2 Understanding the production of “events” In the previous chapter it was argued that instead of trying to explain “events” in terms of what they represent, the important task should to examine the ways in which they are produced. The aim of this chapter, then, is to explore how it might be possible to think about the “event” in terms of a production, and specifically how this production can be understood in relation to the processes, lines and movements that underlie and condition it. Focusing on these processes, lines and movements means that I will initially move away from a notion of the “event” as an object or a unitary whole and instead try to articulate what happens in the very processes of producing such a notion. One way to articulate these kinds of processes is by returning to Deleuze’s transcendental empiricism and the plane of immanence, which in the previous chapter was referred to as a pure flow of life and experience that underlies notions of subjects and objects, the internal and the external. This plane consists, moreover, of pre-individual and impersonal elements of experience, or what Deleuze also refers to as “singularities”. When developing this notion of experience there is, however, another concept that can be seen as perhaps even more important. This is Deleuze’s own concept of the event. As I will try to show in the first part of this chapter, Deleuze’s concept of the event is radically different from an understanding of the “event” as an object or a whole. For example, the event does not refer to what has happened in a particular moment in time, in relation to a pre-given subject and against an already established background. In contrast to such an understanding of the “event”, Deleuze’s concept of the event can rather be understood as a creative and active movement, which is irreducible to a present moment in time, a pre-existing subject and a given background. As 53 such, it can also be linked to an alternative understanding of time and subjectivity, as well as to various notions of for example sense, thought and experience. Having developed an understanding of Deleuze’s concept of the event in the first part of the chapter, the second part will then look at how this concept can be used as a starting point for understanding the production of “events”. Specifically, this will be done by looking at how the production of “events” can be understood in terms of a relationship between events and the “event”. In brief, according to that relationship, events can be referred to as active and creative movements in relation to which different ideas about the “event” as an abstract object or a whole are produced. When developing this understanding of the production of “events” I will also be referring to two different processes, which Deleuze calls “actualization” and “counter-actualization”. Whereas actualization is a process whereby the event is translated into a “state of affairs” or what is, counter-actualization implies a process of “abstracting” the event from a state of affairs. Hence, whereas actualization can be said to take us away from the event as an active and creative movement towards a state of affairs, counter-actualization goes in the opposite direction and brings the event back to life. As we shall see, this latter process is crucial because it has the potential to disrupt and even dissolve the process of actualization, and thereby also destabilise anything that comes out of it in terms of an actualized state of affairs. In relation to the processes of actualization and counter-actualization I will look at how the “event” can be understood in terms of an outcome of both of these processes. This implies, then, trying to understand the “event” as an outcome of translating the event as an active and creative movement into a state of affairs through the process of actualization. But it also implies understanding how the “event” is constantly disrupted as well as dissolved through the process of counter-actualization. Hence, rather than understanding the “event” as something that is fully determinable or reaches a final point of completion, my aim is to see how it can be understood in 54 terms of an ongoing and continuous process of becoming, whose direction and meaning always remains open to change and transformation. In order to develop this way of thinking about the production of “events” further, the third part of the chapter will explore Deleuze and Guattari’s approach to the role of language in the social field, focusing in particular on how they write about the relationship between form of “content” and form of “expression”. In brief, this relationship will be used in order to think about how the content of the “event” becomes formalized through different forms of expression. And rather than viewing this formalization as a process that leads to a final end or product, I will look at how it can complement an understanding of the “event” as a part of an ongoing and continuous process of becoming, which remains open to change and transformation. 2.1 The singularity of events In The Logic of Sense, Deleuze claims that the event is “always and at the same time something which has just happened and something about to happen; never something happening”. 1 In this part of the chapter I will explore what is meant by this claim. And I will do so by focusing on three different aspects: time and subjectivity, difference and transformation, language and grammar. The reason for choosing these aspects is that all of them in one way or another can be said to enable a reading of the event as a singularity. As such, the event can also be thought of in terms of an active and creative movement, according to which there is an encounter with change, difference and transformation. Crucially, this encounter is always prior to notions of an individualised and personalised form of being, and prior to distinctions between the subject and the object, the internal and the external. This does not mean, however, that the singularity of the event is somehow “superior” to any of those notions. Rather, it means that the event has to be seen as an active and creative movement, which is involved in the 1 Gilles Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, translated by Mark Lester, edited by Constantin V. Boundas, (London: Continuum, 2004), p. 73. 55 ongoing processes of creating different kinds of distinctions. For that reason it also is necessary to take the singularity of events seriously if the aim is to understand how something emerges or is produced in the first place. Time and subjectivity One of the ways in which Deleuze develops his understanding of the event is through a reading of time in Stoic philosophy. In this philosophy, Deleuze explains, there are two main concepts of time: “Chronos” and “Aion”. Briefly, whereas Chronos consists of the present as the constitutive element of time, Aion can be said to escape the present and only let movements of past and future remain. “In accordance with Aion, only the past and future inhere or subsist in time. Instead of a present which absorbs the past and future, a future and past divide the present at every instant and subdivide it ad infinitum into past and future, in both directions at once.” 2 Time, in accordance with Aion, can thus be said to escape the present as a central reference point in time. Instead of the present, it is the past and the future that constitute time. And between past and future there is no present because every instant subdivides the present into past and future. So, rather than the “now” of Chronos there is the “instant” of Aion. When linking Aion to the event, the latter has to be understood in relation to movements of past and future and not to the present. In this way, the event can also be said to take on the form of a “double question”, referring to the questions of “what is going to happen, and what has just happened”.3 There is no underlying purpose of this double question, nor is it raised because it requires a particular answer. Rather, it can be understood as an expression of the “agonizing aspect of the pure event”, highlighting the difficulty of grasping what has just happened but also knowing what is about to happen. This difficulty can thus be explained by the movements of Aion and the lack of a stable and present “now”, as a point from which it is possible to reflect on what has happened in the past and make predictions 2 3 Ibid., p. 188. Ibid., p. 73. 56 about what might happen in the future. Aion, referring to what is always already past and eternally yet to come, destabilises the notion of a pure present and frees the event from a static location in time. Lacking a pure present, Aion can also be said to express an “incorporeal” form of time. This means that time cannot be directly linked to movements and actions of bodies that are already present. Time takes on an “empty form”, which means that it is always “already passed and eternally yet to come”, like a movement that “has freed itself of its present corporeal content and has thereby unwound its own circle, stretching itself out in a straight line”.4 Following this incorporeal time of Aion, there is for example no “being” of the subject that can be located in a present “now”. There is instead only a becoming of the subject. 5 This becoming has neither an identity, nor does it exist in one place or at one time. It is a movement, “by which the line frees itself from the point, and renders points indiscernible”.6 So, rather than the point, or the present, the movement of Aion travels toward a past and a future, it becomes smaller and larger, etc. In his reading of Alice in Wonderland and Through the Looking-Glass Deleuze describes this idea of becoming in the following way: When I say ‘Alice becomes larger,’ I mean that she becomes larger than she was. By the same token, however, she becomes smaller than she is now. Certainly, she is not bigger and smaller at the same time. She is larger now; she was smaller before. But it is at the same moment that one becomes larger than one was and smaller than one becomes. This is the simultaneity of a becoming whose characteristic is to elude the present.7 This notion of becoming thus implies that there is no middle point, or present, in which the subject can be located. The becoming of the subject consists 4 Ibid., p. 189. Ibid., p. 8. 