Plural Monoculturalism Is multiculturalism good for anyone? It depends what you mean by “multiculturalism” and that in turn will make a very significant difference in what you mean if, like me, your argue that it is not. Sometimes multiculturalism is understood as genetic diversity: a society is multicultural in this sense if it comprises citizens of different races and ethnic backgrounds. There is nothing particularly good about multiculturalism thus understood but there is nothing bad about it either. To reject this multiculturalism, to hold that nations should to restrict immigration in the interests of maintaining ethnic purity or exclude citizens from full participation because of ancestry is to embrace racism. More often we think of multiculturalism as a state of affairs where the customs, cuisines and artifacts of diverse cultures are available. This is a good thing to the extent that it provides more variety and so more options for everyone. When it comes to the harmless, superficial features of culture—food, costume, music and dance, language, entertainment and crafts—the more the better: there is no reason to believe that the superficial aspects of Anglo culture are inherently superior and, indeed, compelling reason to believe that some features of the culture, e.g. cuisine, are inherently inferior. As Susan Okin famously argued however, it is quite another matter when it comes to some of the deep features of culture, including the role of women and practices that enforce that role, some cultures are seriously defective. Curries and salsa dancing enrich culture; female genital mutilation, forced marriages and wife-beating do not. Nevertheless so long as we restrict ourselves to what Stanley Fish has called “boutique multiculturalism” we can 1 probably agree that absorbing features of diverse cultures is a good thing. Much of the time however when Americans think of multiculturalism they have in mind what Sen has tagged, “plural monoculturalism,” the doctrine that individuals ought to remain faithful to their ancestral cultures and that a good society ought to be a “salad bowl,” where diverse groups maintain their separate identities and interact peacefully without coalescing. On this account the development and persistence of ethnic communities should be encouraged and individuals, in the interests of “authenticity,” should maintain, reestablish, or invent, connections to their ancestral cultures, however remote. This is the doctrine that I shall refer to when I talk about “multiculturalism” without qualification. I argue that plural monoculturalism is bad for almost everyone because it restricts choice and so undermines desire satisfaction. It benefits members of the “helping professions” and “community leaders” who obtain funding and achieve professional recognition by promoting multicultural projects but sets back the interests of most members of ethnic minorities, particularly visible minorities, insofar as it locks them into “identities” that are ascribed, immutable, salient and scripted. As a preference utilitarian, I assume that welfare is to be identified with the satisfaction of individual’s rationally considered and informed desires. The more options we have, the more likely we are to achieve desire satisfaction and so the better off we are. Moreover, most people prefer having a wide range of options as a good in and of itself: even if, given our actual desires, the narrow range of options we have does not thwart us, ceteris paribus, most of us would still prefer to have the widest possible range of options. We value positive freedom as such. 1 Fish, S. (1997) “Boutique Multiculturalism, or, Why Liberals are Incapable of Thinking About Hate Speech.” Critical Inquiry 23:2 Multiculturalism restricts the range of options available to members of ethnic minorities and so undermines their wellbeing. Consequently, I suggest, we should reject the salad bowl in favor of the melting pot. Before continuing with the argument it is worth noting what this thesis does not entail. First, it does not entail imposing tighter restrictions on immigration. Advocates of such policies underestimate the ability and even more importantly the desire of immigrants to assimilate. So, for example, Samuel P. Huntington,worries that Hispanics by and large are less willing and able to assimilate to the dominant Anglo culture than earlier waves of immigrants. Arguably he does not take seriously the fact that they are currently doubly disadvantaged in being a visible minority and in being the latest immigrants. I suggest that he is, as a matter of empirical fact, wrong: my empirical conjecture is that more generous immigration policies would in fact facilitate assimilation. Secondly, I do not dogmatically assume that most immigrants and other members of ethnic minorities want to assimilate: I argue that they do. What is striking in the literature and rhetoric of plural monoculturalism is the extent to which writers