CHAPTER THREE Bozeman, B. (1979). Public Management and Policy Analysis. New York: St. Martin’s Press. Policy Philosophies, Public Management, and the Public Interest Before turning to the “meat” of the book—the chapters related to theory and practice in the management of public organizations—this chapter is a fanciful fling at ~the broad philosopht6~l-value premises of public management and public policy. In this chapter there is no concern with social science, observable data, verification, operational concepts, and all those other matters dear to the hearts of analytically oriented students and practitioners of public administration. This chapter is designed to encourage reflection about “good” and “bad” in policy and administration, with particular attention to that old bugaboo of empirically oriented social scientists, the public interest. The concept policy philosophy is introduced here to help us explore the value component of policy. The basic notion is that a relatively small number of primal values have influenced policy and administration throughout the ages. These clusters of values—and this is the substance of a policy philosophy, a cluster of values—filter into the policy process through the political culture, the legal system, and even the psychological predispositions of individual decision-makers. Another of the ways that policy philosophies have been influential is through various conceptions of the public interest. If a policy philosophy is an enduring set of values about the basic ends and means of government, any particular conception of the public interest may be thought of as a conclusion drawn from the premises of a policy philosophy. 60 POLICY PHILOSOPHIES To reiterate, a policy philosophy is a set of values about the purposes of government or the most desirable means of achieving purposes. The policy philosophy concept should not be taken as absolute and should not be rigidly defined, nor should the particular policy philosophies identified in this chapter be taken as an exhaustive list. The policy philosophies discussed here have been subjectively developed and loosely defined, and others may wish to develop additional or alternative policy philosophies that are more in accord with their subjective interpretation of the basic value clusters influencing policy and administration. Six policy philosophies will be discussed here—protectorism, rationalism, brokerism, pragmatism, transferalism, and egoism. The values associated with each are discussed, the place of the policy philosophy in modern and classic political thought is alluded to, and in a later section the relation of each to various conceptions of the public interest is explored. Protectorism The chief premise of protectorism is that policy exists to protect people from one another and from themselves. The political executive as protector is a theme that emerges early in political philosophy. One of the first protectorist philosophers was Plato. While there is a strong antidemocratic element involved in the elevation of restraint to a guiding principle, the antidemocratic bias is only one aspect of protectorism and not the most important. The pillar of this conception of governing is a negative view of mankind—both in regard to abilities and, more important, to intentions. Man is, by this view, a natural troublemaker and a consistent malefactor. The view that the common man is ill-equipped for political participation is clearly assumed in Plato’s Republic; the inevitability of conflict and the need for a legitimate enforcing and regulatory agent are beliefs that pervade Hobbes’s Leviathan. The underpinnings of protectorism lie, then, in these assumptions—man must be protected because of his limited knowledge and abilities; man must be protected from his aggressive and avaricious nature. The implications of this policy philosophy are far-reaching. First, the prospects for an open government arc dim. Both Plato and Hobbes viewed governing as a matter to be entrusted to the few. Plato divides society into three classes—the guardians, a largely hereditary 61 PHILOSOPHIES, MANAGEMENT, AND THE PUBLIC INTEREST Box 3.1: Philosophical Roots of Protectorism Such transgressions as the Watergate cover-up, the CIA excesses, and other instances of the “politics of lying” might be viewed as embodying the values of egoism—mindless self-aggrandizement at any price. But a more charitable interpretation Is that many such instances of government deceit are misguided attempts at espousing protectorism. Consider Plato’s commentary on the politics of lying: If anyone, then, is to practise deception, either on the country’s enemies or on its citizens, it must be the Rulers of the commonwealth, acting for its benefit; no one else may meddle with this privilege. For a private person to mislead such Rulers we shall declare to be a worse offence than for a seaman to misinform his captain about the state of the ship. ... But for the quintessential protectorist we must turn to Thomas Hobbes: The obligation of subjects to the sovereign is understood to last as long, and no longer, than the power lasts by which he is able to protect them. For the right men have by nature to protect themselves when none else can protect them, can by no covenant be relinquished. The end of obedience is protection, wheresoever a man sees it either in his own or in another’s sword, nature applies his obedience to it, and his endeavor to maintain it. . . . Source: The Republic of Plato, trans. F. M. Cornford (Oxford university Press, 1945). Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (1651). ruling class of philosophic rulers; the auxiliaries, a class of military men and civil servants; and the class of producers and artisans which composes nearly the entire population. The closed society of Hobbes is a result of the need to unify power to the greatest degree possible in a single sovereign. A more important implication of protectorism is in connection with the activities of government. If the chief purpose of governing is protection, the activities of government are regulatory and enforcing. Conferral of collective benefits, redistribution of society’s resources, and representation are government activities foreign to protectorism. A modern curator of protectorism is Edward Banfield, and his The Unheavenly City embodies several of its values. In assessing the social programs of the 1960s, Banfield observes: Faith in the perfectibility of man and confidence that good intentions together with strenuous exertions will hasten his program onward and upward lead to bold programs that promise to do what no one knows how to do and what perhaps cannot be done...1 In outlining his own twelve-point programs for amelioration of urban problems, Banfield relies heavily on regulation and enforcement and largely ignores structural