6 Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, translated by Brian Massumi, (London: Continuum, 2004), p. 324. 7 Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, p. 3. 5 57 only of an unlimited movement, in relation to which becoming “produces nothing but itself”. 8 And it is in this sense that becoming also has to be understood as “incorporeal”, it is never present as such and it has no direct connection to an already established body. As an expression of this form of becoming, the event can be seen a force or a movement that constantly escapes the present moment in time as well as the corporeal being of the subject: Becoming unlimited comes to be the ideational and incorporeal event, with all of its characteristic reversals between future and past, active and passive, cause and effect, more and less, too much and not enough, already and not yet. The infinitely divisible event is always both at once. It is eternally that which has just happened and that which is about to happen, but never that which is happening.9 The event can thus be linked to an incorporeal and impersonal becoming, which is disembodied and always eludes the present. As such, the event also has to be freed from a point of view, according to which it is possible to reflect on the meaning of what has happened from a position that is external to the processes of becoming. The event, in this sense, is essentially nothing but a movement of becoming, which constantly goes in different directions and therefore cannot be reduced to a state of affairs or what is. Difference and transformation According to Deleuze, it is important to understand the event as something that is constitutive and active rather than representational and reactive. In this way, the event is not an “object” or a “thing”, which can be represented from an external point of view, but rather a force or a movement that creates. This movement can for example be linked to “thought” or “sense” as an event. Beginning with the latter, the notion of sense as an event is important in Deleuze’s philosophy precisely because it can be seen as an expression of the 8 9 Deleuze and Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, p. 262 Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, p. 10. 58 productive and creative element of the event. As an event, sense cannot for example be explained by the objects of perception. That kind of explanation would merely result in a statement that tries to determine the qualities of an object by locating it in an external realm. So, for example, instead of stating that “the tree is green”, the sense event belongs to the verbs: “to green” and “to tree”. 10 And the reason for this, as Claire Colebrook correctly points out is that “we see not just what actually is, but also the seen as it might be remembered, imagined, recalled, repeated, hallucinated”.11 There is in this way a multiplicity of movements involved in the event of sense, movements that do not necessarily point in the same direction or add up to a whole. As such, sense can also be understood as “an incorporeal, complex, and irreducible entity”, or a singularity, which is expressed in a variety of different ways without being linked to some kind of whole or “common sense”.12 Following this understanding of the event, as a movement of ungrounded difference, it can also be argued that there is a potential for change and transformation inherent in the event. For example, in relation to the idea of “thought” as event, Deleuze and Guattari point out that “all of thought is a becoming, a double becoming, rather than the attribute of a Subject and the representation of a Whole”.13 In this way, thought involves a constant process of change and transformation, which has the potential to bring something new. Consequently, the purpose of thought as event is not represent or resemble something by locating it in an external realm and then describe it through the use of language and concepts. Just as sense, thought refers to something much more complex, which cannot simply be reduced to a straightforward logic or formula. As Colebrook explains: 10 Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, p. 8. Claire Colebrook, “The Space of Man: On the Specificity of Affect in Deleuze and Guattari”, in Ian Buchanan and Gregg Lambert (eds.), Deleuze and Space, (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2005), p. 191. 12 Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, p. 22. 13 Deleuze and Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, p. 419. 11 59 Thinking is difference, disruption and encounter. In recognising this ‘heterogenesis’ of thought, philosophy might then affirm itself, and move beyond the recognition or representation of an outside, in favour of thinking the very movement that ‘gives’ the outside. And this means thought would be an active repetition: each time there is thought there is the renewal, affirmation and transformation of difference.14 As something that is active and creative the event of thought highlights the idea of becoming as an unlimited movement with neither beginning nor end. There is no localisable beginning of this movement of becoming – no beginning that can be traced back to a fixed moment of the past. Nor is there a pre-determined goal, a goal that can be said to function as the determinable end point of becoming. Rather, becoming presents only a fluid as well as contingent flow of life, going in various directions and creating different ways of thinking and perceiving. For Deleuze, an important task is to articulate and make thinkable this unlimited movement of becoming, in a way that does not fall back on identity and similarity but rather affirms the active and creative elements of the event. And in a sense this is precisely what Deleuze and Guattari do when they introduce the concepts of “deterritorialization” and “lines of flight”.15 According to Deleuze and Guattari, these concepts should not be understood as ways of decoding movements and becomings by extracting them from an already given context. Deterritorialization and lines of flight highlight movements of becoming as processes without an external background or context. 16 As such, they cannot be connected with any opposable terms or systems of representation, according to which movements and becoming are fixed. There are no oppositions, or beginnings and ends, only the between: 14 Claire Colebrook, Philosophy and Post-structuralist Theory: From Kant to Deleuze, (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2005), p. 227. 15 John Rajchman, The Deleuze Connections, (London: The MIT Press, 2000), p. 67. 16 Deleuze and Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, p. 305. 60 Between things does not designate a localizable relation going from one thing to the other and back again, but a perpendicular direction, a transversal movement that sweeps one and the other away, a stream without beginning or end that undermines its banks and picks up speed in the middle.17 Following this idea of movements, deterritorialization and lines of flight refer to a kind of transformation that lacks any essential characteristics or dialectical terms. Hence, there is for example no “thing” that then turns into something else, resulting in an identifiable difference between one “thing” and another “thing”. Deterritorialization and lines of flight express something much more uncertain and indeterminate than that, always lacking a specific content or agency. As movements without a clear beginning or a predetermined goal they can take on various directions, go in unpredictable ways and create possible worlds. 18 The event is always marked by these kinds of movements and transformations, which means that it also stays open to different kinds of creations and transformations. The grammar of the event In the sense of not having a predetermined goal, the event is not a static element but can rather be seen as something that is ongoing. As such, the event can also be linked to a particular “grammar”. In brief, the point of this grammar is to free the event from the notion of an independently existing object that can be described or represented through language. According to such a notion, Deleuze argues, language is based on a propositional model that includes three different dimensions: “denotation”, “manifestation” and “signification”. 19 With denotation, language is assumed to have a direct correspondence to a state of things or to what objectively is, which also means that it functions by asserting something as being either true or false. 17 Ibid., p. 28. Keith Ansell Pearson, Germinal Life: The Difference and Repetition of Deleuze, (Oxon: Routledge, 1999), p. 132. 19 Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, pp. 16-26. 