Rethinking Anarchy and the State in IR Theory: The Contributions of Classical Anarchism Dr Alex Prichard ESRC Postdoctoral Fellow University of Bristol a.prichard@bristol.ac.uk Draft. Please do not cite without permission. Keywords: Anarchism, International Relations, State Theory, Scientific Realism Abstract: In this paper I intervene in an ongoing debate between Colin Wight and Alex Wendt regarding the nature of the state. My intervention is derived from a reading of the work of the nineteenth-century anarchist Pierre-Joseph Proudhon. The debate to date revolves around whether the state is an agent or a structure and seems to have become stuck as regards to the ontological status of groups. For Wendt the state is a person; for Wight the state is a structure that constrains and enables individuals. Wendt conflates the state with all other groups, and Wight, in an effort to reclaim the individual from Wendt’s organicism, posits that it is only individuals and structures that are ontologically significant when discussing state agency – groups are unimportant. Proudhon’s solution formed the basis of his anarchism. He argued that states, like all other social groups, are emergent from and irreducible to the historically and culturally distinct groupings of individuals of which they are comprised. Indeed, society is comprised of individuals who are simultaneously members of plural groups, and their interrelations (and those between relatively autonomous groups) are mediated by complex institutions and structures (for him law). The normative consequences for a theory of anarchy and world politics are clear: if states are but one, relatively small if disproportionately powerful group among many, we need a quite separate political theory to assert that the state is anything more than just a group. Inter-state anarchy is a form of inter-group relations replicated at all social levels and all inter-group relations take place in anarchy. I will show that anarchism is a source of ethical and political insight here. 1 Introduction1 Kenneth Waltz once argued that ‘[t]he problem [in International Relations (IR)] is this: how to conceive of an order without an orderer and of organizational effects where formal organization is lacking’ (Waltz, 1979: 89). This problem is rarely stated as clearly in the anarchist literature, though the central problem is substantively the same. While in the former the argument is seen to be cynical or tragic realism, when anarchists ask this question it is considered naïve utopianism. The solution, I will argue, is the same for both IR and anarchist theorists. The ‘utopian realism’ (Booth 1991) that emerges from viewing this ‘anarchy problematique’ (Ashley 1988) from an anarchist perspective deserves reconsideration. My way into this problematique is through theories of the state in IR. I will engage with two of the most recent and well thought-through ontologies of the state in IR and present Proudhon’s long-ignored anarchist variation on the theme (Proudhon 1860, 1861, 1863a, b). While there is a mass of literature on the ‘agential capacity of the state’ (for a good overview see Hobson 2000), there is much less writing on what the state is. It is the latter issue with which this paper is concerned and the most prominent articulations of it are those of Alex Wendt (1991, 2004) and Colin Wight (2004, 2007). Wendt and Wight first locked horns over this issue in a special forum in Review of International Studies in 2004. While others have joined the discussion (Chernoff, Jackson, Neuman 2004, Michels), and many of the responses are salient to the discussion here, I will nevertheless focus solely on Wight’s extended discussions with Wendt surrounding his theory of state agency. This is mainly because both Wendt and Wight operate within a shared scientifically realist ontology. This sets the terms of the debate on coherent grounds and because, as I will argue, Proudhon was also a scientific realist, this makes comparison and dialogue much easier. Secondly, the debate has thus far been constrained within the agentstructure debate. Where Wendt sees states as agents, persons even, Wight sees states as structures populated by individuals only. Proudhon argued that states are not the only groups and there is more to social life than structures and individuals. Understanding this contribution brings us to the third reason for keeping the discussion narrow. While for Wendt anarchy becomes what states make of it, grouped as they are in mutual antagonism and crowned with formal sovereignty, for Wight anarchy all but drops out of his social ontology. Since structures permeate all of social life and constrain and enable individuals (as opposed to groups) only, anarchy is not analytically or politically significant. For Proudhon not only was anarchy the ontological condition of social life as such, it was also the precondition of freedom as such. Anarchism arose out of this way of understanding social order. First, Proudhon’s anarchist political theory provides novel conceptual tools of understanding how order is created in anarchy. In brief, states are not the precondition of order, as IR theorists have shown conclusively vis-à-vis international order. Secondly, anarchists argue that states and capitalism are the symbiotic precondition of disorder and conflict. They argue that both are detrimental to human autonomy and flourishing. There is thus a robust ethical and political element to the theory. Finally, given the above, anarchists actively seek a world without sovereigns. In this paper I will focus mainly on the first part of this contribution. I will outline Proudhon’s state theory with a view to showing how he understood social order and do so in dialogue with current debates on the same subject. 1 I would like to thank participants at research seminars at the University of Bristol, the BISA annual conference 2009, Queen Mary, University of London, and the Centre for the Study of Social and Global Justice at Nottingham University for a number of helpful comments and suggestions. 2 There are of course clear normative, political and ethical issues at stake here and I will enage with these issues also – but less so for reasons of space. Wendt argues that his collectivist theory of the state, which has clear Hegelian and Durkheimian roots (Neuman 2004), suggests that liberalism needs to justify political order on grounds other than the state. However, as Wight argues, reducing individuals to ‘cultural dopes’ is ethically and politically, not to mention ontologically or theoretically, unnecessary and dangerous. Wight’s solution is to ignore the collective and irreducible agency of groups and posit that the social world is simply made up of individuals and structures, little else, and in this way, he brings individuals back in to state theory. Again, what we can do with Proudhon’s writings is find a way in which groups and individuals, structures and institutions can be conceptualised as part of the same social whole thereby widening and strengthening the normative force of the theory. However, while the normative implications of Proudhon’s theory for groups and individuals might be welcome to some, the consequences for a theory of state sovereignty will be unwelcome to others. Proudhon’s anarchism, as I will show, leaves no room for positing the state as the highest, as in best, or necessarily the only sovereign form of human organisation, nor does he see the state as the sine qua non of political order. The consequence of this way of framing issues is again to radically transform our conception of anarchy in political theory. It is to this issue that I will devote most attention. As I will show, debates about what the state ‘is’ are never far from debates about what the state should be. I will argue that anarchy is what our (as in us academics) state theory makes of it. I have argued elsewhere that the core contribution of classical anarchism to contemporary IR resides at the level of state theory (Prichard 2007, forthcoming, a, b). Here I will set this contribution out in some detail. My argument is drawn from an original reading of the fourth etude, entitled L’État, of Proudhon’s untranslated magnum opus, De la Justice dans la Revolution et dans l’Église. I will supplement the analysis he provides here with discussions that we find in La Guerre et la Paix (1861), Si les Traites de 1815 ont cesse d’exister (1863), and Federation et l’Unite en Italie (1863) so as to relate his state theory directly to his theory of world politics. To date I am not aware of any literature that sets out Proudhon’s state theory in either English or French, let alone link it to his international political theory and thus the theoretical contribution of this paper is also supported by a degree of historical originality. What going back to Proudhon’s thought allows us to do is unsettle the conventional discursive norms that have settled around concepts of anarchy in contemporary IR theory. By unsettling the norm I hope to make room for an unconventional alternative and demonstrate its analytical and political implications. In this regard, this paper is another layer of under-labouring in preparation for a fuller anarchist theory of world politics. The paper proceeds as follows. In part one I discuss Wendt’s thesis that ‘the state is a person’; I argue that his understanding of group agency is sound, but inconsistently applied. States are not the only groups. To illustrate this oversight I will show that Wendt’s understanding of the pluralist literature is thin and his rejection of pluralism weak. I then turn to Colin Wight’s rejoinder to Wendt. I set out Wight’s contributions in two parts. First, I discuss Wight’s critique of Wendt’s collectivism and his elision of the individual and secondly, I repeat Wight’s critique of Wendt’s decision to ignore the structural aspects of states. Both are valid critiques in my view. However, Wight does a disservice to Wendt’s theory of corporate agency and his decision to bifurcate the social world between individuals and structures would seem to denude IR theory of a realistic understanding of corporate agency, be that classes, trade unions, NGOs, multinationals and so forth. We must retain a conception of these groups in order to explain how individuals achieve what they do within state and wider social structures. 