Philippe Fournier (lecturer in political science at the Université de Montréal, postdoc in sociology at the University of Québec at Montreal) Presented at the Millennium Annual Conference (2012); Materialism and World Politics Governmentality and Marxism; promises and difficulties. Abstract: Over the last decade or so, governmentality has become an increasingly popular analytical approach in International Relations. Recently, a few commentators have identified fundamental problems with the scaling-up of governmentality, arguing that the conditions for it to take hold are simply not present in many developing countries. In order to remedy this difficulty, they propose to integrate governmentality to a Marxian framework, which would account for the structural inequalities that explain the highly uneven governmentalisation of the international sphere. The paper considers this suggestion in more depth and highlights the promises, difficulties and wider implications of this combination for critical theories of International Relations. First, I argue that the amalgamation of Foucault and Marx constitutes a potentially effective political sociology that charters the social reproduction of capitalism in a detailed and non-reductionist manner. In contrast with Foucault’s focus on disciplinary power, governmentality extends the microphysics of power by representing the wider relations between state, society and the constitution of subjectivity. It will be shown that these preoccupations are shared by a variety of critical theorists who aim to represent the social and cultural reproduction of capitalism. Second, I take stock of the complexities and tensions in the intellectual rapport between Marxians and Foucaultians, with a particular focus on ontological and political divergences. The final part of the paper insists on the opening of a sustained dialogue between post-structuralism and broadly Marxian perspectives in International Relations. I suggest that Hardt and Negri’s work, which, bar a few exceptions, has been inexplicably overlooked or rapidly dismissed by International Relations scholars, can provide a good starting point for such a theoretical dialogue and for a wider discussion of power and resistance in the global sphere. Introduction Over the last few years, the idea of bringing governmentality and Marxism together to analyse International Relations has been gathering steam. One of the main motivations behind this combination is, ironically, the implicitly Western and statist vantage point of foucaultian governmentality. Indeed, governmentality’s very existence and effectiveness depends on a variety of institutional, social and material conditions (see Selby, 2007 and Joseph, 2010) that are not present everywhere. The extension of governmentality throughout the global sphere is thus incomplete, and the crucial issue of material imbalances and of the corresponding issue of uneven governmentalisation is best accounted for by historical materialism. Even if the dissemination of ethical norms and performance standards through the ever more present and numerous agencies of international development suggests that a transnational form of governmentality is beginning to emerge, the effectiveness of advanced liberal norms depends on pre-existing dispositions to 1 internalize the requirements set out by neoliberal behavioural and institutional models. It is often the case that governmentality is best applied to very specific regulatory regimes and to countries where the conditions are amenable to such an analysis. The other reason behind the inclusion of Marxism as a complementary rejoinder is, in rather more basic terms, governmentality’s sheer popularity as an approach and the inevitable critical discussion that this popularity entails. Yet, there is a sense that Marxists and foucaultians have not really engaged on the core issues, and have been hesitant to address more profound disagreements over the course of several decades. There may be a variety of reason for this. Some may be content to be a part of the extended family of critical International Relations and not be too concerned with epistemological differences. Or it may be that this lack of engagement is borne out of the recognition that those philosophical divergences are unbridgeable and that we best toil in our own respective fields. The objective of the paper is to take a closer look at both the promises and difficulties involved in the potential combination of Marxism and Governmentality. I make the case that the success and effectiveness of this peculiar blend depends on a series of epistemological and political choices and on the establishment of fairly specific conceptual grounds. I also claim that the re-emergence of Marxism in its various guises speaks to our current historical, social and material predicament and to the general need to develop adequate theoretical instruments to study emerging forms of subjectivation and resistance. The combination of Marxism and Governmentality should therefore respond to emerging practices of assent and resistance. The paper proceeds in two steps. First, it looks at the relationship between Foucault and Marx and at the relationship between Foucault and Marxism. Second, it attempts to set the conditions for a reasonably harmonious and effective combination of both lines of thought. Third, it traces the potential difficulties that such an encounter implies and suggests that the amalgamation of Marxism and Governmentality is also an invitation to think about the current state of critical theory. The paper closes with a preliminary extension of these questions to International Relations. 