Immanuel Kant vs. AJ Ayer: A Comparison By Darren Coughtrey (B.Math) Carleton University Before the advent of Non-Euclidean Geometry in the late nineteenth century, mainstream philosophy was dominated by the many ideas set forth in Immanuel Kant’s* Critique of Pure Reason. It was thought that Kant’s quest to define truth had come closer than any other philosopher up until that time, and set philosophy on the path to becoming an exact science. Kant’s philosophy relied heavily on the distinction between synthetic and analytic propositions, and it was upon the foundation of his views about the necessity and certainty of the axioms of Euclidean Geometry that Kant built much of his doctrine. Since the discovery of consistent Non-Euclidean Geometries by the likes of Hilbert, Poincaré, and Lambert in the late eighteen hundreds, Kant has been, perhaps unfairly, widely attacked and his view of truth, especially with respect to mathematics, has been all but discredited. This paper will give a brief introduction to Kant’s perspective, but then focus on one such criticism of his philosophy, namely that which Sir A.J Ayer set forth in the mid 1900’s. Additional examples will be taken from the writings of famous philosophers such as Bertrand Russell and Ludwig Wittgenstein, in order to show how Ayer made the progression from the philosophy of Kant to what he propounds in his seminal work Language, Truth and Logic. In order to succeed in molding philosophy into an exact science Kant needed a way to quantify human reasoning. What he came up with was to use the natural partition of all statements into two categories: analytic and synthetic. He defines an analytic * As this paper is intended for students of mathematics, who may not have much background in philosophy, more biographical information may be of use. For a concise account of Kant’s life and works consult the following web page: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Kant statement as one in which the predicate of the statement belongs to the subject, and a synthetic statement is one in which the predicate is external to the subject. He says: “Thus it is evident: 1. that through analytic judgment our knowledge is in no way extended, and that the concept which I already have is merely set forth and made intelligible to me; 2. that in synthetic judgments I must have besides the concept of the subjects something else (X), upon which the understanding may rely, if it is to know that a predicate, not contained in this concept, nevertheless belongs to it” (Critique of Pure Reason, Introduction) The first interesting fact about these definitions is that the predicate in an analytic judgment lies within the subject of the statement; therefore, the truth of an analytic statement is given linguistically and not through experience. That is to say, analytic statements are a priori, rather than empirical. For instance, when considering the statement “All men at the Canadian Undergraduate Math Conference are men” we need not go any further than the statement itself to observe its validity, making it an analytic a priori statement (see Figure 1). We can also see from this is that there are no empirical analytic statements, since the truth of an analytic statement is given without appeal to the senses (i.e. empirical facts). Now, it is easy to see that there are synthetic statements whose truth is found empirically, such as “All participants of the Canadian Undergraduate Math Conference are male”. There is nothing intrinsic to the subject “participants of the Canadian Undergraduate Math Conference” that implies that it would be a male. Thus, we need some experience outside of the subject to be able to validate, or refute, this statement. In this case it may a survey of all participants, a thorough check of all of their birth certificates, or, if we wish to go to extremes, a medical examination of everyone at the conference. The point is that some empirical fact is needed to make sense of this statement. (Figure 1) What is not clear is whether a synthetic statement can be given a priori. In fact, before Kant, it was thought that analytic statements were the only a priori truths, and synthetic statements were all empirical facts. However, Kant argued that there must exist synthetic a priori statements, and that they must spring from pure understanding and reason. What is important to the purpose of this paper is Kant’s belief that the existence of synthetic a priori statements is drawn from his view of the nature of mathematical reasoning. He argues that, because empirical statements are validated through experience, they are inherently fallible, and accordingly cannot be necessary truths or absolute certainties. Mathematical judgments must be a priori as they carry with them necessity and certainty, which cannot be obtained by experience. Furthermore, he states that mathematical propositions must be synthetic; his point is easily shown by way of an example, such as the statement of Euclidean Geometry that says “The shortest distance between two points is a straight line”*. Kant’s belief is that nowhere in the defined terms “point” and “straight line” is there any consideration of distance, so this statement relies on concept outside of the statement itself. Hence such statements must be synthetic, and coupled with their presumed absolute certainty and necessity, we must