Thomas Hobbes, “The State of Nature and the Basis of Obligation” In these extracts, taken from Leviathan, one of the most important works in Western political theory, Thomas Hobbes helps lay the groundwork for the emergence of the first political ideology, liberalism. Hobbes himself was not a liberal; indeed, he advocated a form of political absolutism antithetical to liberals. Nevertheless, a number of Hobbes’s foundational premises would prove definitional for later advocates of liberalism. Hobbes was one of the pioneers of the idea that human beings should begin thinking about politics as practiced within civil society by imagining a world which preceded it, a “state of nature” inhabited by free and equal individuals. These assumptions—of individual freedom and equality—are foundational for liberalism. Similarly, many liberals would later follow Hobbes in arguing that the political world was an artificial construct that people entered into by means of a “social contract” that led them out of the state of nature through a voluntary act of self-assumed obligation. This means that the parameters of political power are spelled out through an agreement that is authorized by the people who enter into it, and that such a contractual agreement specifies the extent of the government’s powers over individuals. Absent such voluntary agreement, many liberals argue, political power is illegitimate. However, it is the sort of contract, or “covenant” that Hobbes imagines will inevitably be agreed to by individuals in a state of nature that distinguishes his position from a clearly recognizable “liberal” one. Hobbes memorably described the state of nature as a “war of all against all,” in which none of the amenities of society could be created because it would be impossible for people to trust each other enough to cooperate. Instead, he depicted life in the state of nature as “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short” (p. 58). Nevertheless, Hobbes believed that people could collectively use their capacity for rationality to reason their way out of this world, by discovering “articles of peace,” “precepts,” or “general rules of reason”—which Hobbes calls “laws of nature” (p. 59). These “laws of nature” suggest that if others are willing to transfer their right of nature—in effect, their right of doing whatever they deem necessary to preserve their life in the state of nature—one should be willing to do the same. He believes that the result of this will be the creation of a new artificial body, rationally arrived at by rational, fearful and self-interested individuals. This is the sovereign, or “leviathan,” whose only task is to keep everyone safe, which is precisely what they lacked in the state of nature. The catch, of course, is that this sovereign has been authorized by these individuals to do whatever it deems necessary to provide for the general peace and security of society, and is subject only to this constraint. That is, it has virtually unlimited or absolute power, so long as it keeps the peace. John Locke, “Toleration and Government” It would be difficult to overestimate John Locke’s importance in the development of the political ideology we have come to call liberalism. The selections from Locke’s work presented here, from A Letter Concerning Toleration and the Second Treatise of Government demonstrate the enormity of that influence. In the Letter Locke makes one of the most powerful arguments ever offered for the separation of church and state, one of the hallmarks of liberalism, and of political modernity. He rejects arguments for religious conformity by de-politicizing religion and making it a private matter of individual conscience. This was especially important in the aftermath of the wars of religion that had ravaged Europe. The question driving these wars was essentially what the official state religion would be in particular countries. In Locke’s own time, this problem had been at the heart of the English Civil War, and later in the controversy surrounding Protestant King Charles II, his Catholic brother James II, and the Glorious Revolution of 1688. Locke argued that the state had no legitimate business determining the religious beliefs of its citizens; its power “neither can nor ought in any manner to be extended to the salvation of souls” (p. 64). The power of the state, that is, “relates only to men’s civil interests, is confined to the care of the things of this world, and hath nothing to do with the world to come” (p. 65). Instead, Locke maintains, the state should treat churches as voluntary associations of free individuals making their best assessments of what will be most conducive to saving their souls, and grant broad toleration of a multiplicity of religious sects. This toleration was not absolute—Locke infamously denied it to Catholics (because they were beholden to the Pope, not to their own king and country), and to atheists (who, since they didn’t believe in God, could never be trusted). However, even here Locke’s arguments are important, because they point out that liberal religious tolerance was not absolute at its inception; and it never has been. In the Second Treatise, Locke would start out with