2 1_ Marx and Foucault The most revealing insights about Foucault’s relationship with Marx are to be found in a variety of interviews, as Foucault purposely avoided direct references to Marx in his own work. In 1960 and 1970’s France, the hegemony of Marxist thought in all its guises was at its peak. Foucault’s entire corpus indicates an implicit desire with do away with the manifold power-effects of Marxian theorising. It is worth noting that Foucault did not struggle with Marx as such but with the presumably authoritative adaptations of his work (Foucault, 2008). The three aspects of Marxian thought that Foucault regarded as particularly objectionable were its scientific pretence, its prophetic nature and its incarnation as a philosophy of the state or class ideology. To the first point, Marx’s intellectual production is intimately tied to a scientific discourse that had great currency in the second half of the 19th century. The notion that science was an embodiment of truth was reiterated in many varieties of Marxism in the twentieth century, not least by one of Foucault’s old mentors, Louis Althusser. We can also gather that the teleological inflections of several Marxian currents did not sit well with Foucault. Equally, he saw the enthronisation of the communist project into the state structure as one more step in the impoverishment of our political imagination (Foucault, 2008: 599). The uniformity and rigidity of the French Communist Party was certainly a factor in the demise of its political project. The idea that the party was the unique intellectual and cultural space through which classconsciousness could develop made it ill adapted to the expression of multiple wills and existential forms (Foucault, 2008: 614-615) from the late 1960’s on. Foucault, who was briefly a member of the Communist Party in the early 1950’s, quickly understood that this association was unsustainable. As he says in an interview “to be a Nietzschean communist was intolerable and even ridiculous, I knew that all too well” (Foucault, 2008: 869). Having specified that he objected to the contemporary expressions of Marxism and not to Marx as such, Foucault, rather playfully, situates his own work in the lineage of the Second Book of Capital. He asserts that most of the Marxists of his age were primarily concerned with the first Book of Capital and therefore with the technical modalities of the capitalist economy (commodity, the market, theory of value, etc.) (Foucault, Gordon, Patton and Beaulieu, 2012: 3 100-101). In contrast, he is more interested in the historical conditions of Capitalism’s development. As is well know, Foucault’s interest lies less in the subjugation of the working class in the economic structure than in the multiple institutional sites of control that shape the subject’s behaviour in more specific as well as in more profound ways. Foucault is undoubtedly influenced by Marx’s materialism but wants to apply it to ideas. In a revealing interview conducted by Colin Gordon in 1978, he states that his overall intention is to provide “a materialist history of idealities or of rationalities” (Foucault, Gordon, Patton and Beaulieu, 2012: 106). Again, he claims that the link between materialities and idealities is to be found in relations of power rather than in economic relations (Foucault, Gordon, Patton and Beaulieu, 2012: 106). Whilst Foucault was no phenomenologist, he also sought to identify the points at which subjectivity and materiality met in concrete historical settings (Foucault, Gordon, Patton and Beaulieu, 2012: 110). After a philosophical investigation of the modalities of truth, knowledge and meaning in the Order of Things and the Archeology of Knowledge, Foucault turned his attention to the practical instantiations of power at the intersection of the body and the norm, as well as that between psychological dispositions and rationalities of government. In this context, subjectivity is produced through a variety of spatial, actuarial and administrative techniques; freedom and volition can be nothing more than a perpetual and somewhat strained encounter with the endless diversity of power. Throughout most of his career, Foucault did not engage directly with the leading strands of French Marxism and certainly had no interest in embarking upon a detailed commentary of Marx’s own books, where many others set out to find new kernels of truth. Interestingly, he did not come across the Frankfurt School until much later in his life, a delayed discovery that was both, as he claimed, salutary for the development of his own thinking and a lost opportunity for a productive intellectual engagement. In one of his last and most intriguing texts, What is Enlightenment? (1984), Foucault associates more or less explicitly with the critical ethos of Enlightenment though. In truth, as much as he was sympathetic to the philosophical concerns of the Frankfurt School, Foucault could not have bought into the humanistic premises of their intellectual project. Yet, one senses that he was less bothered by these predispositions than by the doctrinal and economistic readings of Marx, which had great currency in his time. 4 2_ Governmentality and Marxism; complementarity and critique I argue that the combination of Marxism and governmentality must take place within a certain mind-frame. At an elementary level, each perspective is presumably brought in mitigate the other’s weaknesses or oversights. Second, their coming together needs to be considered in the context of contemporary events and must be based on an acknowledgement that the gap between living conditions and the soundness of the solutions that are being proposed to the impoverished and the unemployed, is growing. In other words, it should have an avowedly critical