SEXING ARGUMENTS Whether an argument is deductive or inductive depends only on purely formal features of the argument, and how it is to be evaluated depends only on what kind of argument it is. I call this the logistical approach and it is the approach that is embedded in tradition. An opposing approach basing the distinction on psychological features of the situation will be shown to be involved in studying a different thing and as having different aims; if it weren’t for the fact that they also want to use arguments as traditionally described and laid down as a set of propositions whose premises are in some relation or other to their conclusion, there would be no conflict between them. A different conceptual apparatus is required to model psychological and epistemic features and “arguments” should be left to logicians. It is, however, conceded that logic gives only a partial account of justification. What is an argument? There have been two rival theories of how best to make the distinction between deductive and inductive arguments, although there is a broad consensus over what such a distinction needs to do and what conditions it needs to satisfy: these are that every argument should be able to be uniquely designated as a valid deductive argument, an invalid deductive argument, a valid inductive argument, or an invalid inductive argument. Whatever the distinction is, it must be mutually exclusive and exhaustive. I suggest in addition that these designations should accord with a certain degree of intuitiveness. The methodological principle here is simple: if it seems strange, or counter-intuitive, or absurd to assert or to judge that p, then the most likely 1 explanation is that p is false, and we should choose the most likely explanation in so far as a rival account has the burden of proof and must show that in some way the likely explanation does not satisfy the other conditions or falls short of its own stated aims, or achieves them only by making ad hoc exceptions. Presuming that the most likely explanation of why some particular argument is judged to be, e.g., deductive, is because it is deductive, I will show in turn that the most likely explanation of why it is deductive is a logistic explanation; other explanations do not meet the burden of proof and furthermore involve counter-intuitive consequences. Just as a chicken-sexer distinguishes baby chicks into male and female without being able to tell how, so also we distinguish between good and bad arguments, between arguments that are deductive or inductive, without necessarily knowing how we do this, and without the theoretical apparatus needed to describe what we are doing even if we did know. In many contexts it is enough of an explanation to say that the reason p is judged to be false is because p is false, but a philosophical context demands an account of those cognizable conditions that sexers’ intuitions track. What is being sexed? The obvious answer is “arguments”. The sexer need say no more than this since he is entitled to take “argument” as a mere name for an unstructured and unclassified entity. The analyst, on the other hand, is immediately faced with an ambiguity in this answer; like the term “statement” that might mean the act of stating or what is stated, and “prediction” that might mean the act of predicting or what is predicted, so also “argument” can mean the act of arguing or what is argued. Is what is being sexed the object/product of the act, or the act itself? The exploration into the underlying structure, and the kind of analytical enterprise enjoined, will vary greatly depending on how we answer. Logicians have always been concerned with the actual structural relations that 2 obtain between the premises and conclusion of the object of argument. The premises and conclusion by themselves individuate the argument from others and determine the logical nature of the relation, i.e., whether the argument is deductive or inductive, and thereby what norm is appropriate for evaluating the argument and whether that norm is satisfied. It is these norms, I claim, that the sexer’s intuitions are tracking in sorting between good and bad arguments. It has recently been claimed (Goddu 2002) that distinguishing between deductive and inductive arguments is an unnecessary distraction, and that all that needs to be evaluated is the strength with which the premises support the argument and the strength with which the premises are required by the context to support the argument, bypassing the deductive/inductive distinction altogether. His claims vary from a modest deflationary position that the inductive/deductive distinction is unimportant – “I see no reason even to attempt to divide arguments into deductive and inductive kinds. The work we wish to accomplish with arguments can be achieved without appealing to this distinction” – to the more extreme position that it doesn’t exist when only a few sentences later he says more hyperbolically, “without appealing to some mythical distinction between inductive and deductive arguments” (Goddu 2002, 15 [my italics]. See also pages 12-13 where he accuses everybody from Locke to Hempel of making a distinction that doesn’t actually exist). This equivocation infects his entire paper. It is also unclear whether he thinks that it is mythical on the grounds that there is no distinction on a purely conceptual level and that the concepts themselves are incoherent in some way, or whether he believes a distinction can be made conceptually but that such concepts do not actually apply to what we usually call arguments, or do not apply in any way that is useful. Goddu bases this contention on cases like where the standard of strength for a 3 jury’s finding a defendant guilty in a criminal trial is higher than for a civil trial. The argument “E; so, C” is held by Goddu to be potentially a “good” or “adequate” argument in a civil trial but a “bad” or “inadequate” argument in a criminal trial; the context determines what standards need to be met, and then we evaluate whether they are met. But what is C here? Goddu (2002, 6) suggests that it is simply that the defendant is guilty, but this is not the case since all the members of a jury can believe that a criminal is guilty and yet still deliver a verdict of “not guilty” because they find reasonable doubt.1 There is a difference between believing somebody to be guilty and “finding” them guilty in the legal sense; the context determines which conclusion is legally relevant, so in this case the conclusion should be “There is no reasonable doubt about the guilt of the defendant”. The premises support a set of distinct but often related conclusions, e.g. {“The defendant is guilty”, “There is reasonable doubt that the defendant is guilty”, “The defendant is more likely to be guilty than not”} from which the context selects the one that is appropriate, rather than having one conclusion (“The defendant is guilty”) and the context determining the strength. The strength of the argument for each of these conclusions is determined solely by the premises and is either strong or weak without bringing any issues about context into the equation. Where we have different contexts, as is the case in criminal versus civil trials, we simply have different demonstranda, not different “strengths”. But do juries evaluate the conclusion at all? Discursive dilemmas have revealed the dangers of this kind of procedure. Often the rules of inference to be used in reaching the conclusion have already been agreed to or otherwise stipulated. The issue for a jury is only indirectly to reach a conclusion but is directly to do with evaluating the premises. If all members of the jury agree as to the facts of the case (normally these are something like “Did the defendant perform the act?”, “Is the act 4 correctly described?”, “Was the defendant aware that what he was doing was so describable?”, “Is the responsibility of the defendant diminished in some way?”) then the conclusion follows by a mechanical application of the rule.2 The great advantage of deductive rules of inference is that once the premises are accepted and the rule applied, the conclusion cannot be denied without self-contradiction. But