WHAT EVERY OKLAHOMA ELDER LAWYER SHOULD KNOW ABOUT PHYSICIAN-ASSISTED SUICIDE By Tim Whittlesey December 1, 2003 Throughout American history suicide has been forbidden, first as a violation of a conventions and later as a legal wrong. The legal standing of physician-assisted suicide in Oklahoma is clearly defined by statute, but a number of other issues, legal, ethical, and social must be considered. STATUTORY The Oklahoma criminal code states that “every person who willfully, in any manner, advises, encourages, abets, or assists another person in taking his own life, is guilty of aiding suicide.”1 This provision is generally addressed to physicians, yet attorneys or others could easily be brought within its scope, and so the Oklahoma elder lawyer must be careful when discussing the issue with clients. After the Supreme Court upheld two laws banning assisted suicide, the Oklahoma legislature passed 63 O.S. § 3141, the Oklahoma Assisted Suicide Prevention Act, to clarify further the situation. This Act provides, in part, that anyone who “(1) provides the physical means by which another person commits or attempts to commit suicide; or (2) participates in a physical act by which another person commits or attempts to commit suicide” is in violation of the Act.2 The Act provides no additional criminal penalties, but instead introduces civil remedies, 1 2 OKLA. STAT. tit. 21 § 813 (2003). OKLA. STAT. tit. 63 § 3141.3 (1998). 1 such as injunction or damages. The Act also provides specific exemptions for medical personnel providing high levels of medication for the purpose of pain relief. The purpose of the Act seems to be to reduce the fear of criminal liability for physicians, so they will be free to prescribe the high levels of pain relieving medication required by some terminally ill patients. If physicians are allowed to control pain effectively - even though it hastens the death of the patient - the belief is that fewer patients will feel the need to resort to suicide. DUE PROCESS The Supreme Court has addressed this issue in a number of ways and differing cases. The court consistently takes a dim view of suicide under any circumstances, and its analysis of law and fact is colored by this. The constitutional arguments are all analyzed according to rational basis theory, in that they must be rationally related to a legitimate governmental end. To determine the application of this test, the court held in Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620 (1996) that “…if a law neither burdens a fundamental right nor targets a suspect class, we will uphold [it] so long as it bears a rational relation to some legitimate end.”3 The difficulty here is that the court never even considers whether assisted suicide - or, more broadly, the right to die - is a fundamental right. Through historical vagaries and questionable legal precedent the court automatically assigns it to some lesser classification of rights and proceeds with the analysis. In Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702 (1997), the Supreme Court addressed a Washington state statute which banned assisted suicide. In upholding the constitutionality of the 2 statute, the court looked to a legal and social history of suicide generally, both in this country and around the world. The court found that Washington’s interest in protecting its citizenry, especially groups which may be especially vulnerable to an inappropriate application of such a statute, was rationally related to a legitimate governmental end. In this case the Court classified the issue as to whether or not there is a liberty interest in determining the manner, place, and time of one’s own death. More narrowly, the court said, “the question before us is whether the ‘liberty’ specially protected by the Due Process Clause includes a right to commit suicide which itself includes a right to assistance in doing so.”4 Even the broadest interpretation of the constitution could not likely be said to provide such a right. If, however, the issue had been formulated as one of privacy, the statute might have been struck down. If physician-assisted suicide had been articulated as one of a wealth of treatment options, it might have survived. The court then turned to a historical perspective of suicide generally. It noted the longstanding tradition opposing suicide, stating that: [i]n almost every State - indeed, in almost every western democracy - it is a crime to assist a suicide. The States' assisted-suicide bans are not innovations. Rather, they are long-standing expressions of the States' commitment to the protection and preservation of all human life.5 The court found itself: 3 Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 631 (1996). Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 723 (1997). 5 Id. at 710. 4 3 …confronted with a consistent and almost universal tradition that has long rejected the asserted right, and continues explicitly to reject it today, even for terminally ill, mentally competent adults. To hold for respondents, we would have to reverse centuries of legal doctrine and practice, and strike down the considered policy choice of almost every State.6 In addressing physician-assisted suicide, the court found that “…our decisions lead us to conclude that the asserted ‘right’ to assistance in committing suicide is not a fundamental liberty interest protected by the Due Process Clause.”7 Physician-assisted suicide is a recent development, brought about by increasing efficiency and effectiveness in end-of-life care. The human lifespan has been greatly increasing over the last century, the period from which the court took its historical data. On average, people are now living longer than ever before. This is creating a host of new legal, ethical, and medical considerations which have not been addressed before. The court approaches this case as if it were one in a long string of similar cases, and thus easily decided by precedent. However, given such recent demographic trends, this is really a case of first impression and previous cases and historical perspective can only provide authoritative insight, not binding precedent. The court went on to distinguish and explain some of this precedent. In Cruzan v. Director, Missouri Dept. of Health, 497 U.S. 261 (1990), the court recognized that a competent person has the right to refuse medical treatment. In that case, it was the parents of a woman in a permanent vegetative state requesting the removal of feeding and hydration. Petitioners in Washington v. Glucksberg would expand that principle to also apply to physician-assisted suicide. The court focused on traditional legal theories, holding with “…the common-law rule 6 Id. at 723. 