1 Henry Bacon: Cognition and the aesthetics of reexperience There have been artist who have made bold attempts to insure that their work could be encountered only once as a single fresh experience. Antonin Artaud for one even suggested that if a poem was to be read at all, it was to be read once and once only, then quickly burned.1 Less drastically, in performing arts improvisation has sustained the ideal of spontaneity. As a whole, however, making works of art which can be and often are encountered repeatedly is by far the dominant cultural practice. Aesthetic reexperience is not only extremely common, it is a basic category of aesthetic experience as a whole. There are many interrelated reasons why stories are retold, books reread, films re-viewed. In order to sort them out we must first of all make a distinction between rereading soon after the first reading and rereading after a longer time lapse.2 Even more importantly, in both cases we must make the further distinction between rereading for the pleasure of the familiar and for the gains awarded by a more reflective approach driven by intellectual curiosity in the face of potential for new or enriched meaning. These two should not be seen in opposition as they often function in a complementary fashion in aesthetic re-experience. Motivations for rereading can be grouped under the headings sameness and novelty thus: Sameness Pleasure of repetition per se Comfort of the familiar Assurance granted by knowledge of plot development Persistence of narrative excitement Novelty: the pleasure of refined observation and reinterpretation due to (enhanced) awareness of the whole secondary information gained after first experience greater aesthetic sensibility due to encountering other works of art matured outlook on life new historical and cultural conditions The lower threshold or aesthetic reexperience is the almost infantile pleasure of repetition as such, while the upper threshold is the cultural historical process, where in the words of the opera producer Götz Friedrich, history acts as a “ghost writer”, offering ever new horizons of expectation and prospects for meaning. While at the one end we have something that verges on the psychologically regressive, at the other we have our bold aspiration of developing ever more subtle ways of appreciation of texts and their relation to our historical and cultural experience. Whereas the former may most satisfactorily be explained in terms of psychology, the later belongs primarily to the sphere of art and cultural studies. I will seek to demonstrate that cognitivism together with formalist poetics have considerable explanatory power in exploring the ground between these framing aspects of aesthetic reexperience. 2 Reading vs. rereading Most accounts of the actual process of reading a book or seeing a film are implicitly accounts of a hypothetical, not to say idealised, first reading. It is tacitly assumed that the reader or spectator does not know what will happen in the course of the narration. Wolfgang Iser in his the Act of Reading emphasizes the contribution the reader brings into constructing the narrative world of the text: “Any successful transfer [of text to reader]… depends on the extent to which this text can activate the individual reader’s faculties of perceiving and processing.”3 Unfortunately Iser does not here discuss how a text might activate these faculties in the process of rereading.4 If there is, as he suggests, throughout the reading “a continual interplay between modified expectations and transformed memories”,5 if switches of perspectives constitute “an inseparable combination of differentiated perspectives, foreshortened memories, present modifications, and future expectations”,6 and if grasping a text requires a “hermeneutic schema of anticipation and fulfilment in relation to the connections perceived between the signs,”7 then how do all these function in rereading? Inasmuch as rereading is even mentioned in accounts about reading, a first reading is typically expected to be above all pleasurable, rereading in turn more critical and more focused on the means of storytelling. The latter might also be expected to involve a more structured scrutiny of broader social, cultural or existential concerns. In addition to implicitly addressing the question of rereading only certain types of texts this distinction is all too clear-cut as it fails to address many of the most interesting questions about rereading – and reading itself! Already the first reading of a book or viewing of a film has two components, one immediate, involving and affective, the other critical and reflective. Readers or spectators go through the narrative material simultaneously seeking to work out the content of the narrative, its aesthetic qualities and its relevance to their lives and perceptions of the world. Rereading contributes immensely to this process, and of course the mere willingness to reread indicates that the work of art has had an effect on the mind of the reader, probably revising her related schemata while putting them into good use. Reflecting the distinction between these two components a further distinction is made in literary theory between