to know that a deductive rule is appropriate one needs to know first that the argument is a deductive argument.3 The issue is whether we can tell that something is a deductive argument without being told, or having it stipulated or contextually determined in any way, beforehand; in other words, after it has been translated into a formal language. Sometimes, this is all that we have to go on. Someone trying to dispense with the distinction may say at this point “OK, maybe context cannot entirely determine which norm to use, but it can restrict them, and anyway, how many norms are there to choose between? Just evaluate by all of those not otherwise eliminated. We can call some norms the norms of deduction and others the norms of induction, but this is unnecessary verbiage.” Admittedly, the logician could proceed by trial and error: he could evaluate the argument as if it were deductive and check if the relation is deductive validity, and if it is deductively valid then this was the right norm and the argument was a deductive argument, and if it is not deductively valid, then he can check if it is a probabilistic relation. In other words, he would evaluate validity first, and then classify the argument as an afterthought. There are two problems with this approach. The first is that being unable to prove that an argument is deductively valid is not to prove that it is deductively invalid. The second is that this makes all inductive arguments into a type of invalid deductive argument. We could get around this by saying that everything that is not a deductively valid argument is not a deductive argument, period. This would mean that 5 there are no deductively invalid deductive arguments. Alternatively we might say that all arguments that are not deductively valid deductive arguments are simply deductively invalid deductive arguments. This would mean that there are no inductive arguments. What we want is a way of making a distinction between inductive and deductive arguments prior to evaluating them so that we evaluate them according to the validity norms appropriate for that type of argument, i.e., we apply deductive logic to deductive arguments and inductive logic to inductive arguments. This seems to be the activity of the argument-sexer. How do we make the distinction between inductive and deductive arguments? Unfortunately, the logical approach struggles to make much sense of inductive arguments as a class of their own, and seems rather to think of them as bad deductive arguments. This is not surprising since the logician’s resources for making a distinction are meager, having only the premises and conclusion to go on. One traditional thought is that deductive arguments always argue from the general to the particular while inductive arguments always argue from the particular to the general. A general statement is taken to be a statement containing a (un-negated) universal quantifier. Otherwise (i.e. it contains an (un-negated) existential quantifier or no quantifiers) it is particular. Let us call this Logical Criterion 1, or LC1. But although this is often the case, it is not always. Consider the argument All Xs are Y All Ys are Z All Xs are Z which is a deductively valid deductive argument if anything is, but consists of only 6 general statements. Or consider This X is this Y This Y is this Z This X is this Z which apparently consists of only particular (in this case identity) statements. Perhaps the logician could amend his criterion to (LC2) If the argument argues from the particular to the general then it is inductive. Otherwise, it is deductive. Are there counter-examples to this? A counter-example would be either: i. A deductive argument that argues from the particular to the general. ii. An inductive argument that argues from the particular to the particular. iii. An inductive argument that argues from the general to the particular. iv. An inductive argument that argues from the general to the general. Let’s look at some candidates for (i): “My dog is a Dane. Therefore, anyone who feeds my dog will be feeding a Dane.” “One is a lucky number. Three is a lucky number. Five is a lucky number. Seven is a lucky number. Nine is a lucky number. Therefore, all odd numbers between 0 and 10 are lucky.” The common feature of both is that they contain classes that are completely enumerated in the premises – the conclusion of the first is false if I own more than one dog, and the conclusion of the second is false if there is an odd number between 0 and 10 which is not 1, 3, 5, 7, or 9. So the arguments are incomplete as they stand. What do we need to add to make them deductively valid? In the first case, something like “There does not exist a dog that is mine and not a Dane”. This is a general statement, the negation of an existentially quantified being equivalent to a universally 7 quantified sentence. Similarly, the second requires “There does not exist an odd number between 0 and 10 that is not 1,3, 5, 7, or 9.” Although in this latter case the unexpressed premise turns out to be an analytic truth, the form of the argument is nonetheless from the general to the particular; hence, it is no counter-example to LC2.4 What about (ii)? It could be argued that all inductive arguments from the particular to the general can also be thought as from the particular to the particular, since it is an attempt to infer what will happen on the next occasion. For n observations of black ravens, the inference to “All ravens are black” and the inference to “The next raven will be black” might be considered to be on a par. But I think the illusoriness of this becomes evident as soon as you consider probabilities less than certainty. If only m of the observed ravens have been black then you can infer that m/n ravens are black but you cannot infer that the next raven will be black, or even that it has a probability of m/n of being black. How about inductive argument that argue from the general to the particular (iii). Here is a candidate from Weddle (1979, 3): (CE) It is likely that all As are Bs X is an A It is likely that X is a B This looks like an inductive argument stating that X’s being A offers some, but not conclusive, support for the conclusion that X is B. The presence of the linguistic indicator “likely” seems to be significant, but this need not be so, for the very similar (CE*) As are likely Bs 8 X is an A X is a likely B appears to be deductive. It should be noted, though, that there is a genuine logical difference between these two uses of “likely”. In CE “likely” denotes a metalinguistic operator that qualifies the strength of the relation between the premises and the conclusion and can be written as: x. A(x) L B(x) A(X) L B(X) Call this the metalinguistic reading and note that the superscript L occurs twice, both times connected to an inference (firstly the conditional, then the entailment). In contrast, “likely” as it occurs in CE* is a modal operator that operates on the statements rather than the relation and can be written as: x. A(x) L(B(x)) A(X) L(B(x)) Call this the modal reading. Weddle argues that CE can always be transformed into CE*, metalinguistic readings into modal readings, by a process he calls “hedging.” He says (1979, 3): The . . . inference above stated a probabilistic connection between its premises and rain [the conclusion]. But the arguer only said that it was likely to rain. The connection between those premises and the likelihood of rain is not similarly probabilistic. We could not reasonably grant those premises . . . and yet deny that it is likely to rain. 9 Therefore, Weddle says, CE* is deductively valid, and since CE* is a transformation of CE, CE is deductively valid. All arguments that are deductively valid are deductive arguments. Therefore, CE is a deductive argument. If hedging is an acceptable procedure then CE – and any other argument from the general to the particular containing probabilistic inferences – does not constitute a counter-example to LC2. The disputants seem to grant that CE* is deductively valid and on what makes an argument deductively valid. The possible objections remaining seem to be: Objection 1: CE* is not a transformation of CE (hedging should not be