18 61 The second dimension of the proposition, manifestation, “concerns the relation of the proposition to the person who speaks and expresses himself”.20 This dimension can be seen as primary in relation to denotation because it locates the subject in a position from which it is possible denote something in the first place; it is the manifesting “I” who speaks and makes his/her desires and beliefs known to others. Finally, as the third dimension, signification is used to draw out the implications and conclusions of a denoted state of affairs, which means that it seeks to provide generalisations of particular cases and thereby make them applicable to other cases as well. The three dimensions of “manifestation”, “denotation” and “signification” constitute what Deleuze refers to as the “circle of the proposition”21, a circle that functions as a condition for “truth” by establishing a correspondence to an externally existing reality that is just waiting to be discovered. One of the main problems with the assumptions underlying this model, Deleuze argues, is that they rely upon the idea of representing the state of affairs as it is. In this way, the propositional model falls into the trap of representation, assuming a prior distinction between subjects and objects, according to which the former is supposed to determine the true meaning of the latter. As such, this model also suggests that states of affairs are always already static, thereby excluding the potential for change and transformation. In order to oppose such a view and instead include this potential it is therefore necessary to move away from the propositional model. Instead of relying on the propositional model, Deleuze suggests that language can be thought of in terms of an immediate form of “expression”. The latter, in this sense, should not be seen as the expressed of a statement but only as the purely expressed, or the purely expressible: “It is not the object as denoted, but the object as expressed or expressible, never present, but always already in the past and the yet to come.”22 Expression does not correspond to an external reality, the meaning of which is mediated by the representational function of language. Rather, as an active event, expression 20 Ibid., p. 17. Ibid., p. 20. 22 Ibid., p. 155. 21 62 creates the meaning of language without trying to uncover the essence of an object or a thing. In this way, as Deleuze writes: “Pure events ground language because they wait for it as much as they wait for us, and have a pure, singular, impersonal, and pre-individual existence only inside the language which expresses them.”23 According to Deleuze, there is no ontological foundation for language, which means that it is deeply problematic to use language in order to refer to something that is present as such. So, rather than using language in this way it must itself be considered as a movement or a creation of the event. The event, in this sense, refers to an extra-linguistic force or movement, which nevertheless has an intrinsic connection to language. The way in which this connection plays out in its most immediate form is when the grammar of language takes on the role of affirming the idea of movements without ground, rather than trying to represent something that is assumed to be already present. And for Deleuze the most immediate expression of this role of language is the “verb” as an “undetermined infinitive”: The Verb is the univocity of language, in the form of an undetermined infinitive, without person, without present, without any diversity of voice. It is poetry itself. As it expresses in language all events in one, the infinitive verb expresses the event of language – language being a unique event which merges now with that which renders it possible.24 The event of language is thus expressed by the infinitive verb. As such, language can be linked to the past and future without a present, as well as to a form of becoming that lacks a particular being and a predetermined goal. Language, in this sense, has to be thought of in relation to that which is immediately expressed and therefore lacks any definitive directions. Expression is nothing but an event or a movement, which has the potential to create becomings and transformations. As such, it does not correspond to a 23 24 Ibid., p. 189. Ibid., pp. 211-12. 63 mediating present but is always located somewhere along the lines of past and future. Moreover, expression can, just as sense, be understood in terms of a paradox, which does not follow a calculable logic or formula but always goes in different directions at once. Sense and expression can also be related to one another since it is through the purely expressed or the verb as an undetermined infinitive that sense is articulated. In this way, Deleuze notes, we “reach a region where language no longer has any relation to that which it denotes, but only to that which it expresses, that is, to sense”. 25 Sense can thus be directly related to the purely expressed, instead of for example to the actions and passions of present bodies. The event of sense takes place on an incorporeal surface and eludes the depths of bodily interaction. Sense, therefore, cannot be attributed to “someone” or “something”; it can only be expressed as a pure event or a pure act, which means that it subsists or inheres in expression without occupying the space of a particular state of affairs, and without being linked to a subject or a thing. Another important concept in this context is “univocity”, which literally means “one voice” and according Deleuze can be used to express an ultimate form of Being that defines the essential quality of all events as impersonal singularities. There is, in this sense, a “univocity of Being” that is said of all events insofar as they remain impersonal and pre-individual singularities and avoid being attributed to persons and states of affairs. In relation to the univocity of Being, events gather together and communicate with one another whilst at the same time not being comparable to each other. Because their essential quality is precisely to elude any kind of similarity and to affirm difference and becoming, the relationship between events is always characterised by disjunction and divergence rather than sameness and repetition: The univocity of Being does not mean that there is one and the same Being; on the contrary, beings are multiple and different, they are 25 Ibid., p. 31. 64 always produced by a disjunctive synthesis, and they themselves are disjointed and divergent, membra disjuncta. The univocity of Being signifies that Being is Voice that it is said, and that it is said in one and the same “sense” of everything about which it is said. That of which it is said is not at all the same, but Being is the same for everything about which it is said. It occurs, therefore, as a unique event for everything that happens to the most diverse things, Eventum tantum for all events, the ultimate form for all of the forms which remain disjointed in it, but which bring about the resonance and the ramification of their disjunction.26 This idea of the univocity of Being can also be linked to Deleuze’s reading of Nietzsche’s concept of the “eternal return”, which in the previous chapter was referred to as a form of repetition that only lets difference return whilst excluding the same or the identical. As such, the eternal return is a selective process that prioritises encounters with change, difference and transformation over the static being of things. The univocity of Being is crucial for understanding this selective process because it highlights the ultimate form of events, the differential form that applies to all events regardless of their divergence. At the centre of difference and divergence there is univocity, one voice that expresses every single event at once. This notion of univocity refers, moreover, “both to what occurs and to what is said”, which implies “that it is the same thing which occurs and is said: the attributable to all bodies or states of affairs and the expressible of every proposition”.27 Univocity thus refers to the purely expressed or expressible, as well as to the very act of an occurrence. But it also refers to the quality or ultimate form of that which occurs and is said; it is the form of an impersonal and pre-individual singularity, an event that eludes any kind of attribution to bodies and states of affairs. It is not what is happening to someone or something, but rather what happens, a pure movement that stretches itself 26 27 Ibid., p. 205. Ibid., pp. 205-6. 65 out on a line, pointing towards the past and the future without a mediating present or corporeal content of bodies. 2.2 Between events and the “event” So far we have seen how Deleuze’s concept of the event can be understood in relation to time and subjectivity, difference and transformation, language and grammar. The event, in this sense, can also be thought of as a singularity, or as a force or a movement that is active and creative rather than reactive and representational. As such, it is also a movement that is prior to distinctions between subjects and objects, the internal and the external. Against the backdrop of this understanding of the event, I will now return to the question of how to understand the production of “events”. And I will do so by looking at how the singularity of events can be used as an alternative starting point for examining the processes and movements that condition and underlie the production of “events”. In order to articulate such a starting point, however, it is first necessary to understand how the event can be translated into something else in the first place, or how its singularity can be said to pass over into an actualized state of affairs. Here, I will address this question by focusing on what Deleuze refers to as the “double structure” of the event.28 According to this structure, it is important that the event is always grasped as a double, which means that apart from seeing it as a singularity it also has to be understood in relation to the ways in which it is “actualized” and thereby translated into a state of affairs. This implies, for example, translating the future-past of the event into a present moment in time, or translating movements of becoming into a notion of “being”. However, following the “double structure” of the event it is also important to take into account the process of “counter-actualization”, This