3 Part three seeks to demonstrate the ontological importance of all ‘natural groups’ as Proudhon called them, and the importance of developing a theory of their complex and crosscutting inter-relations. States are not the only groups, but their structural power clearly supersedes most other groups considered individually. However, states act in concert as do other social groups and for a realistic social theory of world politics we need to understand how trade unions, multi-nationals and so forth are social groups with causally efficacious corporate agency. If we see states and other natural groups as enmeshed within complex social relations, far from being peculiar to IR, anarchy becomes the sine qua non of politics as such. It is here that a bit of realistic utopianism is required. What I will show is that by turning to Proudhon’s thought we will see that anarchism can help us conceptualise the normative ethics of this way of seeing (world) politics. Again, anarchy is what our state theory makes it. Wendt – the state as person While, there is a wealth of implicit state theory in IR, there is little thorough state theory and little of the type of state theory Alex Wendt wants to see more of: that is theory that seeks to conceptualise the things which make the state an agent (Wendt, 1999: 195-198; 2004: 290291). It is all very well talking about state agency and looking to understand the things that enable and inhibit it, but how can a state actually be an agent? This is an ontological question first – particularly if one approaches this question from the perspective of scientific realism. Wendt posits that the state has agential capacity and, perhaps more controversially, that it is ‘a person’. In order to claim the former, something like the latter would have to be true, but the significance of Wendt’s work is that he is both a scientific realist and a thorough theorist, which means that his theory is largely internally coherent, realist and rigorous to a degree strikingly absent in the literature. Following Kant, scientific realists ask: what must be the case in order for such and such to be possible (Bhaskar and special ed of New Formations). What must there be in order to explain why apples consistently fall downwards from the tree when overripe? The answer, gravity, is an unobservable background process or mechanism that must exist in order to explain like occurrences. This is not to say that once posited gravity takes on a transcendental quality, only that it becomes intransitive. That is to say no matter what we think about it (though we may come to understand it better), gravity exerts causal pressures. Moreover, understanding the nature of gravity allows scientists to perform elaborate experiments and launch humans into space. Scientists do not proceed as if gravity existed (but some might think like this and this does not affect gravity itself), but know that it must exist in order to be able to explain why it is always so difficult to launch a rocket and why things always fall towards earth (Bhaskar 1978, 1989). Gravity exists even though you can’t see it and observation therefore becomes the criterion for a crude empiricist epistemology and is widely dismissed by realists. For scientific realists, the same principle of realism applies to ideas, to social forms and facts and to abstract theory. There is always an intransitive reality behind what is directly observable that we gain progressively better (or in degenerating research programmes, worse) access to it through theory building and empirical analysis. So, for Wendt, positing the reality of the personhood of the state is important because it helps explain effects in the world. It is real rather than a convenient fiction. His theory of corporate agency allows us to theorise anarchy as populated by states-as-persons and it is only if we posit this reality that we can explain why international relations has the character it does. 4 States-as-persons have identities and while anarchy, for Wendt, is permissive, its existence alone cannot explain, nor is it causal of, war, conflict or anything else. For that we need to understand the mutual constitution of state identity and from there we will see that ‘anarchy is what states make of it.’ (Wendt, 1991) This is not a metaphor, nor is it an analogy. ‘States are people too.’ (Wendt, 2004) So how does Wendt sustain this argument? It is impossible to survey the wealth of material he brings to bear on this discussion, and so a brief summary will have to suffice. Wendt (2004) draws our attention to the scientific literature on intentional systems, supervenience, emergence, superorganisms and collective conscience.2 Each of these theories, backed up by empirical analysis, sustains the argument that states are persons and that their corporate identity is real. In order to get to the position where it becomes possible to talk of corporate agency, Wendt, like a good neo-realist, rejects reductionism. In the context of his argument this first involves rejecting the idea that consciousness can be reduced to the hard matter of the brain, a position we might also call materialism or, more technically, ‘physicalism’. Drawing on a large and growing body of scientific literature, Wendt sustains the argument that consciousness is more than the sum, or the co-acting parts of the brain. Consciousness is dependent upon, but irreducible to, brain matter. Furthermore, he argues, personhood is irreducible to consciousness, and involves formal and informal social recognition. Identityproduction is, Wendt argues, ‘mutually constituted’ through social interactions, specifically ‘process’, (learning and ideas), and ‘institutions’ (or rules, norms etc) (Wendt 1991). Wendt also supports work that argues, ontologically consistently, that collective consciousness, or collective persons, can likewise not be reduced to the individual consciousness of which such collectives are composed. Corporate identity is more than the sum of its parts and irreducible to them. This, again, is not an analogy but a social fact of a Durkheimian variety (cf. Jackson 2004). If you want to explain individual actions like suicide, Durkheim argued, you should not look at the individuals or their actions, but the society in which they live. Society, ‘social facts’, or the collective rationalisations in socially and temporally specific times and places, exert exogenous pressures on the individuals which compose them. As an aside, Kenneth Waltz (1979) has been considered a Durkheimian in the way in which he conceptualises anarchy as exerting pressures on state behaviour irrespective of their individual preferences. Wendt strips back his conception of personhood to at a minimum comprise of intentionality, to be an organism, and to have ‘consciousness, by which I mean a capacity for first-person subjective experience’ (2004: 296). States are intentional systems, Wendt argues, because they are groups and groups, just like people, can be shown to be intentional (I will discuss their organismic qualities below). The intentionality of a group can be seen in any mass action, a riot, a war, a class action law suit, etc. Here groups have agency which is irreducible to any one individual and by the nature of the collective action itself, irreducible to all individuals together as well. That said, group intentions are more easily attributable to individuals in a class action law suit than in a riot, but it is without question that neither a riot nor a class action law suit can be reduced to particular (or the sum of) individuals – it is the collective nature of the group and the plurality or uniformity of the members which gives it its collective character. These groups are distinct for three further reasons. First, they have a collective ‘idea’ which provides them with group identity and intentionality. Secondly, decision-making in the group is institutionalised, third, the decisions of the group are authoritative and direct the actions of 2 He also discusses reductionism and the literature on personhood, which I have covered briefly above. 