allowed) Objection 2: A transformation of CE is not identical to CE, so it may not have the same logical properties. Objection 3: Not all deductively valid arguments are deductive arguments! I will be treating these in reverse order. When is a deductively valid argument not a deductive argument? Objection 3 is almost guaranteed to leave the logician (and, I suggest, the argumentsexer) nonplussed. On the face of it the objection seems absurd. However, this absurdity, Bowles (1990) claims, is due to the fact that our previous judgments are informed by the logical theory anyway and that it is begging the question to state that it is absurd to have deductively valid inductive arguments. Likewise, Vorobej (1992, 108) writes: “To insist that every instance of modus ponens, say, must be a deductive argument is simply to beg the question.” Sorting arguments into inductive or deductive, they suggest, depends on whether the person making the argument intended5 it to be inductive or deductive. Hence, even though an argument may be deductively valid, this does not mean that it is a deductive argument, the relation actually obtaining between the premises and conclusion of the argument being no 10 longer all-important. Wilbanks (2009) calls the psychological approach the speakerdetermined thesis (SDT) and the logistical approach the speakerless thesis (SLT). A number of related objections to the SDT can be considered at this point: the speaker may not have a determinate strength of support in mind; by temperament some arguers will under- or over-estimate the strength of the support; arguers may not have the conceptual resources to make the distinction between a logically necessary connection and a probabilistic one, or even between different degrees of probabilistic support; or if they have the conceptual resources, they may still lack the linguistic resources to make their intentions explicit in the argument itself. I do not think that these objections are very strong. Being indeterminate between two things is not a third thing that falls outside of a deductive/inductive distinction altogether. Also, as argument-sexers, we should not be required to be able to make all our beliefs and intentions explicit. There may be a problem in interpreting from the argument-as-product what the speaker takes the relation to be, but this shows the limitation of looking at arguments and arguers as static objects instantiating particular relations rather than dynamically as part of an ongoing inter-subjective process, with arguers as players in a game or series of games in which they will make many moves. It is vital to note that the SDT’s emphasis, unlike the logician’s, is on the act rather than the product of arguing, and it conceives the aim of the inductive/deductive distinction as allowing an analysis of whether the arguer has satisfied the felicity conditions, rather than the truth conditions, of the speech acts constituting his arguing.5 It is conceded that language may be misleading with regard to the strength of support, but rather than trying to weigh up different linguistic indicators that may well be misleading anyway, Vorobej suggests that the analyst try to work out one thing alone – the speaker’s belief – which although difficult is already 11 presupposed by a view that sees argument as process and is concerned with whether speakers satisfy rules of discourse, describing as “a principal tenet of both rationality and ethics . . . that others have a personal point of view that first of all deserves a hearing, and second is something from which we as a community could possibly benefit” (Vorobej 1992, 107). Over time the analyst will learn the particular idioms, temperaments, and dispositions of the arguers, and when unsure should adopt the Principle of Charity and make the argument as strong as possible. Bowles (1994) deals with these, and many more objections, in a way that is mostly satisfactory. It is difficult to deny that the SDT provides a theory that is consistent with its proponents’ own admitted methodological aims, and they do not hide the fact that their definitions will not match the judgments given by the logicians or by tradition (which they will argue is the same thing). They do provide a distinction between deductive and inductive arguments that is mutually exclusive and exhaustive, thus satisfying the first conditions. The question is whether they have satisfied the additional condition of explaining away counter-intuitive results such as the claim that a deductively valid argument might not be a deductive argument. Remember the methodological principle introduced at the beginning: if it seems strange, or counterintuitive, or absurd to assert or to judge that a deductively valid argument is not a deductive argument, then the most likely explanation is that it is false. If the argument-sexer classes a deductively valid argument as a deductive argument irrespective of what the arguer thinks about it (supposing that the sexer is even in a position to make some kind of educated guess at this) then the theorist must have a better explanation of why this should be wrong than simply “it is begging the question”. Theory informs our judgments, but judgments also inform theory. 12 I submit that the SDT does not meet the burden of proof. One indication that the burden of proof is not met is that Wilbanks, who is sympathetic to the SDT, nevertheless tries to justify making an exception in the case of deductively valid arguments. Her approach combines the SLT and SDT by claiming that the speaker generally determines the deductive/inductive distinction and that the valid/invalid distinction depends on a match between the actual relation between the premises and the conclusion and the relation that the speaker claims or believes to obtain. She makes an interesting suggestion to give different judgments for when the speaker over-estimates the support her premises offer than for when she under-estimates the support. If the actual relation between premises and conclusion are weaker than claimed, then the argument is invalid, but if it is stronger than claimed, then it is nonvalid. Although generally the speaker determines whether the argument is deductive or inductive, there is an exception: “The speaker does not claim that the conclusion follows necessarily from the premises but claims that it is rendered probable to some degree by them; nevertheless, the conclusion in fact follows necessarily from them” (Wilbanks 2009); hence, this argument is deductively valid. This is a deductive argument for Wilbanks, but is neither valid nor invalid but non-valid. This accommodates the counter-intuitiveness of the idea of deductively valid inductive arguments (although a non-valid deductively valid deductive argument is perhaps only marginally less counter-intuitive) and would annul Objection 3. What is interesting here is simply that a need is felt to make such an exception at all. There is evidence that the proponents of the SDT are putting into the argument things that do not belong there. Toulmin (2003) does this by complaining that modal terms do not make some statement about the probability of something, but rather 13 inform the hearer that something can be taken in such and such a way. This results in distinguishing ‘warrants’ from their ‘backing’. However, the fact that the use of modal terms in speech acts such as the uttering of predictions has certain felicity conditions and perlocutionary effects has nothing to do with the meaning of the terms6, and it is the meaning we must evaluate if we are to know what to do. It is this that we want to know most of all – whether we should take an umbrella when we leave the house, whether we should really add that extension – and not whether all the rules of discourse have been followed. Now, although the general statements that occur in the premises, unless they are themselves necessary truths, will require ‘backing’, this does not mean to say that this backing should be made explicit in this argument, or even belongs with this argument. The truth of the premises of an argument is not in question with respect to the argument in which they occur as premises, and it is irrelevant to the argument