involvement and absorption. In Matei Calinescu’s words: [Involvement] implies a definite if not always evident emotional commitment, as a result of which one is transported to another world. An involved reader thus participates in the experience of fictive people through some sort of fantasy and may identify with them or empathize with them or, at the least, be there to watch them (always taking sides, favoring some, opposing others): Absorption, on the other hand, is a state of high concentration of attention; and though it may display some of the appearances of involvement (such as obliviousness to the immediate surroundings), it lacks the sense of personal immersion so characteristic of involvement. Absorption, then, would be more imaginatively detached and more intellectual.8 Involvement and absorption may well be in operation simultaneously both in reading and rereading. This is partly because even a basic narrative experiences evokes a double foci: On the one hand, we focus on the characters at the narrative point in the story which we have reached together with them; on the other, we view them and the story as a whole from the outside, aware of the intricacies of syuzhet construction and 3 of the relevance the story might have for us. The former calls for involvement, the latter for absorption. Both are required in any reading or viewing, and presumably on repeated readings or viewings the balance shifts from involvement to absorption, from story excitement to the enhanced appreciation of the aesthetic qualities and wider implications. Aesthetics of rereading Certain texts beg to be reread. Books and films can be both narratively and texturally too rich to be processed at a single encounter. Calinescu begins his study with an analysis of Borges’ The Aleph, pointing out that the work does not call for an “implied reader”, but rather for a “rereader, someone who would feel the need to read it over again and would enjoy it more fully on rereading.”9 A book, Calinescu argues – can be eminently either readable or rereadable. There are narrative strategies which make the text particularly rewarding on a first reading (e.g. a detective story of the puzzle type), but this may to some extent be at the cost of the possibility of an interesting rereading. On the other hand there may also be “calculated, strategic textual obstacles (…) that are designed to make the first reading harder and ‘messier’ while mysteriously persuading the reader that a second reading of the work would be more revealing and rewarding than the first.”10 Certain films, say, most of Peter Greenaway’s, seem to offer such a promise. In the very best of cases a text may be both highly readable and rereadable. In this case the rereading is not just a “repetition of a previous act of reading, but more importantly it is the rediscovery of an already known text from a different vantage point, for example its reconsideration within intertextual frames whose relevance has become clear only after the completion of a first reading.”11 A lot of the story information as well as various textural features will gain new relevance when viewed in terms of the work as a whole. Thus seeing a film again (and again) can be an extremely rewarding experience as familiarity mingles with novelty. Presumably, in re-viewing a film less mental effort is spent in constructing the diegetic world than during the first viewing. Our observational capacity is thus likely to be directed elsewhere. In any re-viewing there will surely be at least a heightened sensitivity for diegetic details as we are much more able to relate them to the whole than on the first viewing. Greg Smith discusses in passing why seeing Casablanca repeatedly might award certain new pleasures: … the opportunity to observe the faces once again in light of what you know has happened in the diegetic past and what will happen in the film’s denouement. Can you see the hints of what is to come in the actor’s faces? In subsequent viewings one can look for cues about how the past impinges on the present, knowing how important that information is to driving the plot.12 One might also expect that the mental construction of the pattern characters-goalattempts-outcome-resolution would be different in re-viewing. David Bordwell points out that the earlier during the course of narration the character’s goals become apparent the easier it is for the spectators to fill in causal and temporal connections.13 As regards re-viewing films that could be classified as instances of classical narration this challenge would be further alleviated, if not abolished entirely in re-viewing. The knowledge about the goals would then function as another frame which would give 4 new significance to character traits and various activities. In art film this could conceivably function as a new interpretational frame. The question is, how do procedural schemata, “those operational protocols which dynamically acquire and organize information”,14 function in re-viewing. Again, if the initial challenge has been great, the re-viewing must obviously be somehow different. Of course, if the work is eminently rereadable the challenge might remain quite considerable, perhaps even acquire new