5 the individuals. While ‘group intentions […] are dependent on the structured interaction of individuals’ (Wendt, 2004: 298), group intentionality, once constituted, shapes the actions of individuals in turn, but this shaping force cannot be reduced to any one individual – it is a group decision, ergo, group intentions are real because they are causal too. In this sense, group intentions supervene those of individuals. Supervenience is an argument that posits that ‘We-intentions’ are not reducible to ‘I-intentions’ but that the collective form of the former needs some form of collective agreement that the supervening nature of group intentions and decisions are consensually acceded to (as in a class action law suit, but not necessarily in a riot). Wendt moves from these arguments to his state-as-a-person argument without taking a breath when he argues that ‘even though the intentions of a state person at any given moment are ontologically dependent on its constituent members, its intentions are not dependent on any particular members.’ (Ibid: 300). However, Wendt is unhappy with this argument. Supervenience arguments are too reductionist for Wendt because they presuppose the structured interaction of individuals and the clear apportioning of agency to key individuals. He does not state clearly why this is a problem, only that the concept of emergence seems to capture reality more adequately. With the concept of emergence, Wendt is able to argue that collective ideas are irreducible to those of individuals irrespective of formal decision making procedures – class action law suits become more like well-organised riots! For all its elegant simplicity, the argument that the decision of the US to invade Iraq can be reduced to the intentions of George W. Bush, Tony Blair, or any other individual or collections of individuals, is, by this analysis, false. Complex ‘processes’ and ‘institutions’ mediate and facilitate an outcome and a collective ‘brain state’ such as a US decision to go to war, is or was ‘relatively insensitive to which of its members hold it’ (ibid: 299). Again, the point here is to show that collective intentions, ‘in this case state persons’ (ibid: 304), cannot be reduced to individuals, but that individuals mutually constitute the higher-order relations that emerge from their interactions. We might well ask, in the context of the invasion of Iraq, whether the UK’s decision to work with the US produced an emergent super-super brain or whether the UK became part of the US brainperson. Supervenience theory would make either position ridiculous, because of the need to always pay attention to the formal mechanisms and processes of decision-making, but emergence theory would not. The question is, can we still understand the intentions of the US and the UK in these terms? Surely something like reductionism must take place to demonstrate which part of the state-persons in the UK and US merged and which didn’t. I will show that it is here that Colin Wight argues that Wendt is inconsistently a methodological structuralist, and is guilty of what Margaret archer would call ‘upwards conflation’ (Archer 1995). We can make this clear in the following way. Wendt’s aim is to consistently distance himself from the physicalist bias in supervenience theory in favour of a theory that allows him to posit an irreducible collective conscience that is internally formed and relatively autonomous from its surroundings and constituent units. Indeed, if states are people this is what he must posit. The problem is that Wendt is inconsistent in his definition of emergence. Wendt defines emergence like this: ‘in the emergence approach individual intentions are constituted by shared meanings in which they are embedded, making the relationship between individual and group intentions mutually constitutive rather than asymmetric’ (ibid: 305). But if Wendt is to be consistent he must surely argue that emergence produces qualities that are irreducible to their constituent units – otherwise some sort of physicalism would do just fine. The relations must not only be complex and asymmetric, but also irreducible to any one or more of the individuals that co-act (intentionally or otherwise). A consistent stand on emergence 6 would produce a ‘depth ontology’, in which the higher layers emerge from lower ones and are irreducible to them. Mutual constitution is problematic in this context, because if emergent properties are shared or mutually constituted, in what sense can they be said to be irreducible? This, as Colin Wight has argued, shows that Wendt is more of a structurationist than a Bhaskarian scientific realist (Wight ???). It also means that he is somewhat inconsistent and his ontology is somewhat ‘flat’. It is composed of individuals and states which are persons with little or nothing in between , Not only are there no emergent intervening groups, but symmetrical mutual constitution, which presupposes intentional human interaction and can be reduced to it, would suggest a degree of irrealism surely unwarranted and inconsistent with Wendt’s own emergentist ambitions? I hope I have now outlined coherently how Wendt conceptualises the possibility of collective consciousness. What I want to do now is show how this works in the context of states. Here Wendt employs to two further theories to sustain the unitary collective intentions of his states-as-actors. The first is the theory that the state is a superorganism and the second that it has collective conscience, both work in this theory to give the state an organismic quality – and actual physical and real quality to the personhood of the state. Formal source of collective agency The concept of a superorganism is quite straightforward to explain. An anthill or a termite mound, for example, is a superorganism. It is irreducible to an ant but through the collective actions of ants, the anthill is a living thing. It is not the vessel for a lot of ants, it is fundamentally part of the possibility of being an ant and yet is irreducible to ants. Wendt argues that states are the same. The concept of collective conscience has been touched upon earlier, but implies something like a religion. Religions are similar, functionally and conceptually distinct and internally complex, and they are irreducible to the intentions of individuals. They nevertheless give meaning to individuals and for many their existence would be incomprehensible without it. It is irrelevant whether religion is true or not, or whether God exists or not. It suffices to say that religion does exist and that it is causal. We can link religions to churches, mosques and other physical things, and we might claim the rules of particular religions set down in books are also important. While this is important, the religion itself is not reducible to these things in the same way that a superorganism like an ant hill has a clear physical form. Collective conscience is a very important sociological theory in these sorts of contexts. However, the concept of ‘collective conscience’ is relatively under-developed by Wendt and this is a shame. I will develop it considerably in my discussion of Proudhon’s work, but a few conjectures as to why Wendt leaves this part of his work relatively under-exploited will open this up to some critique. We might conclude from the narrative, a narrative I cannot for reasons of space reproduce here, that Wendt feels uncomfortable with the logical conclusions of his argument. If we marry collective conscience with his argument that the state is a ‘homeostatic cluster’ of sovereignty, an authoritative and determining legal institutionalorder, a monopoly of legitimate violence, an undifferentiated society and a determinate and defended territory (Wendt 1999: 202 emphasis added), the ‘uncomfortable truths’ Wendt highlights become more pronounced. Liberal individualism simply cannot be squared with this echo of nineteenth-century organicist doctrines that produced the sort of fascism that saw authority monopolised and centralised, individuals of dubious political or normative importance and history as static or at an end (Wendt 2004: 292). What worries Wendt is the idea that the scientific literature points in precisely this direction. The statism that Wendt 7 knew was ‘depressingly familiar’ in his early work (Wendt 1991: 163), here takes on a far more ominous tone. But this theory is absolutely central to Wendt’s ability to sustain the ontology of world politics that he does. He would be unable to posit the ‘three logics of anarchy’ (Wendt 1999), unless he could show that states in anarchy create Lockean, Kantian and Hobbesian collective identities, and he would be unable to argue that a world state was inevitable unless he could show that of the three logics of anarchy the Kantian is most likely to triumph (Wendt 2003). Only without disaggregating states and conflating all of society in a given and arbitrarily defined territorial boundary, could such a simplistic concept of large-scale political agency be viable. Wendt has hoped from the outset of his investigations that the state has a progressive nature (Wendt 1991: 163-164), but not only is it hard to see where it derives its legitimacy from in this analysis, but it seems his own conclusions lead him to the position that it is fundamentally illiberal. The harder Wendt pushes in the directions he wishes to, the less Kantian his states seem and the more Hobbesian they become.3 If a world state is inevitable at all, I think Wendt has mischaracterised its cause and future form. At least if we follow his way of conceptualising states. There are other less politically questionable incoherences and inconsistencies in Wendt’s argument. The first is the inconsistency in the argument that states are internally constituted, externally constituted and ‘mutually constituted’ and Wendt’s seeming inability to consider that the state might not be the only corporate agent of theoretical and ontological value in developing a theory of world politics. Wendt argued that the mutual recognition of sovereignty by states in ‘mature anarchies’ ‘determines the qualities of their interactions’. Sovereignty provides ‘a social basis for the individuality and security of states [and …] The essence of this community is a mutual recognition of one another’s right to exercise exclusive political authority within territorial limits.’ (Wendt 1992: 146-147) This internal constitution of a state’s ‘individuality’ is sustained and enforced by ‘regular practices [which] produce mutually constituting sovereign identities (agents) and their associated institutional norms (structures).’ (ibid: 151) In Social Theory of International Politics Wendt expands on this discussion of state agency in some detail and it becomes clear that he is not concerned with what we might call ‘second image’ variables at all. Here, in a somewhat thin analysis of pluralist state theory that extends across less than two pages, Wendt summarises that if ‘‘state’ for Weberians is an organisational actor, and for pluralists is really just society, then for Marxists the reference is the structure that binds the two in a relationship of mutual constitution’. (Wendt, 1999: 200 emphasis added) What I want to draw attention to here is Wendt’s summary that for pluralists ‘state’ means nothing more than ‘interest groups and individuals’ (Ibid: 200), but throughout the rest of his many discussions, interest groups drop out and society is composed of atom-like individuals united in a common sense of a shared destiny only. When Wendt discusses society he argues that the pluralism of society can be reduced to ‘shared knowledge that induces them [people] to follow most of the rules of their society most of the time’ (ibid: 209). This disaggregated or homogenous conception of society is a huge over-simplification, but one that is central to sustaining the parsimony and coherence of Wendt’s social theory, in particular his theory of the personhood of the state. Wendt is quite explicit that his argument that ‘states are people too’ (ibid: 215) reaffirms the explanatory efficacy of the ‘‘billiard ball’ model of states in systemic IR’ (ibid: 202). 3 Robert Paul Wolff (DATE???) has argued that any consistent Kanitanism leads directly to anarchism not a world state, which at a minimum complicates Wendt’s neat theory, but more damagingly illustrates what a poor political and social theorist a background in IR makes us. 8 And so it must; for if states are not person’s that we might consider metaphorically to be sovereign billiard balls, then what is anarchy? But surely the same arguments can be applied to every corporate agent and this opens up the possibility that IR might have to have a more pluralist social ontology (cf. Prichard forthcoming). If we do, we need to have some idea of the way in which these social groups are interrelated, how or why we do not consider them to be in condition of anarchy vis-à-vis one another and on what grounds the state is considered not to be the expression of the collective agency of a particular group in society, rather than society as a whole. Despite these criticisms, Wendt’s theory has clear value to any philosophically realist theory of world politics. Indeed, much of my defence of Proudhon will rely on the assumption that Wendt is right on many of the issues he raises. As I will show in my discussion of Proudhon’s theory below, it is important to be able to distinguish collective agency from individual agency and to show that both are real. It is also important to be able to distinguish collective agency from structure – as I will illustrate next in my discussion of Wight’s work. The concepts of emergence and the commitment to scientific realism are also of huge importance in a discipline given over to idealist irrealism throughout all the non-conservative literature. Irrespective of the obvious unintended consequences of Wendt’s somewhat naïve political theory, it is a huge advance on the norm. It also provides us with something to criticise. While Wendt’s ambition and method is original, the theory of state-personhood is nearly four hundred years old and usually considered to be quite conservative if not reactionary. Wendt also highlights the normative implications of this move: what of individualism if states, our nominally sovereign collective form, are irreducible to individuals? Does this lead to illiberal politics? This is the argument Colin Wight picks up on, and while his alternative puts individuals squarely back in the middle of a global social ontology, we lose the force and importance of the collectivist argument. Wight – the state as structure Wight, perhaps sensing the morally questionable direction this sort of theory leads, rejects it outright. His conclusion is that ‘we must reject any notion of the state as a psychological person and inter alia any ascription of moral personhood to the state. This is not to say that the state cannot be held causally, or legally accountable, but it is in its status as a structural entity that this accountability occurs.’ (Wight, 2007: 194) For Wight, Wendt’s personification ‘accords human agency no role’, because the state takes on the properties of human agency and the real human agents that act in the world are ‘theoretically redundant’ ‘cultural dopes’ (ibid: 198, 183). Despite both scholars sharing a scientific realist philosophy of science, Wendt and Wight disagree fundamentally in their analysis. What I will do here is outline Wight’s critique of Wendt and then his alternative. What I will show is that Wight thrown the proverbial baby out with the bathwater. Let us focus first on emergence. Recall that for Wendt, emergence is framed in structurationist terms as ‘mutual constitution’. If it is the constituent parts that are ontologically determinate, why postulate an emergent property? Surely on this basis, Wight argues that a ‘reductionist explanatory programme would suffice’ (Wight 2007: 145). Indeed, not only this, but when Wendt discusses emergence at the state level, the attribution of human characteristics to something which must be irreducible to individuals, implies that either Wendt is personifying, which is not a realist position, or he is not committed to emergence theory at all. States cannot be persons, because we all know what persons are. States must be something else – superorganisms or collective conscience for example, but not persons. 9 Wight goes further and argues that ‘Wendt’s theory of the state rests on the classic error of methodological structuralism: the attribution of the agential powers and attributes of human agents to a collective social form.’ (Ibid: 188) It is thus fatally flawed from the perspective of philosophical realism. Wight argues that if Wendt is to be consistent and non-reductionist, emergent properties must be irreducible to the constituent units. If Wendt wants to claim that states exhibit emergent properties, he must abandon the idea that they are mutually constituted in structurationist terms and defend the stronger emergentist claim. He must also abandon the idea that states are people. States, if they emerge from the structured interactions of people, must therefore be something else other than people. But this is not Wendt’s tactic and as such he defends a theoretically inconsistent theory of state agency and one which is also normatively suspect. Wight’s response is to emphasise the place of individuals and the emergent and irreducible quality of structures. All sorts of things can be classed as structures for Wight, rules, buildings, capitalism, and so on, and this makes his analysis somewhat loose. ‘Structure’ he argues, ‘binds the various planes of the social world [e.g., resources, rules, class, identity] together’ (Wight 2007: 175). I am not sure how this is so from his analysis, but we can assume that structures are plural and multi-faceted. States, in Wendt’s analysis, are formal and informal ‘rule structures’ and Wight argues that ‘the idea of a rule structure that authorises some agents to act in certain ways does not require that we then assign intentionality and personhood to the structure. The state functions well enough in this role as structure whilst leaving room for human agency.’ (Wight, 2007: 185) As we can see here, Wight is put flesh onto the leviathan. Paraphrasing Roy Bhaskar, Wight supports the argument that ‘nothing happens in the social world but through the actions of individuals’ (Wight, 2007: 187), and from the relevant passages in Bhaskar’s work it is clear that Bhaskar also means that there are two things in the social world, individuals and structures. It is unclear whether Bhaskar intends structures to include such things as trade unions or prayer meetings, transnational de-centred social movements or just formal institutions, but it is clear for Bhaskar that structures are ‘enabling, not just coercive’ of individuals (Bhaskar 1989: 43). This ambiguity is important, because we get little sense in Wight’s work that irreducible corporate agency exists. Indeed, even when Wight discusses Bob Jessop’s Marxist social theory it is only the structural elements he highlights. Paraphrasing Jessop, Wight posits that ‘[a] state can be considered a structuratum consisted of many structured organisational entities and institutions, which are themselves structured in certain ways.’ (Wight 2007: 219) Within these structures, the only things that exist that are of sufficient ontological import to warrant inclusion in any state theory, are individuals. Here Wight leans on Ralph Miliband and argues that ‘it is in … government institutions that state power lies (or something), and it is through them that power is wielded by people who occupy the leading positions in each of these intuitions’ (Ibid: 182). In these, ‘complex institutional ensembles’ individuals are both constrained and enabled depending on their subject-position within the state. The state is ‘the totality of this structured ensemble’ (Ibid: 220). Wight is categorical: ‘State activity is always the activity of particular individuals acting within particular social forms.’ (Ibid: 188). ‘If the state has agency, it can only be accessed through the agency of individuals’ (Ibid: 189). ‘In short the state does not exercise power, but facilitates the exercise of power by agents.’ (Ibid: 220) 10 Perhaps if given the opportunity Wight would pluralise his social ontology to include social groups, but the evidence he presents here, social groups are ontologically insignificant. What is more striking, is the political individualism that emerges from the analysis. Are we to assume therefore that we are but isolated individuals related through structures not of our own making with no link to others other than through said structures and institutions? Can I not share my identity with someone I have never met not ever come into contact with? Does our shared identity not constitute us as a (small) group and would we not have a collective capacity that is irreducible to either structures or institutions? If I were an isolated Catholic priest during the reformation, or an intellectual during Pol Pot’s reign, the mere fact that there were others like me whom I may never have met, and the fact of our collective existence, was enough to justify massive repression and killing. Surely the force of our collective existence – and little if anything more – is theoretically significant for the ontology of politics? In the final analysis it seems that because Colin Wight is so determined to provide an antidote to Wendt’s collectivism, that he lays disproportionate emphasis on individuals. But what does Wight say about groups? He first defines them on methodologically individualist grounds, as a collection of individuals, and then dismisses them on these grounds as being unrealistic. This is a clear mis-reading of Wendt and the wider literatures. Wight argues that ‘[t]he simple point is that the state is not simply a group of individuals, nor is it composed of only a collection of groups. Groups are not the issue in relation to state agency unless the state is nothing more than a group of individuals.’ (Wight, 2007: 186) Despite the fact that this sentence makes little sense, surely if we define groups in theoretically consistent emergentist terms then we can posit their agency? We might then find that ‘the social’ is complicated for Wight because groups and individuals would both co-exist within complex institutional ensembles and agency would be far more complex than humans acting. The challenge for IR (not to mention positing its disciplinary autonomy) would then be far more challenging. To theorise the relationship between individuals, emergent groups, the structures within groups, and the structures that relate them to one another (or not as the case may be) is a hugely complex task. It is nevertheless far more realistic than juxtaposing individuals and structures with collective agent. Following Seamus Miller, Wight does argue that to explain social outcomes we need to distinguish between social groups, institutions and organisations. This should be a fantastic addition to his theory. By showing that groups, institutions (rules, norms etc) and organisations (structures) are functionally distinct but overlap, this would allow us to disaggregate states and embedded them in wider complexes of other organisations, social groups and institutions. Yet Wight maintains that ‘social groups consist of a set of individuals who participate in a number of spheres, or fields, of activity governed by a common structure’ REFERENCE. Wight is surely right to bring individual agency back to IR and to show how the state is a complex structure, but is this really all there is? And finally, because Wight sees structures everywhere, like the green numbers floating down the screen in The Matrix, he is incapable of understanding or conceptualising the concept of anarchy. In one of the two places Wight discusses the concept of anarchy he sees it as a structure. ‘Anarchy […as a structure] has to be seen as part of what a state is, and what a state does’ (Wight, 2007: 293). This makes little sense and the reason for this, I content, is because Wight has an unrealistic social ontology. Proudhon, Pluralism and the State as a ‘natural Group’ 11 The politics of corporate agency have been with us from the seventeenth century at least. Hobbes’ Leviathan, Rousseau’s General Will, the theories of Collective Reason central to the political philosophy of the Enlightenment were rejected by the Kantians but widely used by everyone else. It goes without saying that the theory of corporate agency is quintessentially political. Here I want to discuss the way Proudhon’s theory of corporate agency fed through into what is the first anarchist state theory.4 The text I will discuss here is the fourth of thirteen études of Proudhon’s magnum opus, De la Justice dans la Révolution et dans l’Église. Essais d’une Philosophie Populaire (1860), entitled L’État (pp. 106-152). In this particular étude, or study, Proudhon sets out three forms of state theory: the state theory of necessity, providential state theory, and the state according to his own theory of justice. The first is that of the church which posits a transcendental and unchanging natural order; the second is of the philosophers or metaphysicians and is premised on a providentialist philosophy of history. Proudhon’s alternative is the theory of the Revolution, which is to say historical and scientific, one in which he sets out his ‘revolutionary ontology’ (ibid: 137) and his theory of the reality of social forces. This is set out in the last forty pages of the study entitled ‘Petit Catéchisme Politique’. The secular religion suggested by the title was typical of all works of social theory at the time and links the text to Comte’s sociological and historical attempt to construct a scientific ‘Religion of Humanity’. The connections between Comte and Proudhon are implicit but have been widely commented upon (Bouglé, Haubtmann, Vernon). Proudhon rejected Comte’s collectivism while he embraced a theory of collective agency. He embraced Kant’s individualism while he rejected the idealism and irrealism of his method. What we find in Proudhon’s ideas is a theory of the state as a group, how the state and other social groups relate to one another, and how the individual and the group are related. What I will show is that throughout this we find in Proudhon a theory of how law provides the formal structure of social order sustained by force. As I hope to show, Proudhon’s theory allows us to move beyond the sticking point in current thinking about the state in contemporary IR by showing that it is not the only group, that individuals and groups are intimately related and that the of the structures and institutions which relate them to one another, Proudhon believes law to provide the rules of the game. There are clear normative, political and ethical consequences of this theory that I will outline as we proceed. The section is structured in the following way. First I want to establish Proudhon’s credentials as a scientific realist in order to show that Wendt, Wight and Proudhon are all talking about the same thing in the same sorts of ways. Illustrating his debt to August Comte will show that my interpretation of his work is also not anachronistic. Second, I will set out Proudhon’s theory of collective force. The key will be to show that Proudhon does not conflate society with the state, but conceptualises all social groups as having relative autonomy vis-à-vis one another. I then give two examples of how Proudhon uses the concepts of alienation and appropriation to illustrate the ways in which individuals relate to groups. I will then discuss how he understands internal structures and inter-groups structures. While there are a number of obvious normative issues that arise from this discussion, I will focus only on those raised in the previous discussion – namely the moral status of groups and individuals. What I will argue is that if we value the autonomy of wither, a statist political ontology is counter-productive. By de-centering the state I also show that anarchy is far more complex than we generally assume it to be. From this perspective, anarchism suggests far more in the way of conceptual and political innovation. As far as I am aware, other than Kropotkin’s The State: Its Historic Role and Bakunin’s Statism and Anarchy, there is, ironically, little by way of explicit state theory in the anarchist literature. 