MANNAN, Adam Intellectual Property (LW 556) Dissertation Convenor: Mr Alan Story 23rd February 2003 Intellectual Property As A Tool Of Social Repression This paper, focussing on the effect of plant monopoly rights in agriculture, shows that the regime of intellectual property protection in this sphere, despite its vaunted aspirations, is detrimental to society. The regime is analysed using a rationalist approach complimented by empirical examples. It is found that by permitting intellectual property protection for agricultural plants that the cost of these plants is increased, and biodiversity diminished resulting in further social dislocation between the lesser developed countries and the most developed countries. Moreover, it is found that in the most industrialised nations that plant monopoly rights lead to control of the food chain by the rights holders. The impact of monopoly rights in agriculture has grave consequences on not only those countries of low Gross National Product, but also within the societies with high Gross National Product. Furthermore, it is shown that the presence of plant monopoly rights over agricultural plants shifts the focus of research and development from the legitimate demands of societies to methods by which monopolists can force their products onto the market or gain unconscionable profit. This paper concludes that permitting plant monopoly rights does not benefit society. It rather transforms social and environmental resources into monopolist property thereby hindering societal access to such resources. Avarice and greed are poor guides to humanity. The author has asserted his moral rights in accordance with the Copyright Designs and Patents Act 1988. INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS AS A TOOL OF SOCIAL REPRESSION 1. Introduction In 2001 the Canadian Court of Appeal1 ruled that a canola farmer, Schmeiser, was liable for substantial damages for patent infringement. It was found that his crop, cross pollinated through natural processes,2 expressed a gene, the property of Monsanto, conveying resistance to glycophosphate herbicides. Despite a lack of evidence on Monsanto’s part, that Schmeiser had exploited the gene by using glycophosphate herbicides on his crop, patent infringement was found by the mere incorporation of the gene into Schmeiser’s crop. According to Rousseau civilization, most notably the introduction of property, is responsible for introducing evil into the world. Hume shared3 Rousseau’s view by holding that the human nature is a vessel of strife; a conflict of humanity on the one hand and ‘avarice and greed’ on the other.4 However, avarice and greed are not the only detrimental results of property. As Cohen points out, “ …we must not overlook the actual fact that dominium over things is also imperium over our fellow human beings.”5 Why then is property such a fundamental part of the western conception of society? Justification for the existence of property is argued on the basis of four theories. The first, known as the ‘possession theory,’ is merely a statement of empirical logic that a res can only be possessed by an individual. For example a grain of rice6 may be consumed by 1 Monsanto Canada Inc v Schmeiser [2001] 12 C.P.R. (4th) 204 (Fed Ct (Can)) Insect and wind pollination from the gene rich crops of neighbouring farmers. 3 Both Russeau and Hume’s writings indicate a link between ethics and feelings. Kant rejects their position by advocating objective ‘pure moral law,’ which is independent of all inclinations or feelings. The difficulty with Kant’s proposition is the question of identifying the ‘pure moral law.’ Kant contends that only by rationality devoid of all sentiment and feeling can the ‘pure moral law’ be found. The difficulty I see with the Kantian perspective is proving rationality can be pure. After all, how were the first principles of rationalism derived? 4 Hume, Enquiries concerning human understanding and concerning the principles of morals, (Reprinted) [Clarendon Press, 3rd Ed., 2002, Oxford] 5 Cohan, ‘Property and Sovereignty,’ 2 only one person; whilst a pen7 can only be used by one person at a time. This theory, whilst coherent when applied to tangible objects, becomes absurd when applied to intangible objects.8 Consider for example a word,9 or a song.10 Either of these can be used by more than one person concurrently. It is indeed questionable whether the ‘possession theory’ can even be applied conceptually to res incorporalis. After all, how does one possess11 or occupy an intangible object? The second is the reward trope that “wealth is entirely and absolutely mine as a result of my own unaided effort.”12 It stems from the rationale that labour has to be encouraged and one way is to convey wealth. As it will be shown not all things produced are ultimately good, nor is the labour proportionate to the wealth. Furthermore, the notion of granting wealth, as an incentive to work, through a vehicle of rights is inherently flawed. The award of a right to one party may forbid or restrict the labour of all others. The third justification is the ‘economic theory’ whereby it is considered that the successful economic agent is the one that benefits from the greatest increase in wealth. Effectively the notional agent is considered as being able to foresee or create demand, thereby being an efficient director of economic activities. Considering the important role played in the generation of new forms of property by large multinational lobbyists, the relevance of the economic theory cannot be disputed.13 However as will be shown the generation of profits by an economic agent need not be in societies’ interests. Indeed, demand is most effectively generated by establishing shortage or dependence14 and neither situation is of social benefit. As will be shown there is a difference between socially desirable productivity and the desire for individual profits. The fourth justificatory theorem relates to personal autonomy. It is premised on the belief that, 6 Tangible fongible object Tangible infongible object 8 Derived from the Latin word objectum in the late 16th Century, with an attributed meaning of a thing presented to the mind. 9 Capable of being res incorporalis under Trade Mark provisions. 10 Lyrics capable of being res incorporalis as a literary work under copyright provisions, whilst the music is capable of protection as a musical work under copyright provisions. 11 Possession requires physical interaction. Intangible objects by definition are unable to be touched. 12 The Labour Theory, per Cohan, ‘Property and Sovereignty,’ 13 Lukes, ‘Can the Base be Distinguished from the Superstructure?’ {Miller eds.) The Nature of Political Theory [Oxford University Press, 1 st Ed., 1983, Oxford] 14 Monopoly. 7 “To be free one must have a sphere of self-assertion in the external world [and that] one’s private property provides such an opportunity.”15 Despite committing a fallacy of reasoning by mixing two separate systems of logic16 the theorem poses another difficulty. It will be recalled for a person to hold dominium over things is for that person to hold imperium over other persons. How can self-assertion, if it extends to property lead to greater freedom? The response given is egocentric, the greater the wealth of an individual the greater their freedom. As Ahrens stated, “It is undoubtedly contrary to the right of personality to have persons dependant on others on account of material goods.”17 Further errors of reasoning occur when some expounders of increased property rights unconsciously commingle personality theory and the labour theory;18 resulting in the conclusion that those of greatest industry enjoy the greatest freedom.19 Thus, only the labour theory, the economic theory and the theory of personal autonomy can be used to justify res incorporalis. The particular form of res incorporalis that will be considered are those entities that are by convention collected together under the title ‘intellectual property.’20 A coherent definition of ‘intellectual property’ has and will continue to pose difficulties; a consequence is that no adequate definition yet exists.21 Simply, intellectual property is a legal construct whereby a ‘person’22 may ‘own’23 abstract entities and thus be entitled to exclude Cohen, ‘Property and Sovereignty’ See Hume, Enquiries concerning human understanding and concerning the principles of morals 17 Ahrens, Cours de Droit Naturel, 6th Ed., 1886, p. 108. c.f. Cohen, ‘Property and Sovereignty’ 18 Demsetz, “Toward a Theory of Property Rights,” (1967) 57 American Economic Review Proceedings 347 19 Example of a fallacy of misplaced correctness. The conclusion is also wrong as it has been shown that unearned increment is the greatest source of wealth. See Davenport, ‘Extent and significance of Unearned Increment,” Bulletin of the American Economic Association, Series 4, No.2 (1911) c.f. Cohen, ‘Property and Sovereignty’ 20 The unsatisfactory convention usually adopted is that ‘Intellectual Property’ refers to that genus of entities as provided for under WIPO and the TRIPS agreement. 