a similar set of assumptions about the freedom and equality of human beings in the “state of nature” as his predecessor, Thomas Hobbes, but draw liberal conclusions that differed radically from Hobbes’s authoritarian ones. For Locke, the state of nature is governed by natural law, or God’s law, which has substantive moral content. Natural law specifies certain natural rights (life, liberty, and property) that all individuals possess, at least theoretically. These rights come directly from God, who also tells us we ought not to deprive other people of their right to the same. On Locke’s account, human beings are possessed of sufficient rationality to ascertain God’s law, which therefore effectively governs the state of nature. At a general level (and unlike for Hobbes), this makes the state of nature one of “liberty,” but not “licence,” because it is governed by God’s law (p. 68). Nevertheless, Locke notes that the state of nature has a number of “inconveniences” that make it desirable for human beings to exit it. He notes that many people interpret natural law in ways that are biased in their own interest. The state of nature, then, lacks an impartial judge and an overarching executive force to carry out the rulings any such judge would make. Hence people create the artificial construct known as political society through a mechanism of voluntary consent, known as the social contract. However, government’s purposes are strictly limited; it is meant simply to guarantee and protect the natural rights that individuals had in the state of nature. Moreover, since this is true, the failure of any government to protect these natural rights over an extended period of time gives the people a legitimate right of revolution to change it, as the last portion of Locke’s work excerpted in this reading makes clear. Finally, Locke’s chapter, “Of Property,” in the Second Treatise, would prove profoundly influential for the development of liberal economic theory. In it, Locke argues that, while “God gave the world to men in common…it cannot be supposed he meant is should always remain common and uncultivated.” Rather, Locke insists, God really gave the earth to the “industrious and rational,” and he “commanded…him to labour” (p. 73). Thus by laboring, especially on the land, people demonstrated their industrious and rational capacities, and carried out God’s will. Moreover, by mixing their “property in the person” with common property external to them, they transformed it into their own private property. For Locke, however, this was a “win-win” situation, because laboring on land, for example, improved its value enormously, and when the produce of that private property was productively employed via trading and selling, it was a net benefit to all members of society, he believed. All of these economic arguments would be vital for later liberals. Thomas Paine, “Government, Rights, and the Freedom of Generations” This reading combines excerpts from two works by Thomas Paine, Common Sense (1776), and The Rights of Man (1791-1792). Common Sense was a wildly bestselling pamphlet that has been called the tinderbox of the American Revolution. In it, Paine elaborates some of the foundational precepts of classical liberalism in memorable language. Rather than describing government as natural and essential to the development of human potential and purposes Paine calls it “a necessary evil.” It is “the badge of lost innocence”—simultaneously proof of humans’ inability to refrain from vice, and the mechanism needed to “supply the defect [i.e., lack] of moral virtue” that plagues us all (p. 79). The freedom and security of individuals are government’s true (and limited) purposes. In The Rights of Man, Paine argues, furthermore, that each generation has the right to reconstitute government when it sees fit to do so, unencumbered by the will of preceding generations, whose claims cease when they are no longer alive. As Paine puts it, in response to his great adversary and the founder of modern conservatism, Edmund Burke: “I am contending for the rights of theliving…and Mr. Burke is contending for the authority of the dead over the rights and freedom of the living" (pp. 80-81). “Declaration of Independence of the United States” The Declaration (1776) was written mainly by Thomas Jefferson, and provides the justificatory rationale for the American Colonies’ separation from Great Britain. The most famous lines from the Declaration, as well as a number of its most basic assumptions, are strikingly Lockean. Like Locke, Jefferson argues that all men are born equal; endowed by God with certain natural rights (Jefferson included life and liberty here, but changed Locke’s “Property” to “the pursuit of Happiness”). And, as Locke had done, Jefferson insisted that government’s true purpose was to protect these pre-political, natural rights, and defended a right to revolution if they are violated by government. Furthermore, these truth are meant to be “self-evident,” or easily apprehended by all human beings, much as Locke understood the precepts of natural law. These assumptions make the Declaration, in many ways, a strikingly liberal document. At the same time, placed in