assume, without producing data or argumentation, that minorities like their ancestral cultures and want to preserve them, that they want to maintain distinctive communities, and that they only conform, grudgingly to mainstream culture in order to obtain extrinsic social and economic benefits. I shall suggest that this is a consequence of false empirical assumptions and, more interestingly, conceptual confusions about the notion of preference. Finally, I note that promoting assimilation as a goal does not mean adopting “color-blind” policies that deny the brute fact of pervasive, ongoing discrimination. In the aftermath of the recent riots in French immigrant suburbs we saw the shortcomings of this policy. While committed to assimilation as a goal, the French government refused to recognize the fact of discrimination and dogmatically assumed that official colorblind policies would make French citizens colorblind. Au contraire. Most of us recognize that only draconian, ongoing state intervention involving strictly enforced affirmative action regulations, will go any way toward ameliorating gross, ongoing discrimination against women and members of visible minorities. Formal equality under the law is virtually worthless because the practices that lock women and minorities out of the mainstream are informal. Critics of liberal feminism sometimes imagine that adopting assimilation as a goal entails committing to gender-blindness and color-blindness as means. That is false: it is an empirical question whether such policies facilitate assimilation—and empirical evidence suggests otherwise. Because of ongoing discrimination, immigrants and other minorities find it difficult, costly and or impossible to assimilate and the ideology of plural monoculturalism further reinforces their exclusion by promoting the doctrine that they do not want to assimilate or, in any case, should not want to. Multiculturalism imposes “thick” identities on members of minority groups that exclude them from the mainstream, restrict their options and therefore undermines their wellbeing. What is white privilege? At this point critics will ask: “what is so great about the mainstream?” The answer, I suggest, is simply that it is the mainstream: the majority culture is the culture that imposes the “thinnest” identity on its members. To be a member of the majority culture is to be generic and that is a consummation devoutly to be wished. There are a variety of benefits that attach to being white but the chief privilege of whiteness is negative: whiteness is, as it were, transparent—to be white, in the US, is to lack a “thick” racial identity. In this respect white privilege is like male privilege: of all the innumerable benefits procured to men in virtue of being male, the most important perhaps is that of being socially generic. In most social contexts we do not expect men to exhibit a characteristically masculine point of view or explain their behavior by reference to gender. We rarely talk about “male faculty,” “male politicians” or even “male writers” but we still talk about female faculty, female politicians and female writers. We only characterize individuals’ occupations or preoccupations as “male” where the activities in question are strongly identified as female: there are male nurses and male feminists. This is symptomatic of the fact that being female is a “thicker” identity than being male: it is more salient and more tightly scripted. Minority racial and ethnic identities are like this too: we talk about “black faculty,” “Hispanic politicians” and even occasionally “Jewish writers” though the last category seems to be defined more by authors’ literary preoccupations rather than their ancestry alone. In any case, I suggest, being stuck with a “thick” identity is a bad thing. The operative word here is “stuck.” The circumstances of our lives are both, as Anthony Appiah notes, parameters and limits. Most of us do not want to be naked transcendental unities of apperception: we seek out group loyalties and cling to empirical characteristics that define us. I am proud to be a Johns Hopkins alumna: I kick in $40 to the alumni association every year and go to the annual crab feasts with my husband, also a Hopkins PhD, where we commiserate with other Hopkins alums about how miserable it was. Our oldest son is at Hopkins too and when he gets his degree I will loan him my flashy gold regalia. JHU is our family thing. That is a (mildly) thick identity—but it is an identity that I chose and one whose “thickness” I choose. I decided to go to Hopkins—probably unwisely. In addition, I choose to make it a big deal in my life, that is, to make it thicker than it had to be: I go to the crab feasts, support the lacrosse team and display the logo merchandise on my car, in my office and, occasionally, on my person. Ethnic identity, by contrast, is both ascribed and salient. It is ascribed insofar as it is unchosen and immutable. Under the multicultural