Virtue, Individuality and Emptiness in Kant and Hegel REV 2/18/11 Christopher Yeomans (cyeomans@purdue.edu) DO NOT CITE OR DISTRIBUTE WITHOUT AUTHOR’S PERMISSION. One of the deepest puzzles in Hegel’s treatment of human agency is found in the problem of the connection and coherence of his many discussions of practical reason in the Phenomenology of Spirit. On the one hand, one of the real strengths of those discussions is the fullness with which different self-conceptions of agency are imagined as specific forms of life with their own characteristic fates. On the other hand, they are juxtaposed in such an original and surprising way that it is difficult to see the logic that connects them as the continual development of the idea of freedom. This difficulty is magnified when one tries to read these discussions as suggesting, if not constituting, a critical history of practical philosophy, a project that is all the more tempting precisely because the fullness with which Hegel imagines these self-understandings of agency appears to unearth the lived context and existential stakes of practical philosophy, and thus to provide a vital background for the evaluation of theories of agency. The apotheosis of this connection of promise and opacity is certainly to be found in Hegel’s discussion of Kant’s practical philosophy. To begin with the promise, it is clear that no figure is more decisive for Hegel than Kant: Hegel himself claims that Kant first put practical philosophy on a solid foundation precisely by the way in which he located freedom in the “infinite autonomy” of the will (PR§135R). And it is clear that Hegel takes his own view to have captured this element of Kant to its fullest extent precisely in virtue of extending it into the social field as such. 1 Finally, the way in which Hegel treats theories of practical reason as guiding selfunderstandings of the full lives of individual agents promises to leaven the abstraction of Kant’s presentation and thus to provide a bridge between Kant’s theoretical apparatus and lived experience. But the barriers to understanding Hegel on this point become immediately apparent. First, the centerpiece of Hegel’s critique of Kant – the so-called ‘emptiness objection’ – is presented in two near throw-away sections immediately following what appears to be a discussion of the production and evaluation of cultural products such as works of art; Hegel calls this realm ‘the spiritual animal kingdom,’ and it does not at first seem to have any deep resonance with any of Kant’s texts. Second, the emptiness objection is separated by over 100 pages from Hegel’s fuller discussion of Kant’s moral worldview in the chapter on spirit. Third, though even the most sympathetic Kant scholar must acknowledge that there is a grain of truth in Hegel’s charges of formalism, even the most sympathetic Hegel scholar must acknowledge that this point doesn’t have as much force as Hegel seems to think it does. Finally, and perhaps most puzzling, how can Hegel claim to have captured and incorporated into his own theory the Kantian conception of freedom as autonomy when he rejects the formality of law that appears to be central to autonomy on Kant’s own view? In my view, the textual key to completing this particular puzzle lies in the discussion of virtue that precedes the ‘spiritual animal kingdom.’ Between these two sections there is even more continuity than is usual in the Phenomenology, and this continuity is provided by the notion of the development and employment of talents. Though admittedly difficult at first, probing these sections for a context in terms of 2 which to make sense of the emptiness objection and Hegel’s critique of Kant more generally gradually brings out the fact that they present a sustained and insightful critical reconstruction of certain neglected but crucial themes in Kant’s moral psychology.i This reconstruction is oriented by the way in which individuality is important to Kant’s doctrine of virtue (inner morality), an importance that fits somewhat uneasily with Kant’s general emphasis on formal universality as the basic principle of autonomy. This tension between universality and individuality is reflected in Hegel’s summary of his critical appraisal of Kant’s ethics in his lectures on the history of philosophy: “What merits the name of truth in the Kantian philosophy, is that thinking is grasped as concrete in itself, self-determining itself [sich selbst bestimmend]; thus freedom is recognized.”ii But: “[Kant] knows not to become master of the individuality of self-consciousness; [he] describes reason very well, but does this in a thoughtless, empirical way by which it again robs itself of its truth.”iii It is difficult at first to make out how Kant’s alleged empiricism is related to the problem of individuality. But we can shed light on the subject by considering Schopenhauer in contrast to both Hegel and Kant, since perhaps no one has taken more seriously than Schopenhauer Kant’s claim that one can be an empirical realist only by being a transcendental idealist.iv On Schopenhauer’s view, Kant has not consistently applied this dictum to his own practical philosophy. When the consistency is enforced, Schopenhauer argues, transcendental idealism denies the fundamental differentiation of agents at the noumenal level of free will. As a result, there is no autonomy where there is individuality (in the phenomenal realm), and 3 there is no individuality where there is autonomy (in the noumenal). I take it that both Kant and Hegel want to reject this result that we cannot be individuated qua free, and thus the tension between individuality and universality must be resolved or at least productively articulated in some way for both thinkers. In the process of considering options for such a resolution or articulation, four Kantian threads can be traced through Hegel’s discussion of virtue and the spiritual animal kingdom: (1) the notion of virtue as the individualization of duty; (2) the conception of virtue in terms of duties that persons have in virtue of also being animals; (3) the picture of virtue as the fight between reason and the inclinations; and (4) the placement of the development of talents as a duty of virtue. After following the way in which Kant weaves and Hegel re-weaves these threads together in an attempt to produce a solution to the problem of individualization, I show how the ‘emptiness objection’ may be read in this light. 1. Virtue as the individualization of duty The strand that ties together most securely Hegel’s discussion of virtue in the Phenomenology and Kant’s doctrine of virtue is the notion of virtue as the individualization of duty. In the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant specifically marks this individualization as the distinctive task of the doctrine of virtue: “Ethics adds [to the categorical imperative] only that this principle is to be thought as the law of your own will and not of will in general, which could also be the will of others…” (MS 6:389). As a matter of moral judgment, this means that duties of virtue are inherently wide duties that prescribe only general maxims and not specific actions, 4 where individual interests are necessarily involved in translating those maxims into actions (MS 6:390 and 451 (discussing the role of interests in benevolence)). But paradoxically, the way any particular agent is to accomplish this moral individualization involves the subordination of their individual, subjective ends to three different universals: (1) the indeterminacy of different natural ends (also understood as the capacity to set ends abstracted from its specific exercise), (2) duty itself (i.e., motivation by the form of law as such), and (3) the happiness of others (MS 6:386-8). The first indeterminacy is not to be mistaken for a general or collective description of the specific natural ends agents pursue. That would be to identify it with happiness, and the rejection of this identification is important for Kant’s distinction between duties to self and to others. Kant’s arguments for the development of talents – a duty to self – require the indeterminacy of ends as such, since talents are to be developed not just for specific ends that are in view of the agent at the time, but rather for further possible, uncontemplated and unspecified ends. In contrast, every agent has a duty to further the (morally permissible) specific ends of others that collectively constitute others’ happiness. This subordination of the individual has two forms: First, as a matter of the material ends that they set for themselves, virtuous agents are guided by the three sorts of universals (MS 6:391-3). Second, as a matter of the philosophical grounding of duties of virtue, such justification must always begin with the form of law rather than the matter of the will (the end), since feeling (which is connected with the end) always belongs to the order of nature (MS 6:376). 5 Kant’s suggestion that a theory of virtue must provide resources for the individualization of the formal principle of duty is somewhat surprising. Particularly in the Groundwork and the second Critique, Kant grounds the autonomy in the immediate determination of the will by the formality and universality of its constitutive norm, and thus the particular features that would individuate agents appear to be, at best, morally irrelevant. (e.g., GW 4:444, KpV 5:33 and MS 6:213-4) From Hegel’s perspective, however, the Doctrine of Virtuev is a point at which Kant recognizes an important unmet need in his practical philosophy. This need can be clarified by considering Schopenhauer’s development of Kantian moral theory. As we briefly considered above, Schopenhauer thinks that Kant should have realized that the consistent application of transcendental idealism to practical philosophy shows that the theoretical resources necessary for the individuation of agents (i.e., space, time, and causation) are unavailable at the level of the (noumenal) free will, so one agent’s will is not metaphysically distinct from another. As the foundation of ethics, pity is the affective recognition of this underlying non-differentiation.vi But transcendental idealism quarantines this underlying mystical conception from the phenomenal experience of individual agents, and as a result moral responsibility and sanction become rather utilitarian affairs in Schopenhauer’s view, and the human being is denied any fundamental dignity as compared with animals – both consequences that Hegel wants to reject just as much as Kant. But the root problem that generates these consequences is the lack of morally relevant resources for the individuation of agents. 