context, theDeclaration highlights some of the internal tensions that have been inherent in liberalism from the beginning. “All men,” of course, excluded all women from “self-evident” equality. Also, like many of the Founders, Jefferson was a slave owner until the day he died, and wrote at length to justify slavery and the supposed inferiority of black people in his Notes on the State of Virginia(1784). He later recanted many of the views that we would now call racist. In this respect, he was like Locke, himself, who held stock in a slave trading company, and helped draw up the Fundamental Constitutions of Carolina, which established a slave owning society in that colony. This cannot be ignored. Nevertheless, the doctrine of universal equality, like the proverbial genie, proved very difficult to put back in the bottle once it had been let out, or in this case written down in a foundational American document. Successive generations of reformers, from abolitionists, suffragists, and civil rights advocates would all return to the Declaration as their touchstone, and point out the painful gap that existed between American theory and practice. Oftentimes, their efforts have eventually been successful, in no small part because a stated commitment to universality is a powerful tool in the hands of those advocating change. “Declaration of the Rights of Man and of Citizens” Promulgated by the National Assembly in France at the outset of the French Revolution, the Declaration of the Rights of Man and of Citizens would immediately prove to be a world-transforming document. In one fell swoop, the Declaration attacked the pillars of the so-called ancien régime (or “old order”) in France. Underpinned by Enlightenment principles of rationality, theDeclarationstruck at the heart of aristocratic privilege, which relied on ascribed status (or being born into this or that social rank), as the basis for determining individuals’ rights, or lack of them. It attacked political absolutism, or the notion that the king was all-powerful and above the law. And, finally, it struck at the notion of religious conformity, or the idea that all people in society had to affirm the same set of religious beliefs. Moreover, unlike the American Revolution, the French Revolution and Declaration would help to remake the modern world in very short order. This was because late eighteenth-century France was a military superpower and a large empire. And, as such, it waged war on all of Europe during the French Revolution, effectively destroying not only the old order in France, but on much of the European continent, as well, while spreading the principles of the Declaration.And, as with the American Declaration of Independence, the principles laid out in the French Declaration soon went far beyond their authors’ intent. For example, Olympe de Gouges railed against the fact that women were excluded from civil and political rights, and wrote a “Declaration of the Rights of Woman and the Female Citizen” (1791; see selection 8.53). She was executed at the guillotine, but her ideas did not perish with her. Similarly—and ironically—the principles of the Declaration were used immediately by African slaves in the French colony of Haiti. There, the slave Toussaint L’ouverture led a revolt that expelled the French from the colony and led to Haitian independence; it was a revolt based on the Revolution’s own Enlightenment principles of “Liberty, Equality, and Fraternity.” Adam Smith, “Private Profit, Public Good” Adam Smith’s Wealth of Nations, published in the year Americans declared their independence (1776), is considered the quintessential defense of laissez faire (“leave it alone”) capitalism. Arguing against mercantilism, Smith recommended an economic policy in which free and equal individuals competed in the marketplace to sell their goods. Smith believed that by unshackling people from government-imposed economic restrictions and allowing them to compete for profits, the result would be more, better, and cheaper products that would in turn benefit society, almost as if their distribution had been guided by an “invisible hand.” In this way, he argued that the public good would emerge as an unintended but beneficial consequence of private, selfinterested behavior. As a classical liberal, Smith insisted that the government had no business promoting some substantive conception of the good life. Rather, the minimal role of government was largely to act like an umpire, or neutral arbiter within a capitalist society, strictly enforcing justice by protecting property rights and ensuring order, thereby making certain that one competitor in the “race for wealth and preferment,” as he called it, not gain unfair and illegal competitive advantage over others. Additionally, government should provide for the common defense, create infrastructure (which Smith called “public works”) to facilitate exchange, and (interestingly), at least partially subsidize public education to mitigate the mind- numbing consequences of the division of labor on workers. In this selection from The Wealth of Nations, Smith argues that there is a “propensity in human nature” to “truck, barter, and exchange one thing for another” which