aim that foregoes functionalist applications of both modes of analysis and should recognise that the current economic crisis restricts existential possibilities, an element that will presumably affect the morphology of liberal-capitalism both as a socio-economic architecture and a rationality of government. Through his work on discipline and government, Foucault is more concerned with the multifarious support systems of capitalism than in its intricate mechanisms. He concentrates on the multiple practices that sustain the overall architecture of the socio-economic structure. Government and discipline’s exclusions and selections certainly have economic and organisational uses. As Bob Jessop points out, Foucault was generally interested in the ways in which capitalism permeated daily life. Indeed, capitalism requires “diverse techniques of power to enable capital to exploit people’s bodies and their time” (141: 2008). Of course, Foucault did not see Capital as a pre-given social force that sets the totality of social relations. Governmentality is particularly useful in understanding just how engrained the subjectifying logics of a neoliberal way of doing things really are. It is rather more precise than Marxism in its identification of the dispersed individual and social practices that converge towards collectivised aims, which are primarily the happiness and productivity of the population. It allows us to measure the nature and the extent of liberalism’s power effects and to identify the array of behaviours that sustain the development and survival of the Capitalist system. It contributes to an appreciation of the highly compelling or engrained character of a neoliberalism even in the face of great adversity. It may also warn us about the enormity of the task of transforming it and about the sheer quantity of practices and reflexes that we may need to unlearn. In all these respects, it 5 goes one better than the existing analyses of ideology, Marxian or otherwise. The Marxian tradition, with the notable exception of Gramsci, has struggled to represent both the appeal and the durability of liberal capitalism. Marx thought it evident that Capitalism could not last very long, at least in the form that it took in the 19th century. Many of the more creative or philosophically inclined Marxians in the twentieth century were equally puzzled by this resiliency and saw the reasonably widespread acceptance of capitalism as a case of outright alienation or of methodical indoctrination. On the other hand, Marxism is particularly effective at tracing the changing modalities of the capitalist economy and at underlining the importance of their effects on the living conditions of human beings. If one recognises the very real consequences of structural dysfunctions and crises of capitalism on existential possibilities, then the diagnoses of the current financial and economic crisis offered by prominent contemporary Marxian thinkers like David Harvey and Leo Panitch, for example, are important. By focusing on the extraordinary expansion and complexification of finance, Marxians have been able to account for and in some cases predict the unfolding crisis. The analyses of the rise of finance are often supplemented with a portrayal of the transition from an industrial base to the service-based economy, the weakening of trade Unions, the rolling-back of the Welfare state, the steady decline in salaries and purchasing power, the expansion of credit and the emergence of a global financier class from the 1970’s to the 2000’s. The idea behind the combination or strategic alliance of Marxism and governmentality is to respond to the need for mutual reinforcement in the task of detailing the cultural and social reproduction of capitalist relations. However, the combination of Governmentality and Marxism cannot only be based on the requirement to craft a more effective instrument for analysing state power or International Relations. It must be cast as a self-consciously critical enterprise in keeping with the radical tradition that takes as much inspiration from Marx as it does from Nietzsche. This critical enterprise is of course full of tensions. It might seem self-defeating to offer an inventory of the difficulties involved in the combination of Marxism and governmentality but I think it may allow for a keener awareness of the multiple instantiation of power and to get a sense of the current state of critical theory. 6 3_ Tensions and difficulties This part of the paper addresses the tensions between the normative underpinnings, the different conceptions of power and the place of critique in both governmentality and Marxism. Looking at the premises of both perspectives, the integration of governmentality and Marxism leads us to consider two distinct critical endpoints. On the one hand we can hold on to the Young Marx’s humanism and to the dual objective of critiquing Capitalism and working towards its demise (something that seems unthinkable and impractical even in the current context). On the other, we can side with Foucault’s rejection of humanism and acknowledge that critique and resistance are fluctuating modes of being that move with the constant innovations of power. Suffice to say that this is one of the more thorny points around the content and definition of critique, and that it is a reflection the current fragmentation of critical theory. The sources of this divergence are fairly recent. The post 1968 era gave way to the public and eventually political expression of marginalised subjectivities, which incidentally opened the way for a wider reception of Foucault’s work on the mad, the incarcerated, etc. The other condition of possibility for this greater