6 There is much in the Metaphysics of Morals to support Schopenhauer’s contentions. Despite Kant’s suggestion that virtue is the individualization of morality, it is not clear what resources there are for the differentiation of agents. Moreover, in the arguments of the Doctrine of Virtue, Kant does not say much about what specific sort of individuality of the agent is to be considered. In terms of kinds of individuation, we might want to distinguish between the subjective appropriation of duty (something like my own distinctive concern or care for the moral law) and the specification of the content of duty.vii Both forms of individuation seem to be important Kant’s conception of virtue. The former can be seen in Kant’s view that I need to develop my own specific receptiveness to duty by counteracting the hindrances to duty that are particular to me as an individual. I will discuss this in more detail in §3 with respect to what I will call the Indirect Strategy for individuation. The latter conception of individuation can be seen in the aforementioned general feature of duties of virtue that they are wide duties that can only be specified through their conjunction with individual interests, and is the primary target of what I will call the Subsumption and Direct Strategies of individuation. In terms of resources for individuation, one occasionally gets hints in the discussions of the “casuistical questions.” There, the relevant forms of particularity appear to be given by natural and social features of the context of action that are not themselves direct objects of duty (e.g., the strength of sexual desire and the position of a king subject to capture in war (MS 6:426 & 423)). One might then think that individualization would be a matter of the connection of empirical desires or other 7 features with the moral form of duties. I will refer to this suggestion as the Subsumption Strategy, as it would have it that empirical particularity is subsumed under the moral law and thereby made relevant to individuation of the agent qua free. But several things that Kant says mitigate against this reading. The first concerns individuation in the sense of the specification of content. Early on in the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant specifically distinguishes empirical attributes as irrelevant to the agent qua homo noumenon, and so any direct appeal to independent empirical features as individuating agents qua free is ruled out, and it appears that Kant merely helps himself to the identity of homo phaenomenon and homo noumenon while undermining the possibility of an account of that identity (MS 6:239). And yet the phenomenal presence of the individual subject is central to presenting duties towards her (including, one must think, duties to oneself). This is made clear by Kant’s reasoning for why the category of duties to God is empty: “since such a being is not an object of possible experience” (MS 6:241). The second concerns subjection appropriation: the difference between duties of right (whose articulation in the agent’s will is essentially the same for everyone) and duties of virtue (whose articulation in the agent’s will is particularized and thus distinct from the articulation in other agents’ wills) is that duties of right allow for different incentives that would vary between agents, whereas in virtue all agents must have the same incentive, namely duty itself. But this means that the particular empirical features that might differentiate agents are relevant to actions that fulfill duties of right, but not to actions that fulfill duties of virtue, and this is precisely the opposite 8 of what one would expect if such empirical features were to play the individuating role for virtuous actions in the way envisioned by the Subsumption Strategy.viii We can see a second, indirect connection between duty as norm of autonomy and individualizing natural and social characteristics in Kant’s first argument for why there must be a distinctively moral end: “For since the sensible inclinations of human beings tempt them to ends (the matter of choice) that can be contrary to duty, lawgiving reason can in turn check their influence only by a moral end set up against the ends of inclination, an end that must therefore be given a priori, independently of inclinations” (MS 6:380-1). I will refer to this suggestion as the Indirect Strategy of individuation. In this argument Selbstzwang (self-constraint) is connected with virtue in precisely the same way that Zwang (coercion) is connected with right, i.e., as a counterbalance to hindrances to freedom and therefore a promotion of freedom (MS 6:231). The important thing to note here is the precisely the conflict between the individualizing features of our sensible nature and the universal character of the moral end. Indirectly, the moral end derives its individual character from the fact that it is set up as a counterweight to specifically individual features of the character of the agent. Thus this tension between the sensible and the rational seems to introduce into Kant’s theory the resources required for individualizing the demands of duty for particular agents, via the struggle of the agent to discipline her sensible nature. Thus the subordination of natural individuality to universality might take on a morally or autonomously individual form. In this case individuation by means of subjective appropriation appears to produce specification of content, at least as far as the end of virtue is concerned. 9 But Kant’s fullest discussion of the axes of morally relevant individuality suggests a somewhat different approach, one that I will refer to as the Direct Strategy of individuation. This discussion comes in the fascinating, short section entitled “On ethical duties of human beings toward one another with regard to their condition (Zustand)” (MS 6:468-9). There, Kant suggests that there are difficult questions concerning the application of the duties of virtue to persons in their specific condition, and that their answers require a schematization of the principles of virtue.ix The focus on application suggests that the specific problem considered here is the specification of the content of duty. The different variables in specific condition mentioned are moral virtue itself, cultivation, learning, and kinds of expertise. Here, the relevant forms of particularity appear to be quite different: rather than being independent empirical features, they are differences in a kind of condition that is itself subject to the duty of virtue to promote one’s own perfection. Thus in this third strategy, individualization does not need to be indirect in the same way that it is in the self-struggle model of the Indirect Strategy; our duty of virtue is to be individuated in part by reference to our previous attempts to fulfill this duty and the outcomes of those attempts. Thus the problem of individuation takes on a recursive form that in addition has certain prominent Aristotelian resonances. On the one hand, this eliminates the problematic indirectness of the self-struggle model; on the other hand, it threatens to become a vicious circularity, since individualization seems to require prior individualization. As we will see later, Hegel thinks the two strategies can be combined through Kant’s own notion of the 10 interest-guided development of talents in a way that makes the circle productive rather than vicious. With this complex of problems from Kant as our horizon, we can make sense of some of the distinctive features of Hegel’s discussion of virtue. In the Phenomenology, Hegel describes virtue as being distinctively constituted by the relation between individuality and universality.x Hegel does not seem to see the Subsumption Strategy as a live option for considering this relation specifically as a relation of virtue. The strategy plays a role in Hegel’s argument in the preceding section on the law of the heart, but consideration of that section would take us too far afield. We will come back to this strategy in the last section, since it is reintroduced in Hegel’s versions of the emptiness objection. Instead, Hegel focuses in his discussion of virtue on the other two strategies (Indirect and Direct). Hegel first treats virtue as exemplified by the Indirect Strategy. On this view of moral individuation, the paradox of the struggle to be virtuous is that one must individualize one’s own sacrifice of individuality to the universal. Virtue is the commitment to validate personal consciousness precisely by submitting individuality to the discipline (Zucht) of the universal through action that is itself inherently an expression of individuality (PhG¶381; cf. Kant, KpV 5:82). Hegel’s way of understanding this Kantian theme is that the actualization of virtue always takes place in the medium of individuality, and that abstraction from this medium seriously distorts both our moral theory and individual agents’ selfunderstanding. Part of Hegel’s point in discussing virtue and the development of talents first, and only then proceeding to the question of the form of law (and later 11 on to other, more specific features of Kant’s moral worldview) is to emphasize that Kant is not entirely guilty of such abstraction, and yet nonetheless does not recognize the full consequences of the centrality of individuality to inner morality. When we do, Hegel thinks, we must recognize that all the things which engage individuality are ends in themselves, and the use of powers, along with playing the game of giving them outward expression is what gives life to what otherwise would be the dead in-itself. The in-itself is not an abstract universal without existence, not something which is never accomplished. Rather, it is immediately itself this present moment and this actuality of the processes of individuality (PhG¶393). Central to Hegel’s conception here is a certain account of goal-directedness that can only be hinted at here. The centerpiece of this account is a kind of reciprocal interaction between end and means such that each comes to particularize the other in the process of goal-directed activity. On Hegel’s view, what Kant marginalizes as an issue of the application of concepts of duty to specific conditions can only be adequately understood as the mutual production and constitution of conditions and the concrete operating conception of the moral end in the understandings of individual agents. One might think this is a technical point, but on Hegel’s view this undermines the distinctiveness of the morally required ends of virtue as opposed to the normal material ends of individual reason by undermining Kant’s distinction between immediate determination of the will by reason and mediated determination by desires.xi Later, we will see that this consequence is important for Hegel’s attempt to shift the debate away from the problem of the categorical imperative procedure returning the right result to the subtly different problem of its functioning in the right way as a structure of autonomy. In Hegel’s presentation, the danger that Kant’s account collapses into something like Schopenhauer’s is 12 presented as the double result of the struggle of virtue with the selfish way of the world: on the conception of desire-driven particularity that they both share, the virtuous person is unable to sacrifice, and the self-seeking agent is unable to express their individuality (PhG¶¶390-3). For Hegel, individuality is the very principle of the inversion of moral into material ends and vice versa, and thus this inversion is the price of the concreteness of moral ends (PhG¶¶381-3). 