regime, you are born Italian or Jewish, Irish, Black or Puerto Rican and cannot get out of it. Moreover if you are a member of a visible minority group in all likelihood you cannot even “pass.” Being black or brown is like being female: you are not only stuck with it—and you are stuck with being identified with it. Ethnic identity is, in addition, socially salient: under the multiculturalist regime ethnic identity is thick, and individuals for the most part cannot determine how thick it will be for them. A property is socially salient within a community to the extent that members of the community take it to predict or explain beliefs, character traits, tastes or other socially significant psychological characteristics. Social salience is a matter of degree: it depends upon how many other characteristics it is thought to predict or explain, how important they are, how many members of the community believe it has this explanatory or predictive power and the degree of conviction with which they hold this belief… The salience of a property does not arise from its visibility or noticability. Freckles are highly visible but wholly non-salient. In many communities, by contrast, some invisible ethnic origins, occupations and avocations are salient: people have notions of what Germans and Italians, lawyers, librarians and academics, stamp-collectors and soccer fans are like. Finally, for some properties, which are salient to a given degree, the absence of these properties, or possession of other properties of the same category may be less salient or non-salient. People have notions about what used car salesmen are like; they don’t generally have preconceived ideas about what veterinarians, geologists or copy-editors are 2 like. Even where our characteristics are chosen and our affiliations are voluntary, and indeed even where they are highly valued, we rarely want them to be socially salient: no one wants to be a “typical lawyer” or a “typical middle class suburbanite,” and no one wants others to make assumptions about his character, tastes, interests, abilities, commitments and beliefs, or to explain his behavior, on the basis of such socially salient characteristics. Where socially salient characteristics are ascribed, immutable and visible, so much the worse: no one, but no one, wants to hear “just like a women” or to deal with remarks about his “natural sense of rhythm.” This is how clichés about the importance of “treating people as individuals” and “not putting them in boxes” cash out: we do not want our personal characteristics, particularly ascribed and immutable characteristics, to be socially salient. We do not want to have to fight our way out of boxes. Almost everyone has known, at some time or other, what it is like to fight their way out of a box. If you are identified with any socially salient group, whether as a member of a racial or ethnic minority, a political liberal amongst conservatives, a woman in most social settings, a Christian in Academia or an atheist anywhere else, if you are old or very young, disabled or just physically unprepossessing, you confront a swarm of tacit assumptions about your intelligence and abilities, your beliefs, moral commitments and interests, your lifestyle and character, that you have to fight your way through in order to be seen for who you. And sometimes no amount of effort will get you through. Multiculturalism, when it is more than a fiction or entertainment, puts people whose racial or ethnic characteristics are socially salient into boxes and imposes on them the burden of fighting their way out to establish their individuality. Multiculturalism thus restricts choice: most people have fairly strong preferences about how they want others to view them. They want to be seen for who they are. The salience of ascribed ethnic identities makes this difficult for members of ethnic minorities. Finally, in addition to being ascribed and salient, ethnic identity is scripted. Multiculturalism not only promulgates doctrines about what members of ethnic minorities are like: it promotes normative claims about what they ought to be like. As Anthony Appiah notes, even where ethnic scripts are self-affirming they impose constraints on individual choice: An African-American after the Black Power movement takes the old script of selfhatred, the script in which he or she is a nigger, and works, in community, to construct a series of positive black life scripts…What demanding respect for people as blacks or as gays requires is that there be some scripts that go with being an African-American or having samesex desires: there will be expectations to be met; demands will be made. It is at this point that someone who takes autonomy seriously will want to ask whether we have not replaced one kind of tyranny with another. If I had to choose between Uncle Tom and Black Power, I would, 3 of course, choose the latter. But I would like not to have to choose. 