dimensions. These may relate to the narrative and stylistic features of the film but more interestingly to thematic, philosophical and existential concerns. These cannot be separated from extra-textual factors that are likely to influence rereading. The delight of ever new frames After some distance has been gained from the first encounter with a story, new factors are likely to influence a rereading. Our aesthetic sensibility has developed, perhaps partly as a result of how the first encounter with the film has opened up new questions: it may have modified the relevant schemata in our mind. The work might have opened up issues or posed questions for which we either consciously or unconsciously have sought for answers. Often we have consulted critical or scholarly accounts or studied other works which we relate or associate with this work which has challenged us, and thus we have been influenced by the interpretive community. We might even have perceived our environment, human relationships or social structures with different eyes. Thus we will have enhanced the relevant schemata in our minds allowing us to experience the film anew. At best there is a loop between the perception and understanding of a work of art and the perception and understanding of life and oneself. All this is a part of growing older and hopefully also more mature: Our interpretative horizons expand, our sensitivity to meaning develops and grows more refined, our sense of relevance becomes ever more subtle. In cognitive terms we could say that our ways of classifying and cross referencing of information of all sorts become ever more elaborate, or, that we develop ever more refined schemata. Such schemata develop to a significant extent in the chiasmic relationships between life and art. Together with the heightened awareness of the part-whole hermeneutic these new interpretative frames give rise to new patterns give rise to new top-down processes which in turn evoke new bottom-up processes on all levels: construction of the diegetic world, awareness of stylistic patterns, appreciation of meaning. We observe more when we have a richer framework into which we can integrate our perceptions. The aspects of rereading mentioned so far are about the novelty value that a rereading or a reviewing offers. But what about that aspect of sameness, of repetition which also awards it pleasures? Immediate pleasures of rereading Apparently all repetition awards certain infantile pleasure, connected with a feeling of security, possibly deriving from a sense of mastery, at least if we accept Freud’s analysis of what he called the Fort/Da game as an explanation as to why a child should enjoy throwing away a wooden reel and then pulling it back by a string fixed round it: the reel stands for the absent mother who can not always we pulled back 5 quite so easily. By analogy, it has been suggested that the pleasure of rereading comes from the sense of mastery which emerges from the knowledge of what is to happen. On this level the pleasure of rereading connects closely with the assurance granted by stories with clearly defined good and bad characters as well as with heroes who are easy to identify with while the may gradually acquire anything up to a superhero status in fighting the baddies. Going through a story in these terms can, no doubt, be emotionally pleasurable and that pleasure is effortlessly repeatable, offering ever more assurance by fortifying comforting imaginary scenarios through repetition – an age old device of political rhetoric.15 Going through the story with the knowledge of how the plot develops can even increases the sense of superiority of the hero whose fundamental invincibility is even more obvious to the reader, as well as the sense of superiority of the reader herself, who is even more in the position of an omniscient intelligence than the first time reader of even the most formulaic popular fiction.16 Furthermore, the familiar work which seems to touch the very core of our sensitivity, our basic orientation in life, is always there, however painful the vicissitudes of life.17 There is also the formal aspect of repetition, which has always been put into great use first in play, then in art. Both music and narrative works can give rise to certain physiological reactions, arousal, tensities and emotivities, and apparently these can work out well, sometimes even better when the work is familiar. It is almost as if we trained our system to award us a certain pleasurable reactions which connect with such important issues as identity formation and sense of belonging to a community. A story, film or a piece of music may function as a means of identity construction in a community as repetition awards the imaginary sense of assurance. However, rereading may also be something for which we have an innate need for in a way which can be seen in much more positive light. Rereading or reviewing is a return to a cherished experience in a way which is not only uncritical but which may involve, sometimes quite involuntarily, taking distance from the easy comforts of returning to the familiar. This may function all the more so if that familiarity connects with one’s self-image. As Sven