solutions. Intensified law enforcement, abridgement of offenders’ freedom, and promotion of individual rather than social responsibility for misdeeds are all important elements of the Banfleld proposals. The policy philosophy of protectorism appears to exert some influence in the policy making and activities of a great many bureaucratic agencies, and in some it is the dominant theme. Agencies that are chiefly involved in regulatory or enforcing activities are most likely to be operating with a protectorist conception of the public interest. Examples of agencies that are predominantly protectorist include the Federal Bureau of Investigation and the Federal Trade Commission, both of which protect people from others, and, in a very different sense, the Social Security Administration, which protects people against their own thriftlessness. Any agency may manifest several policy philosophies, or parts of several policy philosophies in their activities. The Social Security Administration is an example of a mixed type, whereas the Federal Bureau of Investigation is a purer type. It should be expected that most agencies will embody several policy philosophies. One reason for this is that policy philosophies, as conceived here, involve not only the ends of bureaucracy but also the means. Protectorism is chiefly concerned with ends; rationalism, by contrast, is chiefly concerned with means. Rationalism The policy philosophy of rationalism is rooted in a faith in man’s reason and the assumption that problems of governance are amenable to reasonable solution through scientific analysis, logic, and systematic inquiry. The prototypical rationalist administrator is the management scientist. Rationalism as a policy philosophy is reflected in the writings of several classic philosophers. The writings of empiricists such as Berkeley, Hume, and Locke include themes that are related to this policy philosophy, but typically their empiricism—even that of Locke— is less related to governance than to a more general philosophy of Box 3.2: Rationalism and the Value of Human Life In a sense, rationalism is the most optimistic policy philosophy. It says that the world may be complex but by employing reason and developing analytical tools, we can manage complexity. But if rationalism is optimistic in its prospect for the human (and policy) condition, its hard-nosed adherence to objectivity and technique (and its lack of regard for the intangible and subjective) can lead to coldblooded approaches and outcomes. There are few better examples of hard-hearted rationalism than policy analysts’ calculations of the value of the “most qualitative” of values~ human life. As Steven Rhoads notes in a recent article, analysts find themselves groping for figures representing the value of life when considering such matters as government sponsorship of kidney dialysis machines ($30,000 per year to keep one patient alive) and costs of pollution control devices (recently the Council on Wage and Price Stability questioned the costs of coke-fume standards: $4.5 million per worker saved). The most common technique used by policy analysts to evaluate human life is the discounted future earnings (DEE) approach. Rhoads describes it: “The basic DEE approach takes the average age at which death of people killed by a certain type of disease or accident occurs and computes what their expected future income would have been if they had lived a normal term. This future income is discounted since a dollar received today can be invested, and is thus worth more than a dollar received in future years. The ‘present value’ figure that results is taken as the value of life for the average member of the group in question.” This approach, despite an undeniable logic, can lead to bizarre conclusions, such as that males are usually more valuable than females; young, white adults are the most cherished segment of the population; lives are additive. In an example used by Rhoads, Department of Health, Education, and Welfare studies showed that a media campaign encouraging the wearing of motorcycle helmets might save a life for $3,000; a cervix cancer program that was also being contemplated would save a life for about the same cost. But DEE figures showed the programs not to be even close in “return on investment” The benefit ratio for the motorcyclehelmet program was 55.6 because the lives saved would chiefly be those of young adult males, while the benefit ratio for the cancer program was only 8.9 because the lives saved were chiefly those of older females. Source: Steven Rhoads, “How Much Should we Spend to Save a Life?,” Public Interest, 51 (Spring 1978), 74—92. inquiry. There is also a strong element of rationalist policy philosophy in Aristotle’s Politic, but it is a less than perfect example because of his organic conception of the state. As conceived here, rationalism implies an instrumental conception of the state that places value on planning and assumes that effective administration involves design. The pre-twentieth-century philosopher who provides the best illustration of the rationalist approach to public affairs is Bacon. The ideal of the scientist—public official is realized to the fullest in Bacon’s Novum Organum (1620). Bacon’s “House of Solomon” is a decision-making body composed entirely of scientists. In modern political theory the link between science and public decision making is of a more specialized nature; while it is true that some scholars advocate a bureaucracy composed of a greater number of liberally trained scientists,2 the more routine means of bringing the blessings of the scientific approach to the administration of public affairs is by the inclusion of scientific management techniques in the curriculum of would-be public servants. Taylorism was an approach (a partly bogus approach) to bringing science to administration. The writings of Taylor, whether or not scientific, certainly gave impetus to a concern with the possibilities for a science of public administration. Another important contributor to rationalism in public administration was the German sociologist Max Weber. Unlike Taylor and his disciples, Weber never made a strong argument for applying science to public affairs, but his classic typology of bureaucracy provided a framework that enhanced the application of social science methods and techniques to the study of public administration. Of the several contemporary theorists involved in the development of a scientific administration, two of the most prominent are C. W. Churchman and Russell Ackoff.5 These two pioneers of systems analysis and operations research have been especially influential in the development and popularization of quantitative approaches to management and administration. The recent spread of management science in both public agencies and private industry