whether they are logically necessary truths, factual truths reached by valid inductions, or happy guesses. Of course, there could be a further argument in which some premise of the first argument is the conclusion and which if invalid renders the first argument unsound, but this is another argument and another story. In summary, although I do not say that the SDT is inconsistent, I do believe that it is insufficiently motivated. We need much better reasons to accept something as strange as Objection 3 than that to deny it is to “beg the question”. Ultimately their hopes rest on the accusation that the logicians simply cannot sort arguments in a way consistent with their aims. This brings us back to Weddle’s Claim and Objection 2. When are two arguments the same? What about Objection 2? The SDT has rather too easy an answer to the fact that 14 arguments of one type can be transformed into arguments of another type. This is because of the individuation conditions for arguments that comes from their view is a case of individuating between acts, and provides in addition to the premises and the conclusion the relation that the speaker attributes to obtain between them – or rather, not the type of relation attributed, but the actual act of attributing. So, when an argument that looks inductive is rewritten so as to look deductive, as CE is rewritten as CE*, it is open to the objector to say “Suppose that you can do that. What is that to do with me? When you attribute a different degree of support, eo ipso you produce a different argument.”7 Consider what happens to the argumentation-structure when we consider the results of such transformations as distinct (and in so doing consider a different way of making the deductive/inductive distinction): “The distinction then is that in a deductive argument the premises need to be taken together to constitute a reason, whereas in an inductive argument a combination of reasons is needed to make the conclusion more or less probable” (Henkemans, 109). Once you have one deductive argument for a conclusion, the conclusion becomes detached from its premises, rendering any other arguments, whether deductive or inductive, superfluous. This is the feature of deductive arguments known as monotonicity – that the removal of superfluous premises or addition of further premises cannot affect the truth of the conclusion. The argumentation-structure reached thereby is called subordinative to indicate the fact that there is a single, conclusive chain of inferences from the premises to the conclusion. In contrast, no argument can ever become superfluous and conclusions are never detached from their premises when supported by induction, irrespective of whether each premise, or subset of premises, supports the conclusion independently in 15 a convergent argumentation-structure or when combined with the other premises in a coordinative argumentation-structure. Inductive arguments are non-monotonic. The reason for this is that a conclusion can be highly probable with regards to one reference class but highly improbable with regards to another. Let us illustrate this with a counter-example to our counter-example: (CE-CE*) Cs are unlikely Bs X is a C X is an unlikely B This modal reading seems as deductive as CE* did, but if we combine them we get: As are likely Bs X is an A Cs are unlikely Bs X is a C X is a likely B X is an unlikely B CE* and CE-CE* give opposing verdicts, leading to a contradictory conclusion. It is for this reason that Hempel, in his account of the Inductive-Statistical model of explanation, insisted on a metalinguistic reading. There is no inconsistency between CE and (CE-CE) x. C(x) 0.01 B(x) i.e. 1% of Cs are Bs X is a C0.01 It is unlikely that X is a B i.e. relative to the fact that 1% of Cs are Bs, X is not likely to be a B since here the conclusion in not detached from its grounds, the probability being 16 attached to the relation. This is usually called logical probability and will be discussed in greater detail when we deal with Objection 1. For the moment, I just want to consider two possibilities. The first is a convergent argumentation-structure with inductive supports I1, I2 and I3. Suppose that we transform I1 to a deductive support D1. Now I1 conclusively – rather than probabilistically – supports D1 and D1 conclusively supports the conclusion, making a subordinative structure so peculiar as to be almost unintelligible. If we are consistent with what we said above, I2 and I3 have now become superfluous and should be eliminated, destroying the convergent characteristic of the structure completely. On the other hand, we could have transformed I2 and eliminated I1 and I3. The whole notion of argumentation-structure seems to become unintelligible if we allow inductive arguments to be transformed into equivalent but token-distinct deductive arguments. It is much more intelligible to say that the argument was never inductive in the first place but a (possibly enthymematic) deductive argument. Suppose that we transform each of I1, I2, and I3 into D1, D2, and D3 respectively. Is the demand to eliminate all but one of the deductive supports wellgrounded? Consider D1 D2 D3 1 pq rs p 2 qr sr ptonkr 3 p s 4 q (1,3 M.P) | pr (1,2 H.S) r (1,3 M.P) | r (2,3 M.T) r (T.E) 5 r (2,4 M.P) | r (4,3 M.P) The chain of inferences for D1 can be carried out the way I have done on the left-hand side – with two application of modus ponens – or on the right-hand side – with one 17 application of hypothetical syllogism and one of modus ponens. Suppose that the person faced with whether or not to accept the conclusion r has, for whatever reason, an aversion to hypothetical syllogism, and is not as confident in it as he is in modus ponens. Therefore, eliminating the left-hand side derivation will make the support for r weaker for the person concerned; their inferring may not be doxastically justified. The rule that says to eliminate alternatives in a monotonic system considers only truth, and runs roughshod over this kind of justification. I suggest that this is unfair, and that the general principle that the more ways that you can reach a particular conclusion then the more confidence you have in it – like the more witnesses testify independently to some fact then the more readily it should be accepted as true – need not be abandoned, even in cases like this where we are only considering different derivations from the same premises. Likewise, if the person believes that some particular lemma, say q, is false, then he might lose confidence in the truth of the conclusion, or he might lose confidence in the truth of the premises, in the validity of the rules of inference, or in the correctness of his application of the rules of inference. On the other hand, if he has D2 and D3 both supporting r, then his confidence in r becomes stronger again, as might his confidence in the troublesome lemma. Thus, it may turn out that the person believes the conclusion more on the basis of invalid deductive arguments (D2 affirms the consequent on the left-hand side and denies the antecedent on the right-hand side, while D3 uses the improper logical connective tonk which has the introduction rule of and the elimination rule of ) than on valid deductive arguments. Should he notice this, at this point the person may lose all confidence in his ability to transform inductive supports into deductive ones and trust only in circular arguments.8 What this seems to suggest is that the monotonicity of deductive arguments is 18 only an idealization, as is Toulmin’s distinction between warrant-using and warrantestablishing arguments which is also sometimes used to make the inductive/deductive distinction (e.g. Yezzi 1992). All arguments both use and establish their warrants. To say that an argument is deductively valid is not to say that its conclusion is true, only that it must be true if the premises are true. If we do not believe the conclusion, then we are free to abandon one or more of the premises or one or more of the rules of inference. What road we take must be determined at least in part by other arguments for the same conclusion, or arguments that utilize some of the same premises or rules and seem to lead