Birkerts writes, while novels may be “where we store our fantasies and ambitions” they may on reencounter equally well turn out to be “like running into an old lover on the street: the flat plane of the present gets a hole punched through it.” And as books, unlike ex-lovers, do not change, we have to admit that we ourselves have changed.18 But all this does not explain some of the most astonishing feature of going through the same stories repeatedly. If making hypothesis and having them confirmed or disconfirmed is an integral part of the cognitive process of going through a narrative, is this aspect simply abolished in rereading where hypothesizing should really be unnecessary? And above all, how can the excitement usually associated with novelty be a distinct part of the pleasure of rereading?19 Calinescu suggests that children like to hear stories repeatedly because familiarity allows them to play the game of involvement skilfully. Anticipation gives a sense of reassurance if the story is almost too frightening on the first hearing.20 Calinescu refers to what C.S. Lewis calls “ideal surprisingness” as opposed to “the shock of actual surprise” in order to make the distinction between “the quality of unexpectedness” as opposed to the actual fact of something being unexpected. Apparently, it is the “quality of unexpectedness” that actually delights us: the surprise is even better when you know it is coming. We may also account for this phenomenon in terms of make-believe. Kendal Walton tells about one Charles, avid consumer of Bhorror films, who is make-believedly afraid when watching these films. Calinescu is intrigued by this and treats Charles as a kind of an “actor impersonating himself in the 6 imaginary situation presented in the movie.”21 He thinks a similar pattern can be perceived in rereading as the reader is engaged once again in the same game of makebelieve and now further pretends that she does not know what will happen.22 But how is it that we can pretend to ourselves being ignorant about a story outcome? Resurprising music We can find an interesting alternative way of looking at the question of aesthetic reexperience, or, at least an intriguing and illuminating metaphor for aesthetic reexperience, in Peter Kivy’s Osmin’s Rage – Philosophical reflections on Opera, Drama, and Text. Kivy is one of the few musicologists who have addressed the question of why repetitions and repeated hearings are such an integral part of out musical experience and musical culture. He notes that Haydn often creates sophisticated musical effects by going against the expectations of an educated listener. But what about after one has heard the piece several times, when “all surprise has been dissipated by familiarity”? The paradox here being, of course, that Western culture cultivates both aesthetics of surprise and aesthetics of repetition. “How can surprise survive the ordeal of familiarity”, Kivy asks.23 Answering this question Kivy refers to the Müller-Lyer Lines and The Fraser Spiral. In the former we tend to see to lines of equal length being different because of the arrows pointing either inwards or outwards, in the latter we perceive a spiral, although the figure actually displays perturbed concentric circles. We may follow one of the circular lines with our finger and realize this, but we will not stop thus perceiving a spiral. Kivy writes about two beliefs, the “epistemic” and the “perceptual”. He then uses these terms to account for the delights of the frequently unexpected … once we have become familiar with the work through rehearing, although we epistemically believe (and expect) the aesthetically unexpected [in actual fact familiar] musical event to occur, we nonetheless continue to perceptually believe that the more “expected” (i.e. more common) event will transpire, and therefore are “perceptually” surprised when it does not.24 Kivy admits that this does not really explain why this phenomenon takes place. He even suggests that it might not be possible to explain the perceptual mechanisms involved in either the optical illusions or the experience of rehearing musical surprises. He concludes by noting that “music has form, and that part of the aesthetic vocabulary of musical form is the building up and frustrating or perceptual expectations: in other words, ‘surprise.’” Drama as virtual form It would appear, then. that the delight of surprise is a formal effect that a temporal work can have on us, and that it might somewhat paradoxically function even better when there is a tantalizing tension between our cognitive re-processing of material as it enfolds once again, and our enhanced awareness of how all that we see and hear builds up into an aesthetically more or less satisfying whole which we already master to a considerable degree. Suspense is even more obviously such a formal device. For 7 Susan Langer “art is the creation of forms symbolic of human feeling.”25 In Feeling and Form she quotes an essay by Charles Morgan called “The Nature of Dramatic Illusion.” He writes: This suspense of form, by which is meant the incompleteness of a known completion, is to be clearly distinguished from common suspense – suspense of plot – the ignorance