Andrew Chau Hume and Kant: The Biology of Ethics When studying the ethical systems amongst philosophers of the modern period, one would be hard pressed to find two theories more opposed than those of David Hume and Immanuel Kant. Each moral philosophy is virtually a well-formed antithesis of the other; each stance a clear picture of the underlying foundations of empiricism in Hume and rationalism in Kant. They also contrast greatly in their approaches towards realism. Kant clearly believes in objective truths and universal morals defined by reason, while Hume argues that morality is found outside of the facts by the subjective standards of our sentiments and emotions. In the historical framework of their time their disparities seem irreconcilable, however given the advances of modern theories, specifically in evolutionary theory, both philosophies start to take on a new form. When grounded with an evolutionary stance, Hume and Kant’s ethics are both applicable in today’s society. Current studies in biology suggest that bringing ethics into the realm of science could open up entirely new ways of understanding the sources of our concepts of morals. Psychology and cognitive science have brought about vast improvements in the study of memory and human behavior, areas of knowledge that were formerly left to philosophy. Biology and the theory of evolution could do the same for the study of ethics. That is not to say that the answers to philosophical questions can only be found through science, but that science in many ways depends on philosophy. Many notions within science tacitly rely on philosophy for support such as the often-confused maxims of simplicity, reducibility, and parsimony1. Applying philosophical theories to the scientific fields with 1 These terms are hotly debated among philosophers of science with regards to their explicit definitions and their practical applications in the field. 1 Andrew Chau which they correspond has the potential to substantially enhance our knowledge of the world and of ourselves. First consider Hume’s empirical view of ethics, his explanation of the origin of morals, and dismissal of a rationalistic approach. Simply stated Hume believes morality rests in our sentiments and emotions. His entire philosophy is deeply rooted in the idea of causality and relies heavily on experience as the foundation of knowledge. In his ethics he claims that our morals are established through experience and surface when we react to an action without calling on our so-called faculty for reason. The vital aspect of this view is found in his reliance on emotional response (Fieser). If someone has a bad experience and believes an action directly caused that experience, they will have an aversion to that action. For example, if someone were to observe their friend being shot by a gun they would likely experience a great deal of pain as an emotional response. They associate that experience of pain to the action of shooting someone with a gun and the natural emotive response is corollary to forming a moral judgment. The same process can happen even if the person is not directly influenced by an action. When an observer witnesses someone experiencing an emotion due to some action, the observer feels sympathy and therefore forms the same connection as the recipient of that particular action. This is equally true concerning positive events. If an observer sees someone give money to a homeless man, they would see the man’s response of being happy or grateful, and sympathize with those feelings – it is that very sympathy that embodies their moral approval (Fieser). This approach seems to force Hume into a very relativistic stance because not everyone will react the same way in every situation. What will instill shock and awe in 2 Andrew Chau one culture may be perfectly normal and appropriate in another. Based on Hume’s theory both cultures are justified – what is morally right in one may or may not be morally right in the other. Once cultural relativism is allowed many problems arise such as the argument from evil. If the Nazi’s reaction to genocide was one of happiness, then their actions were morally right for them. Clearly there is something intuitively wrong with such an assertion. It is impossible to find a way to justify what seem like universal, objective morals when any moral justification must be relative by Hume’s definition. Another factor is the instability of emotions and the possibility of mood swings. If someone is particularly angry with their friend and shoots them in a fit of rage, they may feel satisfaction as an emotional response, even if it is only fleeting. According to Hume that satisfaction amounts to moral approval and would indicate that shooting your friend out of rage is morally right. This objection comes from a psychological stance, pointing out that people are unpredictable and often do crazy things that are considered immoral by normative standards. One reason Hume avoids committing to realism and any objective truth is his objection to the is-ought fallacy found in many ethical systems. He stresses that you cannot derive moral obligations from factual statements about the world (Fieser). One well-known example of the is-ought fallacy is found in Hobbes’s ethical egoism. Hobbes claims that because all of our actions are motivated by self-interest, all of our actions should be motivated by self-interest. Clearly just because something is one way in the state of nature does not necessitate that it ought to be that way. From Hume’s standpoint morality has to fall into one of two categories: analytic or synthetic. He makes the claim that moral judgment cannot be analytic, that we have no innate ability to make those 3 Andrew Chau judgments a priori. The only other option is that morality must be synthetic, based on experience. This ultimately leads Hume to his conclusion