way of thinking about the production of “events” has much in common with Paul Patton’s article: “The World Seen From Within: Deleuze and the Philosophy of Events”, Theory & Event, 1 (1), 1997. In this article Patton discusses Deleuze and Guattari’s idea about philosophy becoming “worthy of the event” by examining “Deleuze’s concept of the event” and “how this might apply to present social and political events”. In a similar way to Patton I draw upon Deleuze’s idea of the event as having a “pure” or virtual dimension as well as being actualized in “particular states of affairs”, which is what the “double structure” of the event refers to. 28 66 which goes in the opposite direction of actualization. According to counteractualization, the event as a singularity is “abstracted” from a state of affairs, which means that it is no longer imprisoned in a particular actualization. In this way, it is possible to understand the relationship between the two sides of the “double structure” of the event as open-ended and fluid rather than determinate and static. In this part of the chapter I will explore how these two processes can be used in order to think about the production of “events”. The actualization of events In The Logic of Sense, Deleuze articulates the idea of a “double structure” of the event in the following way: With every event, there is indeed the present moment of its actualisation, the moment in which the event is embodied in a state of affairs, an individual, or a person, the moment we designate by saying ‘here, the moment has come.’ The future and the past of the event are evaluated only with respect to this definitive present, and from the point of view of that which embodies it. But on the other hand, there is the future and the past of the event considered in itself, sidestepping each present, being free of the limitations of a state of affairs, impersonal and preindividual, neutral, neither general nor particular.29 So, according to the “double structure” of the event there are two different sides of the event. Whereas one side refers to the event as a singularity, the other refers to how the event is actualized and thereby translated into a state of affairs. In order to understand this latter side of the event further it is useful to begin by going back to Deleuze’s discussion of time, and to look in more detail at how Deleuze elaborates on the second Stoic conception of time: Chronos. One way to explain Chronos is by thinking of it in terms of a succession of instants or cases, which are repeated in the present, to which 29 Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, p. 172. 67 the past as well as the future belongs. The past and the future, in this sense, do not exist independently of the present but can rather be seen as essential parts of the present. The present connects different instants or cases by weaving them together in order to form an impression of a homogenous movement, which always goes from the past to the future. Chronos is the present which alone exists. It makes of the past and future its two oriented dimensions, so that one goes always from the past to the future – but only to the degree that presents follow one another inside partial worlds or partial systems.”30 Chronos, then, does not represent a “universal” order of time, but is always expressed within “partial systems”. According to these systems, the present “regularizes” time by connecting the future and the past into a seemingly coherent movement. More specifically, this regularization can be said to measure the movements of bodies as it fills and limits them by inscribing a particular corporeal content or matter. 31 In this sense, time is no longer “empty” but rather “embodied”, and instead of being “incorporeal” it is “corporeal”. The process that enables this regularization to take place is also what Deleuze refers to as actualization. It is important to note, however, that actualization does not refer to a process of copying something through representation and resemblance. Rather, according to Deleuze, actualization has to be understood as a genuinely creative process: Actualisation breaks with resemblance as a process no less than it does with identity as a principle. Actual terms never resemble the singularities they incarnate. In this sense, actualisation or differenciation is always a genuine creation. It does not result from any limitation of pre-existing possibility. (…) For a potential or virtual 30 31 Ibid., p. 89. Ibid., p. 73. 68 object, to be actualised is to create divergent lines which correspond to – without resembling – a virtual multiplicity.32 In order to escape the limits that are imposed by identity and resemblance, actualization has to be understood in terms of a genuine creation. And according to Deleuze, it is the potential that exists in the “virtual” that enables this creation to happen in the first place. As we saw in the previous chapter, the virtual can be linked to the concept of difference “in itself”, the aim of which is to reverse the subordination of difference to identity. Following this reversal, difference lacks any form of identity and similarity and can therefore also be thought of as all there is. “It is always differences which resemble one another, which are analogous, opposed or identical: difference is behind everything but behind difference there is nothing.”33 When developing the connection between this notion of difference and the process of actualization, Deleuze introduces yet another concept: “differenciation”. Through this concept Deleuze tries to articulate what happens when difference is no longer sustained as difference “in itself” and when the virtual or free play of differences (multiplicity) suddenly gives way to a more systematic play of differences. Differenciation, in this sense, can be understood as “a second part of difference”, the main function of which is to actualize the free play of differences. 34 When thinking of this process it is thus crucial, according to Deleuze, not to see it as a representation of the virtual but rather as a process that draws upon the potential of the virtual whilst at the same time moving away from it in order to create something other, which is no longer directly linked to the virtual. In this way, for example, the process of actualizing a systematic play of differences does not in any way resemble the free play of differences, and an individualized or personalized “Self” does not resemble the pre-individual or impersonal singularities it incarnates. Thus, it is more useful to think of the free play of 32 Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, translated by Paul Patton, (London: Continuum, 2004), p. 264. 33 Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, p. 69. 34 Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, p. 261. 69 differences and impersonal singularities in terms of a potential that underlies and enables a systematic play of differences and a personalized “Self” to emerge in the first place, but without necessarily turning into either of the latter. According to Deleuze: Far from being individual or personal, singularities preside over the genesis of individuals and persons; they are distributed in a “potential” which admits neither Self nor I, but which produces them by actualizing or realizing itself, although the figures of this actualization do not at all resemble the realized potential.35 In this way, the virtual can be said to express a potential that enables the process of actualization to take place whilst at the same time not being exhausted by it. Hence, rather than fully “belonging” to actualization, the virtual remains in the background of actualization. And despite different attempts to grasp it, through the process of actualization, the reality of the virtual continues to exist, or subsist, in an actualized state of affairs. So, even after the latter has been produced, the virtual continues to play a vital role as a never-ending potential that enables the process of actualization to sustain itself and to produce and reproduce the “actual”. Actualization, in this sense, does not lead to a final product that acquires the status of an independently existing object. Rather, as an outcome of actualization, the “actual” can only be said to exist insofar as it remains a part of the process in which it is produced and reproduced. In this way, it can also be noted that actualization does not lead to anything static but is always guided by encounters with change, difference and transformation. Because actualization constantly has to renew itself and because it does not rely on resemblance and representation, whatever comes out of it must itself be seen as a part of an active and creative process. Hence, as Deleuze and Guattari point out: “The 35 Ibid., p. 118. 70 actual is not what we are but, rather, what we become, what we are in the process of becoming.”36 Counter-actualization According to Deleuze and Guattari, the relationship between the actual and the virtual is always mutual. This means that in addition to the process of actualizing the virtual there must also be a process that goes in the opposite direction, “from virtuals we descend to actual states of affairs, and from states of affairs we ascend to virtuals, without being able to isolate one from the other”. 37 Deleuze and Guattari call this latter process “counter- actualization”, which, in contrast to actualization happens whenever the event is “abstracted from a state of affairs”. 