4 that forced medication was a battery, and the long legal tradition protecting the decision to refuse unwanted medical treatment…”8 However the court refused to update this view to bring it in line with modern trends, saying instead that while “[t]he decision to commit suicide with the assistance of another may be just as personal and profound as the decision to refuse unwanted medical treatment, but it has never enjoyed similar legal protection.”9 While it is true that assisted suicide has never shared such tacit legal approval, a closer look at the underlying theory and reasoning would give support to both refusal of medical treatment and assisted suicide. Both speak to the fundamental belief that a person should have the absolute right to control the fate of their own bodies. The court’s differentiation between the two procedures - both requiring the affirmative acts of another, both designed to comply with the patient’s wishes and reduce suffering, and both ending at the same result - is legal hair-splitting at best, and specious at worst. The court is correct when it says that “[t]he right assumed in Cruzan, however, was not simply deduced from abstract concepts of personal autonomy” but on principles of common law.10 However those principles of common law were deduced from the very abstract concepts of personal autonomy with which the court seems so unimpressed. Again the court seems simply to apply precedent with no consideration of cultural changes, or even the philosophical underpinnings of that precedent. The court goes on to distinguish Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (1992), which also applied the Due Process Clause to an intimate and personal medical decision, in that 7 Id. at 728. Id. at 725. 9 Id. 8 5 case abortion. The Casey court found that “[c]onstitutional protection of the woman's decision to terminate her pregnancy derives from the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment” and that “[t]he controlling word in the cases before us is ‘liberty.’”11 Thus, the court in that case found that an abortion was a constitutionally protected liberty. However, in the Glucksberg case, the court refused to expand the definition of liberty to include a right to suicide, saying that simply because “many of the rights and liberties protected by the Due Process Clause sound in personal autonomy does not warrant the sweeping conclusion that any and all important, intimate, and personal decisions are so protected.”12 And yet what decision could sound more in personal autonomy, could be more important, intimate, and personal a decision that the decision to die? Certainly if the right to have an abortion - an important right, to be sure - is considered a ‘liberty’ within the context of the Fourteenth Amendment, why not the paramount right of choosing to live or die? The court concludes with a review of the legitimate governmental ends Washington seeks to protect, and whether or not the statute in question is rationally related to those ends. The court found that suicide was a manifestation of a mental disorder, and that those suffering mental incapacity require state protection.13 The court also found legitimate the state’s interest in protecting the medical industry, both from ethical dilemmas and legal liability.14 Perhaps of paramount concern for the court was the state’s interest in protecting the groups most vulnerable 10 Id. Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 846 (1992). 12 Glucksberg, supra note 4, at 727. 13 Id. at 730-731. 14 Id. at 731. 11 6 to an abuse of assisted suicide, namely the poor, the elderly, and the disabled. The fear here was that such groups would be more likely to succumb to pressure, coercion, or prejudice.15 The court was also concerned that allowing assisted suicide could remove physicians from the decisionmaking process and leave the determination in the hands of family members or other laypeople.16 The court noted that this could lead down a slippery slope into involuntary euthanasia, because such a system would be practically impossible to administer or maintain. To this the respondents countered - and the Court of Appeals agreed - that all of the state’s interests should be weighed against the interests, wishes, and medical conditions of the patients involved. This court, again relying on Cruzan, refused to mandate such a subjective, case-by-case investigation of the quality of a person’s life, even for those near death.17 EQUAL PROTECTION In Vacco v. Quill, 521 U.S. 793 (1997), a group of New York physicians challenged that state’s statute prohibiting assisted suicide. Their argument turned on the fact that the state treated differently patients who wish to accelerate their deaths with medication than those who wish to do so by withholding treatment. Respondents there claimed such disparate treatment violated the Equal Protection Clause in that it was not rationally related to ant legitimate governmental ends. The respondents are physicians who feel that it is consonant with their duties to provide lethal treatment to patients who are terminally ill, if those patients are still mentally competent. The 15 Id. at 731-732. Id. at 732-733. 17 Id. 728-729. 