has been remarkable, and the entrance of large numbers of management scientists into the federal bureaucracy has produced a basic change in the approach of several agencies to administration. The agency that has been in the forefront of this movement has been the Office of Management and Budget. The impact of rationalism on bureaucracy has been so extensive as to virtually defy analysis. At the level of the individual greater acceptance of and familiarity with scientific analysis in administration and management has had an impact on the day-to-day operation of bureaucracy. From a broader perspective the policy philosophy of rationalism has been influential in policy making because it inspires confidence. It says that though the world may be complex and its problems of great magnitude, social, economic, and political problems may be understood and perhaps solved. The rationalist brings a Lockean optimism to public affairs. The human condition is not irremediable, policy processes need not inevitably entail conflict and power politics; there is a best way to proceed, and by resorting to reason we may find that best way (or at least a close approximation). Thus, unlike several of the policy philosophies, rationalism encourages government by design— planning, social engineering, and intervention. Brokerism The pluralist conception of government is a strong theme in brokerism. Society is conceived as an amalgam of group interests, and government is a glue that helps hold society together by balancing interests and serving as an integrating force. David Easton views politics as the allocation of values and resources in society by an agent (the government) that is perceived by the affected parties as a legitimate authority. Easton’s is a brokerist view of policy making. 4 Representativeness is a value given high priority in brokerism. If policy is to be employed as a balance wheel, then it is essential that all the most relevant interests be clearly articulated and that some consideration of these interests enter into policy making. Additionally, group politics has increased significance. The government cannot hope to operate as a balance of individual interests given (1) the difficulty of securing information about the preference of individuals, (2) the absence of preference in a great many policy matters, (3) the complexity of calculating some equilibrium of individual interests, and (4) the lack of a standardized and ongoing means for communicating individual interests. The vote is an important indicator of individual preference but is too generalized to be of use in most instances of brokerist policy making. Thus the associational (as opposed to categorical) group becomes a virtually indispensable element of the policy process. Organized groups can routinely make inputs into the policy process and can be expected to do so when an issue is sufficiently pertinent to their interests—providing that they are aware the issue is on some official agenda and that they can make their opinions heard. Thus, another requisite value of brokerism is widespread access to policymaking apparatus. If governing is the balancing of interests and good policy reflects an awareness and accommodation of diverse interests, then every effort must be made to insure that the interests have a forum. A penetrating critique of brokerist policy making is provided by Theodore Lowi in his The End of Liberalism 5 Lowi attacks interestgroup liberalism, a cousin of brokerism, as a mechanism for assuring conservatism in policy making. Giving precedence to the view of established groups insures conservatism because established groups are by nature conservative. Less established groups don’t usually have easy access to policy-making machinery. Lowi’s indictment of interest-group liberalism is somewhat less pertinent for brokerism. Pure brokerism assumes access of all groups, while interest-group liberalism recognizes that groups do not have equal access. A more troubling issue is that interests may not be balanced effectively even if all organized groups are assured access and influence. Some interests are not represented in an organized fashion by any group. Until recently the interests of the poor were not included in the brokerist policy equation because no significant organized group represented them. Likewise, the interests of the consumer have not been articulated by organized groups until recently. The thousands of persons in prisons and mental institutions are represented in second-hand fashion if at all, even though these political “nonpersons” have a great stake in many policy issues. The extreme emphasis placed on interest balancing in the brokerist policy philosophy can lead to logrolling and coalition building with only passing consideration to questions of justice and morality. Lowi speaks of “the decline of meaningful adversary proceedings in favor of administrative, technical, and logrolling considerations questions of equity rather than questions of morality.” 6 The brokerist conception of governing is, according to Lowi, partly responsible for increased political cynicism; citizens are asked to accept policy decisions not because they are good but because they reflect group interest. The origins of brokerism and of the conception of policy making as the balancing of interests are less apparent than are the origins of protectorism. Perhaps this is because, as Lowi asserts, this conception has become a dominant theme only since the second quarter of the twentieth century. Still, some elements of brokerism can be found in the writings of several classic political philosophers. A superficial reading of Bentham might lead one to believe that the utilitarian philosopher was chiefly a brokerist. Bentham is perhaps the single classic philosopher that embodies some of the values of all the policy philosophies outlined here, but interpreting as brokerism his principle . . . of utility—the greatest happiness for the greatest number—shows confusion of ends and means. Brokerism is chiefly a philosophy of means, and while the greatest happiness for the greatest number might be a directive for some brokerists, brokerism does not require such motivation. Nor does Bentham’s approach involve the balancing of expressed group interest. His conception of happiness is not defined in terms of narrow sell-interest. In his Deontology Bentham declared that the “first law of nature is to wish our own happiness; and the united voices of prudence and efficient benevolence add—seek the happiness of others, seek your own happiness in the happiness of others.” No classical political philosopher seems primarily brokerist, perhaps because the rise of associational interest groups as major forces in policy making did not occur until the late nineteenth century. Several contemporary political scientists include