21 For example, a definition that IP is a chose in action is particularly unhelpful since the category ‘chose in action’ is defined by its constituent members. In addition, what within such a definition distinguishes intellectual property from a debt? Another favoured practice is to provide a list of intellectual property’s suggested component parts. 22 Both natural persons and ens legis 23 It is suggested that ownership is in the sense of §903 of the Burgerliches Gesetzbuch: the owner of an asset exercises an absolute right of property over that thing within the limits imposed by law or the rights of others, otherwise they are entitled to exclude all other interference. I disagree with this 15 16 others from using real objects incorporating them.24 This is not ownership of the rights25 to real property, but of the strangely pre-eminent rights to rights over abstract objects. Indeed supremacy over the physical is the nature of all the rights to rights embound under the title of ‘intellectual property.’26 ‘Intellectual Property’ rights can then be considered as ‘monopolist rights’27 and hereafter will be referred to as such. Applying a Hohfeldian analysis28 it is clear that the grant of a right imposes a duty. Since the right is usually granted to an individual29 the duty is imposed on society. A duty imposes obligations, thereby reducing the liberty of the group subject to the duty.30 By natural construction of the English language social repression31 can be described as the action of checking, restraining, keeping down the state of being active of that aggregate of people living together in a more or less ordered community known as society.32 For example, the grant of patent rights for the use of a yew extract in cancer therapy33 would impose a correlative duty on society not to use the yew extract for that purpose without the right holder’s permission. Some of the monopolist rights34 conveyed can impose severe and pervasive duties on society.35 Why then does the number and scope of monopolist rights continue to grow? statement as in German law one cannot, in principle, possess intangible property. A better analogy would be found in relation to Article 544 of the French Code Civil, as in French law apparently you can. 24 Emmert, ‘Intellectual property in the Uruguay Round – Negotiating strategies of the Western industrialised countries,’ Michigan Journal of International Law (1990) at p. 1318 25 A right is always against one or more individuals. 26 Cannot serve as a definition since examples of pre-eminent rights outside the ‘intellectual property’ sphere are too numerous. See for example Attorney General for Hong Kong v Reid [1994] 1 AC 324. On secondary rights in rem see Pretto, Birks and Pretto (eds), Themes in Comparative law [Oxford University Press, 1st Ed., 2002, Oxford] p.65-80 27 Demsetz, “Toward a Theory of Property Rights,” (1967) 57 American Economic Review Proceedings 347 28 Hohfeld, Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied to Judicial Reasoning [Yale University Press, 4th Ed., 1966, London] Chapter 1 29 It can be argued that in the case of a ‘negative copyright’ license that the right is potentially conveyed to the whole world, whilst the duty is on the party accepting the license. 30 “There is an obligation on the neighbour, and in that sense there is a corrolative right on the part of the owner of the first piece of land.” Per Viscount Haldane LC in Howley Park Coal Co v L. & N. W. Ry [1913] A.C. 11 at p. 25 31 New Shorter Oxford English Dictionary, 19997, Version 1.0.3, data version 2.10.96s 32 Campbell, Seven Theories of Human Society, Oxford University Press, 1980 33 http://www.cptech.org/ip/health/taxol/ 34 Maskus, 'Lessons from Studying the International Economics of Intellectual Property Rights,' Vanderbilt Law Review [2000] 53, p. 2219 35 Rights over Anti-AIDS cocktails have purported to obligate infected persons to death by withholding the right holders assent to the drugs use or production. See http://www.cptech.org/ip/health/aids/ Discourse by monopolist rights proponents continually furnishes reassurance that social benefit is dependant on monopolist rights.36 An example of the argument that humanity can only be stimulated37 through avarice is found in the sector of plant monopoly rights.38 These rights will be the focus of the rest of this paper. Following World War II increasing attention focused on world hunger and by the 1950’s reports of famine, maladies resulting from malnutrition, and statistics on deaths from starvation became increasingly available. Growing awareness of world food shortages coupled together with the astounding developments in biotechnology provided an excellent context for plant breeder and the infantile biotechnology companies to lobby for monopolist rights over plants. Their campaign was simple. It held that world hunger could be solved by creating High Yielding Varieties of staple crops39 thereby raising agricultural production per acre.40 They insisted the only way such crops could be created was through substantial investment.41 Investment that could only take place if a return on capital was guaranteed.42 A cure to world hunger, recognised as a profound affront to human dignity and human rights, quickly won over the sovereign powers and by 197043 the International Convention for the Protection of New Varieties of Plants44 provided a fledgling sui generis system for plant monopolist rights.45 High Yielding Varieties became available during the 1980’s. Requiring the extensive use of fertilizers and pesticides they quickly reduced the farmers of industrialized nations to dependence on the fertilizer and pesticide industry, conveniently under the control of the “…ability to invest huge sums in R&D depends upon strong patent protection…no one would make such investment without the prospect that their invention would enjoy a limited period of protection…” Sykes CEO Glaxo Wellcome. 37 For an economic perspective of ‘stimulation’ see Plant, “Economic Theory Concerning Patents for Inventions,” (1934) 1 Economica 30 at 42-44. 38 May be defined as that species of rights identifiable by reference to patents capable of expression in plants (plant patents) and the sui generis systems of right creation; ‘new plant varieties’ (PVR) and ‘plant breeders’ rights’ (PBR). 39 Blakeney, ‘Protection of Plant Varieties and Farmer’s Rights,’ European Intellectual Property Review [2002] 24(1), pp. 9-19 40 Hamilton, 'Who Owns Dinner: Evolving Legal Mechanisms for Ownership of Plant and Genetic Resources,' Tulsa Law Journal [1993] 28, p. 587 41 Labour theory 42 Economic theory 43 UPOV Convention came into force on the 10th of August 1968 after ratification by the United Kingdom, the Netherlands and Germany. 44 Adopted on the 2nd of December 1961 in Paris. Hereafter UPOV 45 Plant Breeders’ Rights (PBR) 36 biotechnology industry.46 Whilst these crops performed poorly in the lesser industrialised nations where there was insufficient wealth to obtain the necessary chemicals, food imports from the more industrialised nations increased in price and although a little diminished world hunger continued. By 1991 through constant lobbying and evidence of increased cereal productivity plant monopolist rights became established within national legislative frameworks. It was a short step to strengthen PBRs preventing farmers from replanting protected plant varieties.47 Seed costs increased dramatically and the disparity between the wealth of the most industrialised nations and the least industrialised nations grew. In the following decade plant variety rights were firmly entrenched in international legal constructs.48 The TRIPS Agreement49 through the auspices of the newly formed World Trade Organisation50 became the substantial tool for the introduction of plant monopoly rights.51 Its infamous article 27(3)(b) providing, “…However, Member States shall provide for the protection of plant varieties either by patents or by an effective sui generis system or by any combination thereof…”52 The European institutions have finally relented to the demands of the biotechnology industry for greater incentive, namely legislation that would make patents on life possible. In 1998 the European Parliament approved the life patents directive,53 the rhetoric of which states that, "the development of biotechnologies is important to developing countries, both in the field of health and … combating hunger…” 46 There is a large correspondence between the monopolist right holders of plant varieties and the respective pesticides and fertilizers optimal for that variety. 47 Greengrass, ‘The 1991 Act of the UPOV Convention,’ European Intellectual Property Review [1991] 13(12), pp. 466-472 48 Cullet, ‘Plant variety protection in Africa: towards compliance with the TRIPS Agreement,’ Journal of African Law [2001] 45(1), pp. 97-122 49 Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights, hereafter TRIPs. Signed 15th April 1994, Marrakesh, Agreement Establishing the World Trade Organization, Annex 1C, Legal Instruments, see Results of the Uruguay Round vol. 31, 33 I.L.M. 81 (1994). 