The ontological argument 4 tnformation Sheet Anselm and the Proslogion The ontological argument is based on Anselm’s stated definition of God as that than which nothing greater can be conceived’, expressing all the perfections of God and assuming that since that which is perfect must exist, then God must exist. The argument works analytically, establishing a proof for the existence of God based on an analysis of the word 'God' If God’ means existence’, as Anselm claims, in the same way that triangle’ means three angles and three sides’, then he must necessarily exist — he cannot not exist. This argument is based on definition and language, and seeks to establish that God necessarily exists because he can do no other by virtue of being the greatest conceivable being. In the Proslogion, Anselm argues that: • God is that than which nothing greater can be conceived since he is such a being God’s non-existence is inconceivable That than which nothing greater can be conceived As that than which nothing greater can be conceived’ God is the sum of all perfections, and no more perfect being can be described. He is not simply the most perfect being that exists, but the most perfect being conceivable. Anselm distinguished between a being existing only in the mind (in intellectu) and in reality (in re). If it exists only in the mind, then there may exist a being greater in reality also. Therefore ‘that than which nothing greater can be conceived’ must exist in reality also, if it truly fulfils that definition. Now we believe that thou art a being than which none greater con be thought. . . clearly that than which a greater cannot be thought cannot exist in the understanding alone. For if it is actually in the understanding alone, it con be thought of as existing in reality, and this is greater. Therefore, if that than which a greater cannot be thought is in the understanding alone, it can be thought of as existing also in reality, and this is greater.... Without doubt therefore, there exists, both in the understanding and in reality, something than which a greater cannot be thought. StAnselm of Canterbury, Proslogion Inconceivable non-existence If God is ‘that than which nothing greater can be conceived’ he must therefore necessarily exist, since by definition it is impossible to conceive of him not existing. At the heart of Gods existence is his aseity — he is independent of all other beings, not limited by time or space — and so it is impossible to speak of him as having come to exist or ceasing to exist. His non-existence is therefore impossible. Anselm’s argument depends on maintaining that it is more perfect to exist necessarily than to exist contingently, and so an unsurpassably perfect being must exist necessarily. Even ‘the fool’ (the atheist of Psalm 53) who denied the existence of God had comprehended what constituted God’s essence, and as such was saying the unsayable when he denied his existence. Con it be that there is no such being since, the fool hath said in his heart There is no God ''' But when this same fool hears what I am saying — “A being than which none greater can be thought” he understands what he hears.. , . even if he does not understand that it exists,, . . Even the fool, then, must be convinced that a being than which none greater can be thought exists at least in his understanding. For something con be thought of as existing which cannot be thought of as not existing, and this is greater than that which can be thought of as not existing.. So, then, there truly is a being than which a greater cannot be thought so truly that it cannot even be thought of as not existing.. . He therefore who understands that God thus exists cannot think of him as non-existent StAnse!rn of Canterbury, Proslogion Remember that: - a necessary being cannot not exist • a contingent being comes into and goes out of existence Descartes and the ontological argument René Descartes (1598—1650) argued that existence belonged analytically to God as three angles were analytically predicated of a triangle, (A predicate is a defining characteristic of a thing or being — something that can be possessed or lacked.) For God to lack existence would be for him to lack perfection, and hence not to be God. Descartes’s argument runs thus: I The idea of God is the idea of a supremely perfect being. 2 A supremely perfect being has all perfections. 3 Existence is a perfection. 4 A supremely perfect being has the perfection of existence. 5 It is impossible to think of God as not existing. 6 God exists, Why does this fail? If ‘existence’ is not a predicate, then Descartes’s approach fails. Some characteristics can be possessed or lacked and are part of the description of a thing or being: green, large round, generous. Immanuel Kant (1724— 1804) argued that ‘exists’ does not work in the same way as these adjectives — it cannot be listed when saying what God is like: ‘Whatever, therefore, and however much our concept of an object may contain, we must go outside it if we are to ascribe existence to the object? In other words, we have to establish that something exists first before we can say what it is like, not the other way round. All that Kant was prepared to say is that if there is an infinitely perfect being, then he must exist, just as if there is a triangle it must have three sides, Bertrand Russell (1872—1970) also denied that existence could operate as a predicate, claiming only that it has a propositional function: it asserts that there are beings in the world that answer to a particular description, but it adds no further information about them. It conveys nothing of their essence or nature, To say cows are brown and exist’ says nothing more than ‘cows are brown~ Gaunilo’s island A contemporary of Anselm, Gaunilo of Marmoutiers, claimed that the argument leads to absurd conclusions if applied to different examples. He demonstrated a reductio aa absurdum by suggesting that he could conceive of an island than which no greater could be conceived, and according to Anselm’s logic that the most perfect conceivable contains existence within its very definition — it must exist. Anselm responded, however that his reasoning was intended to apply only to God, because things that are part of the contingent universe can be thought of as non-existing, whereas God cannot, since he alone possesses necessary existence: So, then, it is peculiar to God to be unable to be thought of as non-existent. Support for the argument Alvin Plantinga suggested that whatever the world in which we live is like, God must exist, even if it is considerably different from the world as we know it. Hence God can exist in all possible worlds; there are many possible worlds in which to exist, including our own, and since God can exist in all possible worlds he is, Plantinga maintained, maximally great. If he possesses all the attributes of God in all possible worlds he must be maximally excellent. In a similar vein Norman Malcolm proposed: If God, a being a greater than which cannot be conceived, does not exist then he cannot come into existence. For if he did he would either hove been caused to come into existence or have happened to come into existence, and in either case he would be a limited being, which by our conception of him he is not,.. Thus God’s self existence is either impossible or necessary. It can be the former only if the concept of such a being is self-contradictory or in some way logically absurd, Assuming that this is not so, it follows that he necessarily exists. Cited n John Hick (ed), The Existence of God (Mocmilloo, 1964), pp. 48ft The ontological argument 4 Wor*sheet I The ontological argument is a deductive, analytic, a priori argument. Discuss the benefits of such an argument. How successful is this method of reasoning in establishing a decisive proof for the existence of God? What particular flaws are inherent in it? You may want to consider the value of an argument that rests on a definition of God. 2 Now consider in what ways an a posteriori argument may prove more successful. What are the particular strengths of this method of reasoning when compared to a priori reasoning? 3 If the ontological argument fails as an argument for the existence of God does it have any other value? Consider the fact that Anseim was not attempting to prove the existence of God, what may he have succeeded in doing nevertheless? Homework tasks Consider the following questions~ I Do we have any grounds on which to say that existence belongs to God by the very nature of his being? Do we need to know God first before we can say this? 2 Is there any absurdity in saying that there exists a being who cannot not exist? Or that a being who cannot not exist nevertheless does not exist? 3 Could the ontological argument ever serve to convince an atheist of God’s existence? 4 Does it tell theists anything they do not already know?