustrated in Problem 1, a wait-and-see policy defers to the
336
future a potentially much larger cost that could be mitigated by immediate action. Our
337
current findings indicate that a wait-and-see policy for climate change may be
338
appealing because of the delayed time horizon of uncertain future costs. Immediate
339
action for climate change could be made more appealing if costs of immediate action
340
were re-framed in terms of long term savings.
341
Effects of extending the time horizon of sure outcomes in our study did not mirror
342
effects of delaying its lottery alternative, suggesting that time horizon has different effects on
343
certain and uncertain outcomes. Waiting for a sure loss rather than risk losing more
344
immediately on a lottery was more appealing to participants than realizing a sure loss now
345
rather than wait for the outcome of a lottery (Figure 2). Our analysis suggests that this
346
tendency did not result from a difficulty to interpret the time horizons of risky and riskless
347
outcomes. Delaying both types of outcomes together had minimal effects on participants’
348
evaluations (Figures 1 and 2). It appears that discounting rates for sure amounts are steeper
349
than for risky prospects, which may reflect an adversity to uncertain events in the future with
14
350
a greater tolerance of sure events. Managing finances to meet a fixed debit at a fixed date in
351
the future is easier to accommodate than an unknown lottery outcome.
352
In conclusion, time horizon of outcomes is a key to risky choice behavior. Our
353
findings demonstrate the importance of time horizon for choices under uncertainty, and
354
highlight a need for further research to investigate effects of time horizon on risky choices.
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
15
375
REFERENCE LIST
376
Bernard, T. S. (2012, May). Getting to retirement with minimal financial risk. The New York
377
Times. Retrieved from http://www.nytimes.com/2012/05/19/your-money/managing-
378
risk-in-your-nest-egg-your-money.html?_r=1&src=me&ref=general.
379
Chapman, G. B., & Weber, B. J. (2006). Decision biases in intertemporal choice and choice
380
under uncertainty: Testing a common account. Memory and Cognition, 34, 589-602.
381
Dunlap, R. E., & Saad, L. (2001 April). Only one in four Americans are anxious about the
382
environment. Retrieved from http://www.gallup.com/poll/1801/only-one-four-
383
americans-anxious-about-environment.aspx
384
Estle, S. J., Green, L., Myerson J., & Holt, D. D. (2006). Differential effects of amount on
385
temporal and probability discounting of gains and losses. Memory & Cognition, 34
386
914-928.
387
388
389
390
Fishbum, P. C., & Rubinstein, A. (1982). Time preference. International Economic Review,
23, 677-694.
Green, L., & Myerson, J. (2004). A discounting framework for choice with delayed and
probabilistic rewards. Psychonomic Bulletin, 130, 769-792.
391
Green, L., Myerson, J., & Ostaszewski, P. (1999). Amount of reward has opposite effects on
392
the discounting of delayed and probabilistic outcomes. Journal of Experimental
393
Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 25, 418-427.
394
395
396
397
398
399
Keren, G., & Roelofsma, P. (1995). Immediacy and certainty in intertemporal choice.
Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 63, 287-297.
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk.
Econometrica, 47, 263-292.
Kirby, K. N., & Maraković, N. N. (1996). Delay-discounting probabilistic rewards: Rates
decrease as amounts increase. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 3, 100-104.
16
400
401
Loewenstein, G., & Prelec, D. (1992). Anomalies in intertemporal choice: Evidence and an
nterpretation. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 107, 573-597.
402
Luce, R. D. (1959). Individual choice behavior: A theoretical analysis. New York: Wiley.
403
Mitchell, S. H., & Wilson, V. B. (2010). The subjective value of delayed and probabilistic
404
outcomes: Outcome size matters for gains but not for losses. Behavioral Processes, 83,
405
36-40.
406
Oppenheimer, D. M., Meyvis, T., & Davidenko, N. (2009). Instructional manipulation
407
checks: Detecting satisficing to increase statistical power. Journal of Experimental
408
Social Psychology, 45, 867–872.