brokerist themes in their writings; one of the most prominent is Robert Dahl. A concise brokerist statement provides the theme of Dahl’s textbook, Pluralist Democracy in the United States.7 Dahl’s “fundamental axiom in the theory and practice of American pluralism” is multiple power centers sharing power, with none in a position to dictate policy. He contends that the existence of several loci of power will help (may indeed be necessary) to tame power, to secure the consent of all, and to settle conflicts peacefully because: [if] one center of power is set against another, power itself will be tamed while coercion will be reduced to a minimum. [when] even minorities are provided with opportunities to veto solutions they strongly object to, the consent of all will be won in the long run. constant negotiations among different centers of power are necessary in order to make decisions, [and in this way] citizens and leaders will perfect the precarious art of dealing peacefully with their conflicts not merely to the benefit of one position but to the mutual benefits of all the parties to a conflict.8 ... ... ... . This quotation sheds light on the seeming “valuelessness” of brokerism. The reduction of conflict is often a core value in brokerist approaches to policy making. The brokerist approach is so commonplace in modern bureaucracy that almost every agency operates in that style to some degree and with respect to some types of issues. An agency in which brokerism is fundamental and routine is the National Labor Relations Board. Here negotiation is almost a substantive concern. Many of the agencies that are protectorist are also likely to be brokerist since brokerism is often an approach to regulatory politics. Thus those agencies that are chiefly regulatory in function typically operate in a brokerist style. Almost as commonly, however, agencies whose objectives are the conferral of benefits operate in a brokerist style. Even such an agency as the late Office of Economic Opportunity—an agency with an explicit substantive mission, the reduction of poverty—had, according to some observers, adopted an operating style that was largely brokerist. Students of the War on Poverty such as Moynihan,9 Levitan,’0 and Donovan ii have argued that the balancing of group interests often took precedence over rational approaches to the amelioration of poverty. Analyses of agencies in several substantive policy domains including science, 12 welfare,13 housing,14 environment,15 and health’6 provide evidence of the pervasiveness of brokerism in policy’ making. In sum, at the higher levels of policy making, brokerism is the dominant policy philosophy in all but a few agencies. Pragmatism It has been said with some justification that pragmatism is America’s only major contribution to philosophy. The writings of James and Dewey gave substance to the direction “If it works—do it.” But pragmatism as a policy philosophy (as opposed to a codified general philosophy) has been with us since long before the advent of modern bureaucracy. In fact, the rise of modern bureaucracy can to some extent be interpreted as a repudiation of ad hoc governing and pragmatism. Bureaucracy is a means of standardizing government, policy, and decision making. The standard operating procedure, record keeping, impersonalism, and formal chain of command in bureaucracy is built on a structure of formality that impedes pragmatism. Despite the constraints that orderliness, routine, and formality impose on pragmatism, bureaucracy (or bureaucrats) can still promote pragmatism in public policy. While the formal structures of bureaucracy almost invariably obstruct pragmatism, the bureaucrat does not always heed formal structures. Sometimes constraining structures (rules, jurisdictions, formal lines of authority) either do not exist, are not clear, or can be ignored without fear of reprisal. The range of discretion for bureaucrats may be enormous, and in such cases pragmatism is likely to be the guiding principle in administering and policy making. One of the best explanations of pragmatism as a policy philosophy is found in the works of Charles Lindblom.” According to Lindblom, policy making and administration are necessarily incremental and suboptimal because decisions must be made quickly, searches for information are costly, and consequences cannot always be anticipated. Policy-makers are often “firemen” responding to the most pressing demand of the moment rather than philosophers pondering all available alternatives or scientists applying a “one best way.” Policy-makers should not, then, be expected to arrive at optimal policy, but are commonly given to pragmatism and the art of the possible. The best feasible solutions often are consistent neither with standard operating procedures nor with legislative intent. Transferalism Transferalism is the policy philosophy of the welfare state—take from the haves and give to the have-nots. While several classic political philosophers contributed to the intellectual lineage of transferalism —Marx, Rousseau, Ricardo—the actual use of policy as a vehicle for reducing economic inequalities was uncommon until after the first quarter of the twentieth century. An insightful commentator on transferalism has been A. C. Pigou. In his The Economics of the Welfare State’8 he discusses the premises of transferalism, along with the economic and philosophical problems of various income transfers in society. A fundamental axiom of transferalism is the importance of relativity in income. As Pigou explains: For a single person or family to be forced to accept a lower living standard while their friends—and their enemies—are left as before may be very distressing; but, if the whole of their class or group suffer alike, they will scarcely suffer at all. In short, a large part of the economic satisfaction which people derive from substantial incomes depends, not on their income being large absolutely, but upon its being larger, or at least not smaller, than those common in their social entourage. This consideration greatly strengthens the commonsense view that transfers away from better-to-do persons do not hurt the victims much, while the beneficiaries, whose needs are more elementary and less complex, gain from them a great deal.19 ... Today the term relative deprivation is increasing in usage and indicates that the conception of need as comparative has gained widespread acceptance. Another assumption of transferalism is that benefits from income transfer accrue to society at large as well as to the individuals receiving the supplement. Increased incomes allow poorer people to pursue ‘71 educational and employment opportunities; thus production is enhanced and society benefits. Yet, as Pigou recognized, there is some point of diminishing return (in economic terms) in the transfer of