50 By 2006 all countries, including the least industrialised nations, seeking membership of the WTO must have implemented TRIPS. Failure will result in extensive trade sanctions and severe reduction in financial assistance from the most industrialised nations, all of which are already WTO members. 51 Rives, ‘Mother Nature and the courts: Are sexually reproducing plants and their progeny patentable under the Utility Patent Act of 1952?’ Cumberland Law Review [2001-2002] p. 187 52 Aricle 27(3)(b) TRIPs 53 Directive 98/44/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council of 6 July 1998 on the legal protection of biotechnological inventions. http://www.copyrighter.ru/lite/index.html?eu98_44_eng.htm The EU directive is more extensive than the TRIPs Agreement54 compelling EU member states to offer patent protection for applications claiming essentially biological processes capable of expression within animals and plants. At present there are an estimated 815 million hungry people55 and the World’s population is continuing to expand. Estimates indicate that food output must increase by sixty percent within the next twenty-five years to maintain the current status of food distribution.56 Sampling indicates that each day approximately 400,000 people die from malnutrition.57 Assessment of the situation in 2000 and again in 2001 placed the decline rate of death at less than 8 million people per year.58 It is estimated that the global demand for staple foods, e.g. cereals, will increase by 20 per cent over the next fifteen years and that net staple food imports by developing countries59 will have to more than double if the gap between production and demand is to be closed.60 These findings appear irreconcilable with the International Food Policy Research Institute’s (IFPRI) 1999 study that concluded world food supply would continue to outpace population growth until 2020.61 Evidently there is a problem. It will be shown that a source of that problem is plant monopolist rights. That these rights hinder the productivity of societies beset by food shortages and raise the price of imports from the most industrialised nations. Section II will therefore focus on International Social Repression. Furthermore, the absurdity of introducing monopoly rights on self-replicating systems will be analysed. Section III will therefore consider National Social Repression. WTO, Council for TRIPs, ‘Review of Article 27.3 (b) Communication from Brazil,’ Doc.IP/C/W/228, 24th November 2000. 55 2002 United Nations Food and Agriculture Organisation (FAO) Data, see http://www.fao.org/ag/ 56 Sadly that leaves about 36 million people still dying from hunger, directly or indirectly, every year. Siegler 57 2002 United Nations Food and Agriculture Organisation (FAO) Data, see http://www.fao.org/ag/ 58 FAO, "Global meeting to assess progress on World Food Summit goals", < www.fao.org/news>. 59 I. Serageldin and G. J. Pursley, Promethean Science. Agricultural Biotechnology, the Environment and the Poor (Washington: CGIAR, 2000), p. 3. 60 P. Pinstrup-Andersen, R. Pandya-Lorch and M. W. Rosegrant, World Food Prospects: Critical Issues for the Early Twenty First Century (Washington, D.C.: International Food Policy Research Institute, 1999), Chap. 1. 61 Ibid. 54 2. International Social Repression. As has been indicated there are two vehicles for generating plant monopolist rights. These are by patents or the sui generis systems.62 The requirements and scope of rights generated under each will be addressed briefly and the problems identified. Until the development of modern biotechnological methods plant patents were not available. It was considered that the breeding of a new variety did not involve an inventive step. Since in all patent systems an inventive step is fundamental to the notion of an invention, new plant varieties were considered to be obvious rather than inventive and failed to qualify for monopolist rights.63 Nevertheless, biotechnological knowledge rapidly advanced to recombinant methods for producing transgenic plants and the right awarding authorities, taking a more favourable view of expanding the monopoly right domain, began to consider the results ‘non-obvious.’ A moral quandary ensued resulting in article 53(b) of the European Patent Convention64 that excludes the award of a patent on,65 “plant and animal varieties and essentially biological processes for the production of plants and animals.” Although plant patents were considered ‘contrary to the public order or morality’ and incapable of being patented, lobbying continued in Brussels.66 The European Commission under great pressure from biotechnology lobbyists drafted a directive that was rejected by the 62 In countries implementing UPOV 1961 attempts are often made to avoid the double award of plant monopoly rights under both patent and the sui generis system. The usual technique is to exclude plant varieties from the award of a patent. Howver note the observance by the Enlarged Board of Appeal in T1054/96 NOVARTIS/Transgenic plant [1999] E.P.O.R. 123 (EPO). 63 Hamilton, 'Who Owns Dinner: Evolving Legal Mechanisms for Ownership of Plant and Genetic Resources,' Tulsa Law Journal [1993] 28, p. 587 64 Current EPC members are: Austria, Belgium, Cyprus, Denmark, Finland, France, Germany, Greece, Ireland, Italy, Liechtenstein, Luxembourg, Monaco, Netherlands, Portugal, Spain, Sweden, Switzerland, Turkey, and the United Kingdom 65 Chambers, ‘Patent eligibility of biotechnological inventions in the United States, Europe, and Japan: How much patent policy is public policy,’ George Washington International Law Review [2002] p. 223 66 Seat of European Parliament and Commission, Rue de la Loi 200, 1049 Brussels, Belgium European Parliament. Undaunted lobbying increased adopting the slogan ‘No patent no cure,’ and finally the European Parliament approved Directive 98/44/EC.67 Article 4.1 of Directive 98/44/EC provides, 68 “The following shall not be patentable: (a) plant and animal varieties; (b) essentially biological processes for the production of plants or animals.” However Article 4.2 of Directive states, “Inventions which concern plants or animals shall be patentable if the technical feasibility of the invention is not confined to a particular plant or animal variety.” The practical effect of the Article taken as a whole is to permit patents on plants that qualify as inventions, whilst refusing the award of plant patents for a variety itself. Thus, the patent application must relate to a characteristic expressed in a plant. It will be noted that plant patents do not have to involve a new outcome but merely a novel manipulation of plant genomic material producing a claimed effect in more than one plant variety. For example, consider the natural process, A B A modification of the process of arriving from A to B within the plant providing that the modification itself was novel, involved an inventive step and was capable of industrial application would result in a patent grant. This can be conceptualised in a number of ways including, A B or A AB B Under this regime it is possible for a person69 to own a plant, or more precisely every plant with certain characteristics. As would be expected from the application of the static security theorem70 the characteristics that are the subject of the plant patent are invariably dominant. 67 Directive 98/44/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council of 6 July 1998 on the legal protection of biotechnological inventions. 68 http://www.copyrighter.ru/lite/index.html?eu98_44_eng.htm 69 Natural person or ens legis. Dominance in the context of a genetic trait means that during the coding phase dominant traits will be coded in preference to recessive traits, thus the dominant trait is more likely to propetuate through successive progeny. This can be illustrated by considering four plants with three different characteristics.71 Of these characteristics A is a dominant modified gene whilst B and C are both recessive genes. As depicted the dominant A gene expresses itself in each subsequent generation. The wealth of genes present in the initial plants are rapidly supplanted until only the dominant A gene, the subject of the monopolist right, remains. In practice the result of introducing strongly dominant genes into plants reduces biodiversity leading to the eradication of many genes. Since the manipulation of genetic material must have an effect, the application claim, the number of loci manipulated have to be sufficient to lead to an expression of the claimed trait. Recessive traits displaced are lost from the environment. Thus, the situation can arise where fields, the principle source of sustenance for a community, consists only of AA plants. If one year AA suffers bacterial blight then as a result the community produces no food. Had the AA not been introduced into the environment the community would have been able to subsist on one of the eighty other types of the plant that would not have been effected by the blight. This is one example of the dangers of diminishing biodiversity72 in lesser industrialized nations.73 70 That property is valueless unless it can be retained AB and AC have the same characteristic 72 Another problem of agricultural chemical use is that in the least industrialised regions of the world those plants that plants that the most industrialised nations regard as weed provide food, fodder and medicine. Hope Shand, "Harvesting Diversity", RAFI, 1997 In Indian 150 different species of plants are used for vegetables, fodder and health care. 124 of these are classed by agricultural biotechnology companies as ‘weeds.’ “In the Expana region of Veracruz, Mexico, peasants utilise about 435 wild plant and animal species of which 229 are eaten.” UNDP, Agroecology: Creating the Synerginism for a Sustainable Agriculture, 1995 73 Blakeney, ‘Protection of Plant Varieties and Farmer’s Rights,’ European Intellectual Property Review [2002] 24(1), pp. 9-19 71 Consider the situation where there is no blight and the AA plant has become predominant in the community’s crops. Assume the AA modification leads to greater photosynthesis, but requires a much greater uptake of magnesium by the plant. The soil unless treated with chemicals will eventually become too poor to grow the AA modified plants.74 Fertilizers are too expensive75 and the AA modification has become predominant in all the community’s crop types for sufficient rotation. The community is likely to suffer a food shortage. This is an example of how a prima facie beneficial modification can have devastating effect amongst the communities of lesser industrialised nations.76 Since over 1.3 billion of the world's population have daily incomes lower than $1.00 US, communities in the poorest regions77 of the world have no security for bad harvests.78 If crops fail, whether through blight, soil erosion, or other causes these populations die. Further difficulties derive from Article 102 of the United States Patent Act 1952.79 This article, defining ‘prior art,’ states, “...A person shall be entitled to a patent unless: The invention was known or used by others in this country or patented or described in a publication in this or a foreign country before the invention thereof by the applicant for patent... The invention was patented or described in a trade publication in this or a foreign country or in public use or on sale in this country more than one year prior to the date of the application for patent in the United States.” 74 It has been found that Round Up Ready crops, as they require the use of the potent herbicide Round Up, considerably reduce biodiversity. The consequence is that farmers cannot use cover crops and crop mixtures for soil conservation leading to accelerated soil erosion. Of course the soil can be adequately replenished through the purchase of the appropriate fertilizers. 75 In lesser industrialised nations farmers harvest small plots of land and grow little more than they need to subsist. 76 Blakeney, ‘Intellectual property rights and global food security,’ BIO-Science Law Review [2000/2001] 4(4), pp. 127-140 77 Gonzalez, ‘Institutionalising inequality: The WTO agreement on agriculture, food security, and developing countries,’ Columbia Journal of Environmental Law [2002] p. 433 78 Ngugi, ‘Making new wine for old wineskins: Can reform of the international law emancipate the third world in the age of globalisation?’ U.C. Davis Journal of International Law and Policy [2002] p.73 79 35 USC 1952 Knowledge or use of the subject of application in a country other than the United States does not constitute ‘prior art’ for the purposes of United States patent law. 80 This refusal permits the grant of patents on existing knowledge.81 Hence, the United States can take knowledge82 from other countries, patent it, and then protect this knowledge through the award of monopolist rights.83 A well-known example is the United States patent for the yellow bean alleged to be the Mexican Enola bean.84 The International Centre for Tropical Agriculture challenged the patent producing evidence that the subject of the application was substantially identical to six bean samples with yellow seeds held within its records and originating from Mexico. In the light of such evidence it seems irrefutable that the yellow bean, the subject of the application, was taken from Mexico. Had the United States ratified the Convention on Biodiversity the genetic material should have been the property of Mexico, the patent however still remains. The consequence of the scenario is that import to the United States of material bearing the monopolised characteristics of the yellow bean will infringe the US patent. Thus the patent holder is able to restrict the import of certain crops or charge a royalty. The question of whether the patent holder exerts any rights over a product derived from a plant that incorporated a monopolised gene has not yet been adequately resolved.85 Another event that has caused controversy concerns a blight resistant strain of wild rice. In 1996 the Regents of the University of California filed a patent application for "Nucleic acids, from Oryza sativa, which encode leucine-rich repeat polypeptides and enhance Xanthomonas resistance in plants". The patent was granted in 1999 by the United States Patent Office. Identification of the single locus Xa21 gene, responsible for blight resistance, had been achieved by the International Rice Research Institute86 from gemoplasm they held in their archives. 80 For example U.S. Patent No. 5,900,240 granted to Cromak Research Inc. Often referred to as biopiracy. 82 Which is not patented or described in a publication in a foreign jurisdiction 83 Machlup, An Economic Review of the Patent System, 85th Congress, 2nd Session, United States Senate Subcommittee on Patent, Trademarks and Copyrights, 1958 84 RAFI, "Enola Bean Patent Challenged", News Release, January 5, 2001 www.rafi.org. 85 Bai, ‘Commentary, Protecting Plant Varieties under TRIPS and NAFTA: Should Utility Patents Be Available for Plants?’ Texas International Law Journal [1997] 32, pp. 139-147 86 IRRI 81 The source of this germoplasm was the wild rice Oryza longistaminata grown in Mali by poor subsistence farmers.87 The result of the US patent is again that rice incorporating the gene cannot be imported to the United States without the patent holder’s permission.88 The sui generis systems, by which plant monopoly rights can be obtained, are Plant Breeders Rights,89 National Breeders Rights90 and Community Plant Variety Rights.91 The monopolist rights generated are of a similar nature and raise the same issues. Plant Breeders’ Rights as administered under UPOV92 are by far the most important93 sui generis system of protection and as a result will be addressed briefly. Plant variety under UPOV is defined by Article 1(vi) of the International Convention for the Protection of New Varieties of Plants which states, "...a plant grouping within a single botanical taxon of the lowest known rank, which grouping, ... can be defined by the expression of the characteristics resulting from a given genotype or combination of genotypes, distinguished from any other plant grouping by the expression of at least one of the said characteristics and considered as a unit with regard to its suitability for being propagated unchanged." To be eligible for protection a plant variety must be new,94 distinct,95 uniform96 and stable.97 At present in the US genetic material can be used and made ‘property’ without acknowledgement of its source. WTO "Review of the Provisions of Article 27.3b) Further Views of the United States of America", Doc. IP/C/W/209, 20th September 2000. pp. 2-3, 5 88 Blakeney, ‘Protection of Plant Varieties and Farmer’s Rights,’ European Intellectual Property Review [2002] 24(1), pp. 9-19 89 Plant Breeders' Rights relate to a series of laws under which a person who develops a unique plant variety can maintain a degree of control over that variety, while allowing other plant breeders to use the protected material to develop still more advanced varieties. http://www.swiftt.cornell.edu/ipcourse/modules/pbr/summary.html 90 Article 92(1) of European Council Regulation 2100/94 proscribes protection for the same variety under both Community Plant Variety Rights and national breeders' rights, however Article 3 of the Regulation provides that member states can continue to provide national breeders' rights. Thus whilst protection for a specific variety cannot be duplicated the two systems can run concurrently. This places the financial burden on the private party should the party elect for protection under the Community Plant Variety Rights rather than national breeders' rights. 