to acceptable conclusions, and such like. This suggests one way in which evaluating deductive arguments is not as different from evaluating inductive arguments as we might like to think. So monotonicity is not a norm for the evaluation of deductive argumentation. I think the matter goes deeper than this. Consider the so-called inclusion fallacy. Reasoners have been confirmed to assent more readily to the inference Robins have an ulnar artery Birds have an ulnar artery than they are to the inference Robins have an ulnar artery Ostriches have an ulnar artery despite the fact that ostriches are included in the class of birds – which we can formalize as the categorical conditional x. (Ostrich (x) Bird(x)) – and logically should be an easier condition to meet (Osherson et al. 2008, 325). This itself is called an inductive argument from classification, but contains another categorical conditional x. (Bird(x) HasUlnarArtery(x)) y. (Ostrich(y) HasUlnarArtery(y)) 19 What is striking about this fallacy is that as soon as you change the “all” to any probability, however high, this ceases to be a fallacy at all. What these results show is that we treat the second categorical conditional as probabilistic, viz. x. (Bird(x) L1 HasUlnarArtery(x)) L2 y. (Ostrich(y) L3 HasUlnarArtery(y)) and argue in the following way. Whatever general features are distributed through birds are distributed to a higher extent in those that are more typical, like robins, and to a lesser extent in those that are less typical, like ostriches. This is just what it means to be “typical”. Since the distribution is higher in birds taken as a whole than in ostriches, it is easier to assent to the inference from robins to birds than from robins to ostriches. This suggests that we do not generally give any special significance to “all”, and by any pragmatic standard there is no reason why we should since what we need most is guidance on what to expect. A similar analysis seems to work for what is called premise non-monotonicity (Osherson et al. 2008, 325): Flies require trace amounts of magnesium for reproduction Bees require trace amounts of magnesium for reproduction is assented to more readily than Flies require trace amounts of magnesium for reproduction Orangutans require trace amounts of magnesium for reproduction Bees require trace amounts of magnesium for reproduction After adding a premise, the inference is sometimes withdrawn, hence it is nonmonotonic. Normally, adding information should make the strength of an argument stronger or the same; at first sight it seems odd that the argument become less strong. Again, the issue is typicality. Flies are typical insects, so any feature distributed through flies will be expected to be distributed to a lesser extent through insects as a 20 whole. But the information about orangutans implies that the distribution through the population of insects may not be relevant, and it is the distribution through some larger class that is relevant to the inference – a class, moreover, of which the fly is not typical. Therefore, the strength of the inference is downgraded accordingly. The point is that talk of differing distributions through populations makes no sense at all if the “all” is taken in the way familiar from syllogistic reasoning rather than probabilistically. It should be noted that the arguments above argue from the general to the general. It was these types of arguments that caused us to abandon LC1 for LC2, and now they seem to pose a problem for LC2 as well because they look like inductive arguments, are evaluated as if they are inductive arguments, and have the form of type (iv) counterexamples, but LC2 says that they are deductive arguments. I will argue in the next section that they are deductive because circular. It will be shown that the answer to Objection 1 will also answer this problem. What is a prediction? This leads us finally to Objection 1. I have already more or less said what the problem is here, which is whether the modal reading can get around the reference-class problem. There are some situations where it can, namely those where the requirement of total evidence is satisfied, i.e., where the premises have all the evidence possibly relevant to the conclusion. For instance, if in CE-CE* being an A and being a C are the only factors affecting the likelihood of being a B then it is a simple mathematical calculation to determine the likelihood of Xs being B given the ratios of their observed instances in A and C, and the argument is once again deductive. Possibly it is this that Weddle (1979, 3) alludes to when he asks what “prevents [the arguer] from 21 providing the conclusive grounds of deductive arguments? Now of course poor arguments called inductive, based on insufficient evidence, will give only some grounds for their conclusions. But is this the case for the careful ones?” If the argument is good, then the “hedging” Weddle suggests seems admissible. Freeman (1983) objects that the “hedged” modal reading does not reflect what is really being stated and gives the example of John, who is usually happy but not too keen on parties, about whom it is said “If John comes, he is usually unhappy about something”. The “usually” is better read as stating something about the relation between John’s coming to the party and his being unhappy, than about his being unhappy simpliciter. This may be so, but it is not clear how much of a difference there really is here. Suppose that we are at the party and we see John enter. Accepting the conditional premise, we draw the conclusion, in the absence of any information to the contrary, that John is unhappy, and the same conclusion is drawn on both the modal and the metalinguistic reading. The issue is really that the modal reading depends, as the metalinguistic reading does not, on additional information that we may not have. We may be able to fill in all the unexpressed premises so that the requirement of total evidence is satisfied, but why should we assume this? 9 Note that what we are talking about when we consider unexpressed premises is not the mere logical possibility of filling them in in such a way as to make the argument deductively valid – this is always trivially possible, e.g., by making the unexpressed premise a contradiction from which anything at all can be entailed. To not express something is an aspect of performance, perhaps a ‘negative’ speech act; it is pragmatic rather than logical. Why should we even assume (if Cartwright is right and some laws are inherently ceteris paribus) that it is satisfiable even in principle? Why should we assume that the inductive argument is a good one? I maintain that we need support for 22 any assertion that total evidence has been supplied, but getting this support is just as difficult, if not more so, than the original argument was to evaluate without it. Freeman’s approach is different though. He seems to challenge the very intelligibility of the modal reading, on the grounds, I think, that it amounts to a singular probability. The choices for a modal reading are between subjective probability and relative frequency, so if these are shown to be unintelligible as singular probabilities then the metalinguistic reading, in which this singular probability is a logical probability, is the only live option and wins by default. I will not be discussing subjective probability but only Freeman’s account of relative frequency. The relative frequency theory works by extrapolating from a finite series to an infinite series. Of course, a person may have more or less confidence that what he has observed so far is a representative sample, i.e., has converged on the same value as the infinite series will in the long run, but I will argue that this has nothing to do with the singular probability in question, which is what is predicted (the object), but only with whether he is entitled to utter that prediction (the act); it is an assertibility or felicity condition. The object of prediction is explained by the relative frequency theory as being elliptical for a restatement of the results of our frequency series. Reichenbach insists that we need only a class-meaning for probability statements, and singular