2 Baber (2001). “Gender Conscious.” Journal of Applied Philosophy 18(1) 3 Appiah, K. A. (1996) “Race, Culture, Identity” in Color Conscious K. Anthony Appiah and Amy Gutman, eds. Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 98-99. Legal scholar Richard Thompson Ford notes that the “difference discourse” of multiculturalism is especially problematic for minorities who are unwilling, or unable, to play their assigned roles: Because difference discourse often establishes lists and canonical accounts of group identity, it tends to favor traditional behavior over behavior that is novel or transgressive within the group…In this respect, rights-to-difference include proscriptions and mandates, not only for those who would assert them and their contemporaries but also for future generations…Every racial group (with the telling exception of whites) has a derogatory term for people who fail to exhibit their assigned racial culture: there are African American ‘Oreos,’ Latino ‘Coconuts,’ Asian-American ‘Bananas’ and Native-American (you guessed it) ‘Apples.’ Decades ago sociologist David Riesman noted the plight of individuals who were 4 “marginally marginal”—middle class blacks who “talked proper,” “mannish” career women and others who were doubly disadvantaged by being saddled with membership in socially salient disadvantaged groups and either unwilling or unable to play the “scripts” associated with group membership. Even in the 1950s when Riesman was writing, before multiculturalism, marginally marginal individuals faced social opprobrium and were regularly trapped in double binds. During that period, women were, in Riesman’s terminology, “marginalized” to the extent that they were de facto excluded from public life and the professions, and locked into suburban domesticity or, if unmarried, into a narrow range of women’s occupations. Marginally marginal females who could not or would not play their prescribed “feminine role” were trashed. As Betty Friedan noted, the behavior and aspirations of such women were construed in the categories of psychological pathology, as maladjustment, neurosis, self-hatred or penis envy. In the wake of Friedan’s expose of the feminine mystique, the second wave of feminism effectively dismantled the pop-psychological theories that defined marginally marginal women as deviants. But, remarkably, these psychological theories were refurbished and recycled by multiculturalists to beat up on marginally marginal Oreos, Coconuts, Bananas and Apples, individuals who were said to be black, brown, yellow or red on the outside but white on the inside and who were therefore held to be held to be self-hating and inauthentic. Like women, damned if they were suitably feminine but doubly damned if they weren’t, minorities under the multicultural regime were caught in double binds because the scripts for members of racial and ethnic minorities quite often rehearsed racist stereotypes and prescribed behavior that was, in the larger social context, unacceptable. Naïve members of racial and ethnic minorities regularly fell into traps by innocently following advice that they were not supposed to take seriously. At “diversity workshops” minorities were encouraged to wear “ethnic” costume and supervisors were urged to be “sensitive” to their non-Western conceptions of time. Black employees who showed up late the next 5 day wearing dashikis were reprimanded and sent home to change. Under the multiculturalist regime, minority ethnic identities are ascribed, immutable, salient and scripted and so impose serious constraints on individual choice. Assuming that welfare is desire satisfaction, all other things being equal the wider the scope of our choices the 4 Ford (2005), pp. 78-79, 87. 5 This actually occurred at my husband’s place of work. better off we are. Since multiculturalism restricts the choices of minorities by ascribing salient identities to them and imposing scripts on them there is prima facie reason to believe that it impedes their desire satisfaction and therefore undermines their wellbeing. Do people want to preserve their ancestral cultures? Nevertheless, ceteris are not always paribus: having the widest possibly range of options may not always be conducive to desire satisfaction. Individuals become confused when they face a range of options that is too extensive for rational choice and in some cases may wish that options were unavailable in order to prevent themselves from being led into temptation. People join the army, enter monasteries and sign themselves into fat farms in the spirit of Ulysses who, as Elster notes, bound himself to the mast in order to satisfy his standing desire not to have his ephemeral, self-destructive desire to jump overboard satisfied. Even if there is prima facie reason to believe that multiculturalism, insofar as it imposes salient, scripted identities on minorities, restricts their options it may be that there are overriding considerations. It may be that most individuals are so enamoured