38 Actualization and counteractualization thus move between the event and a state of affairs, or between the virtual and the actual, but without rendering the two sides clearly separable from one another: No doubt, the event is not only made up from inseparable variations, it is itself inseparable from the state of affairs, bodies, and lived reality in which it is actualized or brought about. But we can also say the converse: the state of affairs is no more separable from the event that nonetheless goes beyond its actualization in every respect.39 Actualization and counter-actualization can thus be seen as relative processes. As such, they render the two sides of the actual and the virtual both independent and inseparable at the same time. And this is precisely why the event also has to be grasped in terms of a “double structure”. Without actualization the event would never come into effect in the first place, and without counter-actualization there would be no force that continues to make the event live in the body, as a continual and never-ending potential for 36 Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, What is Philosophy?, translated by Graham Burchell and Hugh Tomlinson, (London: Verso, 1994), p 112. 37 Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, p. 160. 38 Deleuze and Guattari, What is Philosophy?, p. 159. 39 Ibid., p. 159. 71 change and transformation. “To the extent that the pure event is each time imprisoned forever in its actualization, counter-actualization liberates it, always for other times.”40 So, rather than simply operating on its own, the process of actualization is always doubled by the potential of counteractualization, which in turn opens up the possibility for more actualizations yet to come. In order to understand this potential further it is also important to consider the disruptive elements of the event. An example of those elements is “sense”, which according to Deleuze has the potential to disrupt or undermine notions of “common sense” and “good sense”. Whereas the latter are based on the idea of subordinating sense to a shared understanding of what everyone is “supposed” to know or recognise, sense as event unleashes a singular force of difference, which has the power to disrupt notions of “common sense” and “good sense”. One way to explain the disruptive element of sense is by thinking of it in terms of a “paradox”, which instead of going in one single direction constantly diverges along separate lines. Returning to Deleuze’s reading of Alice in Wonderland, he writes: “‘Which way, which way?’ asks Alice. The question has no answer, since it is the characteristic of sense not to have any direction or ‘good sense’. Rather, sense always goes to both directions at once, in the infinitely subdivided and elongated past-future.”41 In this way, Deleuze links the paradox of sense to movements of past and future as well as to the lack of a stable and mediating present. Without such a present it thus becomes increasingly difficult to determine what it means to talk about “good sense” or “common sense” in the first place. Behind such notions there is another and much more ambiguous “logic of sense”, which cannot be reduced to ideas about what is “good” or “bad”, “right” or “wrong”. Going in both directions at once, sense is an indeterminable element that disrupts and displaces notions of “good sense” and “common sense”, forcing the latter to disappear in a cloud of uncertainty, and overthrowing them “from within by 40 41 Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, p. 182. Ibid., pp. 88-89. 72 paradox”. 42 And even if attempts are made to provide generalizations of “good sense” and “common sense”, the paradox of sense makes them impossible to sustain as such, or as static elements of truth and certainty. In the same way as the actual always has to be understood in relation to the virtual, notions of “good sense” and “common sense” thus have to be understood in relation to the paradox of sense. Moreover, the idea of a present moment in time (Chronos) does not exist independently of, but always in relation to movements of past and future (Aion). This means that the temporal actualization of events cannot be clearly separated from the movements of past and future that are expressed by those events. And perhaps even more important, movements of past and future can be said to have the potential to disrupt and dislocate the present moment in time. According to this kind of disruption, then, the present does not exist as a “fixed” moment in time but rather as a “measureless or dislocated present as the time of depth and subversion”. 43 So, rather than representing an independently existing moment in time, the present only exists as a part of the movements of Aion. In this way, there is no present “moment” that can be located in a particular point in time and that forever remains static. Rather, as a part of the constant movements towards the past and the future the notion of a present moment in time is always open to a process of change and transformation. For this reason, Deleuze points out that the present does not contradict Aion but rather that it is the present as being of reason which is subdivided ad infinitum into something that has just happened and something that is going to happen, always flying in both directions at once. The other present, the living present, happens and brings about the event. But the event nonetheless retains an eternal truth upon the line of Aion, which divides it eternally into a proximate past and an imminent future. The Aion endlessly 42 43 Ibid., p. 133. Ibid., p. 191. 73 subdivides the event and pushes away past as well as future, without ever rendering them less urgent.44 So, instead of representing a separate form of time, Chronos always has to be understood in relation to Aion, which also means that the latter has the potential to disrupt and refigure the former without ever letting it remain the same. This point can also be illustrated by what Deleuze describes as the “agonizing aspect” of the pure event, referring to the fact that movements of past and future cannot be fixed on a temporal present or in a separate moment in time, which makes it increasingly difficult to determine what has happened in the past and to predict what is going to happen in the future purely on the basis of something that is happening in the present. Before it even appears as a separate moment in time this “something” is pushed away by movements of past and future. Nothing remains static and nothing remains the same. Ideas about what has happened might be repeated an endless number of times. But these repetitions can neither be cemented nor result in a static conception of one and the same “thing”. Repetitions ultimately have the effect of displacing such conceptions, revealing the free play of differences without a determinable centre. In his review of Difference and Repetition and The Logic of Sense, Foucault makes a similar point by referring to the art of Andy Warhol, in which images of car crashes and soup cans are repeated to the point where they stop being mere copies of one another and instead emerge as endless variations: [I]n concentrating on this boundless monotony, we find the sudden illumination of multiplicity itself – with nothing at its center, at its highest point, or beyond it – a flickering of light that travels even faster than the eyes and successively lights up the moving labels and the captive snapshots that refer to each other to eternity, without ever saying anything: suddenly, arising from the background of the old inertia of equivalences, the striped form of the event tears through the 44 Ibid., p. 74. 74 darkness, and the eternal phantasm informs that soup can, that singular and depthless face.45 The encounter with the soup is not characterised by repetitions of the same but rather by repetitions of difference. It is consequently this latter form of repetition, which is concerned with difference in itself rather than with the idea of tying difference to identity, that enables the singularity of the event to emerge yet again. The singularity of the event, in this sense, has not disappeared in these repetitions but remains in the background, as a potential for change and transformation. For this reason, Deleuze and Guattari also refer to the event as a “vapour” or a “reserve”, which rather than disappearing always tends to linger on: “[T]he event is pure immanence of what is not actualized or of what remains indifferent to actualization, since its reality does not depend upon it. The event is immaterial, incorporeal, unlivable: pure reserve.” 46 In this way, there can be no full or complete translation of the event into an actualized state of affairs. The latter never exists simply on its own but is always accompanied with a trace of that from which it emerges: the singularity of the event or the virtual. Due to the process of counter-actualization, actualization always includes elements of uncertainty and contingency. Together they illustrate the ambiguity that exists within the “double structure” of the event. Whereas one process tries to move away from the indeterminacy of the singularity of events, the other process constantly seeks to bring the singularity of events back to life by dissolving the notion of a state of affairs. This ambiguity can also be understood in terms of the relationship between the “impersonal” and the “personal”. In one case, as Deleuze points out, “it is I who am too weak for life, it is life which overwhelms me, scattering its singularities all about”, and in another case, “it is my life, which seems too weak for me and slips Michel Foucault, “Theatrum Philosophicum”, in Language, Counter-memory, Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews by Michel Foucault, translated by Donald F. Bouchard and Sherry Simon, edited by Donald F. Bouchard, (New York: Cornell University Press, 1977), p. 189. 46 Deleuze and Guattari, What is Philosophy?, p. 156. 