probability statements have the same class-meaning as its associated statement about the class. Although such statements are not, for Reichenbach, true or false, we can deal with them as if they were true or false. What I think this leads towards, although it is never explicitly stated by Reichenbach, is that singular probability statements have the same meaning but different performative functions than the equivalent statements about the class. The performative function of 23 a prediction(-act) is to get the listener to take the prediction(-object) as being true and a guide for action; when the meteorological office tells you that it is likely to rain tomorrow, then you had better not leave home without an umbrella. However, the meaning of the prediction is nothing more than the series of observations known to the meteorological office concerning the frequency of rain in different referenceclasses of relevant conditions.10 To give a simple example, the argument “This is a fair die; therefore, the next throw will probably be greater than a two” says no more than “This is a fair die”, although it might direct the audience’s attention to “look out” for numbers greater than two, despite the fact that logically speaking looking for these numbers is no different from looking for any of the other possible outcomes. A prediction is more like a promise than a statement. A similar analysis holds for Flies require trace amounts of magnesium for reproduction Bees require trace amounts of magnesium for reproduction The only reason for making the inference from flies to bees is that they are both insects; hence we should add the unexpressed premise to give Flies require trace amounts of magnesium for reproduction Insects require trace amounts of magnesium for reproduction Bees require trace amounts of magnesium for reproduction along with background information (ultimately in the form of frequency series) that flies and bees are both subsets of insects, and what it means for something to be typical. The conclusion says no more than this when looked at, as the logician does, in the context of an argument-as-object. In the context of an argument-as-act, the speech act of uttering a prediction has all kinds of conditions of satisfaction that are unrelated to its truth, and has all kinds of effects. Toulmin (2003) correctly notes these, but errs 24 in making this a part of the argument. Let’s take stock of where we have got to. We were considering a criterion (LC2) that claimed that all arguments that argued from general premises, whether these were universal or probabilistic, were deductive arguments, along with arguments from the particular to the particular. The only arguments that are inductive argue from particular premises to general statements, i.e., they have the logical forms F(a) G(a) F(a) G(a) F(b) G(b) F(b) G(b) F(c) G(c) F(c) G(c) x. F(x) G(x) x. F(x) L G(x) On the left, a non-probabilistic relation is claimed on the basis of the evidence, while on the right a probabilistic relation is claimed on the basis of the evidence. A probabilistic relation can obviously be claimed when there is counter-evidence, e.g., F(d) G(d) or F(d) G(d). Possible counter-examples were considered and rejected. LC2, then, makes the deductive/inductive distinction, and the deductively valid/deductively invalid distinction was never in question. What remains to be made is the distinction between inductively valid and inductively invalid arguments. When is an inductive argument valid? What do we want from the concept of inductive validity? The same thing that we wanted from the concept of deductive validity, which is to be able to say that a person’s belief that some proposition p is true is a good reason for their believing that some other proposition q is true. This is an argument from sign and is clearly satisfied if we believe that the conditional “If p, then q” is true. The truth of this conditional gives us an incontrovertible warrant for inferring q. But is the belief in the truth of the 25 conditional justified? When the belief in some singular propositions gives us a good reason for believing that the conditional is true, we say that the argument is inductively valid to some degree and that the truth of some singular proposition is a good sign of the truth of the conditional, after which we can say that the truth of the antecedent (in some particular substitution-instance) is a good sign of the truth of the consequent. The converse is not typically true, and it is usually further inductions that tell us which way round to write the conditional – being a raven is a good sign for being black, but being black is not a good sign for being a raven. Something being a sign for something else is always in virtue of those things matching a description, and for this we need predicate logic.11 We can not only talk about one thing being a sign for another in virtue of their descriptions, but one thing cohering with another in virtue of their descriptions. I will not attempt a full-blown account of coherence here. I suggest that the more coherent a set of propositions is, the greater the set of questions to which it can give unambiguous answers. Obviously, singular propositions can only answer questions concerning the objects named in them; they only cohere with each other in the negative sense that they must be logically compossible in not making contradictory statements about the same object. My observation of a black raven does not support your observation of a black raven directly, but only in so far as they confirm an empirical generalization that generates automatically answers to questions about ravens. The set of propositions gains coherence in being able to answer questions even about unobserved ravens. Often it is held that one proposition cannot support another unless at least one of them is an observation statement or inferred from an observation statement. I disagree. A logical consequence (such as a substitution-instance) of a 26 generalization supports that generalization even as the generalization supports the consequence. It is qua logical consequence of the generalization that my observation statement coheres with the set of propositions as a whole, and it is qua a contradiction of a logical consequence of the generalization that my observation statement makes the set of propositions as a whole incoherent. Questions are our instruments for measuring coherence and have different values. Coherence, I suggest, is connected to what Bromberger (1992, 152) calls the “Machian” or “added” value. Questions have high values because their answers enable us to answer other questions and to generate more questions. Our scientific theories have such great coherence, in my sense, because the questions they answer have this kind of value. This is especially the case where quantitative causal laws are used. For example, from the equation for the period of a pendulum an answer to the question “What is the length of this pendulum?” will also provide an answer to “What is the period of this pendulum?” and vice versa. This is true not only for this pendulum, but for any pendulum influenced only by gravity (Bromberger 1992, 138). Incoherence arises when we get different answers for a question. This could be because a question is answered by more than one generalization and these answers are different12 or it could be because of an observation statement: the raven is white, the period of the pendulum has been measured and is not what was expected. What are we to do when this happens? One fairly obvious move, which is however rarely made, is to change from a categorical to a probabilistic conditional. We are not often prepared to do this when we are dealing with causal sequences and theoretical kinds – we shy away from genuinely indeterministic laws of nature. But we are at least equally reluctant to reject the observation, since this would imply that the presence of a black raven only caused me to have the impression of a black raven in a certain 27 percentage of cases, even in good light etc., and in other cases caused me to have an impression of a white raven. The reliability of our senses (whether assisted or unassisted by instruments like