distinguishes us from other animals (p. 89). Moreover, when it comes to acting on this dimension of human nature, Smith argues that it is not to the “humanity” of our fellow citizens that we should appeal, but rather their self-interest: “It is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker, that we expect our dinner, but from their regard to their own interest. We address ourselves not to their humanity but to their self-love, and never talk to them of our own necessities but of their advantages” (p. 89). John Stuart Mill, “Liberty and Individuality” John Stuart Mill was the single most influential liberal thinker of the 19th century, and his book, On Liberty (1859), is one of the true classics in the liberal canon. Echoing his friend de Tocqueville, Mill argues that the greatest threat to people in modern, increasingly representative democracies was not the government, itself, but rather the despotism of public opinion, with its tendency towards producing mind-numbing conformity in thought and behavior. Mill laments that the masses of mankind are ascendant, with the result that “public opinion now rules the world,” and “individuals are lost in the crowd.” The result for Mill was as Tocqueville had feared: a tyranny of the majority understood as a form of psychological coercion, culminating in the rule by a “collective mediocrity,” which is invariably “mediocre government” (p. 98). It was against this backdrop that Mill articulates his defense of a maximal level of individual liberty, subject only to limitations imposed by the “harm principle.” As Mill puts it: “The only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of or a civilized community against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, ether physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant” (p. 95). The important point to be made here is that Mill understood the value of individual liberty to be crucial for self-development, to be sure, but it was equally important for society as a whole, especially a democratic society with a representative government. Put differently, Mill regarded liberty as having utility, not just for individuals, but for society as a whole. Indeed, as the second portion of the reading demonstrates, Mill argues that “liberty of thought and discussion” were not only good for individual cultivation, they also lead to a beneficial competition in a free marketplace of ideas that is conducive to social and political progress. Mill maintains that, absent liberty, blind conformity to a few unchallenged ideas will ensue in ways that will lead to poor representative government. Individual liberty, then, has utility for liberal democracy, and as Mill maintained: “I regard utility as the ultimate appeal on all ethical questions; but it must be utility in the largest sense, grounded on the permanent interests of man as a progressive being” (p. 95). William Graham Sumner, “According to the Fitness of Things” This selection represents the work of the best-known American proponent of “Social Darwinism,” William Graham Sumner. The book from which these selections are taken is entitled What Social Classes Owe to Each Other, and the short answer to that question for Sumner is simple: nothing, except to refrain from using the power of the government for their own advantage. The Social Darwinists adapted Darwin’s theory of evolution and natural selection to social and political life, and concluded that it would be unjust for government to intervene in the struggle for existence, and unwise for private charity to do so, even if such action was voluntary. Like his chief intellectual influence, the English philosopher Herbert Spencer (who coined the term “survival of the fittest”), Sumner is best understood as a neoclassical liberal who believed that government should perform only the most minimal of functions, that of protecting men’s property and promoting individual security (Sumner added that it should also protect “the honor of women”). Outside of this, Sumner believed that government should get out of the way, and let people compete in the marketplace for their very survival. The strong and clever would thrive and prosper, the weak and dull would become impoverished and perish, and this was the way it should be. As Sumner put it: “Nature’s remedies against vice are terrible. She removes the victims without pity. A drunkard in the gutter is just where he ought to be, according to the fitness and tendency of things. Nature had set upon him the process of decline and dissolution by which she removes things which have survived their usefulness” (p. 104). T. H. Green, “Liberalism and Positive Freedom” The late 19th century British philosopher Thomas Hill Green was one of the most influential developers of “welfare liberalism” (so-called because it is said to be concerned with the well-being or “well-faring” of individuals). Green is best known for the distinction he draws between “negative freedom” and “positive freedom.” The notion of negative freedom goes all the way back to Hobbes, who argued that people are free so long as there is absence of external impediments or restraints to their actions. This is often expressed as “freedom from”; for