45 75 away at a point which, in a determined relation to me, has become present.”47 What this ambiguity shows, then, is that there is always one part of the event that remains impersonal and therefore ungraspable. It cannot be grasped, actualized or realized because it appears to have no relation to me as a person. At the same time, however, there is also the part of the event that clearly seems to belong to me as a person. In this case it is “I” who embody it; it is within “me” that the event is actualized. When illustrating this ambiguity Deleuze refers Blanchot’s example of “death” as event. On the one hand, Deleuze notes, death “has an extreme and definite relation to me and my body and is grounded in me, but it also has no relation to me at all – it is incorporeal and infinitive, impersonal, grounded only in itself”.48 So, apart from having a strong connection to my body, death can be seen as a force that appears to have no relation to me at all. In this latter case it is therefore not “I” who dies but always an impersonal “they” or “it”. The ambiguous relationship between the impersonal and the personal illustrated by this example is crucial when trying to understand the importance of events. It shows that the event is not something that “I” can simply control but rather something in which “I” both disappear and then again appear. Thus, Deleuze notes that: “Every event is like death. Double and impersonal in its double.”49 The becoming of the “event” Returning to the question of how to understand the production of “events”, one way to address this question would be to analyse the “event” in terms of the “actual”, or as a product of actualization. The “event”, in this sense, can also be referred to as “the moment in which the event is embodied in a state of affairs, an individual, or a person, the moment we designate by saying ‘here, the moment has come’”.50 As such, it can moreover be connected with the process of moving away from the singularity of events and inscribing an 47 Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, p. 172. Ibid., p. 172. 49 Ibid., p. 172. 50 Ibid., p. 172. 48 76 actualized state of affairs. What we have then is a notion of the “event”, located in a particular moment in time, in relation to a well established subject and against a given background or context. However, following the process of counter-actualization, there is also a movement going in the opposite direction, a movement that seeks to disrupt and refigure the place and meaning of the “event”. When taking this process into account, the “event” does not simply exist as an independently existing object or a coherent whole, according to which the paradoxes and problems related to the singularity of events have once and for all been resolved. The “event” must also be linked to a process whereby these paradoxes and problems yet again spring to life and unsettles the “event” as an actualized state of affairs. The production of “events” can thus be linked to both of these processes, actualization and counter-actualization, which work both with and against the notion of the “event” as an independently existing object or a coherent whole. Whereas one process seeks to establish such a notion, the other one seeks to destabilise it. Hence, rather than being definite or static, the “event” remains open to movements and processes, according to which it is refigured and recreated in different ways. In this way, the “event” can also be linked to the ambiguity that exists within the “double structure” of the event, being neither actual nor virtual, neither personal nor impersonal, and neither present nor absent but always caught up somewhere in-between. As such, the “event” can also be analysed as something that in itself is indeterminable and contingent, lacking a fixed essence and meaning as well as a static location in time. It is therefore necessary to specify what it really means to talk about the “event” in terms of an “object”. The following quote by Brian Massumi is very useful in doing so: When we speak of “an” object or thing, what we are referring to is a complex interweaving of attributes and contents as subsumed under a nominal identity (a name). “An” object subsumes a multiplicity that 77 evolves situationally. Every object is an evolving differential: a snow balling, open-ended variation on itself.51 When thinking about the “event” as an “object” or a “thing” it is thus necessary to understand it, not as something that exists independently and in relation to a static location in time, but rather as a part of an ongoing production, according to which the “object” itself is constantly changing and transforming in various ways. So, instead of referring to the being of the “event” as this particular “thing”, it is more useful to think in terms of a becoming of the “event”. Within this becoming, then, there are two interdependent processes involved, actualization and counter-actualization, working both with and against the notion of the “event” as an object or a whole. The “event” is made up of these processes, as well as of the lines and movements that define it as a constantly transforming “multiplicity”. 2.3 Language and the social production of “events” So far in this chapter we have seen how Deleuze’s concept of the event can be used to think about the production of “events”. The outcome of this examination is an understanding of the becoming of the “event”, a double process of producing the place and meaning of the “event” as an object or a whole. According to this double process, the “event” never acquires the status of a final object or a complete whole but is always part of an ongoing and continuous process, which remains open to change and transformation. In order to develop this understanding of the production of “events” further, this part of the chapter will now move on to consider how the “event” acquires a more “formal” status through the use of language in the social field. This will be done by focusing on one common notion of the “event”, which is to see it as a breaking point that separates “before” from “after” and “what is to come” from “what has been”. Such a notion of the “event” might of course come in various shapes and forms, depending on what happens in 51 Brian Massumi, Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation, (London: Duke University Press, 2002), p. 216. 78 the production of a particular “event”. However, what I am interested in here is not to examine the production of a particular “event” but rather to see how it might be possible to think about the conditions under which the “event” is produced as a breaking point. Form of content and form of expression When considering the role of language in the production of “events” it is useful to go back to one particular aspect of the singularity of events that was discussed earlier in this chapter, which is to connect the event with the purely “expressed”. It was noted that this event has the power to express “incorporeal transformations”, which are produced by the verb as an undetermined infinitive. These kinds of incorporeal transformations are moreover characterised by the pure line of becoming, which exists independently of a particular form of being. However, in order to have an effect on the body and to actually make the corporeal content of the body transform in various ways, incorporeal transformations must also be attributed to particular bodies. According to Deleuze and Guattari, this kind of attribution is made possible when the expressed ceases to be the purely expressed and instead becomes the expressed of a statement. In this case language can be said to function by the ways in which it compels “obedience” and “gives life orders”, a function that Deleuze and Guattari also refer to as “order-words”.52 Orderwords and statements can thus be said to enable transformations to have an immediate impact on the body by forcing a certain “corporeal modification” of it to take place. As an example of this modification, Deleuze and Guattari refer to the ways in which different age categories are imposed through statements such as “you are no longer a child”. Although the transformation from being a child into something else is obviously attributed to a body, the transformation itself cannot be reduced to an essence within the body, which is why it also has to be understood as an “incorporeal” transformation.53 So, 52 53 Deleuze and Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, p. 84. Ibid., p. 89. 79 what makes the child suddenly stop being a child and become something else does not come down to any explicit corporeal factors but rather to the power of language in the social field to attribute a particular content and meaning to the body. And it is the order-word that performs this task, through its immediate effect on the body: “The instantaneousness of the order-word, its immediacy, gives it a power of variation in relation to the bodies to which the transformation is attributed.”54 The order-word states that things are no longer the same as they once were and that consequently, the content of the body has changed and taken on a new form too.55 In this context, Deleuze and Guattari point out that there are two different “formalizations” at work: “If in a social field we distinguish the set of corporeal modifications and the set of incorporeal transformations, we are presented, despite the variety in each of the sets, with two formalizations, one of content, the other of expression.” 56 By stressing that content and expression are made up of two different “forms”, the point that Deleuze and Guattari make is that the relationship between them is not one of resemblance or representation. Rather, content and expression belong to different modes of dispersion, between which there is neither a common unity nor form. When making this point they refer to Foucault’s claim that “it is in vain that we say what we see; what we see never resides in what we say”.57 As two different modes of dispersion, the visible and the articulable, or what is seen and what is said, have no immediate connection or resemblance: “Precisely because content, like expression, has a form of its own, one can never assign the form of expression the function of simply representing, describing, or averring a corresponding content: there is neither correspondence nor conformity.” 