microscopes) is our best confirmed empirical hypothesis and the one we always appeal to in the final analysis. So, for the sake of argument we can rule out the move from x.R(x) B(x) to x.R(x) L B(x)13 and the move from R(a)B(a) to R(a)B(a). There are two other options. We could say that ravens cause a tendency for an observer to have an impression of blackness, which tendency may be interfered with, and the answer the generalization gives is the answer that would be true in the absence of this interference. We see this more with theoretical kinds and causal laws: magnets cause pieces of iron to tend to move towards the magnet, an object has a tendency to move in a straight line and constant velocity, even when it isn’t so moving. By modifying the predicate (“attracts iron”) this way the observation (of a piece of iron not moving towards a magnet) no longer falsifies the law. Properly formulated laws will already be interpreted this way, so this may not help us. In this eventuality, we simply deny that what we saw was a raven, i.e., we move from R(a)B(a) to R(a)B(a), again avoiding falsification of the generalization. If we have what seems like a magnet and yet it does not attract iron, then we do not think that the law “All magnets attract iron” is false, or probabilistic, but that what we have is not really a magnet but only seems to be. At this point the empirical law has become more like an analytic statement or convention. I suggest that at this point the set of propositions are well on their way to being strongly coherent. What I am trying to get to is an objective correlate in terms of coherence of that point in our process of inquiry when we are not prepared under any circumstances 28 to give up a general statement. I formulate this as follows: (Inductive Validity) An inductive argument is inductively valid if our model of the world (the set of all accepted propositions) would still be more coherent with the generalization (the conclusion of the argument) than without it, even if this meant denying that there is anything currently instantiated in the world that matched its descriptions. To put it slightly differently, the coherence has become independent of the universe of discourse; it is rigid in the sense that propositional logic, being a logic of meanings that apply in any possible world, is rigid but extensional logic, tied to an extensional interpretation of its terms in some particular world, is not. It is not only this raven that is not a raven, but nothing that we identified as a raven was really a raven, and not only this magnet that is not a magnet, but nothing that we identified as a magnet was really a magnet. This is a sufficient but I do not claim that it is a necessary condition of inductive validity – I think that is possible that there are different norms of inductive validity, and there may not be any non-disjunctive set of conditions that will be both necessary and sufficient. Philosophers who hold that there are non-demonstrative arguments like abductive and conductive arguments that are neither deductive nor inductive may take heart from this and incorporate their views as different norms of inductive validity instead of different forms of argument. The only problem would be if they were to find a form of argument that did not seem in one way or other to be an argument from sign. Conclusion Is the argument-sexer a proto-logician or a proto-psychologist? I have argued, and I 29 suspect those taking the psychological approach would not deny, that he is taking a logistical approach, that he looks at the argumentation as the finished product rather than as the process from which the product emerges. This is a very practical decision, because in many cases the product is all that he has to go on. Perhaps the defender of the speaker-determined thesis would say that this is a false consciousness, that the sexer’s better instincts are being subverted by the hegemony of classical logic. This could be true; the hegemony of Aristotelianism held back scientific progress for centuries. But it is not the most likely explanation. The most likely explanation is that the sexer’s judgments are right in the majority of cases – that a deductively valid argument is a deductive argument – and whatever account of the deductive/inductive distinction we adopt should be able to account also for this fact. The rival criteria for the deductive/inductive distinction are as follows. Inductive arguments move from the particular to the general. Everything else is a deductive argument. This implies that all arguments from the general to the particular are deductive. Some arguments that look inductive because they use words like “probably” are actually deductively valid, but is this true of all of them or is there a further distinction to be made within this class of arguments? It is here that I believe looks are deceptive, and it has been my primary aim in this paper to justify the decision to call all such arguments deductive. Alternatively, the speaker determines what kind of argument it is. If the speaker thinks that his premises establish his conclusion conclusively then it is a deductive argument. The speaker cannot be mistaken about what kind of argument he is giving, although he may over- or under-estimate the actual strength of the relation between his premises and his conclusion. He may offer an argument that is deductively valid, but think that the support offered by his premises is only 30 inconclusive, in which case it is a deductively valid inductive argument. This frankly revisionary theory is consistent within itself but is insufficiently motivated. There is no need to hijack the logical concept of argument and put into it things that do not belong there in order to further their own genuine concerns. The place to model psychological or epistemic factors is in the argumentation-structure.13 The logistic approach should only be abandoned, I believe, if it is proven to be inadequate to the task of distinguishing arguments across the deductive/inductive and valid/invalid distinctions in a way that is exhaustive and mutually exclusive. I have argued that LC2 makes the deductive/inductive distinction, and the deductively valid/deductively invalid distinction was never really in dispute. Entire libraries could be written about what makes some inductive arguments valid and others invalid. I have offered some very brief and speculative hints about the way I think this research might continue. Firstly, I believe that inductive validity might be a disjunctive concept, and that we should work from particular cases towards sufficient conditions for their validity, rather than starting with a theory and working from there for a unified account intended to work for all cases. I believe that the argument-sexer is basically as sound in his inductive practices as he is in classifying arguments. Few people really doubt that induction works – the philosophical problem has always been formalize the conditions under which it works, and to justify why it works. 31 ENDNOTES 1. In Scottish law there is even a “not proven” verdict that they can deliver in these kinds of cases. A stronger argument is required to find a defendant guilty than is required to conclude that he is guilty. 2. It is mechanical in the normative sense; it will tell you in every case what the jury’s verdict should be. In real life, juries can be “nullified” and may disregard, misunderstand, or misapply the rule. The rules are normally conveyed in the judge’s instructions before the jury retires to consider the verdict. The judge can also err by conveying the wrong rules or conveying badly the right rules. 3. Of course, contextual information can sometimes indicate what kind of rule or norm is appropriate, but this says no more than that in a logic class the teacher may say “Here are some deductive arguments. Prove them.” 4. I owe these examples to an anonymous reviewer, who attributes the second example to Skyrms. 5. Not all proponents of the SDT privilege the act over the object, an anonymous reviewer tells me. If so, then the interest of the SDT escapes me. Why should we care whether an arguer thought he was offering a different kind of argument than he actually gave unless it is on the grounds that by misspeaking in this way he failed to successfully perform some speech act, that is to say, unless evaluation of the argument leads to evaluation of the speaker? 