409
Pachur, T., Hanoch, Y., & Gummerum, M. (2010). Prospects behind bars: Analyzing
410
decisions under risk in a prison population. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 17, 630-
411
636.
412
Parker-Pope, T. (2012, July). Choosing ‘watchful waiting’ for prostate cancer. The New York
413
Times. Retrieved from http://well.blogs.nytimes.com/2012/07/23/choosing-watchful-
414
waiting-for-prostate-cancer/
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
Paolacci, G., Chandler, J., & Ipeirotis, P. G. (2010). Running experiments on Amazon
Mechanical Turk. Judgment and Decision Making, 5, 411-419.
Prelec, D., & Loewenstein, G. (1991). Decision making over time and under uncertainty: A
common approach. Management Science, 37, 770-786.
Rachlin, H., Logue, A. W., Gibbon, J., & Frankel, M. (1986). Cognition and behavior in
studies of choice. Psychological Review, 93, 33-45.
Rachlin, H., Raineri, A., & Cross, D. (1991). Subjective probability and delay. Journal of the
Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 55, 233–244.
Rieskamp, J. (2008). The probabilistic nature of preferential choice. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: Learning, Memory, & Cognition, 34, 1446-1465.
17
425
426
Rolison, J. J., Hanoch, Y. & Wood, S. (2012). Risky decision making in younger and older
adults: The role of learning. Psychology and Aging, 27, 129-140.
427
Savage, L. J. (1954). The foundations of statistics. New York: Wiley.
428
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative
429
430
431
432
representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.
Von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1947). Theory of games and economic behavior (2nd
ed.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Wilt, T. J., Brawer, M. K., Jones, K. M., Barry, M. J et al. (2012). Radical prostatectomy
433
versus observation for localized prostate cancer. New England Journal of Medicine,
434
367, 203-213.
435
436
Yohe, G., Andronova, N., & Schlesinger, M. (2004). To hedge or not against an uncertain
climate future? Nature, 306, 416-417.
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
18
Table 1
Best Fitting Cumulative Prospect Theory (CPT) parameter values for each group
CPT Parameters
Group
α
β
γ
δ
λ
IS; IL
0.684
0.719
0.575
0.636
0.889
DS; DL
0.681
0.722
0.628
0.711
0.783
IS; DL
0.586
0.637
0.485
0.611
0.675
DS; IL
1.178
1.336
2.772
0.758
0.152
φ
0.199
0.204
0.367
0.012
Mean G2
97.677
92.709
91.580
101.321
∆G2(IS; IL vs. DS; DL)
0.029
0.035
4.206
6.833
3.917
0.041
P
.864
.852
.040
.009
.048
.839
∆G2(IS; IL vs. IS; DL)
15.286
7.084
19.438
1.266
7.573
23.219
P
<.001
.008
<.001
.260
.006
<.001
∆G2(IS; IL vs. DS; IL)
76.460
129.553
105.645
13.417
67.531
140.956
P
<.001
<.001
<.001
<.001
<.001
<.001
450 Note. Α, β, γ, δ, λ, and φ, are the best fitting CPT parameters values based on participants’ choices
451 when either the lottery outcome (IS:DL), sure outcome (DS:IL), both (DS:DL), or neither (IS:IS) is
452 delayed. Α and β describe participants’ sensitivity to changes in the value of gains and losses,
453 respectively, whereas γ and δ describe participants’ sensitivity to changes in probabilities of gains
454 and losses. Λ measures loss aversion, and φ measures choice consistency. G2 is the model fit, and
455 ∆G2 is the reduction in model fit for each parameter when the parameter is held constant across
456 respective groups. P is the chi-square significance test for the ∆G2 value.