16 7 remaining respondents are terminally ill patients of these physicians, all of whom have since died.18 The court stated that the Equal Protection Clause creates no substantive rights, and that, even though the legislation in question addressed issues of great importance, it did not infringe on a fundamental right or target a suspect class and as such must pass only the rational basis test.19 In addressing the issue of suspect class, the court notes that “[e]veryone, regardless of physical condition, is entitled, if competent, to refuse unwanted lifesaving medical treatment; no one is permitted to assist a suicide” [emphasis in original].20 The lower Court of Appeals drew a distinction between patients who are permitted to refuse care to hasten the end of life and those who are forbidden to take affirmative steps to reach the same conclusion, and found this unconstitutional. The Supreme Court disagreed, believing instead that “…when a patient refuses life-sustaining medical treatment, he dies from an underlying fatal disease or pathology; but if a patient ingests lethal medication prescribed by a physician, he is killed by that medication.”21 However this is a hollow distinction, with only legal and no practical significance. The court hinges its distinction on the intent of the actors; the court found that a physician who withholds care at the patient’s request - or even one who provides painkilling medication which may hasten the patient’s death - is merely trying to ease the patient’s pain, while a physician who assists in a suicide has the intent that the patient should be dead. This is nothing 18 Vacco v. Quill, 521 U.S. 793, 797 (1997). Id. at 800. 20 Id. 19 8 more than judicially ascribing intent after the fact, and it implies that if a physician could prove his intent in assisting suicide was merely to ease the patient’s suffering, he would not be in violation of law. In looking at the patient, the court makes the conclusion that the “…patient who commits suicide with a doctor's aid necessarily has the specific intent to end his or her own life, while a patient who refuses or discontinues treatment might not.”22 The court does not address what other conclusions a patient might wish from refusing treatment. In a concurring opinion, Justice O’Connor recognizes a difficulty posed by both the Glucksberg and Vacco cases, namely that the court broadly characterized the issue as whether one has a right to commit suicide and to have help in doing so. She concurs with the court that there is no such right. She does note, however, that a narrower classification of the issue would present the court with the question of whether or not “…a mentally competent person who is experiencing great suffering has a constitutionally cognizable interest in controlling the circumstances of his or her imminent death”, and even goes so far as to recognize that “…dying patients in Washington and New York can obtain palliative care, even when doing so would hasten their deaths.”23 However she refuses, even in dicta, to address this question. In these cases the court might have been better served by finding a fundamental right and applying the strict scrutiny test, which mandates that governmental action be necessary to furthering a compelling governmental end. This is especially perplexing when one considers the unenumerated ‘fundamental rights’ the court has already recognized or created. see e.g.: Loving 21 Id. at 801. Id. at 801-802. 23 Id. at 809. 22 9 v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967) (right to marry whom one chooses), Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rel. Williamson, 316 U.S. 535 (1942) (right to procreate), Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905) (right of employees to contract), Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.S. 390 (1923) (right to education), Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965) (right of married couples to use birth control). All of these are important rights, but arguably dwarfed in comparison with a larger choice: the choice to live or die. The court also should have recognized that such statutes do, in fact, target suspect classes. The Americans with Disabilities Act, among many other state and federal statutes, have been specifically designed to look after the sick and the elderly in this country. It is a crime to discriminate against them, just as it is a crime to discriminate on the basis of race, ethnicity, or gender. And yet the Supreme Court still insists—in this narrow context only—that statutes which specifically target the terminally ill do not involve a suspect class. OTHER CONSIDERATIONS Currently, the only state which has any kind of law allowing assisted suicide law is Oregon. ORS 127.800 - 127.897, commonly known as the Death with Dignity Act allows residents to receive lethal doses of medication from a physician, when all of a number of procedural requirements are met. The law is important to Oklahoma attorneys for a number of reasons. First, it was passed and later approved by a popular vote, and has received limited judicial approval from a federal district court. This is likely to make it the archetype of any similar future legislation in other states. Also, based on the statutory requirements, it would be 10 possible for a client in another state to establish Oregon residency and avail themselves of this law. The statutory form requires that a patient seeking a prescription for life-ending medication be an adult resident of Oregon, mentally competent, and suffering from a terminal illness diagnosed and confirmed by at least two physicians.24 The statute does not define a resident of Oregon, but lists four factors which might demonstrate residency: possession of a state driver’s license, registration to vote in the state, owning or leasing property in the state, and filing a state tax return in the most recent year.25 So it might be possible for a terminally ill resident of another state to move to Oregon and establish residency for the purpose of receiving life-ending medication. However if a client is suffering from a terminal illness, these requirements might be too high a hurdle to pass. Allowing physician-assisted suicide carries the inherent risk that fraud, coercion, or force will be applied to terminally ill patients - people already under great stress - to induce involuntary euthanasia. However the practice is going on, and is likely to continue, so it should be recognized, monitored, and regulated to reduce this risk as much as possible. 24 25 OR. REV. STAT. § 127.805 (1999). OR. REV. STAT. § 127.860 (1999). 11