that our emotional responses constitute our moral judgments (Fieser). Kant varies greatly from Hume in his ethical theories in almost every respect. He is a rationalist and believes that morality rests upon our ability to reason. His beliefs are founded on realism, necessitating objective truths and therefore objective morals. Kant’s ethics begin with defining “good will”, which he says is good in the Platonic sense. The good will is something he believes “exists already in the sound natural understanding, requiring rather to be cleared up than to be taught (Kant 703).” This seems to be borrowing directly from Plato’s realism and notion of innate ideas, that ideas are not taught but brought out, since the knowledge already exists and is just waiting to be recognized. He makes the distinction between acting “from duty,” from an “inclination,” or “because duty requires (Kant 703).” The inclinations he speaks of are emotional responses devoid of reason. If someone saves their child from a burning building because it is their child, it was not a moral action. It was tainted by the person’s love and bias towards their offspring. When duty requires something it takes away the choice involved in moral action. If someone orders a person, directing him or her to save the child from the burning building, the life saving act is still not a moral act. However, if a total stranger ran into a burning building to save a child it would have been a moral action because the stranger chose that action from duty, not because of an inclination, or because duty required it. The key to morality for Kant is volition, and making the rational choice to act from duty even if it is not required and there are no emotions swaying the decision. Keeping those distinctions in mind, Kant defines duty as, “the 4 Andrew Chau necessity of acting from respect for the law.” The law dictates the ultimate moral good. Our respect for the law, and consequently our choice to act from duty following the law, constitutes a moral action. Kant concludes that the notion of law itself constitutes morality, which is certainly “only possible in a rational being (705).” His theory of morality as a conception of law is accompanied by his categorical imperative of the universality of laws. The move from societal laws to universal laws further illustrates Kant’s belief in objective truths. He claims that “moral laws ought to hold good for every rational creature (Kant 707).” His goal is to eliminate all personal agendas and prejudices from the law making process. A simple example is a law against theft, which is clearly applicable as a universal law. No one could claim that theft is lawful because they would not want their personal possessions stolen from them. The underlying theme of Kant’s categorical imperative echoes the Biblical message of “do unto others as you would have them do unto you.” This age-old maxim however, does not deal aptly with the problem of cross-cultural morals. Simply because one person wants to be treated one particular way does not mean every person wants to be treated that way. A law as simple as “thou shalt not kill” may not hold in a culture that believes in human sacrifice. If we were to truly follow Kant’s categorical imperative we may be left with no laws at all. Before Kant gets very deep into his ethical system he seems to have anticipated the possibility that someone may try to conflate ethics and biology. He writes a defense claiming that if nature produces beings adapted for their purpose, and happiness is the purpose of human life, nature would never have given humans the ability to reason. While our instincts alone could move us to act only in such a way that it would benefit 5 Andrew Chau our community and ourselves, reason gives us the ability to choose otherwise. Our rationality is what separates us from the animals and it is precisely what makes us moral or immoral creatures (Kant 701). In modern terms Kant is saying that for the purposes of survival and happiness our faculty for reason is maladapted. An argument seemingly before its time, it flies in the face of evolutionary theory (even though Darwin did not enter the picture until after Kant’s death), and states convincingly that the study of ethics should not be placed in the hands of science. Before examining the consequences of Kant’s assertion by today’s standards, turn back to Hume’s philosophy and consider its implications in the study of evolutionary theory. Recall that for Hume morality exists in our sentiments and emotions. An emotional response is itself the moral judgment. From one perspective of evolutionary biology our emotional response is an adaptation that contributes to our survival. Recent studies theorize that our aversion to things that disgust us could be based on an evolutionary adaptation that protects us from disease. People observe things that could represent a threat of disease and tend to be disgusted by it, even if it is not an actual threat (Curtis). Our responses to moral or immoral acts may serve a similar purpose. We may react favorably to moral acts because they help us survive and avoid immoral acts because they present a threat. The danger of this idea is that it returns to the relativistic view that something is only moral if it happens to contribute to our chances of survival. It also raises the issue of free will, that if we act only how nature has predisposed us to act, we have no choice in the matter and therefore no freedom. To avoid this dilemma the stance taken by evolutionary theorists is that moral codes are “created by culture under the biasing influence of the epigenetic rules and legitimated by the illusion of 6 Andrew Chau objectivity2 (Ruse and Wilson 434).” The theory proposes that an ethical system is created within a culture, influenced but not dictated by genetic processes, and made to seem right or wrong because