4 12 As the eminent sociologist George Gurvitch has argued, Proudhon set out his ‘social science’ in the context of the intellectual hegemony of Saint-Simonianism and the sociological positivism of Auguste Comte (Gurvitch 1965: 31). Positivism had a bad name even then, and it is for this reason that Proudhon refused either the term sociology or positivism for his work, though there are clear echoes. One of the core features of Comte’s sociology was its philosophical realism and its structural materialism. In Proudhon’s work as in Comte’s, what this implied in practice was a critique of nominalism, or the philosophical idealism which ‘made collective beings and of the power (puissance) within it […mere] words or conceptions’ (Proudhon 1860: 135). Proudhon set out his philosophical realism in the following way: Science tells us that all bodies are composite […] held together by an attraction, a force […] which the intelligence can only grasp through its manifestations and as the expression of a relation. The RELATION, there, in the final analysis, is what all phenomenology, all reality, all force all existence, boils down to’ (ibid). Force is what holds relations together or breaks them down. On the first page of his ‘Short Political Catechism’ Proudhon argues that force is an inherent capacity of all things, indeed, ‘force is inherent or immanent in being’ (ibid: 111) and as I will show, ‘immanent in society’ (ibid: 116). Let us begin with inert or inanimate objects. Proudhon argues that they exert force-as-resistance. Other things exert force in more obvious ways, either through chemical processes, through gravity, and so on. In the social world force underlies all social relations in the same way as force underlies all natural relations. From public opinion to a punch in the face, from war to joinery, there are relations of force within them all. The aim is to clarify and distinguish between them and to build a social theory atop this clarification. Proudhon distinguishes between la force, puissance and pouvoir. The former is a base capacity, the second a collective product (three guys using the force of their muscles to move a large rock) and the third is a political and social capacity (ibid: 112). In the latter, the way in which rock-pushing is organised and directed is power and demands cognition. As Viewed in this way we can see what Proudhon means when he argues that ‘power is immanent in society’ (Proudhon 1863: 116). These distinctions become important when we discuss the nature of collective forces, but all we need retain here is that force is at the base of Proudhon’s realist, relational ontology. All things in nature exert force and all social relations are asymmetric. This implies that we can only understand force in relation to other things – not in and of itself. When forces cohere and combine, the cumulative result is more than and irreducible to the sum of its parts and the relations that constitute puissance or pouvoir are of necessity ‘commutative’ (ibid: 133, 114). This implies two things, that they exhibit no transcendent principle of ordering and that the ordering exhibits no necessary or natural hierarchy. Out of the constitutive or commutative arrangement of the parts ‘a force emerges (jaillit)’ (ibid: 117). It is the character of this emergent force, a force as real as all others but irreducible to any one other thing, that is of principle concern for us here. Our purpose here is to understand the reality and collective character of social groups. Proudhon argues that the emergent character of groups is determined not only by the individual characters of those that populate them, but also by the way in which the group is internally organised – the way power is arranged. Proudhon begins by following Kant 13 arguing that ‘the end of man is in himself’ (Proudhon 1988/1998: 347). However, Proudhon also argues that ‘collective beings are as much realities as individuals’ (Proudhon 1988/1998: 694); ‘just as individualism is the primordial factor in humanity, so association is its complementary term. Both are present constantly.’ (Edwards 1969: 232) While they are present constantly, and individuals are ends in themselves, pace Kant, Proudhon argued that ‘the action of society on the individual is immense. The result is that man can never completely escape this influence in any of his acts, in any of his sentiments, in any of his predispositions or in the potentialities of his nature’. (Proudhon 1988/1990: 1565) However, Proudhon is clear that ‘synthetic ideas’ that arise from the confluence of opinions are ‘very different, often also the inverse of my own conclusions […] But let it be noted that this conversion does not assume the condemnation of individuality; it presupposes it.’ (Proudhon 1988/1990: 1261) The means to the realisation of the political power of a group, and in order to respect the autonomy of individuals and the equality with this social anarchy, direct democracy is the key. If political right is inherent in man and the citizen, consequently if all suffrage must be direct, the same right is also logically inherent to each group naturally formed by citizens, to each corporation, each commune or city; and suffrage in each of these groups must be equally direct. (Proudhon 1865:286 emphasis added) Once so realised, the ‘collective being is neither phantom nor abstraction, but an existence’ (Proudhon 1988/1990: 724) and the ‘quality of social power will vary, its intensity will rise and fall, depending on the number and the differences of groups’. ‘Unity’ however, ‘is immutability.’ (Proudhon 1863: 118) In La Guerre et la Paix (1998 [1863]) Proudhon relates this sentiment to a wider political and historical sociology. The idea of universal sovereignty, the ideal of the Middle Ages and formulated in Charlemagne’s pact, is the negation of the independence and the autonomy of States and the negation of all human liberty, something in which States and nations are eternally right to refuse. Moreover, that would be to oppose change in humanity, precisely as despotism in a State, or communism in a tribe is the immobilisation of that State or tribe. Civilization only moves but for the influence that political groups exert upon one another, exercising the full plenitude of their sovereignty and independence; constrain them all from above and the great organism will halt; neither life nor idea. (Proudhon 1998a: 293) Social dynamism is a function of difference and diversity, where individuals and social forces have free reign. Unity, the doctrine of the Jacobins and Collectivists would bring this movement to a halt. This can also be usefully compared with Comte’s collectivism. For him “Collective Organisms”, societies or states, are not only real but historically providential. In these strictly hierarchical and technocratic societies, the ‘Priest Scientists’ were the only individuals accorded any right to freedom of choice. Positivism was the new ‘Religion of Humanity’ and society had to be structured in such a way that it was completely harmonious – from top to bottom. All that was needed was for ‘Men of Genius’ to divine the correct form of society and then preach the good news and convince all to follow. This newly divined ‘nature of things […] absolutely prohibits freedom of choice by showing, from several distinct points of view, the class of scientists to be the only one suited to carry out the theoretical work of social reorganisation.’ (Comte 1998a: 76) Critical theorists, like Kant or Rousseau were fundamentally misguided in thinking that individuals were in any way bearers 14 of natural rights of any sort. This, ‘the critical prejudice that conceives moral sovereignty as an innate right in each individual[,] would be insurmountable by anyone other than them [Priest Scientists].’ (Comte 1998a 77) Furthermore, since civilization follows only one, predetermined and absolute law, ‘which dominates all particular human differences’ asserting individuality is quite simply a waste of time. (Comte: 1998a: 97) In Comte’s system while the individual is vital to the Collective Organism, politically it then becomes completely subservient to it. Pickering has pointed out, ‘in a sense Rousseau’s Legislator lived on in Comte’s spiritual power’, (Pickering 1993:707), which is something of an understatement, and as Manuel has argued, ‘[t]he impression is inescapable that in the positivist religion there is a total loss of personality as man is merged in the perfect transcendent unity of Humanity.’ (Manuel, 1965: 281) Proudhon makes much the same argument about communism, which at that time was relatively embryonic, but which he understood perfectly. ‘Communism’, he argued, would mean, the indivision of power, an absorbing centralisation, the systematic destruction of all individual thought, corporative and local, considered dividing [scissionnaire]; an inquisitorial police, the abolition or at least the restriction of the family, and even of heredity; universal suffrage organised in such a way as to serve as a perpetual sanction of this anonymous tyranny of the preponderance of the mediocre or scum, always in majority, over the capable citizens and the independent characters, declared subject and naturally in small number. (Proudhon, 1865:115) Let us flesh this out with a counter-example. Proudhon briefly mentions orchestras. Individual material instruments are vital to the collective product of the labour of the orchestra, but the music which issues cannot be reduced to any one material instrument. Indeed, in the same way that instruments are collections of forces (the density of the wood, the tension in the strings), individuals that play instruments have their own irreducible styles and characters with which they relate to the instrument and the score. In an orchestra musicians do not do as they please; they alienate that part of their autonomy necessary to produce collective ends – the music. The musicians also alienate part of their autonomy to the conductor who then guides the music and gives it his or her own interpretation. The musicians are not ‘cultural dopes’ and, maintaining our relational ontology, the conductor cannot ‘be’ without his or her orchestra. These social relations constitute the social force, or pouvoir politique, of the orchestra. It might not seem formally political, but organisation demands politics. However, the relationship is not mutually constitutive, since the collective force that emerges from the orchestra, rather than each individual musician, is irreducible, directed and there is a process of feedback. The relations are more complex than simple coconstitution. Another example prominent throughout Proudhon’s work is that of the workshop. Let us assume a capitalist workshop in which the workers produce and the manager coordinates. We have tools, social puissance again and social power. However, the alienation of the workers’ autonomy is of a quite different sort to that of our orchestra. In capitalist social relations the workers alienate not only their individual labour-time but also the collective product of that collective labour. Collective puissance produces surplus irreducible to any one individual, since without the collective itself, the surplus would be impossible. However, the capitalist has legal title to this surplus, profit or emergent product, of collective labour and can make off with it alone. The relation of individuals to one another, and of the capitalist individual to the workshop, is characterised by alienation and appropriation with the social relations 15 sanctified by law and defended by force. We could easily make a similar argument vis-à-vis representative democracies. Rousseau’s General Will, for example, is the collective expression of the political agency of individuals, but in reality, in the representative system, individuals appropriate this alienated political autonomy and the political class constitute the state-as-group with an emergent force, puissance and pouvoir of their own: it is, he argued, like in the factory system, ‘collective force converted into monopoly’ (Proudhon 1860: 120). Proudhon attributed collective forces with ‘individuality’ (ibid: 112), but stopped a long way from attributing them with personhood. Each one of these groups, ‘might be regarded as a social embryo’ and, when considered collectively, ‘form the base of political power’ (ibid). What he does say, however, is that they have varied capacity, and this capacity is also derived from the types of collective forces they are. In De la Capacite Politique des Classes Ouvurieres, which he narrated on his deathbed in 1865, he specifies two types of capacity: legal and real. The former is ascribed, the latter demonstrable. Law ‘confers’ (Proudhon 1982: 88) capacity upon individuals and groups by supporting or prohibiting them by force. ‘Real’ capacity, on the other hand, is pre-legal or socially emergent derived from the forces that underpin law. Proudhon argued that for a group or individual to have real capacity it must have three further properties. First, it must have consciousness of itself, its dignity, value and place in society. Secondly, the group or individual must affirm this idea as a manifestation of its understanding of social life. Finally, it is no good to simply think it through and proclaim it – the idea of collective or individual capacity must be affirmed practically (ibid: 88-89). Over time, different groups emerge and constitute themselves in various ways for collective ends and treaties and law constitute not only the internal relations of groups, but also intergroup relations. The Magna Carta, for example, specified the inter-relationships between the King and Barons, while the contemporary constellation of the British political system is one which originally recognised a particular constellation of quite distinct collective force: the Lords, the Commons, the King or monarchy, and with the emergence of the Labour party in the twentieth century, the workers or people. However, social groups need not be part of the political order in order to have collective force and constitute social power. Consider the emergence of an industrial labour movement and its unionisation, the rise of religious groups, student groups, terrorist groups, and so forth. Each of these groups is historically situated and asymmetrically related. Their relations are formalised in law, but law does not constitute their reality nor is it the extent of their social relations. For Proudhon law, constitutions and treaties were essentially the same thing: the codification of ‘balance of economic and social forces’ (Proudhon 1860: 131; cf. Proudhon 1863:129). Society is naturally composed of plural social forces, collective and individual. While modern liberal society might have individuated its constitutive elements and bourgeois law refuses to recognise the autonomy of the association, ‘natural groups’ can also persist without political form, solely as puissance. The mark of civilisation, Proudhon argues, is the ability of social groups and inter-social relations to function harmoniously and continue to do so on the basis of both unspoken and formalised constitutional agreement; the more complex, harmonious and auto-kinetic, the more civilised that society. When the social conventions which hold these relations of grouppower break down, society collapses, illustrating how fragile social order is, but also, given the relative infrequency of civilisational collapse, how relatively enduring and stable it is. The flaw in Wight and Wendt’s social ontology then, is to assume that the state is some super-group, or that groups don’t matter. We can also show, through a discussion of the role of law, constitutions and treaties, how we might understand institutions and structures from 16 Proudhon’s perspective. There are clear political and ontological, not to mention ethical issues at stake here. What is the normative value of the individual, the ethical value of group autonomy? To what degree is the state right to be sovereign over all other groups? If states are not the only groups, is not anarchy the constitutive form of all social relations considered in reality, rather than legally? Conclusion I have argued that while Wendt seems to conflate the state with all social groups and Wight seems unwilling to give groups even relative ontological autonomy, Proudhon assigns all groups with political importance because he sees all groups as real. The state is but one such group. The issue of individual autonomy is nicely resolved by Proudhon also. We can see that individuals have complex relations to groups and we might complicate it further here by arguing that individuals can be members of more than one group at once and multiple groups can be related in asymmetric ways within and across other, wider social groups. How this maps out is an empirical not a theoretical issue from here. All groups are not subsumed within a state in reality, even though they are such legally. The law, it can be argued, is often wrong. Raising this issue and exploring it further is beyond the scope of this paper, but needless to say, there are a wide variety