58 Also, Deleuze and Guattari emphasise that content should not be understood as something that is prior to expression, which means that content should not be regarded as a signified, 54 Ibid., p. 91. Here, bodies refer not only to individual bodies but also to for example a society or a class. 56 Deleuze and Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, p. 95. 57 Michel Foucault, The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences, (London: Routledge, 2002), p. 10. 58 Ibid., p. 95. 55 80 no less than expression should be seen as a signifier. Rather than representing or resembling one another, content and expression interact with one another, and in so doing they produce different outcomes. Crucially, these outcomes never consist of neatly composed lines that correspond to one another within some coherent whole. They can rather be described in terms of a chaotic mixture or “assemblage”, in which content and expression constitute their two different variables.59 These variables can thus be said to interact with one another, not by representing but rather by intervening and thereby refiguring each other. This can happen, for example, when a form of expression intervenes and refigures a form of content, thereby making the latter modify in certain ways: The independence of the two kinds of forms, forms of expression and forms of content, is not contradicted but confirmed by the fact that the expressions or expressed are inserted into or intervene in contents, not to represent them but to anticipate them or move them back, slow them down or speed them up, separate or combine them, delimit them in a different way. The warp of the instantaneous transformations is always inserted into the woof of continuous modifications.60 When referring to “modifications”, Deleuze and Guattari are not simply suggesting that expression constitutes or constructs the content. Rather, they are referring to the ways in which content and expression interact with and refigure one another. To illustrate this point Deleuze and Guattari use Foucault’s work on the prison as an example. The prison, they point out, is a form of content. And within this content, the bodies of prisoners enter as a substance, just as the bodies of guards and visitors. However, the prisoners are not prisoners unless they have first passed through sentencing by a judge. The sentence itself is carried out as a form of expression, for example by using concepts such as “delinquency” or “delinquent”, which in this case “express a new way of classifying, stating, translating, and even committing 59 60 Deleuze and Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, p. 101. Ibid., p. 96. 81 criminal acts”. 61 The term “delinquency” as a form of expression thus interacts with the “prison” as a form of content, but without representing or signifying the prison. In this sense, there is no pre-established relationship between “delinquency” as a form of expression and the “prison” as a form of content. The connection between the two rather has to be produced. It is produced by the ways in which the term “delinquency” interacts with the “prison” and modifies the content of it in a particular way. Having no pre-established connection, and belonging to two separate forms of content and expression, “prison” and “delinquency” can also enter new relations with other parts of society through the production of new connections. And following Deleuze’s reading of Foucault’s work, these connections always emerge from the historical formations that define the conditions for knowledge, or the conditions for seeing and speaking in certain ways. These conditions, then, do not rely on a prior ground, nor do they result in a coherent and single “entity”. Rather, according to Deleuze: The conclusion we can draw is that each historical formation sees and reveals all it can within the conditions laid down for visibility, just as it says all it can within the conditions relating to statements. (…) [I]n both cases the conditions do not meet deep within a consciousness of a subject, any more than they compose a single Entity: they are two forms of exteriority within which dispersion and dissemination take place, sometimes of statements, sometimes of visibilities.62 Content and expression, or the visible and the articulable, can thus be related to seeing and speaking as two different modes of dispersion. Moreover, seeing and speaking have their own internal differences, which can neither be related to a complete whole, nor to a pre-established subject. Consequently, content and expression are not static forms but always caught 61 Ibid., p. 74. Gilles Deleuze, Foucault, translated and edited by Seán Hand, (London: Continuum, 1999), pp. 59-60. 62 82 up in different movements, constituting a world that is in a constant process of becoming. At the same time, however, there can also be attempts to inscribe a more established relationship between form of content and form of expression, constituting what Deleuze and Guattari refer to as a “collective assemblage of enunciation”.63 Following this “formalization” it might then be possible to imagine expression and content fitting together as constant variables of one and the same “thing”. In relation to this “thing”, language is given a purely pragmatic function, which is to articulate the “true” relationship between expression and content. However, according to Deleuze and Guattari, language should never be understood as the means for communication or information. 64 Not even the pragmatic function of language can be reduced to communication or information, simply because expression never re-presents the content. Trying to combine content and expression, the visible and the articulable, the pragmatic function of language is nothing but an attempt to bridge the unbridgeable gap between their respective forms. As Deleuze notes, statements are not directed towards anything, since they are not related to a thing any more than they express a subject but refer only to a language, a language-being, that gives them unique subjects and objects that satisfy particular conditions as immanent variables. And visibilities are not deployed in a savage world already opened up to a primitive (pre-predicative) consciousness, but refer only to a light, a light-being, which gives them forms, proportions and perspectives that are immanent in the proper sense – that is, free of any intentional gaze. Neither language nor light will be examined in the areas that relate them to one another (designation, signification, the signifying process of language; a physical environment, a tangible or intelligible world) but rather in the irreducible dimension that gives both of them as separate and self-sufficient entities: ‘there is’ light, and ‘there is’ 63 64 Deleuze and Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, p. 89. Ibid., p. 85. 83 language. All intentionality collapses in the gap that opens up between these two monads, or in the ‘non-relation’ between seeing and speaking.65 Language, in this sense, should not be examined by “tracing” its origins, or by trying to uncover the “true” connections between seeing and speaking, content and expression. Rather, language has to be understood as a “map”, which consists of signs of deterritorialization as well as reterritorialization.66 As such, they are not signs of “things” but can rather be said to “mark a certain threshold crossed” in the movements of deterritorialization and reterritorialization.67 It is necessary to say something here about the concept of “reterritorialization”, which so far has not been discussed in this thesis. This concept can be understood in a similar way to “actualization”, in the sense that it refers to a process of “capturing” an unlimited movement of becoming. As such, reterritorialization can also be referred to as a process of capturing the movements of deterritorialization by filling them with a corporeal content and inscribing a particular way of being. 68 It is important to emphasise, however, that reterritorialization never leads back to an origin or a foundation but can rather be said to produce the illusion of actually possessing an origin or a foundation. As Colebrook explains, “reterritorialization occurs when we imagine a subject who was there all along at the origin of language. We think that ‘man’ invented language, rather than being one of language’s effects.”69 Furthermore, movements of reterritorialization cannot be clearly separated from movements of deterritorialization but should rather be thought of as “relative, always connected”, and “caught up in one another”.70 In this way, reterritorialization functions as a “complement” to 65 Deleuze, Foucault, p. 109. Deleuze and Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, p. 85. 67 Ibid., p. 75. 68 Ibid., p. 321. 69 Claire Colebrook, Gilles Deleuze, (London: Routledge, 2002), p. 116. 70 Deleuze and Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, p. 11. 66 84 deterritorialization: “Deterritorialization must be thought of as a perfectly positive power that has degrees and thresholds (epistrata), is always relative, and has reterritorialization as its flipside or complement.” 71 Moreover, processes of de- and reterritorialization do not respond to any pre-existing territories. In other words, there is not a territory that then becomes de- and reterritorialized. 