of our acceptance of realism. The epigenetic rules refer to a “developmental regularity… [derived] from the biological process of… the interaction of genes and the environment (Bradie 457).” From this view genes are holding culture on a leash, acting restrictively but not deterministically. This saves free will because the biological aspect is not determining morality - it is simply a guide. It also avoids cultural relativism because of the influence of the epigenetic rules. It would be exceedingly rare for a culture to pass a law necessitating the consumption of lethal poison because that would in theory violate the epigenetic survival trait, annihilating the culture as a whole. It follows that a belief claiming cultural suicide is a moral act is not as good as a belief that it is an immoral act. Where does the is-ought fallacy to which Hume objected to fall once biology is in the picture? What appears as moral action to us contributes to our survival, thus we should be moral. Evolutionary concepts do not necessitate any particular code of morals, so the is disappears. Richard Rorty, who has been very outspoken against realism, defends this relative view of morals against accusations of cultural relativism stating, “the fact that a view is ours… our language’s, our tradition’s, our culture’s, is an excellent prima facie reason for holding it (“Hermeneutics” 527).” His point is that a system of beliefs does not appear overnight; it develops (or dare I say ‘evolves’) over time, and is not devoid of reason. Regardless of whether or not we know that reason, it has served us The “illusion of objectivity” seems contradictory to the aims of scientific inquiry; however, with regards to evolutionary theory there are no objective ends. The view is not that we are evolving to become some particular perfectly adapted being with perfect morals, rather that we are evolving to suit our ephemeral needs. 2 7 Andrew Chau well. History also tells us that biology does not force an is-ought approach to ethics since laws and moral codes have changed over time. The fact that ethical systems are ever changing is strong support for an evolutionary approach to the subject. The controversial school of thought known as irrationalism, antifoundationalism, or antirealism3 brings forth the idea that the goal of scientific inquiry as it is traditionally known does not exist. The most influential figures in this movement have been Richard Rorty in philosophy and Thomas Kuhn in science. According to them the correspondence theory of truth is a misguided attempt to draw the dichotomy of the world as it appears and the world as it really is. Instead of grasping onto the Platonic sense of truth, Truth with a capital “T”, they offer a cautiously relativistic view. Rorty quotes John Dewey saying, “growth itself is the only moral end (Rorty “Philosophy” 35).” New theories are not seen as bringing us closer to the truth, rather they are more helpful descriptions of the relations of things; descriptions that are helpful in the sense that they are more useful in aiding us to solve the problems of our time. Science is not seen as converging on the world as it really is, but as solving old problems by creating new ones (Rorty “Hermeneutics” 531). Progress is the continual reinvention of our community that serves our ever-changing purposes. It is based on this sense of relativism that Hume is defended against “vulgar relativism”, the notion that any belief is as good as any other (Rorty “Hermeneutics” 527). This antirealist stance is also the means to bridging the gap between Kant’s objective universal ethics and evolutionary theory’s subjective morals. 3 I could not find any widely agreed upon label for the likes of Richard Rorty (a self-proclaimed neopragmatist) and Thomas Kuhn. They may fit into “postmodern thought”, but that category says nothing in particular about their beliefs and is entirely too general (even derogatory it seems) for me to warrant its use. Their beliefs are probably best identified by their names and not by any particular label. 8 Andrew Chau Kant’s main challenge towards a scientific interpretation of ethics is asking where rationality fits in – or more precisely, asserting that it does not fit in. We are blessed with the ability to choose, yet that seems contradictory to the idea of being well-adapted since we could choose to act contrary to our better interest. Some evolutionary theorists argue that rationality is Mother Nature’s means to an end, that rationality does in fact aid our survival. One claim is that the concept of morality “imparts efficiency to the adaptively correct action (Ruse and Wilson 432),” that our feelings towards moral action act as a mental “shortcut” to make the best choices possible. This provides an alternative answer to the purpose of rationality, contrasting with Kant’s ideas, implying that morals are founded on subjective truth with a biological guide. Given this picture of ethics our ability for reason is in fact well adapted. Next consider Kant’s categorical imperative to “act as if the maxim of your action were to become by your will a universal law of nature (708).” Such acts as he describes are actually seen in nature, although not with rational motivation. The universality of laws Kant calls for seem similar to altruism in human societies and in nature. Altruistic acts are those that benefit others without benefit to the one performing the act. Sometimes the altruistic person or creature even suffers harm because of the act. A universal law is what is best for everyone, or society as a whole, which every individual must follow for the good of the many. Seen from the perspective of evolutionary theory altruism is a group selective trait. Altruism as an adaptation does not serve the individual, but helps the group as a whole. If altruism is comparable to Kant’s categorical imperative, then