2. Virtue as duties that persons have in virtue of being animals The second thread is the conception of virtue in terms of duties that persons have because they are also animals. This conception appears at numerous places in the Doctrine of Virtue, and most pointedly in the discussions of duties to self. Kant argues that the obligatory end of my own perfection involves cultivation of my understanding, which raises me from animality to humanity, since I need concepts to connect ends with duties (MS 6:386-7).xii In defending the very idea of duties to self, Kant argues that our dual constitution as both animal and intelligible is what allows us to make sense of such duties to self, given that they seems to involve two persons, one that puts another under an obligation (MS 6:418). Here Kant takes up a specific difficulty that Schopenhauer will later press. On Schopenhauer’s view, duties to self are impossible: they can be neither duties of justice (since we cannot be unjust to ourselves for we endorse what we do) nor of love (since we look after our well-being automatically).xiii Kant’s response here is interesting. One expects him to resolve the difficulty by arguing that our rational nature puts our animal nature under obligation (so we can make sense of it as a kind of duty of justice, in Schopenhauer’s sense), and thus that there is a kind of moral well-being to which 13 we do not naturally or automatically attend (so there might also be a duty of love, in Schopenhauer’s sense). This would appear to be consistent with Kant’s frequent reference to the natural ends of our animal abilities in the arguments for specific duties of virtue, and to accord with the development of talents as a duty to self. But the argument Kant actually makes is that, qua intelligible free person rather than qua sensible animal with reason, we can be under obligation to humanity in ourselves. One can see the basis for Kant’s reasoning here (no animal without transcendental freedom can be subject to obligation), but with respect to individuation the argument both introduces a new difficulty and robs him of an obvious resource. Now Kant is obligated to provide an account of differentiating at the noumenal or intelligible level between the intelligible agent and humanity within her, and to do so without invoking the natural differences that play such a dominant role in most human practices of individuation. With respect to Schopenhauer’s earlier concern about Kant’s consistency with regard to individuation of agents, this argument amounts to doubling down on the noumenal bet. Hegel refers to this conception somewhat playfully in calling the properly conceptualized operation of virtue in the world “the spiritual animal kingdom (das geistige Tierreich)” (PhG¶397).xiv In this conception, he says that our “original determinate nature” (i.e., our individual character, broadly construed) is like the element in which animals feel at home and self-directed (PhG¶398), and similarly holds that by the interest-oriented development of our talents we become spiritual (or minded – geistige) animals. 14 Given the way we have just seen Hegel reinterpret the Direct Strategy of individuation to identify individuality with the end in itself, the role that individuality plays with respect to the distinction between the animal and the rational is quite necessarily different in Hegel’s account. On Hegel’s view, it is precisely the greater individuality of the rational creature that distinguishes it from less developed animals. As H.S. Harris very suggestively puts it, for Hegel “every Real Individual is a unique species (like the angels of Aquinas)…The destiny of Real Individuality is to know itself as the concretely autonomous principle of Kant’s Practical Reason.” Hegel therefore needs another way of understanding how our individuality is subordinate to universality as is made most explicit in Kant’s Indirect Strategy, and he does so by focusing on the related universalities of (1) indeterminate ends and (3) happiness considered as determined by the whole of the ends of the agent. This comes out in Hegel’s view that our determinate individual nature (our talents and interests) is individuality as the way in which our specific determinacy is represented as a universal range of action qua medium of self-expression (PhG¶398). Here, both the indeterminacy and totality of ends are reconceived. The indeterminacy, which Kant conceives in terms of general utility (and thus ultimately by reference to natural desires) is now present as capacities to express the agent’s distinctive take on issues of human concern (die Sache selbst). The totality, meanwhile, is no longer a heap of ends, but rather a structured articulation of the values of the agent (cf. PR§§19-21). On this view, the individuality of rational ends is much more directly connected to the natural constitution of the agent, since the 15 latter has an important influence on both the range of ends available to us and the interests by which we specify those ends. Thus we can interpret Hegel here as arguing that reinterpretation of the Direct Strategy by bringing out the role that individuality actually plays within it shows that there is less tension between it and the Indirect Strategy than there appears to be in Kant. As Hegel puts it, this original nature is both the content of the end of the individual and the activity of the individual, so we can see Hegel’s point here as responding to the need for individuation both as specification of content and as subjective appropriation.xv As the former it is free qua specific medium of expression, and as the latter qua process of transformation (PhG¶399). For Hegel, the individuality and rationality are not in tension; rather, individuality is the axis along which rational ends are distinguished as being higher than merely natural ends. This is the continuation of a continuum that separates different natural forms as well, as Hegel holds that animals are precisely distinguished from plants in that they are more responsible for their own individuation (e.g., PhG¶246). Spiritual animals then are, for Hegel, those creatures who are just starting to take reflective responsibility for their own individuation, and this is why the notion of the interest-guided development of talents, which is the primary mechanism for such individuation and has its most natural location in the human lifespan in later childhood and adolescence, is the focal point of the moral psychology of this self-understanding of agency in the Phenomenology. We can make a bit more sense of Hegel’s rephrasing of the problem if we understand 16 the specific kind of constraint that constitutes virtue in the light of the mixed nature of the agent. 3. Virtue as the fight between reason and the inclinations The third important Kantian thread in Hegel’s discussion of virtue is the idea of virtue as the fight between reason and the inclinations. Here we have the most specific use of the self-struggle or Indirect Strategy of individuation. For Kant, we have the duty to set a certain material (though a priori) end for ourselves, in part because in this way lawgiving reason checks the influence of the sensible inclinations that tempt us to other ends contrary to duty. This is the form of our self-constraint (Selbstzwang) by duty, which makes it the doctrine of (inner) virtue rather than the doctrine of (outer) right (MS 6:380-1).xvi Hegel, famously, has difficulty keeping a straight face here. He actually presents two different comic images of this fight, which may be best understood as differing in that one does, and one does not, take seriously the transcendental idealist division between the noumenal rational will and phenomenal material desires. If this division is taken with Schopenhauerian seriousness, Hegel calls the combatant here the Knight of Virtue, a figure often compared to Don Quixote. Ferrucio Andolfi puts Hegel’s point here nicely: “The humorous aspect of this figure arises from the fact that an inner morality such as the Kantian undertakes a task that is unachievable for it, namely to be capable of being effective in actuality.”xvii That is, reason is supposed to participate in the very order of desires, its independence of which constitutes its purity and thus its morality. But if, as on Hegel’s view, this division of reason and inclination cannot be taken seriously, then this struggle is really just 17 shadowboxing,xviii a parody of self-constraint, where reason attempts to look as if it is using natural dispositions in a way that is contrary to their selfish employment, but where, as Kant might put it, the “dear self” is always cropping up again in the inherent satisfaction of successful exercises of agency (PhG¶386). Though it is certainly right to emphasize that for Kant, the moral agent is not constantly in the process of repressing unruly inclinations, this is so because the moral agent has already succeeded in the long-term process of disciplining those inclinations. With respect to virtue in particular, Kant is quite clear that the very nature of virtue is to put individuality at the service of universality in its fight against particular inclinations. The argument considered above for the necessity of a priori ends shows this role of individuality, and Kant adds that “a human being’s moral capacity would not be virtue were it not produced by the strength of his resolution in conflict with powerful opposing inclinations. Virtue is the product of pure practical reason insofar as it gains ascendancy over such inclinations with consciousness of its supremacy (based on freedom)” (MS 6:477).xix The nature of the fight is, of course, that autonomy is at stake; natural impulses are necessarily obstacles to freedom and morality (MS 6:380). Or, as Hegel puts it, the weapons are the essences of each combatant (PhG¶383). The difficulty, on Hegel’s view, is in the counting of the combatants. One needs an account of individuation that will allow there to be two instead of just one in order to make sense of the struggle, but the initial temptation to count by distinguishing pure reason from natural inclinations has been undermined by the fact that in this fight, the weapons of both are in fact the same, i.e., the material ends that are a necessary 18 element in all agency. Kant would, of course, reject this characterization. The most obvious way he suggests to do this is to distinguish between ends set prior to and ends set after the formulation of moral maxims: all ends set prior to moral maxims are empirical grounds and self-seeking, but ends that result from maxims adopted as required by the concept of duty can be distinctively moral (MS 6:382). Hegel rejects this conception as inaccurate moral psychology. On Hegel’s view, the same role is played by the specific interests of the agent in both cases: a universal is given life, a concrete form, by the way in which the agent takes an interest in a particular situation. The prior/posterior distinction, whether regarded as an issue of the causal history of the action