of what will happen … for suspense of plot is a structural accident, and suspense of form is, as I understand it, essential to the dramatic form itself … What form is chosen … matters less than that while the drama moves a form is being fulfilled.26 Langer points out some ways in which the narrative mechanism in drama functions, e.g. that “like the distribution of figures on a chessboard, the combination of characters makes a strategic pattern.”27 Even more importantly, a strategic pattern can be perceived in a drama as a whole, because an “indivisible piece of virtual history is implicit in it, as a yet unrealized form, long before the presentation is completed.28 Arguably, this form in suspense is effective irrespective of the spectator’s knowledge of the outcome as it is based more on an innate need to experience completion of a pattern – just like when listening to tonal music, we have a need to hear a cadenza leading back to the tonic. To reemploy Kivy’s concepts, this desire is by nature perceptual rather than epistemic, i.e. it is not a question of knowing what is to follow but of having been aroused to wanting to perceive it. Inasmuch as this feature in our mental design is based on such tensities as described by Torben Grodal in his Moving Pictures, we could at least hypothesize that we are effective trained to having these tensities aroused in certain ways which relate to cultural and psychological issues that are important to us. According to Langer, in a tightly knit drama everything serves the purpose of depicting the functioning of destiny. It is what makes the present action seem like an integral part of the future, howbeit that future has not unfolded yet. The reason is that on the stage, every thought expressed in conversation, every feeling betrayed by voice or look, is determined by the total action of which it is a part – perhaps an embryonic part, the first hint of the motive that will soon gather force. Even before one has any idea of what the conflict is to be (i.e. before the exposition has been given), one feels the tension developing.29 Arguably, in rereading the sense of destiny seeps into the very act of reading. As Birkerts beautifully puts it: “Reading takes place in the order of free choice, rereading in the order of destiny … The second time around, our desires are set into play against our knowing.” Because of this, one added value in rereading is the increased sense of pity we might feel for the characters, who we with increased certainty know to be at the mercy of the fate, in one way or the other.30 The really intriguing thing here is that our desires concerning the narrative outcome which the drama or the film might evoke more often than not go against this sense of destiny. In their Recreative Minds Currie & Ravenscroft discuss Shakespeare’s Othello and the way we respond to this tragedy: “We have the desire-like imagining that Desdemona live, but also the (real) desire for a narrative according to which she does not.31 They then discuss tragic emotion as “a quasi-perceptual sensitivity”, in which 8 The relevant parts of the world – the parts that determine the satisfaction of our desire – are the work itself, which has to end a certain way, and my own psychology, which has to respond in a certain way to the play. A tragic response is thus as much a response to our own responses as a response to the work itself.32 It is as if what Kivy called perceptual belief was spurred by our desire for a positive narrative outcome resulting in a tantalizing tension with our knowledge of the inevitable tragic outcome. This feature of the tragic experience is likely to be as compelling on multiple viewing as on the first. In a sense this is due to the formal effect the tragedy has on us. Neither Calinescu nor Kivy nor Langer appears to have seen the light of cognitive psychology. With the advantage we have over them we can say things such as that there are perceptual phenomena which are cognitively impenetrable. Or, as regards reexperiencing stories, perhaps we should say that the excitement is cognitively only semi-penetrable, as for most of us there is a limit as to how many times we are able to feel really excited about the same old story. In any case, we still need a more developed account of the cognitive functions that allow for such experience. Anomalous reactions In his Experiencing Narrative Worlds Richard Gerrig argues that every time we go through a narrative we can be possessed by it to the extent that our knowledge of solutions to narrative complications does not inhibit us from getting involved and excited. Apparently, the “once upon a time”, or, the “as if” effect, has a degree of cognitive autonomy. Gerrig calls the experience of suspense which tends to come about while going through a story even when we know what will happen anomalous suspense. The way he sees this phenomenon is that when undertaking a “performance of the narrative world” the information previously gained about what will happen somehow becomes inaccessible.33 In other words, our “knowledge from outside a narrative world fails to influence the moment-by-moment experience of the narrative.”34 The narrative triggers in our mind some such cognitive