91 Articles 1-35 Council Regulation 2100/94, 1994 Official Journal of the European Communities at page L227/1. For a commentary see Millett, ‘The Community System of Plant Variety Rights,’ European Law Review (1999) 24, p. 231; van der Kooij, Introduction to the EC Regulation on Plant Variety Protection [Kluwer Law International, 2nd Ed., 1997, Boston] 92 International Union for the Protection of New Varieties of Plants 93 On the 15th January 2003 52 States were party to the International Convention For the Protection of New Varieties of Plants. See http://www.upov.int/en/about/members/index.htm (last accessed 5th February 2003) 94 Article 5(1)(i) UPOV 1991; The variety shall be deemed to be new if, at the date of filing of the application for a breeder's right, propagating or harvested material of the variety has not been sold or 87 Unlike patents plant variety rights act on the physical propagating material and as such are specific only to a particular registered variety. This results in a preference by agricultural biotechnology companies for the broader ambit of patents. Furthermore the patent carries with it greater repressive power as it imposes greater obligations on society than plant variety rights. 3. National Social Repression. Under Article 14 of the UPOV Convention 1991 production or reproduction, conditioning for the purpose of propagation, offering for sale, selling or marketing, exporting, importing or stocking for any of these purposes are all forbidden without authorization from the ‘breeder.’98 There are however a number of exceptions provided for under the following article. Article 15, Exceptions to the Breeder's Right, provides, “(1) [Compulsory exceptions] The breeder's right shall not extend to (i) acts done privately and for non-commercial purposes, (ii) acts done for experimental purposes and (iii) acts done for the purpose of breeding other varieties, and, except where the provisions of Article 14(5) apply, acts referred to in Article 14(1) to Article 14(4) in respect of such other varieties.” otherwise disposed of to others, by or with the consent of the breeder, for purposes of exploitation of the variety Article 6(1) UPOV 1991 95 Article 5(1)(ii) UPOV 1991; The variety shall be deemed to be distinct if it is clearly distinguishable from any other variety whose existence is a matter of common knowledge at the time of the filing of the application. In particular, the filing of an application for the granting of a breeder's right or for the entering of another variety in an official register of varieties, in any country, shall be deemed to render that other variety a matter of common knowledge from the date of the application, provided that the application leads to the granting of a breeder's right or to the entering of the said other variety in the official register of varieties, as the case may be. Article 7 UPOV 1991 96 Article 5(1)(iii) UPOV 1991; The variety shall be deemed to be uniform if, subject to the variation that may be expected from the particular features of its propagation, it is sufficiently uniform in its relevant characteristics. Article 8 UPOV 1991 97 Article 5(1)(iv) UPOV 1991; The variety shall be deemed to be stable if its relevant characteristics remain unchanged after repeated propagation or, in the case of a particular cycle of propagation, at the end of each such cycle. Article 9 UPOV 1991 98 Article 1(iv) UPOV 1991, “…the person who bred, or discovered and developed, a variety; the person who is the employer of the aforementioned person or who has commissioned the latter's work, where the laws of the relevant Contracting Party so provide, or the successor in title of the first or second aforementioned person, as the case may be.” Although exemptions (i) and (ii) are analogous to the limitations on an infringement action under patent legislation acts that would fall under exemption (iii) of the convention would fall foul of patent provisions. For example in the United Kingdom, a jurisdiction regarded as preferential to the status of its farmers, the patent act contains a restriction on infringement actions. It provides, “An act which…would constitute an infringement…shall not do so if…it consists of the use by a farmer of the product of his harvest for propagation or multiplication by him on his own holding, where there has been a sale of plant propagating material to the farmer by the proprietor of the patent or with his consent for agricultural use…”99 Not all jurisdictions possess a patent infringement limitation clause and in those that do the clause is never obligatory.100 Surveys will show that the clause only permits farmers to grow the first crop for sale and that subsequent crops are not authorised and will thus constitute infringement of the seed companies monopoly right. Indeed it is the standard practice of agricultural seed giants101 to impose a contractual term102 requiring the farmer to purchase new seeds each year. Since ten largest seed companies control 30% of the $24.4 billion commercial seed market farmers have little choice in the terms of contractual terms.103 For over ten-millennium farmers have saved the seeds of the previous harvest for the sowing of the next. Many farmers, particularly those with smaller holdings and crops of less value per unit, continue to depend upon the ability to retain a percentage of their seed from which they can grow the next crop.104 However, farmers can be held to infringe monopoly holders’ rights without a positive act. Unlike with all other forms of monopoly rights self-replicating inventions can replicate 99 §60(5)(g) United Kingdom Patent Act 1977 (as amended) Patent provisions survey conducted by the author on Westlaw in December 2002 101 Contractual terms of GM crop seed can be obtained by request to Monsanto UK Limited, The Maris Centre, 45 Hauxton Road, Trumpington, Cambridge, CB2 2LQ 102 “Farmers buying Monsanto's seed must sign a contract promising to buy fresh seed every year. And they must let Monsanto inspect their fields." Dave Margoshes, Vancouver Sun, 14th August 1999. 103 ETC (formerly RAFI): ‘Globalization, Inc. - Concentration in Corporate Power: the Unmentioned Agenda,’ www.rafi.org (accessed 24th September 2001) 104 The Rural Advancement Foundation International (NGO) http://www.rafi.ca. 100 without an ‘illegal act’ being perpetrated by a legal person or by an agent under a legal persons control. A fundamental characteristic of monopolist rights systems is that they are premised on a presumption of mala fides. Thus, with plant monopoly rights the production without authorization of a patented object will constitute infringement. Consider field A, which contains GM canola. It is several miles from field B, but wind carried pollen from field A fertilizes field B’s non GM canola. Seed is gathered from field B and eventually some of it is resown to provide the next years crop. The seed germinates and field B now contains a proportion of GM crop. This crop does not fall under any exemptions from infringement. Nor does it matter whether the owner of field B knew of the crops contamination. The owner of field B has infringed the monopoly right holder’s right. In 1999 Monsanto brought an infringement action against Schmeiser seeking damages105 for the 320 hectares of his land contaminated by Monsanto's herbicide-resistant Roundup Ready canola. Schmeiser insisted that company seed could easily have blown on to his soil from passing canola-laden trucks. He claimed, “I never put those plants on my land.” However, monopolist rights premised on the basis of mala fides make no distinction between the innocent infringer and the guilty.106 Some practitioners hold, that this would not be the case in the United Kingdom, as with a plant patent the farmer would have to take advantage of the patents function in order to infringe the monopolist right holder’s right. If the practitioners’ holding is correct then in the case of Monsanto's herbicide-resistant Roundup Ready canola a farmer would only infringe Monsanto’s patent if they sprayed a glycophosphate herbicide. However, what if the monopolistic right was for an application involving improved drought resistance,107 greater water absorption,108 or greater temperature 105 Monsanto sought patent infringement damages totaling $400,000. This was comprised of; $250,000 in legal fees, $105,000 account of profits, $13,500 ($15 an acre) for technology fees and $25,000 in punitive damages. http://www.percyschmeiser.com/ 106 In terms of damages some jurisdictions do contain the clause limiting exemplary damages without prejudice to other remedies. For a farmer who makes a substantial investment on each year’s crop and who suddenly finds that their crop is another’s property is perhaps little concerned with fine distinctions between mere damages and combined damages. 