72 Rather, the very notion of territory should always be regarded as secondary to the processes of de- and reterritorialization, as an outcome or a product of their correlative movements and interactions.73 It is also in this way that the formalization of expression and content has to be understood. Both expression and content have degrees of deterritorialization, which render their forms more or less deterritorialized and indeterminate. As such, they also remain open to different kinds of reterritorialization, according to which they become more or less stable and determinate. In short, there are degrees of deterritorialization that quantify the respective forms and according to which contents and expression are conjugated, feed into each other, accelerate each other, or on the contrary become stabilized and perform a reterritorialization. (…) Germany, toward November 20, 1923: on the one hand, the deterritorializing inflation of the monetary body and, on the other, in response to the inflation, a semiotic transformation of the reichsmark into the rentenmark, making possible a reterritorialization.74 Germany, 1923, is thus one example of how there is a deterritorialization of content (the monetary body), which is responded to by the reterritorialization of expression (the rentenmark). The latter is not simply a means to represent or uncover the content. Rather, it is a force that creates a “semiotic transformation” of the content, the outcome of which is a certain mixture or assemblage of both content and expression operating in the social field. 71 Ibid., p. 60. Territories do not only refer to geographical space but also to for example ‘property, work and money”. See Ibid., p. 560. 73 Ibid., p. 62. 74 Ibid., p. 97. 72 85 Language and “events” So, how can Deleuze and Guattari’s ideas about the social function of language be used in order to think further about the production of “events”? Or, more specifically, how can these ideas be used in order to think about the relationship between the singularity of events and the “event”? It has already been discussed how the singularity of events can be linked to the purely expressed and the infinitive verb. But in addition to this it could also be argued that the “event” has to be filled with a particular “content” or “matter”. This content might for example relate to ideas about what has happened in a particular moment in time, or to the way in which that moment is attributed to the presence of a body, where the body might be an individual as well as a collective. When trying to understand how the content of the “event” is produced it is also possible to refer to the relationship between incorporeal transformations and corporeal modifications. As was described earlier, this relationship is enabled by the function of the order-word, which compels “obedience” and “gives life orders”. The order-word states that things are no longer the way they used to be and that consequently “we” too have changed. In this way, the order-word can also be said to function as a “breaking point”, which separates before from after, and what has been from what is to come. This function can be linked, moreover, to the temporal order that follows the actualization of the event, Chronos, or the time of the “living present”. Following this temporal order, the future-past of the event is replaced by the notion of an “event”, which marks a specific moment in time. As such, the “event” is no longer overshadowed by doubt and uncertainty; it occupies a more stable location in time, in relation to which it also becomes easier to answer questions about what has happened and what is going to happen and thereby fill the “event” with a particular content and meaning. Moreover, implicit in this process is also the possibility to define the “event” as a certain “type” of “event”. According to Massumi: 86 The singular is exactly what happens. Other events may follow. Its happening may prove to have been the first in a series of occurrences carrying what may well be considered, under systematic comparison, the “same” accidents. These cease retrospectively to be anomalies, becoming identifiable traits. On the basis of the shared properties lately assigned to them, the series of occurrences can now be grouped together as belonging to a type: a new type (a new form of content for the propositional system’s expression). The event has passed from the status of a singularity to that of a particular instance of a general type: a member of a collection. Propositional systems are type-casting collector mechanisms.75 The propositional system that Massumi refers to here can thus be linked to the ways in which expression ceases to be the purely expressed and instead becomes the expressed of a statement. Implicit in this process is thus a certain formalization of expression, which amounts to sameness and identity by assuming a direct correspondence to the content of the “event”. However, as was explained earlier, there is neither resemblance nor conformity between expression and content. As two different modes of dispersion, expression and content consist of two separate forms, the articulable and the visible, neither of which resembles the other. Their relationship is rather one of mutual interaction, according to which one intervenes into and refigures the other. This interaction happens, furthermore, not on the basis of what is already present but rather on the basis of what is missing, the missing link between expression and content. What seems to be missing in the production of “events”, then, is the link between the singularity of events and the notion of the “event” as an object or a whole. Something has happened but we do not know exactly what or how to describe it. Its singularity escapes any pre-fixed notions of a general type of “events”. This requires a response, a form of expression that can intervene into and thereby establish a new form of content. In this Brian Massumi, “Introduction: Like a Thought”, in Brian Massumi (ed.), A Shock to Thought: Expression after Deleuze and Guattari, (London: Routledge, 2002), p. 22. 75 87 context the order-word emerges as a function that seeks to bring the two forms together and thereby establish a form of content that eventually becomes familiar to us and that can be related to in certain ways. Still, however, the point has to be made that the “event” cannot be determined as such, regardless of how many attempts there are to do so. There is no being of the “event” but only a becoming of the “event”. Previously, this idea was developed by pointing to the processes of actualization and counter-actualization, as well as to the ambiguity that exists within the “double structure” of the event, between the virtual and the actual, Aion and Chronos, the impersonal and the personal. But it is also possible to make a similar point in relation to the social function of language, or the formalization of content and expression. Since there will never be a complete determination or “reterritorialization” of either content or expression, neither of them can be said to exist as static elements of one and the same “thing”. So, even though the order-word formalizes the relationship between content and expression, this formalization is never final or complete, and it always has the potential to change and take on new variations. This potential can also be explained by pointing to the excluded middle, which is left in the gap between content and expression, the visible and the articulable. Because this gap is always to some extent left open there is also the potential for something new to emerge from it. So, when thinking about the process of formalizing the content of the “event” it is necessary to do so without assigning the “event” a constant or static form. As a form of content, the “event” always has the potential to change and take on new variations. This potential can thus be explained by the excluded middle or the missing link between content and expression, and especially by the ways in which the form of expression has the potential to dissolve as well as transform the form of content. Conclusion When thinking about the production of “events” in terms of a becoming of the “event”, the main point is to understand the “event” in relation to 88 different processes and movements. These processes and movements have neither a pre-determined goal nor can they be said to signify something static or something that is already present. Hence, their aim is not to uncover something that is hidden but rather to create and produce, drawing their power from the singularity of the events as a force or a movement of ungrounded difference. This movement is mainly productive, but it also has the potential to disrupt that which has been produced. As such, the “event” is never static or complete but always stays open to change and transformation, constantly left with a mark of uncertainty. When thinking about the production of “events” along these lines it is therefore important to emphasise that the “whole” never actually exists. Rather, the “whole” can be seen as something that always moves to the edge or recedes infinitely into the shadows. It isn’t an outline or boundary, but an indeterminate fringing. It is not a closure or framing or subsumption. It is the openness of closed form, form continually running into and out of other dimensions of existence.76 Lacking the form of a complete whole and a determinable object, the content of the “event” always remains open to some extent. Hence, there is always the potential for a new form of expression to intervene, thereby refiguring the form of its content in a new way. How this plays out might vary from case to case, depending on what happens in the production of a particular “event”. So, in order to see how this could play out I will return in the next two chapters to the example of “9/11” as an “event”, in order to examine how this “event” is produced and what kinds of lines, processes and movements condition it. 76 Massumi, Parables for the Virtual, p. 174-5. 89