diffusion was the internal collapse of the French Communist Party and the culmination of highly rigid and doctrinal currents of thought like Maoism, which made Marxism and its contemporary political expressions much less palatable. Marx’s shadow was then getting dimmer by the mid-1970’s and the sheer variety of forms of subjection in the contemporary realm exploded in the light of day in myriad political struggles. In the last 30 years, post-modernism and post-structuralism have become reasonably well-established perspectives with their own reputable journals and with a growing number followers in a variety of disciplines. After all this time, we can rightfully ask if these currents have had any effect on Marxism. Alternatively, we can ask if Marxism has liberated itself from its dependence upon state power and dissociated itself from its authoritarian homogenisation of difference. It is hard to say for sure, but even the more polemical critical cultural theorists recognize the influence of so-called poststructuralists, or at least of the cultural expressions they are trying to conceptualise, on Marxism’s own dialectical journey. A re-emergent Marxism must surely engage with these 7 questions and apply perpetual vigilance with regards to its own ends and methods. Many Marxists have been trying to accommodate the various expressions of identity within a historical materialist framework. Many have also reconsidered the necessity to invest conventional political structures to further their own agenda and have ceased to believe that repossessing the state is any kind of solution. a) Power, critique and borderline ideology Aside from non-negligible differences in critical endpoints and normative underpinnings, there remains, as is well know, a fundamental disagreement over the notion of power. To illustrate my point, I briefly review Marxism and governmentality’s respective understandings of liberalism. Governmentality sees liberalism in a peculiar light. Instead of being an elaborate institutional and cultural structure of falsification, liberalism is more of a response to the specific needs that emerge at a certain stage of historical development, which happens to coincide with the rise of industrial capitalism. Governmentality is rather like an immaterial orchestrator of individual and collective practices, which must be known and documented but also made to converge towards keeping the population productive and happy. In this context, freedom is not so much an illusionary endowment of abstract liberal philosophy, but is manipulated in relation to a given ratio of happiness and productivity. Whereas Marxists would contend that liberal-capitalism squeezes the life out of the population, Foucault claims that a liberal rationality uses and channels the population’s life forces, whilst keeping an eye on the tolerability and effectiveness of its administrative mechanisms. Despite governmentality’s apparent self-consciousness and inherent adaptability, it does not place one particular instance at the helm. Unlike Marxists, Foucault did not believe that the bourgeois class had deliberately installed the welfare state in order to preserve itself. Many Marxists see the rise of neoliberalism as a process of class re-composition and as resulting from a more or less coordinated ideological offensive (Harvey, 2004). Although Frankfurt School theorists were close to arguing that ideology had become reality, a faint glimmer of humanism and an even fainter hope that the transformative potential of technique would be ceased by the dispossessed, still remained. Foucault did not entertain such hopes and took for granted that ideology and 8 reality had become indistinguishable. He admires neoliberalism precisely because of its life-like character (2004b), and because it strips liberalism of its metaphysical shroud and abstract moralizing. A neoliberal rationality of government both connects with and produces the “naturalness” of human endeavours and energies. It is an integrally practical philosophy. Neoliberalism is in other ways a replication of the laws of nature, and in particular of natural selection. As a rationality, it is endlessly adaptative and follows in the midst of life’s transformations. Whilst this particular take on liberalism and neoliberalism are both highly original and perceptive, it is perhaps also where governmentality might be most vulnerable. In their apparent closeness to “reality”, renderings of a neoliberal rationality of government risk doing little more than reiterating it and turning into a sort of descriptive sociology. There is something profoundly paradoxical about governmentality; first, as we have just pointed out, it can come close to replicating and even fetishizing reality, second, if we go a little further in Foucault’s work, practices of resistance and aestheticized modes of being may become co-opted as soon as they emerge. As Hardt and Negri (2001) point out, within Empire, “difference” both legitimates the cultural hold of capitalism and participates in its logic of profit. Whatever imaginative practices we may come up with are bound to be subsumed in the endlessly flexible web of liberal governmentality and of the world market. This somehow ties with Fisher’s Capitalist realism and with Zizek’s ongoing complaint about the limits of contemporary political imagination. For Foucault, the eventual integration of pre-political struggles is an inevitable byproduct of the work of power. These two tendencies inherent to governmentality give the impression that liberalism, because of its uncanny ability to re-invent itself and to accommodate every manner of cultural and aesthetic expression, extends onto an endless historical horizon. It is practically impossible to conceive of a more effective, intelligent and durable form of governmentality. All of these remarks about liberalism point to the issue of power, which is undoubtedly one of the more intractable difficulties in the potential combination of Marxism and Governmentality. 