economic wealth. While giving us insight into the underpinnings of the policy philosophy of transferalism, the economics of income transfer provides only a partial explanation. There is also a moral strand in transferalism, the idea that the poor should be provided for regardless of the economic utility of doing so. Governments sometimes extend the benefits of the poor even during times of inflation, thus contributing to the inflationary spiral. Such a policy is not “rational” and cannot be accounted for in terms of welfare economics; its origins are moral or political. Transferalism is largely a twentieth-century policy philosophy. In past times the poor have been objects of contempt. It was assumed that providing the poor with public assistance would lead to idleness. Further, the explanation for poverty was evolution. Indeed, Herbert Spencer and other Social Darwinists argued that caring for the poor should be discouraged because intervention would interfere with a natural order, the survival of the fittest. Today the common view is that poverty is less a product of an individual’s indolence or the natural order than it is of the structure of society. This assumption is, however, somewhat less common in the United States than in other Western nations. Many Americans tend to divide the poor into two classes—the “deserving poor” and all others. As Gilbert Steiner has pointed out, widows, orphans, and the disabled are generally viewed as deserving.20 The attitudes toward welfare recipients who are young, fit, and black are quite unfavorable. Persons who face economic hardship because they are unskilled, not socialized to employment norms, victims of racial discrimination, or unwed or deserted mothers caring for children are often objects of scorn in the United States, and much of the welfare and poverty legislation has reflected the concept of the deserving poor. Economists who argued that cash payments or income subsidies would be more helpful in the War on Poverty than service-training programs were overruled by President Johnson, who wanted to guard against an image of his programs as the “Johnson dole.” The large role that transferalism has played in recent policy seems a bit puzzling given the “pull-yourself-up-by-the-bootstraps” tradition of the United States. In a land where individualism, the work ethic, and Calvinism are so much a part of the culture, the existence of a multibillion-dollar welfare budget seems incongruous. There are several explanations for this apparent contradiction. First, the Great Depression made poverty “respectable.” When hard-working middle-class PHILOSOPHIES, MANAGEMENT, AND THE PUBLIC INTEREST PHILOSOPHIES, MANAGEMENT, AND THE PUBLIC INTEREST ‘71 people were reduced to poverty, the Spencerian interpretation of poverty seemed less appealing. Moreover, the impetus for the welfare state during the depression came not so much from charity as from the survival of a nation. Also, today’s public leaders are somewhat more likely to view poverty as caused by social ills. Finally, the same nation that pays homage to individual initiative also subscribes to the notion of equal opportunity for all, and both public myths are powerful. Egoism The policy philosophy of egoism entails the assumption that the bureaucracy or the agency exists as an end in itself beyond any social mission and that public careers are a means of advancing oneself, even to the possible detriment of agency goals. This philosophy need not take so crude a form as simple graft or corruption. Extreme careerism may be a manifestation of the policy philosophy of egoism, as may be an obsessive desire to expand one’s agency or organizational unit. Egoism is not only reflected in the aggressive careerist or bureaucratic empire-builder. The “conserver” pattern of behavior—the bureaucrat who avoids controversy and hopes to be so inconspicuous as to blend in with the woodwork—may be based on an egoism policy philosophy. If all one’s actions are framed in terms of survival value (rather than agency objectives), then a policy philosophy of egoism is dominant. Moreover, in regard to the individual’s philosophy of egoism, we may make the distinction between the self-promoter egoist and the detached egoist. One of the earliest works in political philosophy that might be considered a treatise on egoism is Machiavelli’s The Prince. Machiavelli, like the modern egoist, was little concerned with the substance of policy or decision except as it impinged on the personal career of the individual. Strategies are devised to maximize one’s position of power and to promote one’s self-interest. One scholar who has brought great insight into the nature and operation of egoism is Anthony Downs.2’ Downs argues that the motives of bureaucrats are complex but that the desire to maximize one’s selfinterest is consistently significant. The fundamental premise of the theory is that bureaucratic officials, like all other agents in society, are significantly—though not solely —motivated by their own self-interests. Bureaucratic officials in general have a complex set of goals but regardless of the ... ... l~ PUBLIC ADMINISTRATION IN Fkibk’15(JIIV15 particular goals involved, every official is significantly motivated by his own self-interest even when acting in a purely official capacity.22 No great amount of reflection is required to understand that the behavior of public officials will, in most cases, be influenced by their estimation of the consequences of any decisional alternative for their personal needs and interests. While it is true that public officials are sometimes judged by more stringent criteria than private administrators and are expected to act in the public interest, it would be unrealistic to expect them to be more than human. Yet despite the obvious influence of egoism,. some prominent theories of policy making largely ignore the role of self-interest. The common failure to come to grips with this element of decision making is vexing but understandable. Gathering empirical data concerning the motives of policy-makers is a task that is not only delicate but fraught with methodological problems. Even if we could find public officials who would agree to submit a “motive inventory” of some sort, the data would be of questionable validity. Motives may, of course, be inferred from actions, but such inferences can be made only tentatively. Moving from an individual level to an agency level, egoism is reflected in extreme efforts toward agency expansion, agency budget growth, “territoriality,” and bureaucratic imperialism (when these efforts are not designed to promote some social mission). Again, the role of egoism is hard to measure because even the most obvious power grabs are often cloaked in the best of intentions. POLICY PHILOSOPHIES AND THE PUBLIC INTEREST The term public interest has been used in a variety of contexts and to express diverse, sometimes conflicting meanings. Walter Lippman defined the public interest as “what men would choose if they saw clearly, thought rationally, and acted disinterestedly and benevolently.” 