example, one is free if one is free from chains or jail. In contrast, “positive freedom,” as Green puts it, is the “power or capacity of doing or enjoying something” (p. 106). That is, positive freedom is “freedom to”; it is not merely the absence of constraints on action, but the real capacity to develop one’s abilities and capacities as one sees fit. Contrary to classical liberals like Locke, and their neoclassical heirs like Sumner, this distinction leads Green to argue that “the mere removal of compulsion, the mere enabling of a man to do as he likes, is in itself no contribution to true freedom.” Instead, for Green, “the ideal of true freedom is the maximum power for all members of human society alike to make the best of themselves” (p. 106). The difference between classical and neoclassical liberals (on the one hand) and welfare liberals (on the other) is illustrated by the issue of poverty. For classical and neoclassical liberals, the fact that a child is born into poverty does not diminish their freedom; poverty is not like jail. For welfare liberals, poverty radically restricts the range of one’s options in life, one’s real freedom, and is therefore a lot like jail. Underlying Green’s distinction between positive and negative liberty, therefore, is an assumption that we all have “higher” and “lower” selves. The former is concerned with our noblest ideals and actions, and can only be achieved in society with the cooperation of others; while the latter is focused purely on our relativistic and isolated assessments of pain and pleasure, or self interest. The political upshot of Green’s philosophical distinction between positive and negative freedom is clear: The government should play an active role by intervening with laws to create positive freedom for all citizens in society. It should regulate freedom of contract pertaining to maximum hours, minimum wage, health and safety, child labor, and the like. It should fund public education, create hospitals and social programs for the poor; and it should have the ability to progressively tax the income and regulate the property of its citizen to achieve such ends. Franklin Delano Roosevelt, “New Deal Liberalism: A Defense” This is the text of a speech given by Roosevelt in 1936, on the eve of his election to a second term as President of the United States. Roosevelt’s first term had been marked by the launching of the “New Deal,” the greatest attempt to apply the principles of “welfare liberalism” in America, after the stock market crash of 1929 precipitated the Great Depression. During his own time and since, Roosevelt’s enemies castigated him as a “socialist,” but this is an unfounded and uninformed description of his position. As a welfare liberal, Roosevelt did not wish to replace capitalism with a system of publically owned and democratically controlled economic enterprises. Rather, like all welfare liberals, Roosevelt accepted a capitalist economic system predicated on private ownership of the means of production and market competition. What he sought with the New Deal was, rather, to use government actively to regulate economic competition and address the worst social ills and individual injuries caused by capitalism. In this respect, it is interesting to note that one of the leading figures in the rise of the modern welfare state was Otto von Bismarck (1815-1898). Germany’s conservative, harshly anti- socialist “Iron Chancellor.” Bismarck believed that the best way to prevent the emergence of socialism was to create a strong welfare state to curb the excesses of capitalism. While this may seem strange to students these days, it also helps explain why welfare liberals have also been simultaneously attacked by not only conservatives from the right but by socialists and communist to their ideological left. According to their socialist critics, welfare liberals are those who saved capitalism rather than seeking to destroy it. Donald Allen, “Paternalism vs. Democracy: A Libertarian View” In this essay, Donald Allen presents a libertarian view of freedom, which he defends against what he sees as the dangers of a paternalistic state. Allen fears a government that acts increasingly like a parent, treating its citizens like children and depriving them of basic freedoms, supposedly for their own good. This is contrary to the libertarian vision—which is really just a stark form of neoclassical liberalism—that the state should act merely as a “nightwatchman,” protecting only the security and property of individuals and refraining from the pursuit of any broader moral purposes. Interestingly, Allen’s model for this argument is John Stuart Mill, whom he explicitly cites; and specifically Mill’s idea of the “harm principle.” Like Mill, Allen argues that the state has no business interfering with people engaged in actions whose consequences only affect them; it can only legitimately pass laws to limit the actions of individuals when they affect others in a harmful way. Similarly, like Mill and Tocqueville, Allen fears a “tyranny of the majority” in democratic societies, and links his defense of individual liberty to a defense of democracy, by invoking the importance of diversity for the