107 Zhu, ‘Salt and drought stress signal transducing in plants,’ Annual Review of Plant Physiology and Plant Molecular Biology [2002] 52, pp. 247-273 108 Steudle, ‘The cohesion-tension mechanism and the acquisition of water by plant roots,’ Annual Review of Plant Physiology and Plant Molecular Biology [2001] 52, pp. 847-875 resistance109 the farmer unless destroying the crop immediately would have no choice but to infringe the plant patent. Removal of crops is not always a possibility and not merely due to economical considerations. Many GM varieties do not differ to the naked eye from unmodified crops. To the untrained eye the same might be said of a new plant variety. The current monopolist right systems impose on farmers the duty of countermanding nature or should that fail to identify the monopolistic right contaminated crop from their own uninfected crop. In fact, even for the holders of monopoly rights identifying the subjects of their plant monopoly rights can be a difficult task. Unsatisfied with the already imposing legal machinery at their behest they have resorted to other methods of ensuring their sovereign position in the food chain. Genetic Use Restriction Technologies (GURTs), known more appropriately as death seed, do not produce fertile seed. As a result farmers may not save seeds, nor can they benefit from the genetic material of the plant through further breeding. Each time the farmer wishes to plant a crop incorporating the death seed gene they must purchase it directly from the biotechnology company or its agents. Not only does the conception of GURTs seem abhorrent, but when placed in the context of a vendor consumer relationship it will be seen that the biotechnology company poses a monopoly unaffected by perpetuity rules. The GURT is not a monopoly right in a legal sense it is a perverse modification of nature. It does however show that avarice and greed are perhaps not the best stimulus for today’s research institutions. It would have been expected that manipulations designed to inhibit plant fertility would be outlawed. However in the United States Delta and Pine Land110 and the United States Department of Agriculture market seed111 which has been genetically engineered to ensure that it does not germinate on harvest thus forcing farmers to buy seed at each planting season. The presence of this technology serves as an arm of economic repression. The sole purpose of the technology is to expand monopolist rights. An argument ad baculum has become frequently employed it states that, Iba, ‘Acclimative response to temperature stress in higher plants: Approaches of gene engineering for temperature tolerance,’ Annual Review of Plant Physiology and Plant Molecular Biology [2002] 53, pp. 225-245 110 Now controlled by Monsanto 111 See US patent No.5723785 109 “Should a State fail to establish an effective and well balanced system for the protection of plant varieties as foreseen by the UPOV Convention, breeders might wish to resort to other mechanisms, such as GURTs, to assure their economic interests.”112 If legitimacy is possible in monopolistic rights and if it is to be obtained then the ‘moral and ethical consequences of innovations’ should be dealt with by forbidding the grant of monopoly rights where necessary and prohibiting the use of technologies contrary to societies benefit. 4. Conclusion The difficulties inflicted on the developing countries by monopolist rights are the result of a complex web of interacting factors.113 Nevertheless the principal components might be identified as the lack of economic security114 and the forced dependence of the lesser industrialised nations on the most industrialised nations.115 It is interesting to note that trade with lesser industrialised nations produced record profits for multinational biotechnology corporations while increasing rural poverty116 and fuelling further social dislocation in the lesser developed countries.117 Monsanto and the Biotechnology industry still hold that,118 “without genetic engineering the world cannot be fed.”119 112 Memorandum Prepared by the Office of UPOV on the Genetic Use Restriction Technologies, 10 th January 2003 http://www.upov.int/en/about/key_issues.htm (last accessed 5th February 2003) 113 U.N. Food & Agric. Org. (FAO), FAO Symposium on Agriculture, Trade and Food Security, Paper No. 3: Experience with the Implementation of the Uruguay Round Agreement on Agriculture: Developing Country Experiences available at http://www.fao.org/DOCREP/meeting/x3065E.htm 114 World Bank, Poverty And Hunger: Issues And Options For Food Security In Developing Countries (1986). 115 Gonzalez, ‘Institutionalising inequality: The WTO agreement on agriculture, food security, and developing countries,’ Columbia Journal of Environmental Law [2002] p. 433 116 Deen, A Richer World Keeps Failing to End Hunger, Says U.N. http://www.proutworld.org/news/en/2002/oct/20021028ari.htm (accessed 13th February 2003) 117 Maskus, 'Lessons from Studying the International Economics of Intellectual Property Rights,' Vanderbilt Law Review [2000] 53, p. 2219 118 Transcript from speech delivered by Hendrik Verfaillie, President, Monsanto at the Forum on Nature and Human Society, National Academy of Sciences, Washington D.C. 30 th of October 1997. Available from http://www.monsanto.co.uk/ 119 Spinney, ‘Biotechnology in Crops: Issues for the developing world,’ Research paper for Oxfam GB, May 98 They hold that to meet the food security needs of the coming decade there is a need to increase agricultural productivity on presently available land.120 They draw on statistics from 1960 to 1990121 showing the increasing productivity of cereals and expansion of arable land through enormous increases in fertiliser and insecticide use. The statistics concern agricultural output from the more industrialised nations they take little account of food production in the least industrialised nations. The IFPRI’s 1999 study showed that there was sufficient food produced to eradicate world hunger. The difficulty lies in distributing food to those regions in need. The wealth of these regions has to be increased and public122 distribution systems implemented. Granting monopolist rights has the result of shrinking state distribution systems or inhibiting their development. Food security involves ensuring the access of people to nutritious foods at affordable prices. The increased productivity of a cereal plant is not of great relevance to someone who cannot afford its fruit. Food ought to be a human right and its systematic destruction whether to maintain market prices or as a remedy to monopolist right infringement ought to be outlawed. A suggestion is that rather than granting plant monopoly rights research could be undertaken by public institutions in a none proprietary regime. Funding could be drawn from the proportion of society and societies with the greatest wealth.123 Cataloguing and creation of gene libraries would be facilitated since institutions would have no inhibitions to sharing and joint research. Beneficial technologies could be applied almost immediately and without the imposition of royalties. A non-proprietary system would lead to greater transparency whereby the issues of morality, societal need and biodiversity might be discussed on an equal footing. Another suggestion that has generated considerable support in the least industrialised nations is to remove food and agriculture from the ambit of the WTO. This would permit government 120 In 2000 Monsanto's genetically engineered seed accounted for 94% of the total area sown to GM crops. ETC (formerly RAFI): ‘Globalization, Inc. - Concentration in Corporate Power: the Unmentioned Agenda,’ www.rafi.org (accessed 24th September 2001) c.f. http://www.monsanto.co.uk/ 121 Described as the ‘Green Revolution.’ 122 Montesqu’s distinction between civil and public. The United Nations FAO, or the WHO would qualify. 123 The more industrialised nations are empirically observed to cope with property rights on agricultural products better than less industrialised nations. They have the greatest security in terms of purchasing power and therefore food. Redistribution of this wealth would permit the industrialisation of less industrialised nations, whilst by application of the labour theorem stimulate more activity in the most developed countries as unearned increment would be reduced. of food and agriculture by principles of food sovereignty and not by principles misleadingly presented as ‘free-trade.’ For societies with little wealth or industrialisation the benefits of added costs to food is highly questionable. Even for industrialised nations the issues of monopolistic rights on food are laden with difficulties. For example, the imposition of monopolistic rights developed in the context of mechanical inventions on self-replicating objects is wholly bizarre. Not only is it perverse with regard to the natural order of the plant kingdom, it is contrary to the justifications for property. Granting plant monopolistic rights effects the autonomy of everyone.124 Dominium over things is imperium over other human beings.125 If a farmer must destroy their crop, or pay royalties on its sale due to an irresistible process of nature why should they labour to produce? Surely, it would be safer for them to simply build on their land and rent it.126 According to the labour theory, incentive to innovate and research is dependant on the award of wealth. It is evident that plant breeding and selection have been conducted since the days of Catal Hüyük in 6,000 B.C.;127 by comparison, plant monopoly rights are a very recent institution. However, if the labour theorem is correct surely it would seem sensible only to grant monopoly rights that are related to a product that is wholly within the public interest. Thus, a person would be encouraged to develop only those things that society required. This would not prevent the advancement of technology, as objects identified or discovered along the way would not be laden with notions of proprietorship and wealth. They would instead be free for use or incorporation by everyone. A notion of focusing the boundaries on what can qualify for monopolistic rights is not a notion alien to the Western conception of monopoly rights. A mathematical formula or the discovery of natural phenomena, it will be recalled, are not capable of being owned.128 Except, that is by society or rather all societies, as a whole. For intangible objects, this must be the purest form of personal autonomy. 124 By direct construction of rights it will be observed that the imposition by an individual on a product produced by another that also bears some rights of the other results in a direct transmutation of the primary obligation through the other. E.g. if a plant costs a farmer Ŧ per unit then the farmer will charge Ŧ + ε per unit. 125 Cohan, ‘Property and Sovereignty,’ p. 13 126 After all it has been shown that unearned increment is the greatest source of wealth. See Davenport, ‘Extent and significance of Unearned Increment,” Bulletin of the American Economic Association, Series 4, No.2 (1911) c.f. Cohen, ‘Property and Sovereignty’ 127 Helbaek, ‘First impressions of the Çatal Hüyük plant husbandry,’ Anatolian Studies [1964] 14, pp. 121-3. 128 The attribution of gratitude and honour is distinct from notions of ownership as the former lack the right to exclude others. In regard to the labour theory, it ought to be noted that whilst proponents of monopoly rights argue for financial remuneration many of humankind's greatest successes were performed for the good of humanity. As Hume indicated it is property that detracts humankind from their humanity.129 129 In the absence of plant monopoly rights would GURTs have ever been imposed on society? Bibliography Books Albert, Capitalisme contre capitalisme [Éditions du Seuil, 1st ed., 1991, Paris] Audi, Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy [Cambridge University Press, 2nd ed., 1999, Cambridge] Bar-Yaacov, Handling of International Disputes by Means of Inquiry [Oxford University Press, 1st Ed., 1974, London] pp. 248-321 Bettig, Copyrighting Culture [Westview Press, 1st Ed., 1996, Oxford] pp. 1-8, 33-77, 103-110, 117-150, 179- 181, 195-200 Blakeney, Trade Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights. A Concise Guide to the TRIPs Agreement [Sweet & Maxwell, 1st Ed., 1996, London] Cornish, Intellectual Property: Patents, Copyright, Trade Marks and Allied Rights [Sweet & Maxwell, 4th ed., 1999, London] Demaret, Patents, Territorial Restrictions and EEC Law, IIC Studies, 1978, Chap. 1 Drahos, A Philosophy of Intellectual Property [Dartmouth, 1st ed., 1996, Aldershot] Dyer and Mangasarian, Study of International Relations: The State of the Art [Macmillan, 1st Ed., 1989, London] EC Commission, Research and Training Programme in Biomolecular Engineering (April 1982 – 1986): Progress Report 1984 [EC Commission, 1st Ed., 1985, Luxemberg] Frankel and Bennett, Genetic Resources in Plants – Their Exploitation and Conservation [Blackwell Scientific Publications, 1st Ed., 1970, Oxford] Hohfeld, Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied to Judicial Reasoning [Yale University Press, 4th Ed., 1966, London] Honoré, (Guest eds), Oxford Essay in Jurisprudence [Clarendon Press, 1st ed., 1961, Oxford] pp. 107-147 Hortmann, Relations of Nations [Macmillan Company, 2nd Ed., 1964, New York] Hume, Enquiries concerning human understanding and concerning the principles of morals, (Re-printed) [Clarendon Press, 3rd Ed., 2002, Oxford] Hutchinson, The application of genetics to cotton improvement [Cambridge University Press, 1st ed., 1999, London] Jouanneau, Le GATT et l’Organisation Mondiale du Commerce [Presses Universitaires de France, 3rd ed., 1996, Paris] Mandell, Mathews, McKee, Principles of Biotechnology: An Introduction to Genetic Engineering in Plants [Blackwell Scientific Publications, 1st Ed., 1985, Oxford] Miller, Nature, Justice, and Rights in Aristotle's Politics [Oxford University Press, 1st Ed., 1995, Oxford] Miller, The Nature of Political Theory [Oxford University Press, 1st Ed., 1983, Oxford] Pretto, Birks and Pretto (eds), Themes in Comparative law [Oxford University Press, 1st Ed., 2002, Oxford] p.65-80 Quick, Graeme, and Buchele. The Grain Harvesters., [MI: American Society of Agricultural Engineers, 1st Ed., 1978, St. Joseph] p. 2 Rawls, A Theory of Justice [Harvard University Press, 8th ed., 1999, Cambridge MA] Rosenau, Scientific Study of Foreign Policy [Free Press, 1st Ed., 1971, New York] pp. 23-273, 307-338, 401-461 Scherer and D. Ross, Industrial Market Structure and Economic Performance, 1990, at p. 682 Sullivan, International Relations: Theories and Evidence [Prentice Hall, 1st Ed., 1976, New Jersey] van der Kooij, Introduction to the EC Regulation on Plant Variety Protection [Kluwer Law International, 2nd Ed., 1997, Boston] Whyte, Crop Production and Environment [Faber and Faber, 2nd Ed., 1960, London] Articles Adewopo, ‘The Global Intellectual Property System and Sub-Saharan Africa,’ University of Toledo Law Review [2002] p. 749 Bai, ‘Commentary, Protecting Plant Varieties under TRIPS and NAFTA: Should Utility Patents Be Available for Plants?’ Texas International Law Journal [1997] 32, pp. 139-147 Bhutani and Kothari, ‘The biodiversity rights of developing nations: A perspective from India,’ Golden Gate University Law Review [2002] p. 587 Blair, ‘Intellectual Property Protection and Its Impact on the U.S. Seed Industry,’ Drake Journal of Agricultural Law [1999] 4, pp. 297-298 Blakeney, ‘Access to genetic resources: the view from the South,’ BIO-Science Law Review [1997] 3, pp. 94-100 Blakeney, ‘Australia: plant variety rights,’ Commonwealth Law Bulletin [1988] 14(1), pp.305-307 Blakeney, ‘Intellectual property rights and global food security,’ BIO-Science Law Review [2000/2001] 4(4), pp. 127-140 Blakeney, ‘Protection of Plant Varieties and Farmer’s Rights,’ European Intellectual Property Review [2002] 24(1), pp. 9-19 Braga, ‘The economics of intellectual property rights and the GATT: A view from the South,’ Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law [1989] p.243 Bresson, Bohnert, Hasegawa, Zhu, ‘Plant cellular and molecular responses to high salinity,’ Annual Review of Plant Physiology and Plant Molecular Biology [2000] 51, pp. 463-499 Byrne, ‘Plant breeding and the UPOV,’ Review of European Community and International Environmental Law [1993] 2(2), pp. 136-140 Byrne, ‘Revising the UPOV Convention,’ Intellectual Property in Business Review [1991] 3(4), pp. 26-28 Carroll, ‘Not always the best medicine: Biotechnology and the global impact of U.S. patent law,’ American University Law Review [1995] p. 2433 Chambers, ‘Patent eligibility of biotechnological inventions in the United States, Europe, and Japan: How much patent policy is public policy,’ George Washington International Law Review [2002] p. 223 Cohen, ‘Property and Sovereignty,’ Cornell Law Quarterly [1927] 13, p. 8 Cullet, ‘Plant variety protection in Africa: towards compliance with the TRIPS Agreement,’ Journal of African Law [2001] 45(1), pp. 97-122 Drahos, ‘Indigenous knowledge biopiracy: Is a global bio-collecting society the answer?’ European Intellectual Property Review [2000] 22(6), pp. 245-250 Drahos, ‘Intellectual Property and Human Rights,’ Intellectual Property Quarterly [1999] 3, p. 349. Emmert, ‘Intellectual property in the Uruguay Round – Negotiating strategies of the Western industrialised countries,’ Michigan Journal of International Law [1990] p. 1317 Machlup, An Economic Review of the Patent System, 85th Congress, 2nd Session, United States Senate Subcommittee on Patent, Trademarks and Copyrights, 1958, pp. 79-80. Fagard and Vaucheret, ‘(Trans) gene silencing in plants: How many mechanisms?’ Annual Review of Plant Physiology and Plant Molecular Biology [2000] 51, pp. 167-194 Gonzalez, ‘Institutionalising inequality: The WTO agreement on agriculture, food security, and developing countries,’ Columbia Journal of Environmental Law [2002] p. 433 Goss, Comment, ‘Guiding the Hand That Feeds: Toward Socially Optimal Appropriability in Agricultural Biotechnology Innovation,’ California Law Review [1996] 84, pp. 1395, 1397 Greengrass, ‘The 1991 Act of the UPOV Convention,’ European Intellectual Property Review [1991] 13(12), pp. 466-472 Demsetz, “Toward a Theory of Property Rights,” (1967) 57 American Economic Review Proceedings 347 Hamilton, 'Who Owns Dinner: Evolving Legal Mechanisms for Ownership of Plant and Genetic Resources,' Tulsa Law Journal [1993] 28, p. 587 Heitz, ‘Intellectual property in new plant varieties and biotechnological inventions,’ European Intellectual Property Review [1988] 10(10), pp. 297-301 Helbaek, ‘First impressions of the Çatal Hüyük plant husbandry,’ Anatolian Studies [1964] 14, pp. 121-3. Iba, ‘Acclimative response to temperature stress in higher plants: Approaches of gene engineering for temperature tolerance,’ Annual Review of Plant Physiology and Plant Molecular Biology [2002] 53, pp. 225-245 Janis and Kesan, ‘U.S. plant variety protection: Sound and fury…?’ Houston Law Review [2002] p. 727 Janis, ‘Sustainable agriculture, patent rights, and plant innovation,’ Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies [2001] p. 91 Kowalski and Kryder, ‘Golden rice: A case study in intellectual property management and international capacity building,’ Risk: Health, Safety and Environment [2002] p. 47 Ling, ‘Legislative features of China's newly enforced law for the protection of new Llewelyn, ‘Patentability of biological material: continuing contradiction and confusion,’ European Intellectual Property Review [2000] 22(5), pp. 191-197 Mansfield, ‘Patents and Innovation: An Empirical Study,’ Management Science [1986] 32, pp. 173-181 Maskus, 'Lessons from Studying the International Economics of Intellectual Property Rights,' Vanderbilt Law Review [2000] 53, p. 2219 materials in New Zealand,’ European Intellectual Property Review [1995] 17(5), pp. 219-224 Mille, ‘Argentina: plant varieties,’ European Intellectual Property Review [1992] 14(5), p.85 Millett, ‘The Community System of Plant Variety Rights,’ European Law Review [1999] 24, p. 231 Ministry of Agriculture Fisheries and Food (MAFF), ‘Proposals to amend the law on plant breeders' rights,’ 18th November 1994 (Available by request: White House Lane, Huntingdon Road, Cambridge, CB3 0LF) Mooi, ‘Canada: plant breeders' rights - proposed regulation,’ European Intellectual Property Review [1991] 13(9), 170-171 Müller, ‘Protecting biotechnological inventions in Brazil and abroad: Draft, scope and interpretation of claims,’ Albany Law Journal of Science and Technology [2002] p. 145 Ngugi, ‘Making new wine for old wineskins: Can reform of the international law emancipate the third world in the age of globalisation?’ U.C. Davis Journal of International Law and Policy [2002] p.73 Pilling and Bardacke, ‘Genetic Pirates Walk the Plank,’ Financial Times (London), 9-10 January, 1999: p.7 Plant, “Economic Theory Concerning Patents for Inventions,” (1934) 1 Economica 30 at 4244. Rawls, ‘Fairness to goodness,’ Philosophical Review [1975] 84, pp. 536-554 Rawls, ‘Two concepts of rules,’ Philosophical Review [1955] 64, pp. 3-32 Rives, ‘Mother Nature and the courts: Are sexually reproducing plants and their progeny patentable under the Utility Patent Act of 1952?’ Cumberland Law Review [2001-2002] p. 187 Robertson and Calhoun, ‘Treaty on biological diversity: ownership issues and access to genetic plant varieties,’ BIO-Science Law Review [1998/99] 4, pp.154-159 Scalise and Nugent, ‘International Intellectual Property Protections for Living Matter: Biotechnology, Multinational Conventions and the Exception for Agriculture,’ 27 Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law 83, 85 (1995) Shillito, ‘Patenting genetically engineered plants,’ European Intellectual Property Review [2002] 24(6), pp. 333-336 Smith, ‘Plant breeder’s rights – compulsory licence application,’ European Intellectual Property Review [2002] 24(3), 38-40 Spinney, ‘Biotechnology in Crops: Issues for the developing world,’ Research paper for Oxfam GB, May 98 Steudle, ‘The cohesion-tension mechanism and the acquisition of water by plant roots,’ Annual Review of Plant Physiology and Plant Molecular Biology [2001] 52, pp. 847-875 Thornton-Wood, ‘Rose of England? Not necessarily: countries now have floral rights,’ Times, 27th August 2002 Van Overwalle, ‘Belgium goes its own way on biodiversity and patents,’ European Intellectual Property Review [200] 24(5), pp. 233-236 Vaver, “Some Agnostic Thoughts on Intellectual Property”, (1991) 6 Intellectual Property Journal 125 Verma, ‘TRIPs and plant variety protection in developing countries,’ European Intellectual Property Review [1995] 17(6), pp. 281-289 Verma, ‘TRIPs and Plant Variety Protection in Developing Countries,’ European Intellectual Property Review [1995] 6, p. 281 Vidal, ‘Can you really patent a tree? Plans by big companies to own the basics of life are being challenged,’ Guardian, 27th November 1999 Wilkins and Latorre, ‘Biodiversity at a crossroads,’ Environmental Law Review [2002] 4(1), pp. 62-67 WTO ‘Review of the Provisions of Article 27.3(b) Further Views of the United States of America,’ Doc. IP/C/W/209, 20th September 2000. pp. 2-3, 5 WTO, Council for TRIPs, ‘Review of Article 27.3 (b) Communication from Brazil,’ Doc.IP/C/W/228, 24th November 2000. Zhu, ‘Salt and drought stress signal transducing in plants,’ Annual Review of Plant Physiology and Plant Molecular Biology [2002] 52, pp. 247-273 Internet Consumer Project on Technology http://www.cptech.org/ip/health/aids/ Royal Government of Thailand. "Policy Position Paper." 1999. http://www.oz.uc.edu/~harknerj/thaipp.htm Vandana Shiva. "TRIPs and the Environment." Penang, Malaysia: Third World Network, 2001. http://www.twnside.org.sg./title/trips-ch.htm Lori Wallach & Michelle Sforza. Whose Trade Organization? Corporate Globalization and the Erosion of Democracy. Washington, DC: Public Citizen, 1999. (No longer available) "Threat 1: U.S. Charges Thai Anti Bio-Piracy Policy Violates WTO," pp. 108-112. http://www.citizen.org/publications/release.cfm?ID=7081 The full text of the Convention on Biological Diversity can be found at http://www.unep.ch/bio/conv-e.html. Geoff Tansey, Trade, Intellectual Property, Food and Biodiversity: Key Issues and Options for the 1999 Review of Article 27.3(b) of the TRIPS Agreement 6 (Quaker Peace & Service, Feb. 1999) (reviewing intellectual property protection on life forms) http://www.btinternet.com/~ g.Tansey/trips/ (Accessed 10th April 2002). Pollack, Biological Products Raise Genetic Ownership Issues: Governments are Demanding Share of Profits, N.Y. Times, 26th November 1999 (No longer available) Reuters, ‘Monsanto Earnings Higher on Seed Sales,’ http://famulus.msnbc.com/famulusgen/reuters02-05053609.asp?t=recom&vts=2520031046#body (Accessed 5th February 2003) UN Food and Agriculture Organisation http://www.fao.org/ag/ (Accessed 20th October 2002) Deen, A Richer World Keeps Failing to End Hunger, Says U.N. http://www.proutworld.org/news/en/2002/oct/20021028ari.htm (accessed 13th February 2003) http://www.globalpolicy.org/socecon/develop/2002/1028rights.htm (accessed 13th February 2003) U.S. PTO website at www.uspto.gov. The Rural Advancement Foundation International (NGO) http://www.rafi.ca. International Union For the Protection of New Varieties of Plants http://www.upov.int/ (accessed 13th February 2003) United Kingdom Plant Variety Protection Office http://www.defra.gov.uk/plant/plantfrm.htm February 2003) (accessed 13th Pinstrup-Andersen, Pandya-Lorch and Rosegrant, ‘World Food Prospects: Critical Issues for the Early Twenty First Century’ (International Food Policy Research Institute, 1999, Washington D.C.) http://www.ifpri.org/srstaff/pandyar.htm (accessed 10th February 2003) World Food Summit http://www.fao.org/wfs/homepage.htm Directive 98/44/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council of 6 July 1998 on the legal protection of biotechnological inventions http://www.copyrighter.ru/lite/index.html?eu98_44_eng.htm (accessed 10th February 2003) Monsanto UK http://www.monsanto.co.uk/ February 2003) (accessed 10th Case list Attorney-General for Hong Kong v Reid [1994] 1 AC 324 Case C-116/89, BayWa AG v. Hauptzollamt Weiden, 1991, ECJ (1st Chamber) Diamond v. Chakrabarty 447 U.S. 303 Howley Park Coal Co v L. & N. W. Ry [1913] A.C. 11 Monsanto Canada Inc v Schmeiser [2001] 12 C.P.R. (4th) 204 (Fed Ct (Can)) T1054/96 NOVARTIS/Transgenic plant [1999] E.P.O.R. 123 (EPO); O.J. EPO [1998] p. 511 T19/90 HARVARD/Oncomouse, O.J. EPO [1990] p. 476 T356/93 PLANT GENETIC SYSTEMS/Plant cells, O.J. EPO [1995] p.354 Legislation Commission Regulation (EC) No. 1238/95 (‘Fees Regulation’) Commission Regulation (EC) No. 1239/95 (‘Proceedings Regulation’) Commission Regulation (EC) No. 1768/95 (‘Agricultural Exemption Regulation’) Convention on Biological Diversity 1992 (United Nations) Council Regulation (EC) No. 2100/94 of 27 June 1994 on Community Plant Variety Rights Council Regulation 2100/94 on Community plant variety rights [1994] O.J. L227/1 International Convention for the Protection of New Varieties of Plants International Undertaking on Plant Genetic Resources 1983 (United Nations) Plant Varieties and Seeds Act 1964 Seed and Phytogenetical Creations Law 1973 (Argentina)