457
458
459
460
19
461
462
Figure 1. Mean group Certainty Equivalents (CEs) when either the lottery outcome (IS:DL),
463
sure outcome (DS:IL), both (DS:DL), or neither (IS:IL) is delayed for low (p = .10) and high
464
(p = .90) probability gain and loss sets. Dotted lines indicate the expected value of the lottery
465
for each set. Error bars represent 1 standard error above and below the mean.
466
467
468
469
470
20
471
21
472
473
Figure 2. The predicted probability that the lottery is chosen over the sure amount based on
474
the best fitting cumulative prospect theory (CPT) parameter values for each group. The
475
observed probabilities are the proportions of participants who chose the lottery over the sure
476
amount. The probabilities are plotted separately for each gambling set and separately for each
477
group, with either the lottery outcome (IS:DL), sure outcome (DS:IL), both (DS: DL), or
478
neither (IS:IL) delayed.
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
22
497
APPENDIX
498
Within cumulative prospect theory (Tversky & Kahneman, 1992), the subjective value of an
499
outcome, x, is identified by its value function
500
(A1)
501
where the curvature of the value function is determined separately for gains and losses by the
502
α and β parameters, respectively. Α and β were treated as free parameters to be fitted to
503
participants’ data, and were constrained to values greater than zero and <10, producing a
504
concave function for gains and a convex function for losses when below 1. Loss aversion is
505
captured by the λ parameter applied to the value function for losses, and was constrained to
506
values greater than 0 and <10, where values greater than 1 indicate loss aversion.
507
508
509
510
511
The decision weights, γ and 𝛿, transform the probabilities, px, for gains and losses,
respectively, and identify the individual’s sensitivity to gains and losses, where:
;
(A2)
512
.
(A3)
The γ and 𝛿 parameters were constrained to values above 0 and <10. For decision weights
513
smaller than 1, probabilities of rare events are overestimated, and moderate to likely events
514
are underestimated. The transformed probabilities, px, are used to assign subjective
515
probabilities to each choice prospect, such that the probability of an outcome,
516
517
(A4)
;
518
(A5)
519
520
.
Probability weights for prospects refer either to gains, π+, or to losses, π-, and in Equations
521
A4 and A5 are determined by the difference between the probability of an outcome at least as
522
good or better than the outcome for gains, and the difference between the probability of an
523
outcome at least as bad or worse than the outcome for losses.
23
524
The subjective value, V(choice option), for each choice option is determined by
525
combining the subjective values and probability weights of each prospect, such that
526
527
The decision maker then chooses the option with the highest subjective expected value.
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
24
549
FOOTNOTES
550
1Chapman
551
choices in separate blocks of trials that referred to either monetary amounts or health
552
outcomes. While participants’ choices corresponded in the monetary and health
553
contexts, preference reversal in the intertemporal choice sets did not correspond with
554
biases in the risky choice sets. The authors concluded that similar biases in risky and
555
intertemporal choice have different underlying psychological mechanisms.
and Weber (2006) asked participants to make uncertain and intertemporal
556
557
2Fifteen
558
sure amount and the lottery for at least one of the five gambling sets, compared with 15
559
of 55 (27%) participants in the DS:DL group, 14 of 56 (25%) participants in the IS:DL
560
group, and 21 of 55 (38%) participants in the DS:IL group. Across all four groups, 13 of
561
the total 215 (6%) participants switched inconsistently in the low probability gain set,
562
compared with 15 (7%) in the high probability gain set, 25 (12%) in the low probability
563
loss set, 26 (12%) in the high probability loss set, and 18 (8%) in the mixed prospects
564
set. Gambling sets that contained inconsistent switching were excluded from our
565
ANOVA. All data were included in our model analysis.
of 49 (31%) participants in the IS:IL group switched inconsistently between the
566
567
3In
568
immediate and delayed outcomes are equivalent for the sure option.
the mixed prospects set, the sure option is to receive nothing, and thus the
569
570
571
ACKNOWLEDGEMENT
The authors would like to thank Swiss&Global-Ca’ Foscari Foundation for its support.
25
Download