perhaps his ethics are not incompatible with scientific theories after all. 9 Andrew Chau The biggest objection to drawing this parallel is that Kant’s categorical imperative requires objective truth. To satisfy that criterion, even in the minimalist form, altruism must be a universal group selective trait. There is a distinction to be drawn between evolutionary biologists and theorists. In practice, biologists believe that human evolution is culminating towards some ultimate end, the telos of evolution. Theorists, on the other hand, see evolution as adaptive changes that deal with an ever-changing environment. The goals of evolution are relative, serving the transient purpose of adapting to the current state of the environment (Bradie 464). The only way to deal with this issue is to appeal to the antirealist stance of Rorty and Kuhn. From their perspective the universality of moral law is necessarily non-relational because it is unconditional (Rorty “Philosophy” 67). Kant’s assumption that the world as it appears somehow corresponds to the Truth locks him in to this stance. Just as it is the goal of science to converge on the world as it really is, Kant’s hope is to converge on universal objective ideals. The categorical imperative from an evolutionary perspective, therefore, can be seen as an attempt to bring society to realize new descriptions of the relations of things that help solve old problems by creating new ones. Kant’s problem of justifying moral responsibility is replaced with the new problem of developing a complete, generally agreed upon theory of evolution. The categorical imperative aided with this view can be understood as the selective trait of altruism. If epigenetic rules do in fact play an important role in influencing our perception of morals we must reconsider Kant’s definition of what it means to be moral. His first criteria are that a moral action must not be motivated by a mere inclination or because it is required by duty. The biological influence on moral behavior does not seem to fit into 10 Andrew Chau either category. Although it is possible Kant may consider it a genetic inclination, it seems to be acceptable by his standards since genetic make-up is a continuous indirect influence as opposed to an irrational spark like that of our emotions. An evolutionary theory of ethics is also safe from having morals required by duty. However influential genetics may be, they do not strip us of volition – ultimately the decisions we make are our own. Determinism in its other forms may pose a problem for Kant, but not from the biological standpoint. His last criterion is that moral action must come from duty, out of respect for the law. A culture has the power to make its own laws, and the human ability remains to obey or violate those laws. Any act still has the potential to be moral; therefore all individuals are still morally responsible for their actions. Hume and Kant bring forth philosophies of ethics that are quite different, however in the context of modern evolutionary theory they may have value irrespective of their opposition to each other. Hume’s reliance on emotional response and his objection to the is-ought fallacy both fit into biology seamlessly. Emotional response is considered an adaptation that aids our survival. His relativistic stance is acceptable because the genetic influences on our perception of morals guide the changes in any culture’s ethical system. The is-ought fallacy is not a factor because our ethics are directed by our culture, not by the way things are or by a statement of facts about the world. Kant’s ethics can be made to fit the mold of evolutionary theory even though his differ so greatly from Hume’s. A culture’s respect for the law, as derived from the human ability to reason, is preserved since the biological view is not deterministic. His categorical imperative stays in the picture in the form of the well-adapted group selective trait of altruism in evolutionary theory. Although Kant’s philosophy does not conform to the context of science as easily 11 Andrew Chau as Hume’s, it does not appear to be contradictory in practice. Any interpretation of Kant that defies realism may necessarily betray the heart and soul of his philosophy, namely the essentiality of objective morals; however, in the spirit of Kant one must not lament this betrayal at the risk of letting emotions get in the way of reaching the truth4. Clearly Hume and Kant’s theories, when grounded with an evolutionary stance, are both still applicable in today’s society. This instance of truth, or course, is defined as the most helpful description of the relations of things. 4 12 Andrew Chau Works Cited Bradie, Michael. “Epistemology from an Evolutionary Point of View.” Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Biology. Ed. Eliot Sober. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2001. Curtis, Val. “Disgust.” BBC – Science and Nature. n.p., n.d., 12 April 2004. < http://www.bbc.co.uk/science/humanbody/mind/surveys/disgust/>. Fieser, James. “David Hume: Moral Theory.” The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. n.p., 2001., 12 April 2004. <http://www.iep.utm.edu/h/humemora.htm>. Kant, Immanuel. “Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals.” The Mayfield Anthology of Western Philosophy. Ed. Daniel Kolak. Mountain View, CA: Mayfield Publishing Company, 1998. Rorty, Richard. “Hermeneutics, General Studies, and Teaching.” Classic and Contemporary Readings in the Philosophy of Education. Ed. Steven M. Cahn. New York, NY: The McGraw Hill Companies, Inc., 1997. Rorty, Richard. Philosophy and Social Hope. New York, NY: Penguin Books, 1999. Ruse, Michael and Edward Wilson. “Moral Philosophy as Applied Science.” Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Biology. Ed. Eliot Sober. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2001. 13