schemata, that it gains certain autonomy even though we might not entirely forget our physical presence in our living room or the auditorium. And most importantly: “Rather than requiring special-purpose cognitive structures, anomalous suspense emerges as an automatic consequence of the time-course advantage schematic expectancies enjoy with respect to veridical expectancies.35 This chimes with an explanation Ray Jackendoff offers for the persistence of the sense of musical surprise in the face of familiarity. Musical structures have to be processed and this takes place in terms of expectations about those structures. We may hypothesize an “informationally encapsulated” processor which is innocent of the knowledge the listener may have of how the piece will develop and thus separate what Kivy called perceptual and epistemic belief. Or, as Jackendoff puts it: “The conscious knowledge that a deceptive cadence is coming thus does diminish one’s surprise, but it does not diminish the affect that comes from the activity of the processor deriving the structure autonomously.” 36 One may still assume that the balance between the knowledge and the affect may vary on each listening, thus further altering the aesthetic re-experience, capitalizing on the resources and possibilities 9 offered by the parallel processing of complementary temporal structures, one attached to the more immediate stimuli, the other (or others) to the emerging structures. There are some obvious parallels between the expectation of development of tonal structures in music and the way we construct characters when watching a film. In addition to genre based expectations, on the first viewing the first impressions we get, say, of a character, tends to hold to the extent that we make an effort to interpret subsequent information so as to make it fit into that frame. When re-viewing a film of which we know that the character is not what he seems, we may take delight in simultaneously observing how the change is being hinted at and yet in an anomalous way enjoy the pleasure of being fooled once again. Gerrig proposes that this experience of anomalous suspense emerges because of an expectation of uniqueness. We are geared to this because “life presents repeated types, but not repeated tokens”. Rereading is such an anomalous phenomenon that we are not cognitive sufficiently equipped to deal with it as a repetition of the same.37 Noël Carroll is somewhat displeased with this account as it implies that there is something irrational in this experience.38 In his view, “we gauge the relevant probabilities relative to the information available in the story preceding and during the interlude of suspense but bracket the information available after and including the moment when one outcome emerges victorious.”39 This connects with Carroll’s notion that an integral part of suspense is that the fiction offers saliently two logically opposed outcomes, one morally correct but improbable, the other morally incorrect of evil, but probable.40 In assessing these probabilities the spectator is guided by the structural features of the fiction. These are designed so as to give rise to certain tensities in us while giving definition to the moral issues involved by guiding us into getting involved with the characters. Psychologically this feature connects with our ability to become emotionally involved even in purely hypothetical narratives. In Carroll’s view, suspense experienced in re-viewing a film derives from our ability to willingly entertain emotionally engaging hypothesis, by thoughts rather than just beliefs.41 This has an evolutionary advantage as it enables us to train our ability to cope with emotionally involving situations and to train our tunedness for others. However, one may well ask whether getting excited about fictional events is any more rational than getting excited about already familiar plot developments because on some level they are experienced as unique. While the former surely has the ecological advantage Carroll suggests, arguably in the uniqueness experience of Gerrig’s description there might emerge a both aesthetically and heuristically rewarding experiences of being able to apprehend the familiar afresh, avoiding the pitfall of experiencing various kinds of phenomena as merely instances of the same. This too has ecological and social advantages. Whatever the most apt description of the cognitive process involved, this enormously useful faculty may in strange ways get the better of us: fiction may affect real-world judgments even under entirely transparent situations. Gerrig discusses how even lifeguards had to force themselves back into the water after having seen Spielberg’s film Jaws although they knew that the risk was minimal. Thus fictional narratives may affect real-world judgements even against knowledge about the state of affairs.42 It is a bit like with perceptual illusions: knowledge does not necessarily suffice for overcoming the effect. There is evidence that disbelieving actually requires more mental effort than believing. Anyone who has studied how uncritical television audiences are in the face of news broadcasts is only too aware of this. Retaining constant critical scepticism might be taxing even for a media scholar. It appears that “information becomes tagged 10 as fictional only as a function of readers’ conscious scrutiny.” Gerrig even suggests that we should replace the notion of “willing suspension of disbelief” with a “willing construction of disbelief.” 