6. It may be one of the conditions of satisfaction of the speech act that the speaker intends what he says to be taken in a certain way, but this is not the meaning of what he says. Similarly, when I make a prediction it is one of the conditions of satisfaction that I have a high degree of confidence that what I predict will turn out to be true (a prediction which I believe will be falsified being a kind of 32 contradiction in conception) and that I intend the hearer to take my utterance in a certain way, but the meaning of what I say is not that I have such confidence but will rather refer to my evidence. This point will come up later when I discuss predictions. I think it is wrong to give in to a temptation to put this the other way around and claim that what I am saying is that I have this degree of confidence with my reasons or evidence for having this degree of confidence being the condition of satisfaction. I am entitled to assert something if I think it is true even if it is not and even if I am epistemically blameworthy in thinking that it is. 7. It seems to suggest also that the same relation can be attributed, and the same words spoken, and yet the argument will be distinct. In a sense, this makes the job of classification more difficult, because every token, although it may be identical in all respects relevant to its evaluation, will have to be classified separately. 8. What are we to make of the predicament of the reasoner who does not notice? His belief in the conclusion is propositionally justified in so far as it is the conclusion of a logically valid argument. Not only is this argument accessible to him, but he actually has it; hence, one would think that he is also doxastically justified in believing what he does. However, his reason for thinking himself doxastically justified is not in itself a good reason, but is based on bad reasons, on logical fallacies. Does this kind of epistemic luck defeat his justification? Does Descartes’ belief that he may have made a mistake in adding 2 and 2 defeat the justification for his belief that 2+2=4? It is beyond the scope of this paper to discuss cases like this, but my opinion is that, given certain conditions, what is defeated is not his first-order belief but his second-order belief that his first-order belief is true. 33 9. Yezzi (1992) suggests that we can include it as an assumption analogous to assuming the meaning-invariance of the terms when we are dealing with deductive arguments. But I don’t think that this is a fair analogy. A closer analogy with total evidence would be if the domain were closed. But in such a closed domain the fallacies of affirming the consequent and argument from ignorance are not fallacies, e.g., if there is one and only one conditional with q as a consequent and we know that q is true, then we know that the antecedent is true also. Total evidence is a stronger assumption than anything connected to deduction. 10. Freeman (1983, 6) might object instead on more or less the same grounds on which he objects to a subjective probability reading of the prediction: [C]ould the 'likely' in the conclusion be interpreted as expressing a purely subjective degree of actual belief? This seems unintuitive. For by citing premises, reasons, isn't one trying to justify his conclusion objectively and so give some objective evidence for his probability statement? Is one merely suggesting how he came to hold a certain belief? . . . When a weatherman says "it is likely to rain tomorrow," having just expressed his reasons, is he just expressing his subjective degree of belief? This interpretation does not seem plausible. It seems to me that Freeman has run together the expressing of an opinion and the assertion that one has it. On the interpretation I am urging, the phrase “objective evidence for his probability statement” is misleading; what the probability statement states is the evidence, and his reasons are his beliefs that this constitutes good evidence. Freeman complains that this is deductive but trivial. This does not seem to be a good objection, since triviality is a 34 characteristic feature, and no defect, in a deduction. To reiterate, the various things that a speaker might intend or hope to achieve in uttering a speech act are not a part of its meaning, at least as far as logic is concerned. 11. Although we have predicates, because they are interpreted extensionally those predicates are mentioned but not really used in making inferences, and for this reason I think first-order predicate logic does not give us what we want, which is a notation for expressing relations between descriptions. Suppose that we observe a black raven and symbolize this as R(a) B(a). All that this really says is that “a” is being used as a name of an object that is in the intersection of two sets of objects, but it doesn’t even imply that this is because it shares with the other members of those sets some common feature, i.e., the property of being a raven or of being black. Once you have named an object, the truth of any propositions involving it can simply be read off from the universe of discourse. What we want is to be able to say that believing something to be a raven is a reason for thinking it to be black, even, I would say, in universes other than this one, that is, even if the subject term does not successfully refer. We want to be able to get back to meanings as in propositional logic but still be able to make the subject/predicate distinction. Quantifying over predicates may be a means of doing this, but for the purpose of my argument I will simply stipulate that a relation between descriptions is being expressed. 12. This is basically the same as the reference class problem mentioned earlier. 13. Since the relation between being a raven and being black is not a direct causal relation, this move may not be so unlikely here. When two correlated effects can be thought to have a common cause, or perhaps contribute to a common function such as camouflage in insects or the correlation between sharp beaks and sharp 35 claws in birds of prey, we are more likely to take the probabilistic approach, knowing that many things can interfere with a causal chain. It is a different matter with theoretical kinds like pendulums and magnets whose definitions are always partly functional and take their meanings from their use in the relevant theories. 36 REFERENCES Bowles, George. 1994. The deductive/inductive distinction. Informal Logic XVI.3 Bromberger, Sylvain. 1992. On what we know we don’t know. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press. Freeman, James B. 1983. Logical form, probability interpretations, and the deductive/inductive distinction. Informal Logic vol. 5 no. 2 Goddu, G. C. 2002. The ‘most important and fundamental’ distinction in logic. Informal Logic vol. 22 no. 1 Hanson, N.R. 1961. Good inductive reasons. The Philosophical Quarterly vol. 11 no. 43 Osherson, Daniel N., Smith, Edward E., Wilkie, Ormond, Lopez, Alejandro, and Shafiz, Eldar. 2008. Cartegory-based induction. In Reasoning: studies of human inference and its foundations. Ed. Adler, Jonathan E. and Rips, Lance J. New York: Cambridge University Press Snoeck Henkemans, A. Francisca. 2001. Argumentation structures. In Crucial concepts in argumentation theory. Ed. van Eemeren. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press. Reichenbach, Hans. 1938. Experience and prediction. Phoenix Books. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Toulmin, Stephen E. 2003. The uses of argument. New York: Cambridge University Press. Vorobej, Mark. 1992. Defining deduction. Informal Logic XIV.2&3 Weddle, Perry. 1979. Inductive, deductive. Informal Logic vol. 2 no. 1 Wilbanks, Jan J. 2009. Defining deduction, induction, and validity. Argumentation. [Available online]. 37 www.springerlink.com/content/142161k11u1366j5/?p=b71977cc717442238e27 b7a894b999af&pi=0. Last accessed 13th November 2009 Yezzi, Ron. 1992. Practical logic. Mankato: G. Bruno & Co. 38