or the constructed justification for it, is for Hegel an essentially superficial distinction that masks the facts of moral psychology. This is the import, I believe, of Hegel’s claims that Kant’s account of practical reason is undermined by its empirical mode of description (e.g., VGP 462).xx The proper question is not the temporal or deductive ordering of desires with respect to the moral law; the question is their respective function in agency. Kant’s notion of ends as potentially the product of moral maxims does, however, take a step towards the right view, from Hegel’s perspective, but one which is fundamentally obscured by the transcendental distinction between nature and free will that structures Kant’s moral psychology. The question for Hegel is not between habituation without critical reflection and effective critical reflection without habituation (or preceding habituation). For Hegel, the question is whether the force of critical reflection is external or internal to the motivational stance of the agent, i.e., whether pure reason is practical of its own, or only as an element within 19 the larger goal-directed activity of the agent. Hegel’s point about the problem of moral individuation in Kant’s account is designed, in part, to motivate an interpretation of Kantian pure practical reason as, in fact, external to the motivation state of the autonomous individual, and so as making the claim that there remains an irreconcilable tension between individuality and autonomy on Kant’s view. As we will see in the last section, the emptiness objection functions as a further diagnosis of this tension as grounded in the identification of pure practical reason with the formal universalization of law. When we combine this perspective with Hegel’s claim in the Philosophy Right that the Kantian form of practical reflection actually constitutes the naturalness of desires,xxi I believe that Hegel’s account is this: Reason is always active in shaping the motivational stance within which it is the active and critical element (i.e., in Hegel’s terms, in which it is the element of negativity), but in the Kantian selfunderstanding, an agent justifies her own decision to shape the motivational stance in the way that she does by characterizing other possible shapes as being merely natural inclinations. ‘Reason’ and ‘nature’ here do not signify given and fixed metaphysical categories, but are rather our Enlightenment names for chosen and rejected options. The distinction between reason and nature within the moral psychology of the agent is something created by action. This is not to say that it cannot become a presupposition for future individual actions, but that from the long-term point of view of the agent’s character as a whole, it is to be regarded as something produced rather than given. But such a perspective is fundamentally undermined by an empirical mode of description that looks quite locally to the 20 temporal or deductive ordering of reason and nature, and this is the heart of Hegel’s criticism of Kant on this point. This, then, provides a way to read Hegel on Kant’s infinite progressions of virtue: the unholiness of the agent is a product as much as a presupposition of the moral agent, and so naturally the same discrepancy between motivation from duty and from desire recurs with each decision and action. There is no question of an asymptotic approach to holiness, since the reason/nature distinction is in fact recreated with each reflective action. From Hegel’s perspective, Kant is unfortunately right to say that “Virtue is always in progress and yet always starts from the beginning” (MS 6:409), but only because the nature of its progress is to continually recreate the beginning so that there is no progress. To put it in terms of the strategies of individuation, Hegel’s diagnosis is that a misinterpretation of the Direct Strategy induces a fatally flawed overreliance on the Indirect or self-struggle Strategy. From Hegel’s perspective, Kant’s view, if represented by what Henry Allison calls the Incorporation Thesis, has the true situation exactly backwards.xxii Rather than taking a given natural desire and incorporating it into a rational principle, potential rational principles are expelled from reason by the process of decision and action, and this expulsion is signified by the characterization of those principles as ‘natural.’ From within this self-conception, the characteristics thus made natural cannot then be made morally relevant except as the object of a struggle against them, and autonomous action therefore takes the shape of the actual and active rejection of the direct resources for individuation. But from Hegel’s perspective, this 21 diagnosis is quite charitable as a reading of Kant since it softens the distinction between Kant’s Indirect and Direct Strategies of individuation by making at least some of the natural features of the Indirect Strategy a natural by-product of the autonomous self-shaping of the Direct Strategy. A natural way to understand this is through the way that the exercise of talents develops and thus specifies those talents. 4. The development of talents as a duty The fourth important thread is the notion of the development of talents as a duty of virtue. Kant gives at least three versions of an argument for that duty, two in the Groundwork and one in the Metaphysics of Morals. On the FUL version in the former text, lack of development of talents could be consistently universalized, but because of our attachment to purposes (i.e., material ends) for which those talents are useful, we could not will universal lack of development (GW4:422-3). In an FHE version of this argument from the latter text, Kant argues that humanity involves setting ends, and so in cultivating our natural capacities for furthering ends we raise ourselves from animality to humanity (MS 6:391-2). And in a similar argument from the Groundwork, Kant argues that the development of our talents is a matter of harmonization with the natural end of humanity (GW4:430). Here the details of the moral psychology involved start to become clearer. Even in Kant there appears to be a kind of shaping of humanity as the creative expression of autonomy, since this way that we raise ourselves to humanity involves a selective cultivation of individual capacities, and there already appears to be a natural variation in the capacities found in particular individuals even prior to their 22 development. This suggests that our determinate and specific status or condition qua human is one that is achieved as much as given.xxiii In his discussion of duties of virtue in general, Kant associates this duty of cultivation with the Indirect Strategy for moral individuation focusing on subjective appropriation of duty: “For while the capacity (facultas) to overcome all opposing sensible impulses can and must be simply presupposed in man on account of his freedom, yet this capacity as strength (robur) is something he must acquire…” (MS 6:397)xxiv This account fits very naturally with the duty to self of moral perfection, but less so with either the duty to self to develop talents (which is based on the utility of talents with respect to indeterminate ends) or the duty to promote others’ happiness. The notion of cultivation appears to be applied in the latter two cases by way of the notion of humanity as setting ends. As in the Groundwork argument, this is represented as the development of talents, and the wideness of the duty to develop them points to the role of individual interest in guiding that development, and thus to the contrastive and particular forms of that development in different agents. As Kant construes the duty, we are to develop our talents according to our free determination, rather than natural instinct aimed at the benefits of such development to our own happiness, and yet the particular differences in individuals’ ends makes a difference to how the content of this duty is specified in practice: “it is a command of morally practical reason and a duty of a human being to himself to cultivate his capacities (some among them more than others, insofar as people have different ends), and to be in a pragmatic respect a human being equal to the end of his existence” (MS 6:445). To produce in myself a 23 humanity that is equal to its vocation thus involves sensitivity to individual ends (both in myself and in others). For this very reason, the account of cultivation that looked merely quantitative when connected with the Indirect Strategy’s demand to progress from weakness to strength takes on a qualitative dimension through the very different kinds of ends that individuals can set and the very different talents that they possess. Now, Kant repeatedly tries to constrain this duty of cultivation by suggesting that the development of talents is determined specifically by law. As he puts it, though every aptitude is a subjective perfection of choice, only aptitudes that determine actions in accordance with law rather than habit are free Wille rather than arbitrary Willkür (MS 6:407). But the qualitative dimension that Kant’s own sensitivity to individual ends introduces fundamentally undermines the adequacy of law to play this role. In fact Kant makes no attempt to explain how the universal form of law directs the development of talents; instead, Kant’s appeal in these arguments regarding talents is to the universality of the indeterminacy of ends (which one might more naturally associate with Willkür than Wille), and even that appears to be restricted to a certain range that is determined by the individual, natural constitution of the agent. For Hegel, the outcome of the consideration of virtue as the correct employment of talents or natural gifts is the idea that in the development and employment of those talents the agent expresses her individuality, and thus knows herself as a free an autonomous individual; humanity is individualized rational nature (PhG¶¶400-1).xxv In following the discussion of virtue with the discussion of 24 the development of talents through interests in the spiritual animal kingdom, Hegel seems to hold that the truth underlying this apparent confusion about the proper constraint on the development of talents in Kant is that talents play the role of a kind of natural universal that is self-specifying, or at least lends itself to being specified in particular ways. Here, however, talents are universal not in the manner a natural law (whose universality is tied to its exceptionless necessity), but rather through what we might call a determinate indeterminacy (i.e., differential possible routes of development). In this sense talents are naturally connected to the notion of duties of virtue as wide duties.xxvi For Hegel, talents are individuated forms of the capacity to set ends. When combined with Hegel’s earlier claim that individuality is an end in itself, his argument appears to be that we respect others as ends in themselves to the extent that we support them in and allow them to develop their talents according to their interests; and, because our talents are useful to others, when