of their ancestral cultures that they willingly trade off options for cultural preservation. The burden of proof is however on the multiculturalist to show that this is the case and there is little reason to believe that it is. Most people do not give a second thought to their cultures: they accept them in the way that we accept our phone numbers, as a fact of life that we can’t change and rarely think about. Many individuals voluntarily live in ethnic enclaves but it seems likely that this does not reflect their ceteris paribus preferences so much as the difficulty and costs of exit. Responding to Will Kymlicka, Janet Halley for example notes, that it is not that easy to get off the reservation: where land is owned by the tribe, it is difficult for individuals, 6 lacking equity in property, to sell out and move out. And it is not so easy, if you are an immigrant, to become fluent in the language of your host country, learn the social ropes or acquire the support network it takes to negotiate the cultural landscape. The multiculturalist can certainly note that some individuals cling to their ancestral cultures and voluntarily remain within ethnic enclaves but it does not follow that these choices represent their rationally considered, informed, ceteris paribus preferences. A rational and informed individual in circumstances may voluntarily adopt a policy intended to achieve a state S but it does not follow that S is the outcome she would most prefer all other things being equal. She may prefer S’ but believe, rightly or wrongly, that, given the circumstances of her life it is out of reach or she may calculate that the risks of trying for S’ are too great to make pursuing it worthwhile even though she might ardently wish that the circumstances of her life, which she is powerless to change, were different. Rational choice is not the same thing as ceteris paribus preference: we choose what is best from amongst our available options which in most cases is not what we would most prefer prescinding from costs and constraints. This is a home truth which, remarkably, many writers overlook—perhaps because, as members of a privileged elite, they do not understand how limited most people’s options are. So consider Martha Nussbaum writing on “adaptive preference” women in Women and Human Development and elsewhere. Telling the stories of impoverished, illiterate Indian women who choose to stay in bad marriages, put up with domestic violence and poor working conditions she suggests that these choices show that their preferences have been “deformed,” lack self-esteem and are in need of consciousness-raising. Nussbaum doesn’t get it. The women whose stories she tells operate in circumstances where they have few options and cannot afford to assume risk. As I have argued 7 elsewhere they are doing the best they can as rational choosers given their circumstances. None of the anecdotal evidence Nussbaum 6 Halley, J. “Culture Constrains” in Susan Okin, ed. Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women? 7 See my “Adaptive Preference” forthcoming in Social Theory and Practice. produces provides any reason to believe that they would make these choices if they had other options—and indeed as Nussbaum notes, when other options are available, e.g. participation in women’s coops and micro-credit schemes they jump at them. Llike Nussbaum, conservative anti-feminist Christina Sommers assumes that women’s choices represent their ceteris paribus preferences but draws the opposite conclusion: if women voluntarily choose to “live traditional lives,” she argues then that is what they prefer and feminists who suggest that this state of affairs should be remedied must assume that they are brainwashed or lacking in self-esteem. Such feminists, she announces, “do not like women.” Sommers doesn’t get it either—or more likely pretends not to get it. The brute fact is that for the majority of women, including the 76% of adult women in the US who do not have college degrees, most desirable jobs are simply out of reach and they are making the best of a raw deal. It is an empirical question whether given a real opportunity to get traditionally male jobs they would choose them over housewifing or the pink-collar positions that 8 most occupy—and there is substantial empirical evidence to suggest that they would. As highly privileged white women who have beaten the system neither Nussbaum nor Sommers seems to understand that when most people make decisions about their lives or careers, they do not contemplate a staggering range of possibilities and agonize about how to choose from the abundance of riches—in the way that many of our privileged student advisees do. Rather they look at an almost negligible range of options and pick the least worst. As members of an affluent elite, privileged to have a fairly wide range of choices neither Nussbaum nor Sommers nor, I suggest, most advocates of plural monoculturalism recognize that most people