9 Conclusions To fashion a critical framework that takes into account the many facets of the socio-cultural reproduction of capitalism is difficult and requires some important qualifications and an acknowledgment of the tensions and limitations between two of the more compelling analytical perspectives on neoliberalism that are currently available. The main question is, can we keep governmentality’s undoubted analytical power and make it work within a renovated form of Marxism for contemporary times? This leads to another question, namely has Marxism exorcized what Foucault identified as the three demons of scientificity, teleology and state power? Some adaptations of Marxism, perhaps those that are closer to critical theory and farther from purely economistic readings, have certainly taken heed of the admittedly dispersed and vague phenomenon that we tend to call post-modernism. However, the dialogue between two of the more common critical currents of our day remains relatively timid and even more so in International Relations. We can only guess what Foucault’s reaction to the material effects of neoliberalism would have been, but he believed that an art of the self, or any wholesome expression of subjectivity, required basic conditions of possibility, that is a certain freedom from want. This should probably be the minimal threshold for a combination of Marxism and governmentality. Foucault said something quite interesting in one of his interviews, “it is clear, even if one admits Marx will disappear for now, that he will reappear one day” (Foucault, 1999: 458). Perhaps the time for Marx’s re-emergence has come. Marxism has certainly gained more visibility in the last few years, but we would be hard pressed to say that this has been accompanied by a serious consideration of an alternative political project. In any case, whether one decides to look at important historical transformations in socio-economic arrangements from the perspective of governmentality, ideology or Marxian political economy, there is invariably a reference to widespread popular discontent and to ensuing political pressures. In this context, governmentality, which I take to be a radical version of ideology as lived-practice, can be used critically to determine the extent of our own subjection. The morphology of neoliberal 10 government is bound to change through an internal displacement of its own constitutive practices but also through a transformation of the population’s material conditions. A renovated Marxism must dialogue and engage with an approach like governmentality, which has become tremendously popular but is only just starting its own process of self-examination. It will have to be determined if governmentality can be made to be a transformative force but on a grander scale than the self. Marxism itself has gone through a long and strenuous internal dialogue; it has receded and apologized for many years. Over the last few decades, it has become increasingly clear is that it must include a feminist, anti-racist, polysexual, non-essentialist and anti-authoritarian standpoint at the same time as it must expose the mechanisms of neoliberal economics and class-formation. If combined, Marxism and governmentality can provide very apt descriptions of the simultaneously fine-grained, highly differentiated and generic practices that we like to group under the heading of neoliberalism. However, I argue that this analytical precision or effective political sociology must try and go beyond the detailed reconstitution of super-structures and power-effects to include and conceptualise contemporary forms of resistance. These are the preliminary questions and suggestions that I would like to discuss. These interrogations are also applicable to International Relations and Hardt and Negri’s trilogy offers a fertile of discussion that address or touch on many of the above points. Bibliography : Fisher, Mark (2009) Capitalist Realism : Is there no Alternative? London: Zero Books. Foucault, Michel (1984) “What is Enlightenment?” in Rabinow, Paul (ed.), The Foucault Reader, New York: Pantheon Books, pp. 32-50. Foucault, Michel (1999) Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology (Essential Works of Foucault, 1954-1984, Vol. 2), New York: the New Press. Foucault, Michel (2004a) Sécurité, territoire, population : cours au Collège de France (19771978), Paris : Gallimard. Foucault, Michel (2004b) Naissance de la Biopolitique: cours au Collège de France (19781979), Paris: Gallimard. Foucault, Michel (2008) Dits et écrits, volume II, 1976-1988, Paris: Gallimard. Foucault, Gordon, Patton and Beaulieu (2012) “Considerations on Marxism, Phenomenology and Power: Recorded on April 3rd, 1978”, Foucault Studies, No. 14, pp. 98-114. 11 Hardt, Michael and Antonio Negri (2001) Empire, Cambridge MA and London: Harvard University Press. Harvey, David (2004) A Brief History of Neoliberalism, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Jessop, Bob (2007) State Power, Oxford: Polity Press. Joseph, Jonathan (2010) “The Limits of Governmentality: Social Theory and the International”, European Journal of International Relations, Vol. 16, No. 2, 223-246. Panitch, Leo and Sam Gindin (2012) The Making of Global Capitalism, Verso: London. Selby, Jan (2007) “Engaging Foucault: Discourse, Liberal Governance and the Limits of Foucaultian IR”, International Relations, vol. 21, No. 3, 324-345. 12