23 By contrast, J, W. R. Cox contends that the public interest, once the irrelevancies are stripped away, is the equivalent of the majority interest.24 Gunn holds that the public interest is little different from Bentham’s utilitarianism.25 Still others, such as Sorauf26 and Schubert,27 contend that the concept is too vague, too value-laden, too utopian, and too inconsistent with the policies of group accommodation to be of much value, Given the multiple usages of the term, its vagueness and value content, why should we be concerned with such a fuzzy concept? First, being value-laden does not, as Diggs has pointed out,28 disqualify the public interest as a communicative term. Nor does its use in different contexts—philosophy, political debate, statute, judicial interpretation— mean that it is too broad to serve a purpose. Indeed, Colm contends that the term is generally employed in such a fashion that the meaning can be inferred from the usage.29 The most important reason to consider the public interest has little to do with semantics or connotations. Whether or not the term has multiple or vague meanings, it is nevertheless used in the law, judicial proceedings, definitions of agency activities, and the policy statements of both elected and appointed public officials. That the term is used in different ways to justify different, sometimes conflicting, actions simply points to the need for further study. A helpful analysis of the meanings of the public interest has been provided by Leys and Perry.30 They divide the usages of the term’ into “formal meanings” and “substantive meanings.” Formal meanings are easily identified; the formal meaning is the express objective of “duly authorized governmental action.” The substantive meaning of the public interest, according to Leys and Perry, is “the object that should be sought in governmental action” and is subdivided into several categories of usage. One is the “aggregationalist conception,” which conceives the public interest as “the maximization of particular interests.” Another category is the “procedural conception,” which holds that the public interest has been served when the proper procedures have been employed to arrive at public decisions. Leys and Perry also subdivide the procedural conception of the public interest according to the type of procedure that is taken as “proper.” The “single conception” involves absolutist and inflexible rules such as majority rule and due process. The “pluralist conception” is not absolutist; it involves the “observance of the procedural rules of whatever legal or political power that happens to become the decision-makers for a given issue.” A third type of substantive meaning of the public interest is the “normative conception,” in which some substantive value, such as social equality or economic opportunity, must be maximized for the public interest to be served. The categories and subcategories of Leys and Perry can be confusing: Table 3—1 is adapted from their work and summarizes their framework of meanings of the public interest. It is important to understand the Leys and Perry framework because it is employed below to help us understand the relationship of the policy philosophies to various conceptions of the public interest. 74 PUBLIC ADMINISTRATION IN PERSPECTIVE TABLE 3.1 The Leys and Perry Framework of Meanings of the Public Interest I. FORMAL MEANING: the objective of government action II. SUBSTANTIVE MEANING: the objective that should be sought A. AGCREGATIONALIST CONCEPTION: the maximization of particular interests B. PROCEDURAL CONCEPTION: the proper decision procedures are employed 1. SINGLE CONCEPTION: absolutist rules and procedures 2. PLURALIST CONCEPTION: changeable and flexible rules and procedures C. NORMATIVE CONCEPTION: some substantive value is to be maximized Source: Adapted from W. A. 11. Leys and C. M. Perry, Philosophy and the Public Interest (Chicago: Committee to Advance Original Work in Philosophy, 1959). Rationalism: A Formalist Conception of the Public Interest Rationalism is the policy philosophy that is closest to the formalist conception of the public interest. Glendon Schubert characterizes contemporary theorists of the public interest as realists, idealists, and rationalists. The rationalist’s view, described below by Schubert, is compatible with the premises of the policy philosophy of rationalism: Government decision-making processes become value-neutral technical processes, with the authority of expertise. Their job is to translate into specific rules of action the public policy goals already determined by the decisions of the people. Human discretion is minimized or eliminated by defining it out of the decision... making situation According to the rationalist view of the public interest, public administrators respond to the directives of elected officials who have translated the public will into law. A common criticism of the rationalist view, as Schubert points out, is that sometimes there is no clear public will. Brokerism: An Aggregationalist Conception of the Public Interest The realist theory of the public interest advanced by Schubert draws from the values of the policy philosophy of brokerism: PHILOSOPHIES, MANAGEMENT, AND THE PUBLIC INTEREST 75 The Realists are skeptics and sophisticates who have put behind them myths which postulate any independent, substantive concern for such notions as “the public will” and “the public interest.” For them the supreme virtue of a democratic system of government is the multiplicity of points of access that it affords for the manifold conflicting interests which necessarily arise in a pluralistic society. The function of government officials is to facilitate the continuous readjustment of conflicting interest ... The difficulty with the realist view of the public interest, according to Schubert, is a failure to judge one set of interests as better than another. An interest is an interest and must, by this rather mechanistic conception, be represented if equilibrium is to be achieved. Transferalism: An Element in the Normative Conception of the Public Interest All policy philosophies and all conceptions of the public interest have a normative component; even in rationalism, an “objective” philosophy, the values of expertise and minimal discretion introduce an element of normativeness. Transferalism is a policy philosophy with an explicit and operational goal and (unlike rationalism) is less concerned with means than with ends. By most criteria it is distinctly normative. As a policy philosophy with an estimable but limited goal—economic