have very few options, that most of these options are low on their overall preference rankings, and that most of the choices they make do not represent their ceteris paribus preferences. Many immigrants and members of ethnic minorities live in ethnic neighborhoods and enclaves, fraternize primarily with members of their ethnic groups, and maintain some degree of separateness from the larger community. It does not however follow that this state of affairs reflects their ceteris paribus preferences. It is an empirical question whether members of ethnic minorities prefer to maintain their cultural distinctiveness: there is no compelling reason to believe that they do and some empirical evidence to suggest that they do not. One way we to get empirical evidence about what they want is by asking, and the responses from asking suggest that they do not. In the aftermath of the French riots, none of the individuals of Arab decent interviewed in the media expressed an interest in restoring the Caliphate or worried that French assimilationist policies were undermining their traditional culture. They complained that even after 2 or 3 generations they were not regarded as fully French and that they faced serious, ongoing discrimination in all areas of life. This is typical: Some groups do advocate cultural separation for Muslims -but they do not speak for many. Far more common is the attitude of Nour-eddine Skiker, a youth worker near Paris: "I feel completely French. I will do everything for this country, which is mine." Mr Skiker's Moroccan origins mean a lot to him. But, like many youths in the suburbs, he sees no contradiction between being French and having foreign roots. The main problem is that many French people do, says writer Nadir Dendoune. 8 See, e.g. Maureen Honey, The Making of Rosie the Riveter. Honey notes that when traditionally male factory jobs were opened to women during World War II women flocked to these jobs and, cites data from the Women’s Bureau indicating that after the war was over more than 80% said that they would have preferred to keep these jobs if that were possible. Of course, it wasn’t: after the war women were booted out to make room for returning GIs. "How am I supposed to feel French when people always describe me as a Frenchman of Algerian origin? I was born here. I am French. How many generations does it take to stop mentioning my origin?" And crucially, the suburbs are full of people desperate to integrate into the wider society. "I do not know a single youth in my estate who does not want to leave," Mr Dendoune says. Immigrants have been housed in estates around French cities. France's Muslim ghettos, in short, are not hotbeds of separatism. Neither do they represent a clear challenge to secularism -a doctrine all national Muslim groups profess to support. "We have no problem with secularism," says Lhaj Thami Breze, president of the Union of Islamic Organisations of France (UOIF). He argues that by establishing state neutrality in religious matters, the doctrine allows all religions to blossom. Islam has adapted to local laws -from Indonesia to Senegal -and is adapting to France, says Azzedine Gaci, who heads the regional Muslim council in Lyon. This is not just the leaders' view. A 2004 poll suggested that 68% of French Muslims regarded the separation of religion and state as "important", and 93% felt the 9 same about republican values. We can always cite anecdotal evidence selectively to support whatever thesis we choose. However, an extensive survey of the available anecdotal evidence suggests that this account is characteristic rather than anomalous. We cannot dismiss opposition to multiculturalism as a preoccupation of white jingoists on the right: currently people of color who are “public intellectuals” of stature, including Richard Thompson Ford and Anthony Appiah cited above, as well as Ayaan Hirsi Ali, Salmon Rushdie and Amartya Sen have argued against plural monoculturalism for precisely the reasons that I have suggested. And the preponderance of anecdotal evidence suggests that members of ethnic minorities, when they are not bullied, bribed or indoctrinated agree. Moreover, even in the absence of any compelling evidence to suggest that most immigrants and members of minorities have any serious, overriding interest in maintaining cultural distinctiveness, there would be reason to believe that multiculturalism on the salad bowl model is contrary to their interests. Multiculturalism restricts the options of members of ethnic minorities by enhancing the salience of their ethnic identities and imposing ethnic scripts on them. That is something people do not want. The preference utilitarian case against multiculturalism is therefore breathtakingly simple: multiculturalism is bad for most people because most people don’t want it. Comments greatly appreciated! Please send to me at baber@sandiego.edu! 9 “Ghettos shackle French Muslims” in BBC News, Monday, October 31, 2005.