conclude that they are synthetic a priori. Kant proceeds with such arguments to build his theory of space (using the “certainty” of the Euclidean Axioms), and time (using similar notions for the laws of arithmetic), which set the foundation for his schema of “Metaphysics as Science”. Kant’s Critique was a breakthrough in philosophical thought, but because it was based on the apparent absolute certainty of mathematics, and Euclidean Geometry in particular, it was left vulnerable to criticism when Non-Euclidean Geometries were discovered towards the end of the 19th century. It was especially damning to Kant and his followers when, in 1899, David Hilbert proved that Non-Euclidean Geometries were as consistent as the geometry of Euclid. Perhaps Kant’s philosophy may have been salvaged if it were found that either geometry was true if the other were false. However to have them being, in some sense, equally as true could be seen as an outright deathblow to the Kantian Doctrine. Now, with one of philosophy’s most prized theories left in limbo, the philosophy of Kant naturally drew the attention of some the world’s brightest minds - all of whom wanted to know what could be salvaged, or what needed to be changed in order to rectify these discrepancies. Moreover, since the holes left in the theory set forth in The Critique Strictly speaking, this is not a statement from Euclid’s Elements, but rest assured it is a statement of Euclidean Geometry. See the following for a detailed proof: http://mathworld.wolfram.com/Point-PointDistance2-Dimensional.html * were of a mathematical nature, many of these scholars were some of the most famous mathematicians of their time. For instance it was around this time when Bertrand Russell published his Essay on the Foundations of Geometry, in which he conjectures several interesting deviations to Kant’s theory. He says, with regard to the synthetic-analytic distinction, that no statement can be taken as purely analytic or purely synthetic. He argues that in making such a distinction for a given statement we are taking it out of its original context, and thus robbing it of any validity. For example, a given theorem of mathematics is a deduction within a larger system, and thus analytic, but it also forms new relationships within the system, and in this way it is synthetic. Ludwig Wittgenstein was also that was drawn to the study of truth through his work in formal logic, much like Russell. Although his work, at first sight, does not seem to pertain to this study, with the knowledge we have gain thus far, it is not hard to tell that Wittgenstein must have given some thought to the system of truth proposed by Kant. In his famous work Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus he states: “If a thought were true a priori, it would be a thought whose possibility ensured its truth. A priori knowledge that a thought were true would be possible only if its truth were recognizable from the thought itself” (Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, 3.04&3.05) So without, naming Kant directly, Wittgenstein clearly states that he does not adhere to Kant’s belief in synthetic a priori truths. Clearly Wittgenstein and Russell have published differing views on the distinctions made by Kant*. However, what they do have in common is that they were two of the forefathers of modern logic, and with this they have both garnered renown and wide spread influence. One place that their influence is directly observed in modern philosophy is within the work of a group of scholars who came to be known as the Vienna Circle. In the 1930’s and 40’s this group of men produced a large amount of original philosophy by mixing their backgrounds in classical philosophy with the logical philosophies of Russell and Wittgenstein. A young Englishman, Sir A.J Ayer, became the Circle’s flag bearer when, in 1936, he published his inspired work called Language, Truth, and Logic. The philosophy of Ayer and the Vienna Circle, which came to be known as Logical Positivism, can be seen as a sort of empiricism in the vain of David Hume that also draws upon the logical philosophies of Russell and Wittgenstein. It was Hume’s contention that the human mind gets confused when dealing with statements that venture beyond the limits of experience, and thus that metaphysics is a useless endeavor. Ayer’s main goal, however, was to show that not only was metaphysics useless, but also that metaphysical utterances carried no meaning whatsoever, thus showing that metaphysics as a whole was not possible. In doing so Ayer went against the doctrine of Kant in several ways. We shall focus on their differing ideas with respect to mathematics via the synthetic-analytic distinction we discussed earlier. * From the passages above it may seem that Russell and Wittgenstein endorse opposing philosophies, but it must be noted that Essay on the Foundations of Geometry is an early work of Russell’s, and that Russell and Wittgenstein were colleagues and collaborators. Russell’s later views were more in synch with those of Wittgenstein, but, as we shall see, Russell’s earlier views of the synthetic-analytic distinction did not go unheralded. Ayer agrees with Russell, in that they both feel that Kant erred in his definition of the synthetic-analytic distinction. Both men claim that Kant’s definitions are not mutually exclusive. However Ayer agrees