Conceptualising and Measuring Power: A Brief Introduction David Marsh (IGPA) In the past Political Scientists, who were mostly pluralists, were more likely to talk of influence than power, and, following Robert Dahl, suggest that an individual/interest group has influence over the government in so far as it/she can make the government do something it wouldn’t otherwise have done. The key point here is that Dahl, like most other Political Scientists, thought that power was manifested in the influence that groups had over government policy, although he argued that, empirically, power in advanced liberal democracies like the US was diffuse, not concentrated; the classical pluralist position. This rather simplistic view of power was increasingly questioned. In particular, some political scientists argued that there were other ‘faces of power’, which didn’t involve individuals or groups directly influencing policy decisions. Lukes (1974) identified three faces of power. The first face involves decision making; here; an individual, or a group, has influence over a government decision to the extent that they persuade the government to do something it initially didn’t intend to do. The second face of power involves agenda setting; here, a group has influence by controlling the agenda, so that some policy options are not considered. A good example here would be UK agricultural policy between the 1930s and the 1980s. During this period, there was a tight institutional link, often called a policy community, between the Government, specifically the Ministry of Agriculture, Food and Fisheries (MAFF), and the farmers, specifically the National Farmers’ Union (NFU). Basically, this policy community negotiated about the level of production and state subsidies in an Annual Price Review. However, there was clear agreement between both parties on the broad policy, which was to grant farmers high subsidies in order to ensure high production. To put it another way, the policy options were constrained by a consensus about the boundary of the policy agenda. The idea of a third face of power proved even more contentious. The argument was that the whole debate about policy occurred within a social, cultural, economic, political and institutional framework which favoured some interests over others. This position was radical, and often Marxist, and rested to a significant extent on the contested idea of ‘real interests’. Here, citizens, especially disadvantaged citizens, are seen as socialised into a partial, even ‘false’, view of their own interests, a view which serves the interests of those who are powerful. So, as an example, it might be argued that, in patriarchal societies, women are socialised into accepting gender roles which constrain their opportunities. This view has something in common with the post-structuralism of Foucault (1980) or Laclau and Mouffe (1985). Foucault suggests that power is everywhere; it is exercised without intention. In his view, power works through, rather than on, people. So, a particular belief system, or discourse, becomes powerful as more people come to accept the particular values and beliefs associated with it. If the discourse is dominant, then different ideas become virtually unthinkable and a particular way of viewing the world, and of acting, becomes normal and right, while alternatives become deviant and wrong. At the same time, particular figures of authority, for example, priests or doctors, are legitimised, even defined, by these discourses. However, these discourses aren’t fixed, they are constantly contested and, in a sense, it is resistance to the dominant discourse that defines power. Obviously, Foucault’s work is rich and complex, but here the main point is that he would see power as inscribed in institutions, process and discourse, not as exercised by individuals or groups. At the same time, unlike Lukes, he does not see dominant belief systems as reflecting or forwarding, real, that is objective and material, interests. In the longer reading given you, Akram, Emerson and I (2015) examine how Foucault and Bourdieu (1977) might be used to develop a more sophisticated understanding of the third face of power. In particular, Bourdieu’s concept of habitus offers a conceptualisation of the way in which agents can be influenced in ways of which they are unware, thus positing a preco0nscious realm. Of course, the idea of different faces of power has clear methodological implications. If one focuses on the first face of power, this involves studying the outcomes of public policy decisions in the light of the prior commitments of government and the representations of interest groups. From this perspective, power would be concentrated to the extent that one group, or a limited number of groups, could consistently persuade government to take an action it initially opposed. However, if one acknowledge the importance of agenda-setting, then one might argue that a group like the NFU could consistency lose out in discussions of detailed policies with government, but still exercise power because the agenda is set in a way which forwards their interests. Here, the empirical focus would be on the extent to which the broader agenda has remained relatively constant over time and whose interest that agenda serves. Focusing on either the third face of power, using a Bourdieusian perspective, or on a post-structuralist perspective like Foucault’s, presents much greater methodological problems because here one needs to establish the nature and development of the belief system(s) and the contestations between them. Similarly, to defend a notion of real interest, it is crucial to show that a dominant belief system exists which forwards particular interests and, often unknown to them, manipulate the views and interests of others. In my view, if we are studying power, we have to acknowledge that it is inscribed in institutions and processes, as well as exercised by individuals. From this perspective, agents, whether individuals or groups, attempt to influence policy outcomes, but they do so on a strategic terrain which is not a level playing field. So, in Australia there is structured inequality which affects, but doesn’t determine, the influence individuals and groups have. Consequently, we need to examine the structural and ideational terrain as well the policy processes. Bibliography Bourdieu, P. (1977), Outline of a Theory of Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Foucault, M. Power/knowledge, London, Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1980. Laclua, E. and Mouffe, C. (1985) Hegemony and socialist strategy. London, Verso, 1985. Lukes, S (1974, 2005), Power: A Radical View. 2nd Ed. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.