of anarchist responses to the issue. What I have not made clear, at least not fully, is how this changes the way we understand the ontology of global politics. First, I have argued that anarchist political theory provides novel conceptual tools for understanding how order is created in anarchy. The key here was to have an adequate understanding of the nature of the social which meant, in turn, conceptualizing the relationship between individuals and social groups. I have argued that not only are states not the only groups, but that nor are they the precondition of social order. Not only is this more than evident from the writings of theorists of world politics vis-à-vis order in the anarchical society of states (Bull 1979), but also as Proudhon has argued vis-à-vis the social order as well. Secondly, I suggested that anarchists were right to argue that states and capitalism are the symbiotic precondition of disorder and conflict. The key here is the appropriation and monopolization of the collective reason through the monopolization and appropriation of alienated political force, and the in capitalism the monopolization and appropriation of alienated surplus of collective productive force. A separate theory, one it is impossible to develop here, must account for the way in which this appropriation causes conflict, but the basis for the hypothesis is clear enough. From this anarchists will argue that both state and capitalism are detrimental to human autonomy and flourishing. Thus, finally, and given the above, anarchists actively seek a world without sovereigns, of either the capitalist, sovereign proprietors sort, or the more conventional statist form of sovereignty. Anarchy, or anarchism, is what our state theory makes it. Anarchy is the background condition of all politics. There is no transcendent order nor is there a natural form to society. As such, the way we see society and the state, usually in IR this is framed through state theory, determines what anarchy is. This is the same with anarchism. If one assumes that order is only possible because of states, clearly anarchists will be anathema to your existential peace. If you do not see order in this way, anarchism becomes something quite different: a perspective on a perennial problem perhaps, or a set of tools to understand the system in which we live. 17 Bibliography (incomplete) Ansart, Pierre. "La Présence Du Proudhonisme Dans Les Sociologies Contemporaines." Mil Neuf Cent: Revue d'Histoire Intellectuelle 10 (1992): 94-110. ———. "Proudhon À Travers Le Temps." L'Homme et Société 123-124 (1997): 17-24. Ansart, Pierre Attache. Sociologie De Proudhon. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1967. Archer, Margaret. S. Realist Social Theory: The Morphogenetic Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995. Aron, Raymond. Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations. Translated by Richard Howard and Annette Baker Fox. New York: Doubleday, 1966. Ashley, Richard K. "Imposing International Purpose: Notes on a Problematic of Governance." In Global Changes and Theoretical Challenges: Approaches to World Politics for the 1990s, edited by Ernst-Otto Czempiel and James N. Rosenau, 251-90. Cambridge, Mass: Lexington, 1989. ———. "Untying the Sovereign State: A Double Reading of the Anarchy Problematique." Millennium 17, no. 2 (1988): 227-62. Axelrod, Robert, and William D. Hamilton. "The Evolution of Cooperation." Science 211, no. 4489 (1981): 1390-96. Barnard, F.M. , and Richard Vernon. "Pluralism, Participation, and Politics: Reflections on the Intermediate Group." Political Theory 3, no. 2 (1975): 180-97. Berth, Édouard. "Proudhon En Sorbonne." L'Indipéndence, no. 27 (1912): 122-40. Bhaskar, Roy. The Possibility of Naturalism: A Philosophical Critique of the Contemporary Human Sciences. 3rd ed. London: Routledge, 1989. ———. A Realist Theory of Science. [2nd ed.] ed. Hassocks: Harvester Press [etc.], 1978. Booth, Ken. "Security in Anarchy: Utopian Realism in Theory and Practice." International Affairs 67, no. 3 (1991): ???? Bouglé, Celestin. La Sociologie De Proudhon. Paris: Armand Colin, 1911. Bouglé, Célestin Charles Alfred. Proudhon. Paris: F. Alcan, 1930. Bull, Hedley. The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics. London: Macmillan, 1977. Chambost, Sophie. Proudhon Et La Norm: Pensé Juridique D'un Anarchiste. Rennes: Presses Universitaires de Rennes, 2004. Clark, Ian Mar, and Ian Mar Reform and resistance in the international order Clark. The Hierarchy of States : Reform and Resistance in the International Order. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989. Comte, Auguste. "Plan of the Scientific Work Necessary for the Reorganisation of Society." In Comte: Early Political Writings, edited by H. S. Jones, 47-144. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. ———. System of Positive Polity. Translated by Edward Spencer Beesly et al. New York: Burt Franklin, 1968. Cox, Robert. "Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory." In Approaches to World Order, edited by Robert Cox and Timothy Sinclair, 85-123. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996. Durkheim, Emile. The Division of Labour in Society, Contemporary Social Theory. Theoretical Traditions in the Social Sciences. London: Macmillan, 1984. ———. On Suicide, Penguin Classics. London: Penguin, 2006. Edwards, Stewart, ed. Selected Writings of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon. London: Macmillan, 1969. 18 Falk, Richard. "Anarchism and World Order." In Nomos Xix: Anarchism, edited by J. Roland Pennock and John Chapman, 63-87. New York: New York University Press, 1979. Gurvitch, Georges. Proudhon: Sa Vie, Son Oeuvre Avec Un Exposé De Sa Philosophie. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1965. Haubtmann, Pierre. La Philosophie Sociale De P.-J. Proudhon. Grenoble: Presses Universitaires de Grenoble, 1980. Humphreys, Joshua M. "Durkheimian Sociology and 20th-Century Politics: The Case of Célestin Bouglé." History of the Human Sciences 12, no. 3 (1999): 117-38. Jessop, Bob. State Theory : Putting the Capitalist State in Its Place. Cambridge: Polity, 1990. Keohane, Robert O. After Hegemony : Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy. Princeton: Guildford : Princeton University Press, 1984. Milner, Helen. "The Assumption of Anarchy in International Relations Theory: A Critique." Review of International Studies 17 (1991): 67-85. Nelson, Ralph. "The Federal Principle in French Political Thought." In Federalism as Grand Design: Political Philosophers and the Federal Principle, edited by Daniel J. Elazar. Lanham: University Press of America, 1987. Noland, Aaron. "Pierre-Joseph Proudhon - Socialist as Social Scientist." American Journal of Economics and Sociology 26 (1967): 313-28. ———. "Proudhon's Sociology of War." The American Journal of Economics and Sociology 29, no. 3 (1970): 289-304. Prichard, Alex. 2007. "Justice, Order and Anarchy: The International Political Theory of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon (1809-1865)." Millennium: Journal of International Studies 35(3):623-645. Prichard Forthcoming a ‘Ethical Foundations of Proudhon’s Republican Anarchism’ Prichard Forthcoming b. ‘What can the Absence… Prichard forthcoming c. ‘Deepening Anarchism’ Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph. Du Principe Fédératif Et De La Nécessité De Reconstituer Le Parti De La Révolution. (Inc) Si Les Traités De 1815 Ont Cessé D'exister. Paris: Ernest Flammarion, 1863. ———. France Et Rhin, Oeuvres Posthumes De P. J. Proudhon. Paris: A. Lacroix, Verboeckhoven et Companie, 1868. ———. La Fédération Et L'unité En Italie. Paris: E. Dentu, 1862. ———. La Guerre Et La Paix, Recherches Sur La Principe Et La Constitution Du Droit Des Gens. Nouvelle ed. 2 vols. Paris: Editions Tops, 1998. ———. La Guerre Et La Paix, Recherches Sur La Principe Et La Constitution Du Droit Des Gens. II vols. Paris: E. Dentu, 1861. ———. Nouvelles Observations Sur L'unité Italienne. Paris: E. Dentu, 1865. Sinclair, Adriana, and Michael Byers. "When Us Scholars Speak of 'Sovereignty', What Do They Mean?" Political Studies 55, no. 2 (2007): 318-40. Teschke, Benno. The Myth of 1648 : Class, Geopolitics, and the Making of Modern International Relations. London: Verso, 2003. Urry, John. Global Complexity. Oxford: Polity, 2002. Walker, R.B.J. Inside/Outside: International Relations as Political Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993. Wendt, Alexander. "Anarchy Is What States Make of It: The Social Construction of Power Politics." International Organization 46, no. 2 (1992): 391-425. ———. Social Theory of International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999. ———. "The State as Person in International Theory." Review of international studies 30, no. 2 (2004): 289-316. 19 ———. "Why a World State Is Inevitable." European Journal of International Relations 9, no. 4 (2003): 491-542. Wight, Colin. Agents, Structures and International Relations: Politics as Ontology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006. ———. "State Agency and Human Activity." Review of International Studies 30, no. 2 (2004): 269-80. 20