with Wittgenstein in their belief that there does indeed exist an analytic-synthetic partition. Ayer reworks Kant’s definitions by saying that “a statement is analytic when its validity depends solely on the definitions of the symbols it contains, and synthetic when its validity is determined by facts of experience” (Ayer 1936, pg 73). What one should notice about Ayer’s definitions is that he has automatically ruled out Kant’s concept of synthetic a priori truths, since Ayer believes any synthetic is validated through experience. Ayer also contradicts Kant by saying that analytic statements do, in a way, give us new knowledge. He claims that an analytic statement, although showing us what was already deducible, does bring forward new linguistic usages for the subjects of such statements. This is an idea very closely linked to that of Russell quoted previously. For example, what Ayer is saying is that if we are given an analytic statement like “All dogs are animals”, then we’ve added to our knowledge because we can now use the term “dog” in certain sentences pertaining to animals and vice versa. It is in this way, he claims, that analytic statements “can reveal unexpected implications in our assertions and beliefs” (Ayer 1936, pg 75). In accordance with this result, Ayer states further that the statements of mathematics are all analytic, and not synthetic a priori as Kant argued. Geometry, he claims, is the one area of mathematics that is likely to be perceived as being synthetic, but through Ayer’s eyes it is not so. He argues that Kant’s views were based on the fact that geometry was the study of physical space, and hence the propositions of geometry have factual content (i.e. synthetic) and are not merely tautological (i.e. analytic). However, with the emergence of Non-Euclidean Geometry we can see, as Poincaré put it, that the axioms of any geometry are mere definitions and the theorems are simply the logical consequences of these definitions. Thus, a given geometry cannot not be said to be about physical space, and indeed, as a formal axiom system, a geometry is not about anything in particular at all. Ayer does admit, and rightly so, that in this respect Kant was a victim of his time, as he had no knowledge of consistent Non-Euclidean Geometries. So, once Ayer has stripped geometry of the factual basis that Kant depended on, he is free to state that Geometry is analytic, and with this he claims to topple Kant’s theory of space. Kant’s theory of time is similarly based on his assumption that statements of arithmetic were all synthetic a priori; Ayer once again refutes this claim. In his famous example Kant holds that the statement “7+5=12” is synthetic because the term “7+5” subjectively contain the notion of the number 12, and as before he claims that such a statement must be a priori because it carries an absolute certainty that can never be obtained empirically. Ayer contends that logically the term “7+5” is synonymous with the term “12” (i.e. we can always replace “12” with “7+5” and still maintain the validity of any statement containing the term “12”), and thus the sentence “7+5=12” is merely a tautology, which means it is still a priori, but must be analytic. The fact that the statements of arithmetic are tautologies implies that they contain no factual content as Kant supposed for the basis of his system of time. Given this brief introduction to two opposing philosophical theories, it should be obvious that mathematics, and especially Geometry, holds an essential place in the study of philosophy. By contrasting the ideas of Kant with those of Ayer we have seen some striking differences when it comes to the very nature of mathematical thought. By now it should be clear that, within the realm of philosophical thought, mathematics is not as cut and dry as many people studying elementary mathematics might believe. Both Ayer and Kant gave very original views of mathematics in order to support their widely differing theories of metaphysics. However, this paper has only touched upon the underlying mathematical concepts of both theories; the interested reader is strongly encouraged to read further about the purely philosophical aspects of these theories, as the aspects discussed in this paper give rise to some very interesting ideas about the nature of human thought. Bibliography Ayer, A.J. (2001). Language Truth, and Logic. Penguin Books Limited: London, England Ayer, A.J. (1959). Logical Positivisim. The Free Press: New York, New York. Ayer A.J. (1973). The Central Questions of Philosophy. Weidenfeld and Nicolson: London, England Grower, Barry (1987). Logical Positivisim in Perspective: Essays on Language, Truth, and Logic. Croom Helm Ltd.: Croom Helm, Australia. Kant, Immanuel (2003). Critique of Pure Reason. Palgrave MacMillan: New York, New York. Kant, Immanuel (1933). Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. The Open Court Publishing Company: Chicago, Illinois. Russell, Bertrand (1956). Essay on the Foundations of Geometry. Dover Publications, INC: New York, New York. Trudeau, Richard J. (2001). The Non-Euclidean Revolution. Birkhäuser: Boston Mass. Waismann Friedrich (1979). Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle. Basil Blackwell: London, England. Wittgenstein, Ludwig (2004): Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Routledge & Kegan Paul: New York, New York.