equality in society—transferalism doesn’t give rise to a general conception of the public interest. Even the most ardent transferalist would not be likely to contend that the meaning of the public interest is the redistribution of wealth. There are simply too many significant public issues in which economic equality is not a central consideration. While questions of economic equality might impinge on a wide array of public issues, transferalism is more a value to be taken into account in particular questions concerning the public interest. Protectorism: A Procedural Conception of the Public Interest Just as the protectorist approach to governing is protection via constraint, protectorism implies an approach to the public interest based on constraint. In this case the constraining factor, as is generally the case in protectorist policy making, lies in setting and following procedure. After reviewing several usages of the term public interest, Frank 76 PUBLIC ADMINISTRATION IN PERSPECTIVE Sorauf38 comes to the same conclusion as Schubert—that the term is generally so muddled as to be virtually useless. Sorauf goes on, however, to propose a conception of the public interest that is basically procedural. Americans have agreed on “a governmental process that reconciles divergent interests according to established rules and processes. We are bound together, therefore, in accepting the process of democracy as a method of compromise, regardless of the policies it may produce. To this extent we may claim a ‘public interest’—our interest in the democratic method.” “ Thus, according to Sorauf, a procedural conception of the public interest is much more realistic than other views. . . . Pragmatism: A Pluralist Conception of the Public Interest Pragmatism implies a pluralist conception of the public interest in the meaning of pluralism employed by Leys and Perry—observance of rules that “happen to become the decision-maker for a given issue. Griffith ~ has described a conception of the public interest that would fit into the pluralist category of Leys and Perry. According to Griffith’s conception, the public interest is that which conforms to the norms of a given society at a given time. The approach to the public interest implied by pragmatism involves following rather than leading the prevailing social norm and, extending the Griffith model, following the narrow organizational and institutional norms in defining the public interest for a given case. By this conception the public interest is fluid. Egoism: A Disregard for the Public Interest By definition the policy philosophy of egoism precludes consideration of the public interest. Since the predominant factor in policy making is the interest of the organization or the individual bureaucrat, it makes little sense to speak of the public interest implications of egoism. Two works by Anthony Downs argue the importance of the selfinterest view.36 According to Downs, bureaucrats are motivated primarily by personal needs; hence philosophical arguments about the public interest are largely futile. In another work Downs responds to the criticism that his analysis of bureaucratic behavior is amoral. 37 While arguing that his conception of how bureaucrats do behave is accurate, he goes on to formulate a conception of the public interest PHILOSOPHIES, MANAGEMENT, AND THE PUBLIC INTEREST 77 Box 3.3: Ethical Dilemmas Robert K., a government accountant in the auditing department of a large city, discovered that funds that were supposed to be in the maintenance and supply account of the office of the city clerk were missing. The missing funds amounted to about $20,000. He approached his good personal friend the city clerk and asked, off the record, about the missing funds. The clerk replied, “I’m embarrassed to admit this, but I really don’t know what happened to those funds. They’ve been on the books now for about three years without a dime in the account. I was afraid to report that the money was missing because I knew no one would believe it was just lost; they would think I took it. I hope you won’t have to say anything about this because it could get me into an awful mess.” Knowing the city clerk to be a man of high moral character and knowing that disclosure of the finding would have a disastrous effect on the clerk’s reelection bid (the election was only a week away), Robert K. decided not to mention the missing funds in his report. Having just begun his job as state highway inspector, Morris J. asked his supervisor about the department’s policy in regard to travel reimbursement. Morris’s job would require a great deal of traveling, and he was anxious that he not lose money traveling for the state. “Listen, Morris,” his boss began, “we’re the most underpaid office in this underpaid department, right? Where can you get qualified engineers to work for what we do? The state is very loose about its travel policies, so given our underpayment it’s been our policy to claim our real expenses plus 50 percent. Anyway, a lot of the things that we spend outof-pocket money on while we’re on the road don’t really fit the state’s expense account categories. And don’t worry about doing it this way; everyone knows about it, even the state legislature. It’s a good way for them to look good to the voters by holding down our salaries, but the fudge factor gives us a decent living.” Morris had to agree that he was underpaid, and this seemed to be a pretty good way to compensate. In her capacity as planner and evaluator in the state department of social services, Jean T. was responsible for gathering and analyzing data related to proposed programs. The most recent program was the innovative deinstitutionalizatlon program that had been formulated by the head of the department. Her analysis revealed that the program, which would take mental patients out of state and private institutions and release them on their own recognizance to find jobs and residences within nearby communities, was seriously flawed. While the program would help solve a major PHILOSOPHIES, MANAGEMENT, AND THE PUBLIC INTEREST problem—the tremendous overcrowding of the state’s mental institutions—it would create others. The basic problems were: (1) inadequate care had been taken in locating acceptable residences prior to release; (2) patients received no more assistance in finding a job than anyone else would who had recently visited the state bureau of unemployment; (3) too little care had been taken in screening the patients to be released, some of whom had not received a serious examination in several years; (4) the best available data indicated that similarly designed programs had not worked well in other states. Jean reported these problems, giving supporting data, in her formal evaluation and sent it to her supervisor, who sent it along to the head of the department of social services. In a few days a terse message came back from the head of social services: “Change the numbers. I know you can do anything you want to with statistics, so why shoot down a program that will free people, relieve overcrowding, and save the taxpayer money? Besides, you said yourself that some of these people hadn’t been examined in several years; this should be evidence that we need to reduce the load, not build it up.” Jean T., fearing for her job, changed the numbers and wrote a report that presented the deinstitutionalization program in a favorable light. 