we develop our own talents according to our interests we serve others as well. It is for this reason that Hegel characterizes talents as the self-actualizing good (PhG¶386). Talents and interests together are both the material and the purpose of activity, and the element that absorbs the shape of individuality (PhG¶396 and 401). But we should not go too far in distinguishing Hegel and Kant here. H.S. Harris is surely right to hold that it is the discipline imposed by the struggle that forces this development – thus the struggle itself is the actualization of the good. The Indirect Strategy with its need for discipline and strength of character does not disappear in Hegel; it is merely reconceived as the discipline to develop one’s talents as guided by one’s interests. Despite the fact that the universal and the individual are no longer 25 fundamentally or inevitably in tension, this discipline is still hard work and involves some element of sacrifice.xxvii Interests here play the crucial role of guiding free development, and thus replace the appeal to law in Kant’s conception, but it strikes me that here Hegel is working with basically Kantian resources to shift the balance of responsibility of the different elements in Kant’s moral psychology. According to Kant, an interest is “an incentive of the will insofar as it is represented by reason” (KpV 5:79). An interest, therefore, involves rational consideration above a mere drive, but Hegel has a very specific idea about what is involved in such rational consideration. In line with his general conception of desire as a drive to confirm the independence of the individual, Hegel holds that when linked with talent, interest is the positing of the “given circumstances as its own, that is, as purpose” (PhG¶401). Hegel’s idea here is that interest represents talent as a means to a purpose that is found present in the circumstances of action, and which the agent furthers just as much as she sets it as an end. But the interest plays the guiding role with respect to talent in a fundamentally different way than does the universality of law. Whereas law is a given form that constrains individuation through its instantiation in specific circumstances, interests are themselves transformed by the process of their effectiveness in the development of talents. Kant sometimes sees this when he discusses how the duty to develop talents is related to the choice of profession, but again the universality that replaces the form of law as controlling is indeterminate utility (MS 6:392 and 445-6). Hegel attempts here to do justice to Kant’s provocative but undeveloped insight that humanity is produced just as much as it is 26 presupposed, but his reconstruction undermines a central feature of Kant’s doctrine of virtue, which is the asymmetry between the duty of virtue to self and to other. This undermining signals the final exhaustion of Kantian resources for individuation, since the asymmetry between duties of virtue to self and to others is the most theorized account of the individuation of agents offered in the Doctrine of Virtue, even though it only quite generally distinguishes between self and other, and not between persons in specific conditions. Our duty to ourselves is to develop our talents and will, but our duty to others is to promote their happiness. On Kant’s view, to promote our own happiness cannot be a direct duty for us because it does not involve Zwang (coercion or constraint): “What everyone already wants unavoidably, of his own accord, does not come under the concept of duty, which is constraint to an end adopted reluctantly” (MS 6:386). On the other side, we cannot have a duty to develop others’ talents or will, since the perfection of the agent is his ability “to set his end in accordance with his own concepts of duty,” and this cannot be done for anyone else (MS 6:386). Hegel’s rejection of the central premise of the second argument – that individuals necessarily set their own ends for themselves – is so global in the Phenomenology that it cannot be treated in any detail here.xxviii Proximally, if talents are individuated forms of the capacity to set ends, it must be said that they take on their individual forms in the decidedly social contexts of training and education. In this connection, we have just seen the way in which Hegel sees interests as identifying purposes in the circumstances of the exercise of talent, where these circumstances are in many ways independent of the will of the agent. 27 Concerning the argument that happiness cannot be my own duty, we have just seen why Hegel takes Kant’s own commitments to undermine this. If individual interests are necessarily involved in the specification of ethical duties – directly in duties to self but also in the duty of benevolence to others – then acting morally brings with it a confirmation of one’s own autonomy as refracted through the particular features of one’s individual outlook and circumstances.xxix Thus, Hegel thinks, Kant also should recognize that both desire (Begierde) and pleasure (Lust) involve an element of self-confirmation. The pleasure that results from the satisfaction of desire is not a merely natural state, but is centrally tied to the validation of the individual as free and autonomous.xxx And there is some evidence that Kant does recognize this, though it is admittedly less than fully convincing.xxxi 5. The emptiness objection in the context of individualized virtue In the Phenomenology, the official emptiness objection immediately follows the discussion of virtue and the development of talents, in two sections devoted to reason as law-giving and reason as law-testing. In my view, this structural placement is consistent with Hegel’s orienting remark in the VGP that though Kant recognizes the concreteness of autonomous reason, he cannot present it in its individuality due to his empiricism, and so autonomy and individuality remain in tension. As a result, Hegel thinks that Kant is forced to conceive of this individualization as an infinite progression through which the individual tries, in her own particular way, to subordinate individuality to universality. This is embodied in Kant’s return back to the formality of law after he has been unable to master the complexity of phenomenal individuality through the development of talents 28 according to interests. This is why in his framing of the emptiness objection in the sections on law-giving and law-testing, Hegel represents the appeal to law there as a retreat from a fuller moral psychology of freedom.xxxii The emptiness objection must therefore be understood more broadly than is usually the case, since the earlier re-weaving of the Kantian threads really constitutes the first stage in the argument, with the second stage itself coming in two parts in the sections on reason and law-giving and law-testing. In fact, Hegel claims that the whole development of Active Reason is an emptiness objection, and he is further clear that the empty universal is to be identified with law (PhG¶381). This project to realize individual autonomy is undone, Hegel thinks, by the fact that every attempt reinstates the particularity that was to be subordinated. This is his diagnosis for why, on Kant’s view, moral perfection is unachievable for human beings (MS 6:446-7). In the Philosophy of Right, this diagnosis is phrased in individual terms as the idea that the reflective will generates the naturalness of desires by its decisions and actions, but in the Phenomenology this is phrased in more social terms as the idea that virtue recreates the ‘way of the world’ in its own attempts to combat it. As becomes clear in his presentation of the second stage of the emptiness objection, Hegel takes the difference between the individual and the social form of presenting the problem as of significant import. Kantian universal law formulations of practical reason are already a kind of retreat from the social relations central to Kant’s theory of virtue and the problems for reason guided by laws are generated by the fact that it abstracts in this way. 29 In the first stage of the objection Hegel argues that modern advocates of virtue are in a fundamentally different situation than the ancients. Whereas the content of the ancient conception of virtue is tied to the status of the good as something already existing as the community, the modern, Kantian virtuous agent is reduced to the meager hope of contributing, for her own part, to the realization of the good. The gap between the agent’s actions and their significance is to be filled in by faith, and in two senses. First, individually, that God will recognize their (ultimately unsuccessful efforts) to be virtuous to count as being virtuous (KpV 5:122-4); and second, collectively, that God will apportion happiness to virtue and create the greatest good (KpV 5:124-5). On Hegel’s view, this faith connects the individual and the social in the practice of virtue in the alienating conditions of modern societies, since he holds that the virtuous agent aims to contribute to the production of the highest good, but can only have faith that this highest good will come about, or even that his efforts will contribute to it (PhG¶¶383-4). This is supposed to connect Kant’s appeal to faith with the fact that for Kant, our natural perfections are essentially capacities useful for others (MS 6:445-6), but in indeterminate ways. Properly understood, this uncertainty is quite generally to be attributed to the contingency endemic to social relations under the anarchic conditions of capitalist societies, and it is significant that Hegel returns to the Kantian moral worldview in the chapter on spirit in the context of modes of life that retreat from this alienating feature of modern social relations. 