healthy functioning of a free marketplace of ideas, which he believes is essential for a flourishing democracy: “If it is to survive, and flourish, democracy requires an intelligent and informed citizenry, just as the free market requires intelligent and informed consumers” (p. 117). Because they seek to “dam and channel the free flow of information as they see fit,” Allen maintains, the defenders of state-sponsored paternalism “are inherently antidemocratic” (p. 115). Murray Rothbard, “Libertarian Anarchism” In this essay, the late economist Murray Rothbard takes neoclassical liberalism to what he believes to be its logical libertarian conclusion. Rothbard begins with what he claims all libertarians share in common, the socalled “nonaggression axiom,” which he defines as opposition to “the use or threat of physical violence against the person or property of someone else” (p. 120). He then goes on to depict the state as “the one central, dominant, and overriding aggressor upon all of these rights” (p. 120). For example, the state effectively aggresses upon individuals when it violates their civil liberties, preventing them (for example) from absolute unregulated freedom of speech and publication, and preventing them from engaging in “victimless” behavior like watching pornography or using drugs. Similarly, it engages in “mass murder” every time it conducts a war. Simultaneously every government economic regulation, subsidy, or tax—in fact, any diminution of a completely free market economy by the state—is effectively an attack on individuals, an attempt to diminish their freedom by robbing from them or enslaving them by degrees, or both. Taxation, for example, is anything but voluntary, Rothbard argues, and he invites people who think it is to experiment with not paying their taxes. When they end up in jail, he argues, then they will understand that taxation is really a form of state coercion or aggression. For these reasons, libertarian anarchists support the abolition of the state, and the replacement of all of its functions—education, fire and police protection, defense, roads and traffic regulation and others—by private enterprise. They argue that the results of this shift would be more efficiently delivered, higher quality goods and services that were also cheaper, all of which would be the result of competition and the uncoerced, free choices made by individuals in the marketplace. Terence Ball, “A Libertarian Utopia” In this reading, the contemporary American political theorist Terence Ball imagines what a world governed entirely by the principles of libertarianism would look like. After engaging in a thought-experiment whose aim is to delineate the features of such a society, Ball asks his readers to ponder whether this libertarian utopia, which he calls “marketopia,” would really be a “utopia” or a “dystopia.” Ball is not at all opposed to markets as allocators of goods and services, per se. He writes: “By and large, markets are a good thing—a reasonably efficient means of discerning and satisfying people’s preferences, of allocating goods and resources, and rewarding the more enterprising members of a society” (p. 128). However, he isolates two core problems with “Marketopia”: its “systematic violation of a fundamental sense of fairness” (p. 128); and its “language of redescription” (p. 129) in which every form of human interaction is reductively redescribed as a simple exchange of commodities. Ball fears that if we speak the language of commodification in all of our relationships—turning politicians and professors into “entrepreneurs” and “service providers,” and voters and students into “consumers,” we will eventually behave towards one another in this fashion. As he puts it: “as we speak, so do we think, and therefore act” (p. 129). Immanuel Kant, “Freedom and Enlightenment” In his essay, “What is Enlightenment?” the German philosopher Immanuel Kant seeks both to answer that question, and to discuss the relationship between the concepts of enlightenment and freedom. Kant is not defining “the Enlightenment” as a historical period, but rather “Enlightenment” as a critical attitude. He argues that, as such, Enlightenment can be understood as “mankind’s leaving behind its self-imposed immaturity,” where immaturity is “the inability to employ one’s own intelligence without being directed by someone else” (p. 92). It is in this regard that the motto of theEnlightenment, as a historical phenomenon should be, in Kant’s estimation, the formula for the process of enlightenment as a process of shedding one’s ignorance; namely, “Sapere Aude!”—have the courage, or audacity, to think for yourself. In order to take this step, however, one thing is necessary: freedom of thought and speech. That is, the government must guarantee a wide degree of individual liberty to encourage free-thinking and the willingness to throw off old ways of doing things. It is in this sense that Kant can be understood as a liberal; he even goes so far as to claim that “enlightenment is virtually assured under conditions of freedom" (p. 92). Since this is a process, however, Kant concludes that his “is not an enlightened age, but it is an age of enlightenment” (p. 93).