1. Which, if any, of the behaviors in these cases do you find objectionable? Which is most objectionable? Least? Why? Can you formulate any general ethical rule that would cover these situations? 2. Do you empathize with any of these people? Could you see yourself behaving similarly if you were in their place? How might you behave differently? 3. Which of the behaviors in these cases is most seriously counter to the public interest? Why? that prescribes how bureaucrats should behave. His conception is one of majority benefit and is basically aggregationalist: Anything that is in the long run detrimental to the majority of citizens cannot be in the public interest, unless it is essential to the protection of those individual rights included in the minimal consensus (about the basic rules of conduct and decision making that should be followed and about the general principles and fundamental social policies that the government should carry out). 3 8 77 CONCLUSION Conceptions of policy philosophies and the public interest are unlikely to contribute materially to behavioral analysis of bureaucracy and administration. But such broad philosophical interpretation can be useful in understanding assumptions about how government should operate and what is worth achieving. Behavioral approaches contribute to our understanding of “how things work” but provide only a few clues to “how things should work.” Abstract categories of policy philosophy and the public interest are an inadequate guide to the inner workings of bureaucratic machinery but may help us determine the type of policy product that the “machine” can be expected to produce. NOTES 1. Edward Banfield, The Unheavenly City (Boston: Little, Brown, 1968), p. 257. 2. See, for example, Alvin Weinberg, “Criteria for Scientific Choice,” Minerva, 1 (Winter 1963), 159—171. 3. See, for example, Russell Ackoff, Scientific Method, Optimizing Applied Research Decisions (New York: John Wiley, 1962). Russell Ackoff and Fred Emery, On Purposeful Systems (Chicago: Aldine-Atherton, 1972); C. W. Churchman, Prediction and Optimal Decision: Philosophical Issues of a Science of Values (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1961). 4. Easton’s theory of politics is detailed in his A Systems Analysis of Political Life (New York: John Wiley, 1965). 5. Theodore Lowi, The End of Liberalism (New York: W. W. Norton, 1969). 6. Ibid., p. 57. 7. Robert Dahl, Pluralist Democracy in the United States (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1967). 8. Ibid., p. 124. 9. Daniel P. Moynihan, Maximum Feasible Misunderstanding (New York: The Free Press, 1969). 10. Sar Levitan, The Great Society’s Poor Law (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins Press, 1969). 11. John Donovan, The Politics of Poverty (New York: Pegasus, 1967). 12. Daniel Greenburg, The Politics of Pure Science (New York: New American Library, 1968). 13. Gilbert Steiner, The State of Welfare (Washington, D.C.: The Brookings Institution Press, 1971). 14. Harold Wolman, The Politics of Federal Housing (New York: Dodd, Mead, 1971). 15. J. C. Davies and B. S. Davies, The Politics of Pollution, 2nd ed. (New York: Pegasus, 1975). 16. Theodore Marmor, The Politics of Medicare (Chicago: Aldine, 1973). 17. See especially D. Braybrooke and Charles Lindblom, A Strategy of Decision (New York: The Free Press, 1963); and Charles Lindblom, The Policymaking Process (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1968). 18. A. C. Pigou, The Economics of the Welfare State (New York: Macmillan, 1932). 19. Ibid., p. 235. 20. Steiner, The State of Welfare. 21. Anthony Downs, Inside Bureaucracy (Boston: Little, Brown, 1967). 22. Ibid., p. 2. 23. Walter Lippman, The Public Philosophy (London: Hamish Hamilton, 1955), p. 4. 24. J. W. R. Cox, “The Appeal to the Public Interest,” British Journal of Political Science, 3, 3 (April 1973), 229—241. 25. J. A. W. Gunn, “Jeremy Bentham and the Public Interest,” Canadian Journal of Political Science, 1, 4 (December 1968), 398—413. 26. Frank Sorauf, “The Public Interest Reconsidered,” Journal of Politics, 19, 4 (November 1957), 616—639. 27. Glendon Schubert, “The Theory of ‘The Public Interest’ in Judicial Decisionmaking,” Midwest Journal of Political Science, 2, 1 (February 1958), 1—25; Schubert, The Public Interest (Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1961). 28. B. J. Diggs, “The Common Good as Reason for Political Action,” Ethics, 83, 4 (July 1973), 283—293. 29. C. Colm, “In Defense of the Public Interest,” Social Research, 27, 3 (Autumn 1960), 295—307. 30. W. A. R. Leys and C. M. Perry, Philosophy and the Public Interest (Chicago: Committee to Advance Original Work in Philosophy, 1959). 31. Schubert, The Public Interest, p. 31. 32. Ibid., p. 136. 33. Sorauf, Public Interest Reconsidered. 34. Ibid., p. 633. 35. In C. J. Friedrich, ed., Nomos V: The Public Interest (New York: Atherton Press, 1962). 36. Anthony Downs, An Economic Theory of Democracy (New York: Harper 1957); Inside Bureaucracy. 37. Anthony Downs, “The Public Interest: Its Meaning in Democracy,” Social Research, 29 (Spring 1962). 38. Ibid., p. 9. FURTHER READING Appleby, P. H. Morality and Administration in Democratic Government. Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1952. Domhoff, C. William. Who Really Rules? New Haven and Community Power Reexamined. New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction Books, 1978. Dvorin, Eugene and R. H. Simmons. From Amoral to Humane Bureaucracy. San Francisco: Canfield Press, 1972. Flathman, R. E. Public Interest. New York: John Wiley and Sons, 1966. Grondin, R. E. “Ethical Perspectives on Political Excuses.” Policy and Politics, 5 (June 1977), 71—78. Harmon, M. M. “Social Equity and Organizational Man: Motivation and Organizational Democracy.” Public Administration Review, 34 (January/ February 1974), 11—18. Lowi, T. J. The End of Liberalism. New York: W. W. Norton, 1969. Mitnick, Barry. “A Typology of Conceptions of the Public Interest.” Administration and Society, 8 (May 1976), 5—28. Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971. Wakefield, Susan. “Ethics and the Public Service: A Case for Individual Responsibility.” Public Administration Review, 36 (November/December 1976), 661—666.