43 This is not all that surprising considering how flexible our mind is in imagining. According to Currie & Ravenscroft: When we imagine P, the tendency is for any belief that contradicts P, or which stands in substantial probabilistic tension with P, to fall into the background for the duration and purposes of imagining. The imagining then combines inferentially with those relevant beliefs that don’t contradict or stand in tension with it.44 This capacity may be fundamental, not only for aesthetic appreciation, but in making sense of other people and all sorts of strange situations in which we may find ourselves in real life: “Placing yourself, in imagination, in another’s position requires the capacity to make use of appropriate imaginative states; temporarily, one puts aside some aspect of one’s own mental economy – some belief or desire – and substitutes for it a thought content you actually don’t believe, or don’t want.” 45Correspondingly, it requires less mental effort to go along with a narrative flow than it is to observe the narrative as if from the standpoint of an outsider, without involvement. Perhaps complete detachment would even be a symptom of a lack of narrative comprehension as narratives requires an understanding of the mental situation of the characters. From involvement to possession There may be yet another reason why we may be possessed by rereading. Recalling the distinction between involvement and absorption, we may now notice how dynamically the two may be in operation in rereading. To quote Iser once more: While we are caught up in a text, we do not at first know what is happening to us…. The more ‘present’ the text is to us, the more our habitual selves – at least for the duration of the reading – recede into the ‘past’. … The literary text relegates our own prevailing views into the past by itself becoming a present experience, for what is now happening or may happen was not possible as long as our characteristic views formed our present.46 For Iser reading is clearly a matter of very deep absorption and involvement, possibly amounting in a radical switch of schemata, as we might say. Iser studies “grasping a text” as a process of forming gestalts in one’s mind. This calls for consistencybuilding from the part of the reader, i.e. trying organize narrative information into a meaningful experience. It takes place in a dynamic interaction between the text and “our own projections, which are our share in gestalten which we produce and in which we are entangled.” Iser emphasizes that this entanglement is never total, because the gestalten may be challenged by all the excluded possibilities which the text offers. Going through this process the reader is effectively suspended between total entanglement and latent detachment. Iser sees this resulting in a dialectic between gestalt forming and gestalt breaking, leading into the “reader constantly oscillating between involvement and observation” and experiencing the text as a living event, constantly provoking the reader to react not only to the text but to what she herself has produced on the basis of earlier parts of the text.47 11 For someone exploring the mysteries of rereading, it is astonishing that Iser discusses these notions entirely in terms of an idealized first reading. Would not the kind of text that requires constant revising of gestalten cry for a rereading? Would it not give rise to wholly new kind of texts as events? Iser actually ends up in a formulation of the reading experience which would without a single alternation fit to describe the experience of rereading: The new experience emerges from restructuring of the one we have stored, and this restructuring is what gives the new experience its form. But what actually happens during this process can again only be experienced when the past feelings, views, and values have been evoked and then made to merge with the new experience. The old conditions the form of the new, and the new selectively restructures the old. The reader’s reception of the text is not based on identifying two different experiences (old versus new), but on the interaction between the two.48 Through these various processes of aesthetic reexperience, of forming and reforming meaning binding gestalten, in a dialectic between indulging in the familiar and relishing the novel, we appropriate works of art by allowing them to become parts of our own way of perceiving, understanding and relating to the world. Aesthetic reexperience is a fundamental aesthetic category because it has deep resonance in our mental architecture. It is linked with issues such as being suspended between repetition compulsion and neophilia, the need to find constant reaffirmation to our sense of self as well as our orientation into the world and being equally compelled by a desire to find something new, to ever refine our perception and understanding of whatever has caught our imagination. Base on a presentation held at the CCSMI Conference, on July 20, 2006, at the Konrad Wolf Film and Television Academy, Pottsdam-Babelsberg. I wish to thank my colleague Heta Pyrhönen for important hints concerning works on rereading as well as all those colleagues at the conference who gave me feedback and helped me in further developing my ideas.. I am particularly grateful to Richard Allen for his perceptive comments. Bibliography BORDWELL, DAVID Narration in the Fiction Film. London, Routledge, 1985. CALINESCU, MATEI Rereading. New Haven & London, Yale University Press, 1993. CURRIE, GREGORY & RAVENSCROFT, IAN Recreative Minds. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002. GALEF, DAVID Second Thoughts – A Focus on Rereading. Detroit, Wayne State University Press, 1998. GERRIG, RICHARD J: Experiencing Narrative Worlds – On the Psychological Activities of Reading. Boulder, Westview Press, (1993) 1998. GRODAL, TORBEN Moving Pictures – A New Theory of Film Genres, Feelings, and Cognition. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1997. 12 ISER, WOLFGANG The Act of Reading – A Theory of Aesthetic Response. Baltimore and London, The Johns Hopkins University Press, (1978) 1987 Jackendoff, Consciousness and the Computational Mind. Cambridge, Mass., The MIT Press, 1987. KIVY, PETER Osmin’s Rage – Philosophical reflections on Opera, Drama, and Text. Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1988 LANGER, SUSANNE K. Feeling and From – A Theory of Art Developed from Philosophy in a New Key. London, Routledge & Kegan Paul Limited, (1953) 1963. ROACH, JOSEPH R. The Player’s Passion – Studies in the Science of Acting. London and Toronto: Associated University Presses, 1985. SMITH, GREG M. Film Structure and the Emotion System. New York and Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2003. VORDERER, PETER, WULFF, HANS J,, & FRIEDRICHSEN, MIKE (eds.) Suspense – Conceptualizations, Theoretical Analyses, and Empirical Explorations. Mahwah, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Publishers, 1996. References Roach, The Player’s Passion, p. 222. For the sake of convenience I will use rereading as a general term to refer to going through a book, a film, or any from of narrative for a second, third or umpteenth time. This is also because I will be adopting ideas from literary theory. By re-viewing I will be referring more specifically to the activity of seeing a film repeatedly. 3 Iser, The Act of Reading, p. 197. 4 Elsewhere Iser refers to an active interweaving of anticipation and retrospection, which on a second reading may turn into a kind of advance retrospection.” (The Implied reader, p. 282. Quoted in David Galef. “Observations on Rereading”, published in Galef, Second Thoughts, p. 19) 5 Iser, The Act of Reading, p. 111. 6 ibid, p. 116. 7 ibid, p. 120. 8 Calinescu, Rereading, p. 164. 9 ibid, p. 3-4. 10 ibid, p.32. 11 ibid, p. 8. 12 Smith, Film Structure and the Emotion System, p. 164. 13 Bordwell, Narration in the Fiction Film, p. 35. 14 ibid m, p. 36. 15 Karen Odden argues in her “Retrieving Childhood Fantasies” (published in Galef, Second thoughts) that “we reread popular literature in order to return to childhood dramas that may not have been acted out as we wished or that were not worked through appropriately (and therefore become traumas) in order to recover our belied in the fantasies before they were destroyed.” (p. 132) 16 Odden, “Retrieving Childhood Fantasies”. Published in Galef, Second thoughts, p. 142. Odden elaborates this in her Freudian analysis: “Rereading fulfils a fantasy that no first reading of any text ever can: I am all-knowing and can avoid the negative effect of trauma by anticipating frightening events perfectly, every time.” (p. 146.) 1 2 13 17 ibid, p. 140. Sven Birkerts: “Some Thoughts on Rereading.” Published in Galef, Second thoughts, p. 341. 19 Assuming that the stories are remembered, that is; reencountering a work which has already been sinking behind the horizon of one’s memory is a wholly different kind of pleasure 20 Calinescu, Rereading, p.191. 21 ibid, p. 189. 22 ibid, p. 190. 23 Kivy, Osmin’s Rage, p. 54. 24 ibid, p. 56. 25 Langer, Feeling and Form, p. 40 26 ibid, p 309. Quotation from Charles Morgan: “The Nature of Dramatic Illusion”, p. 70-72. Published in Essays by Divers Hands, a volume of Transactions of the Royal Society of Literature, N.S. Vol. 12, ed. by R.W. Macan, 1933, p. 61-77. 27 ibid, p. 311. 28 ibid, p. 310 29 ibid, p. 308. 30 Sven Birkerts: “Some Thoughts on Rereading.” Published in Galef, Second thoughts, p. 343. 31 Currie &Ravenscroft, Recreative Minds, p. 40. 32 ibid, p. 203. 33 Gerrig, Experiencing Narrative Worlds, p. 80. 34 ibid, p. 176. 35 ibid, p. 238. 36 Jackendoff, Consciousness and the Computational Mind, p. 245. 37 Gerrig, Experiencing Narrative Worlds, p. 238. 38 Carroll, “The Paradox of Suspense”, published in Vorderer, Wulff & Friedrichsen (eds.), Suspense, p. 90. 39 ibid, p. 82. 40 ibid, p. 78. 41 ibid, p. 87. 42 Gerrig, Experiencing Narrative Worlds, p. 198. 43 ibid, p. 230. 44 ibid, p. 16. 45 Currie &Ravenscroft, Recreative Minds, p. 147. 46 Iser, The Act of Reading, p. 131. 47 ibid, p. 127-128. 48 ibid, p. 132. 18