30 This first step of Hegel’s argument is then completed in the spiritual animal kingdom, which Hegel presents as an abstract form of the re-socialization of the Kantian perspective on virtue. I say that this is an abstract form, because the spiritual animal kingdom lacks the two central social institutions that for Hegel play the crucial role in the direction of individual autonomy, namely the family and the estates. The spiritual animal kingdom is, from Hegel’s perspective, a natural way to understand Kant’s appeal to an external perspective as necessary for giving our actions their true significance once one recognizes that the asymptotic approach that was supposed to count as evidence for God’s judgment in this matter is rendered impossible by the continual recreation of vice in the process of realizing virtue. Once the infinite duration required to trace the asymptotic approach is rendered irrelevant, the role of an external, universal perspective that previously required an infinite God can now be played by other agents (see PhG¶¶400 & 404). But since, as Kant himself emphasizes, action must have a material end – and autonomy requires a distinctively moral material end – humanity as an end in itself must be re-interpreted as something capable of being given distinctive shape by individual agents within their finite lives. This then becomes what Hegel calls the Sache selbst, the heart of the matter, and it represents something of universal significance expressed specifically through the interest-guided employment and development of talents in public actions. Responsiveness to this form of significance is now taken to constitute autonomy, replacing the notion of humanity as a rational nature that is universally shared by all agents at all times. This results directly from the way in which Hegel’s re-weaving of the thread of virtues as duties we have 31 because we are also animals (§2) together with the thread of the development of talents as a duty of virtue (§4) results in a reformulation of the universals (1) of the indeterminacy of ends and (3) of the collection of ends into a conception that humanity is achieved by different agents through the contrastive development of different talents according to individual interests. The discussion of virtue and talents thus deserves to be considered a proper first part of the emptiness objection. That is, the first step attempts to show that the new project is one way of consistently developing Kant’s moral psychology of virtue, a way that leads in a strikingly different direction than Schopenhauer’s development. Schopenhauer rests his case on the distinction between phenomena and things-in-themselves as the fundamental criterion of fidelity to Kant. Since for Hegel this distinction is fundamentally a symptom of Kant’s empiricism, the spiritual animal kingdom represents a non-empiricist development of Kant’s moral psychology. The second step of this more broadly conceived emptiness objection – the step found in the specific sections on law-giving and law-testing – is designed to show that the notion of universal law is of no use for agents who are trying to guide their actions by responsiveness to the heart of the matter (¶¶418,428, and 432); the universality involved in such guidance must be of a fundamentally different form. Of course, as the first step makes clear, this project is not Kant’s own official project, and so, if taken on its own, the emptiness objection presented in the sections on reason as law-giving and law-testing is bound to appear decidedly off-target. But from Hegel’s perspective, the spiritual animal kingdom already represents the most 32 charitable reconstruction possible of Kant’s practical philosophy, since it is the reconstruction that goes the furthest towards solving the problem of the individuation of free agency with the resources of Kant’s moral psychology of virtue. To put this point in terms of our strategies, the appeal to law fits most naturally with the Subsumption Strategy. If it is right to think that in the spiritual animal kingdom Hegel brings together the Indirect and Direct strategies, then responsiveness to the heart of the matter should be a form of both subjection appropriation and specification of content (the two kinds of individuation we have considered as important to Kant). The emptiness objection in its second stage then has the function of clearly separating the Direct Strategy from the Subsumption Strategy so as to make the conjunction of the Direct and Indirect Strategies more secure. But since the Subsumption Strategy is not Kant’s considered view, the second stage of the emptiness objection can be read as an argument that Kant should have seen that his rejection of that strategy also entailed the rejection of the appeal to the nomological conception of the moral universal. Thus Hegel is again trying to enforce a different kind of Kantian consistency than Schopenhauer. Hegel begins with reason as law-giving, since this is the most natural Kantian account of autonomy. And yet this form of autonomy is specifically described as being an abstraction from both the individuality of the agent and the social reality of the action. The former abstraction is signified by the fact that Hegel says that the character of the individual has lost its status as the medium and purpose of its activities, and now counts merely as qualitative difference within the universal – a return to the failed Subsumption Strategy (¶418). The second abstraction from 33 social reality is signaled in the very next paragraph by the idea that the true result of the spiritual animal kingdom is the notion of spirit as consisting of distinct social spheres (what will become the estates). Hegel is thus already describing moral reflection focused on the form of law as a retreat from a more adequate conception that is implicit in it. With respect to Kant this is best read as the claim that Kant’s own doctrine of virtue presents a higher point of view than the constructions of universal law. Thus it is not surprising to see that Hegel’s procedure in presenting the emptiness objection is a familiar one to readers of the Phenomenology – to draw out commitments that are internal to the form of consciousness being described but are obscured by its self-presentation. The primary form this takes in the analysis of law-giving is in terms of the notion of immediacy. The immediacy of the determination of the will by the moral law is a central element in Kant’s theory of autonomy, but we have already in §1 seen the way in which Hegel argues that any adequate account of free individuality must dispense with the distinction between immediate determination of the will by law and mediated determination by desires. The focus on immediacy in law-giving explains Hegel’s otherwise puzzling formulation of the first moral command he considers: “Every one ought to speak the truth” (¶423). We are accustomed to hearing this command in the negative as a perfect duty (“Don’t lie.”), and so at first Hegel’s derivations of the problems with such a command appear to attack a straw man (cf. MS 6:429). But Hegel’s idea here is that only the positive version could answer to the criterion of serving as an immediate determiner of the will, since the negative version could only be relevant in the context of other motivations, and only produces its signature effect by that 34 contrast (cf. KpV 5:74-5). Hegel then develops out of this positive version a contingency at its heart: “Each ought to speak the truth according to his knowledge and conviction about it at the time. – However, as a result what is universally necessary, what is valid in itself, that is, what the proposition wanted to articulate is to a greater degree turned topsy-turvy into a complete contingency” (¶423). This contingency is made into even more of a distinctively practical problem in Hegel’s discussion of the command to “Love thy neighbor as thyself” (¶424), where Hegel notes that benefiting others is not merely a matter of intention, but of knowledge and ability as well. The argument here is that Kant’s own requirement of immediacy of determination of the will cannot be satisfied by the nomological conception of universality as exceptionless necessity that animates Kant’s universal law formulations. Again, if I am right about the importance of the placement of the lawgiving and law-testing sections after the discussion of virtue, the function of this point of Hegel’s is to motivate a conception of autonomy as responsiveness to another form of significance, namely that which Hegel terms the heart of the matter. The immediacy of free moral determination of the will remains an important component in Hegel’s account of autonomy, but the nature of that immediacy must be radically reinterpreted in a way that absorbs the contingency of social relations. Hegel makes this most explicit in the section on law-testing, where he considers the question, “Ought it be a law in and for itself that there should be property?” (¶429), which he later connects with Kant’s example of the deposit (¶436). The ethical disposition that maintains recognition of the deposit as the property of the other is 35 not to be explained by any potential inconsistency in refusing to recognize it as such. Because of the rather loose relation between the multiple elements of the social existence of property and its universal conception, consistency or inconsistency is always a matter of perspective, and thus mediated. But the immediate constancy of perspective is what constitutes the ethical disposition – an unwavering point of view that itself defines the perspective from which consistency or inconsistency is determined. Again, the fundamental point Hegel is trying to make here is that the nomological conception of universality is of no use to agents trying to express something of universal significance from their own particular perspective. But the issues raised in §1 should remind us that this problem is not unimportant for Kant himself, even if it is not as important as the clarification of the fundamental moral criterion, and Hegel’s emptiness objection is best understood as attempting to motivate a re-interpretation as more central than Kant realizes of Kant’s own claim that “it is a command of morally practical reason and a duty of a human being to himself to cultivate his capacities (some among them more than others, insofar as people have different ends), and to be in a pragmatic respect a human being equal to the end of his existence” (MS 6:445). It is perhaps best to read Hegel here as inverting the order of significance of individuation and the moral criterion; whereas the problem of individuation receives its distinctive formulation in virtue of being a subordinate problem to that of the pure moral criterion for Kant, for Hegel the problem of the criterion is presented as one element in the larger problem of the expression of individual autonomy. xxxiii This would be confirmed by Hegel’s view that the failures of law- 36 giving and law-testing come from their abstraction from the social reality of the agent, and his claim that the lesson to be learned is that they are actually subsidiary elements (moments) that define the honest consciousness’ attempt to navigate the varied terrain of that reality (¶¶432-4). In this inversion, the problems of judgment that Kant tends to marginalize become central, because autonomy is now understood as constituted by expressive particularization of the universal, rather than being secured by that universal itself (with judgment acting only as a further application). Or perhaps it is better to say that in Hegel’s conception, the question is not so much one of (determining) judgment but rather one of interpretation; not ‘What is the morally necessary or permissible thing to do?’ but ‘Does X’s action articulate from X’s perspective what is fundamental significance in this situation?’ This comes out in the distinctive form of the law-giving example that one must speak the truth, where contingency is introduced precisely as a problem for the interpretation of the relation between individual expression and universal truth. I believe that this also helps to make some sense of Hegel’s superficially bizarre transformation of the moral question of theft into a referendum on the justice of property relations in the section on law-testing.xxxiv If one shifts to seeing autonomy as responsiveness to the heart of the matter, then the question of moral evaluation becomes whether a thief’s action shows, from his particular perspective, an appreciation for why we organize our social relations by property claims. But as the right of necessity shows, such a question cannot always be answered in the negative. Kant is deeply suspicious of such a right, calling it at one point “an absurdity.”xxxv When he does endorse it, Kant thinks of it as an impotence of law: 37 [T]here can be no penal law that would assign the death penalty to someone in a shipwreck who, in order to save his own life, shoves another, whose life is equally in danger, off a plank on which he had saved himself. For the punishment threatened by the law could not be greater than the loss of his own life…Hence the deed of saving one’s own life by violence is not to be judged inculpable… but only unpunishable…The motto of the right of necessity says: ‘Necessity has no law’… Yet there could be no necessity that would make what is wrong conform with law (MS 6:235-6). In contrast, Hegel defends a rather robust right of necessity as follows: “If...[life] can be preserved by stealing a loaf [of bread], this certainly constitutes an infringement of someone’s property, but it would be wrong to regard such an action as common theft,” since the point (Sache) of the institution of property is to make free human life possible (PR§127Z). For this reason Hegel is able to embed a right of necessity into the very system of property law, in part in the form the protection of debtor’s tools and other necessary productive resources from the grasp of creditors (PR§127R). Sometimes, the exception proves the rule and this cannot be accommodated within the nomological conception of moral universality, any more than such a conception can orient interpretation of individual expression with respect to the truth. To come back to the issue of faith, we can understand Hegel’s argument that the immediacy of moral determination cannot be nomological as providing the basis for a diagnosis of why faith becomes so central to Kant’s practical philosophy. In the summation of his consideration of law-giving and law-testing, Hegel says that the former is an invalid establishment of laws and the latter is an invalid freedom from the laws. On Hegel’s views, both mistakes arise from the fact that for Kant, the moral law is not the internal essence of individual consciousness in the way that 38 Kant holds it to be. The only way to understand this is in terms of the failure with empiricist Kantian resources to make any headway on the problem of individuation. On Hegel’s view, the true nature of this immediate relation between moral commands and the conscious individual is actually to be located in the agent’s identification with her social reality – the roles and relations in terms of which she reflects morally. The major function of the emptiness objection is to demonstrate the knowledge of social forms that is necessarily implicit in self-direction immediately through law (PhG¶¶421-2). Hegel is essentially offering a protoMarxist social explanation for the conflict between the universal and particular in Kant: the actual experience of this conflict is in the lack of control that the individual has over her works in the modern context in which there is an indeterminate and socially contested relation between her works and their significance, and this is then theorized as the incompatibility of the self-identical universality of activity as such (the formal element of rational autonomy) and the indeterminate individuality of the nature that is expressed in the work (the particular element of motivations, abilities, and circumstances) (PhG¶¶405 and 429). But again, it seems to me that from this perspective, Hegel is largely working in a Kantian vein. Kant explicitly acknowledges that universalization as such does not generate the maxim to develop one’s talents, or even rule out the maxim not to develop them (GW4:422-3). And, as we noted before, Kant holds that a complete presentation of a moral system must include a schematization of the principles of virtue in terms of the condition of the agent. We can summarize the emptiness objection in the Phenomenology in the following way: it consists of a reiteration of 39 Kant’s own recognition of the necessity of a schematization of moral commands, but with the additional argument that one must radically alter the conception of the significance of those commands for such a schematization to be possible. But if it must be said that Hegel is right to see in Kant’s practical philosophy a kind of retreat from the alienation of the modern social order, it must equally be said that the contemporary social order has long ago outrun Hegel’s own analysis of its incipient form in early 19th Century Germany (where history had already stopped on that side of the Rhine, as Marx puts it). The social institutions so crucial to Hegel’s conception of social agency – the family and the estates – have traversed a quite different path of development than the one envisioned by Hegel in the pages of his Philosophy of Right. The estates – the bridge between Willkür and Wille on Hegel’s view (PR§206) – have perhaps never functioned in the way that Hegel imagined; in any event, we are all workers now, even farmers and (unionized) civil servants. And though the family continues to play a vital and philosophically severely under-recognized role, it must be said that the patriarchalism and narrow structure of Hegel’s own analysis of the family must render it only slightly less foreign to us today than Aristotle’s functionalist account. We might be tempted to fall back on a bare account of mutual recognition stripped of its specific institutional articulations, but the power of Hegel’s emptiness objection can be motivated just as easily against such a project as against Kant’s. The future of a broadly Hegelian social philosophy can only be found in a new critical theory that tries to identify within current social and economic conditions those structures and institutions in 40 virtue of which human agents are enabled and frustrated in their attempts to express something of universal significance from their own particular perspective. The relevant discussion is in PhG¶¶381-417. Citations are as follows: Hegel: ‘PhG’ = Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, cited by paragraph number to Terry Pinkard’s bilingual edition (available at http://web.mac.com/titpaul/Site/Phenomenology_of_Spirit_page.html); ‘VGP’ = Hegel’s Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie (Vol. 20 in Hegel’s Werke, ed. E. Moldenhauer and K.M. Michel (Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp, 1970); ‘PR’ = Hegel’s Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts (Vol. 7 in Hegel’s Werke). Kant: ‘MS’ = Metaphysik der Sitten; ‘KpV’ = Kritik der praktischen Vernunft; and ‘GW’ = Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten. Kant’s works are cited by Academy pagination (except for the A/B pagination of the first Critique), and translations are from Practical Philosophy, trans. M. Gregor (Cambridge University Press, 1996). ii VGP 460. iii VGP 462. iv See Kant KrV A27-8/B43-4. v I will follow the standard practice of using capitalization to signal the stretch of text that constitutes the second part of the Metaphysics of Morals, and lower-case letters to refer to the theoretical project presented there and in other texts. vi On the Basis of Morality, trans. E.F.J. Payne (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1995), 203-222. vii Patrick Kain helped me to see the relevance of this distinction. viii Another individuating strategy that one might consider would be differences in maxims, since Kant writes that different agents can have different maxims for the same practical law (MS 6:225). But I suspect that what would make maxims different would be some sort of empirical natural or social feature, and so this proposal is just a rephrasing of the Subsumption Strategy. In any event, it is not clear that such a strategy would work for virtue, since Kant holds that ethics gives laws for maxims themselves, and the “playroom” for individuality appears to be between maxims and actions, i.e., in the way that the maxims that we all share are translated into specific actions given our circumstances. ix Though Kant suggests that such a schematization and application “belongs to the complete presentation of the system” of ethics, he does not himself present one. One can easily see Hegel’s presentation of specific ethical institutions in his philosophy of objective spirit as the presentation of this schematization, and I will argue in section 7 that the emptiness objection is understood best as Hegel’s version of the argument Kant himself makes here for the necessity of such a schematization. Cf. MS 6:216-7, where Kant similarly says that the metaphysics of morality requires principles of application just as the metaphysics of nature does, but there claims that such principles would touch only on subjective conditions. x Though I will have very little to say about Hegel’s treatment of some of the same material in the Philosophy of Right, it is important to note that there as well Hegel associates virtue with individuality. This association plays an important role in Hegel’s argument for why, in the modern world, virtue plays a subsidiary role: in the i 41 modern world, the universal does the job that was left to “the distinctive genius of individuals” in earlier times (PR§150R). In the same discussion, Hegel writes of virtues as “the ethical in its particular application.” xi H.S.Harris is right to say that for Hegel, “The ‘end’ of Virtue is to display Reason ‘for its own sake.’ But the ‘truth’ of this display is that Reason is revealed as the means-end continuum of the free activity of rational individuality.” Harris, Hegel’s Ladder (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1997), vol.2, p. 57 xii This is connected with his characterization of human freedom in these mixed terms, according to which “freie Willkür” is determinable by pure reason, “tierische Willkür” is determined by sensible impulses, and “menschliche Willkür” is affected (affiziert) but not determined (bestimmt) by impulses and can therefore be determined by pure will (“aus reinem Willen”) (MS 6:213). At MS 6:379-80 (and note), in one of the more evocative passages on this point, Kant argues that duty is a kind of reciprocal self-constraint (Selbstzwang) of a rational natural being who is unholy enough to break the law or to obey it only reluctantly, but also holy enough that they break the law only reluctantly as well. Additionally, several MS arguments for specific duties make use of the notion of either a natural purposiveness of our natural being for specific goals (e.g., of lust for the perpetuation of the species, and of the capacity to communicate for others’ awareness of my own mental states), or for the way in which the natural being in general should be subordinate to personality (e.g., the discussions of suicide and drunkenness). xiii On the Basis of Morality, 58-9. xiv In the Philosophy of Right there is analogous language: virtue is described as “The ethical, in so far as it is reflected in the naturally determined character of the individual as such” (PR§150); and the theory of particular duties is said to be a “spiritual natural history” (“eine geistige Naturgeschichte”) (PR§150R). xv Though there is no space to delve into the issue in this paper, Hegel’s point here is deeply connected with the productivity of the concept as it is articulated at WL409/SL571 with reference to EL§148. I hope to have more to say about this connection in future work. xvi Since, as Kant puts it in his justification for external coercion (die Befugnis zu zwingen), “Resitance that counteracts the hindering of an effect promotes this effect and is consistent with it,” (MS 6:231), the setting of this material end is an indirect way of acting from duty, motivated by the form of law alone. xvii 220. xviii Spiegelfechterei, literally ‘fencing at mirrors’. xix Kant’s official definition of virtue includes this as well: “[T]he capacity and considered resolve to withstand a strong but unjust opponent is fortitude (fortitudo) and, with respect to what opposes the moral disposition within us, virtue (virtus, fortitudo moralis)” (MS 6:380). See also MS 6:376: As applied to virtue, the relevant concept of duty must be one “of the force and herculean strength needed to subdue the vice-breeding inclinations…” and MS 6:405-6 and 408 (where the point is that we need to shape our inclinations to avoid passions that structure reflection). xx In Hegel’s conception of ethical life, even the specific pursuit of particular interests as merely constrained by respect for universal principles has moral import 42 as the expression of individual autonomy – this is the importance of civil society in modern institutional life. In contrast, Kant tends to view the inequalities inherent in modern capitalist economies with a much greater moral skepticism than Hegel. As he famously puts in the casuistical questions about beneficence, “Having the resources to practice such beneficence as depends on the goods of fortune is, for the most part, a result of certain human beings being favored through the injustice of the government, which introduces an inequality of wealth that makes others need their beneficence. Under such circumstances, does a rich man’s help to the needy, on which he so readily prides himself as something meritorious, really deserve to be called beneficence at all?” (MS 6:454). Though Hegel has his own deep concerns about the threat of poverty in modern societies, he does not see the inequality of wealth as being produced by government injustice, but rather by the unequal distribution of the means by which individuals are useful to each other. In Hegel’s terms in the Phenomenology, Kant sees the rich person as having succeeded by following the vicious “way of the world” instead of virtue, whereas Hegel sees him as having – perhaps indirectly – discharged his duty to attend to the happiness of others through his productive activity, and having been rewarded by the market for his usefulness to others. xxi PR§21R; PR§15R identifies the reflective will discussed in PR§21R with Kant’s account. xxii See Allison, Kant’s Theory of Freedom (New York: Cambridge, 1990), pp. 5-6 and Kant’s Religion at 6:24. xxiii On this theme, see Robert Pippin, Hegel’s Practical Philosophy (New York: Cambridge, 2008). xxiv Also MS 6:399ff spells out what is presupposed, but must be cultivated xxv It is important to note here that Hegel does not put the discussion of virtue in terms of duty. H.S. Harris advances this as a reason for thinking that Kant is not Hegel’s intended reference here (Hegel’s Ladder vol. 2, p. 63). But the same notion of an imperative oriented by a conception of the soul in tension is unmistakably there. In Hegel, it is further explicit that the imperative is to know oneself as free. Furthermore, in the Philosophy of Right, the build-up to the emptiness objection (i.e., the structurally analogous discussion) is precisely in terms of duty. xxvi With respect to the second imperfect duty to self, i.e., the duty of moral perfection, even the maxim to strive to do duty from duty is general (i.e., indeterminate) with respect to the “inner action in the human mind” that attempts to apply this principle. Thus the law that gives us moral perfection as our end is similarly wide and imperfect (MS 6:392-3). xxvii Harris vol. 2, p.54. xxviii Given his doctrine of the constitution of subjectivity through mutual recognition, it is perhaps best to read Hegel as rejecting Kant’s principle as dangerously naïve. This naivete is presented in the spiritual animal kingdom as generating the surprise that the individual agent registers when she sees that her own interpretation of her action involves an important element of contingency in the determination of her purpose, and that others are so immediately involved in this interpretation (PhG¶¶404 and 417). 43 As Allison puts it in discussing Schiller’s criticism of Kant, Kant’s point is that “we cannot have an inclination to do something because it is our duty to do it (an inclination to duty). If we did, then the moral requirement would not be represented as a duty because the law would not take the form of an imperative. And since the latter is necessary for unholy beings such as ourselves, so too is the moment of moral constraint” (Kant’s Theory of Freedom, 184). But Hegel’s point is that - quite obviously, constantly and parochially – we do have an inclination to do something because it is our duty to do it. This follows, for Hegel, from the satisfaction that agents necessarily derive from action that confirms their free individuality, and like Kant he thinks that free individuality is a matter of rational self-direction. But it therefore follows for Hegel that there is no real point to the talk of duty and imperatives, nor of the unholiness of individual agents. Hegel replaces this stance with the acknowledgment, through forgiveness, of the inevitable distance between individual action and universal norms. xxx In a passage that contains Hegel’s starting point for his discussion of agency, and which might equally serve as a summary of his critical appreciation of Kant’s moral psychology, Hegel connects these notions with the idea of action as a unification of persons in a universal: “[Acting self-consciousness] therefore arrives at the enjoyment of pleasure, that is, it arrives at the consciousness of its actualization in a consciousness which appears to be self-sufficient, that is, it arrives at the intuition of the unity of both self-sufficient self-consciousnesses. It achieves its purpose, and it then experiences in that achievement what the truth of its purpose is. It comprehends itself as this individual essence existing- for-itself. However, the actualization of this purpose is itself the sublation of the purpose, since selfconsciousness becomes not an object to itself as this individual self- consciousness but to a greater degree as the unity of itself and the other self- consciousness, and thereby as a sublated individual, that is, as universal” (PhG¶362). xxxi There is not too much Kantian text to work with here, so I will just summarize the different points at which this connection comes up or appears to be implied. Kant sometimes talks of the third natural end of humanity as if it is enjoyment of life (e.g. MS 6:420), but sometimes as if it is more closely connected with agency (as in the second edition). Sometimes it looks as if it is perhaps his idea that there is a kind of an awareness of agency that counts as proper enjoyment. At this point the connection is specifically put in terms of the natural ends that we have insofar as we are animals. In addition, the perfection that is our duty is a kind of qualitative, i.e., teleological perfection (i.e., “the harmony (Zusammenstimmung) of a thing’s properties with an end” (MS 6:386)). The relevant harmony is that towards the end that we have qua human, so successful action would be a confirmation of our human status. Even the struggle of the virtuous person against her inclinations is combined with pleasure in triumph, and this pleasure is taken by Kant to be crucial to the longterm constancy of the virtuous character (MS 6:484), so the teleological picture gives one a positive sense of holding one’s own against external forces. For Kant, of course, the key difference between pathological and moral pleasure is that the first is a preceding motivation but the second is only the result of having done duty for xxix 44 the sake of law directly and immediately (MS 6:377-8), so it makes sense to think that this moral pleasure might be the satisfaction of being autonomous. Finally, the vice of stinginess (Geiz) is that of maintaining “all the means to good living, but with no intention of enjoyment” (MS 6:432). Kant says that this makes us subordinate to our possessions rather than their masters, and so it makes sense to think of the pleasure we take in our possessions as either producing or produced by our recognition of our independence with respect to them. xxxii The form of this retreat is set out nicely by Sally Sedgwick with respect to the Natural Law essay as the move from empiricism to formalism. This move ties the presentation of the emptiness objection in the Phenomenology to that of the Natural Law essay. Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 50:4 (Oct. - Dec., 1996), pp. 563584. xxxiii In many respects, I think, Hegel and critics of the emptiness of objection have been talking past one another on this point, given their very different senses of the distinctive problem to which modern moral philosophy responds. For contemporary critics (and perhaps for Kant as well), the problem is the specter of relativism, and the Kantian solution is an a priori foundation, based on autonomy, to establish liberal moral and political principles. But for Hegel, the problem is whether the universal moral reflection demanded of modern individuals can play a role in expressing their free individuality, which individuality is itself the basic moral and political value. As a result, for Hegel, the problem isolated by the emptiness objection is not that of generating the right result for moral dilemmas, but rather clarifying the self-constitution of the agent through universal moral principles. This is why, in the development of the problem to which universal law is auditioned as the solution, Hegel puts the indeterminacy of moral reflection not abstractly in terms of relativism, but rather interpersonally in terms of deception (Betrug). This is the problem of determining whether the individual has adequately expressed the universal through her own interest, or only something idiosyncratic (where the particular at best falls under the universal rather than animating it) (PhG¶¶414-7). xxxiv See also Hegel’s treatment of the deposit example in this light in the essay on natural law (TWA II, 462-3). xxxv “On the common saying: That may be correct in theory, but it is of no use in practice,” 8:300. 45