Abortion and Ambivalence in America: Is the Moral Theory behind Personhood Justified? Master Thesis Marina Espinoza Student Number: 3862879 Supervisor: Ineke Bolt Erasmus Mundus Master Program Applied Ethics Utrecht University August 2012 The Netherlands Abstract Currently in America there is a movement to legally consider fetuses as persons in order to ban not only abortion, but also certain contraceptives and in-vitro fertilization, in order to prohibit the destruction of zygotes and fetuses. Proponents of “fetal personhood” use a moral theory that always renders abortion morally impermissible. Their theory uses one principle: it is absolutely immoral to kill an innocent human being. This is how they morally justify banning abortion. The objective of this thesis is to show that the moral theory used by anti-abortionists is not justified or adequate to the task of judging abortion for many Americans. In order to do this I will draw heavily from Margaret Little. In the first chapter I will argue that the two main arguments for fetal personhood: intrinsic value and numerical continuity between fetuses and persons are disputable. More importantly, I will argue that personhood does not confer moral status the way proponents believe it does. Additionally, since personhood proponents are trying to affect policy I will highlight America’s ambivalence on the issue to show that the moral theory used by antiabortionists does not reflect how many Americans judge or view abortion. The second chapter will be concerned with how abortion’s permissibility varies and how information affects ethical judgments of abortion. Personhood proponents’ use of a deontological moral theory will be critiqued in order to show that it is not sensible or ethically justified. Due to the inadequacies of the anti-abortionist moral framework and the ambivalence of most Americans, I agree with Margaret Little that a moral framework is needed that takes seriously “fetal geography.” In the third chapter I will discuss and analyze Margaret Little’s relationship framework for abortion to show its appeal and why it is better suited to the task of judging the morality of abortion. 2 Contents Abstract 2 Introduction 5 Chapter 1 The Personhood Movement 8 1.1 Why This Push for Personhood? 8 1.2 Argument for Fetal Personhood 11 1.3 Are the Anti-abortionists’ Arguments Accurate? 13 1.4 Personhood’s Consequences 20 1.5 Does Personhood Fulfill its Function? 22 1.6 Ambivalence 25 1.7 Gradual Moral Status 27 1.8 Why Gradual Moral Status? 30 1.9 Conclusion 33 3 Chapter 2 Ethical Decision Making 35 2.1 Exceptionless Moral Principles 36 2.2 Why Women Abort 37 2.3 Reproduction & Women’s Autonomy 40 2.4 Conflicting Responsibilities 44 2.5 Personhood’s Moral Theory 46 2.6 Conclusion 50 Chapter 3 Margaret Little’s Relationship Framework 50 3.1 A Limited Right to Life 53 3.2 Fetal Geography 54 3.3 Parenting and Relationships 56 3.4 Appeal of the Relationship Framework 60 3.5 Relationship Framework’s Shortfalls 63 3.6 Conclusion 65 Works Cited 68 4 Introduction Currently in America there has been a movement by anti-abortionists to redefine personhood and change the national debate. This push to redefine personhood is to fill the “Blackmun Hole” (PersonhoodUSA.com). The Blackmun Hole refers the landmark Supreme Court case Roe v. Wade that legalized abortion. Justice Blackmun stated in the majority opinion, “If this suggestion of personhood is established, the appellant’s case, of course, collapses, for the fetus’ right to life would then be guaranteed specifically by the [Fourteenth] Amendment” (qtd. in PersonhoodUSA.com). Hence, if it were found that the fetus is a person then abortion would be rendered illegal. The personhood movement is to “. . . clearly define the pre-born baby as a person” and grant that there is a person at conception (PersonhoodUSA.com). Personhood proponents assert that human beings are persons since fertilization and therefore, legally have the unalienable right to life. This push for personhood is fundamentally religious. PersonhoodUSA.com declares its primary mission “. . . to serve Jesus by being an Advocate for those who cannot speak for themselves, the pre-born child” (PersonhoodUSA.com). Personhood USA’s website states that it is led by Christian ministers who consider themselves missionaries to preborn children and seek to honor Jesus Christ in their work (n. pag.). Most anti-abortionists argue that, “Ultimately, human life matters because God matters, and God is the author of human life (abort73.com). “Not only did God create human beings, but Genesis1:26-27 and James 3:9 tell us that God created us in HIs [sic] own image. This is huge. It is an honor and responsibility bestowed upon no other creature in all the universe” (abort73.com). In 2009, Gallup polls started to show that for the first 5 time more Americans were considering themselves pro-life than pro-choice (Saad n.pag.). Personhood proponents’ religiosity and biological beliefs convince them that the fetus is a person and deserves a right to life. They use one moral principle: that it is immoral to kill an innocent person. This principle would not only force women to bear children, it would have severe repercussions for sexually active couples, couples seeking children, pregnant women and their partners, and even doctors and medical researchers (Armstrong & Hsieh 3). It would ban in-vitro fertilization, certain forms of IUDs, stemcell research and most abortions even in cases of rape and incest. These consequences seem extreme to most Americans and thus, many of these amendments have been voted down—even in very conservative states. Not only is abortion sought to be banned, but also certain forms of birth control, fertility treatments, and medical research that may result in the destruction of the embryo. The goal is protect every zygote from the moment of fertilization (Armstrong & Hsieh 3). Personhood legislation would hurt those that are poor and most vulnerable adding to the ambivalence most Americans feel on the issue of abortion. Furthermore, the arguments for fetal personhood are inconclusive. In light of this, is it reasonable to follow personhood’s moral theory? Should their moral theory be used to inform legislation on abortion? My objective in this thesis is to show that personhood’s moral theory is not justified or adequate to the task of judging abortion. In the first chapter I will argue that the two main arguments for fetal personhood: intrinsic value and numerical continuity between fetuses and persons are disputable. More importantly, I will argue that personhood does not confer moral status the way proponents believe it does. 6 Additionally, since personhood proponents are trying to affect policy I will highlight America’s ambivalence on the issue. The second chapter will be concerned with how abortion’s permissibility varies and how information affects ethical judgments of abortion. Personhood proponents’ use of a deontological moral theory will be critiqued to show that it is not sensible. Due to the inadequacies of the anti-abortionist moral framework and the ambivalence of most Americans, I agree with Margaret Little that a moral framework is needed that takes seriously “fetal geography.” In the third chapter I discuss and analyze Margaret Little’s relationship framework to show its appeal and why it is better suited to the task of judging the morality of abortion. 7 Chapter 1 Personhood Amendments Anti-abortionists believe that fetuses have an intrinsic value. They assert that even a zygote is worthy of respect and inviolable. They not only want to promote life, but also legally preclude anything that destroys it. Although their definition of a person seems to be clear-cut, philosophers and other theorists have failed to come to a consensus. Ethicists have used theories of personhood to try and figure out when a life begins or ceases to have intrinsic value (Newson 278). The point of this chapter is to analyze and critique the arguments used by proponents of fetal personhood. 1.1 Why this push for personhood? In his article “Personhood and Moral Status,” Ainsley Newson states that theories of personhood are important because “Human beings protect themselves with a thicket of rights they do not grant to other beings” (278). Its importance is also tied to moral status, which confers a right to life. When a person has moral status they are morally considerable. As Newson states, “Personhood is the link between a full right to life or no rights all” (Newson 278). When an entity has moral status one cannot treat it however she pleases, “ . . . we are morally obliged to give weight in our deliberations to its needs, interests, or well-being’ (Newson 278). Personhood is one dimension of moral status, but another dimension is the value of life. To assert that one is a person is to implicitly claim that the entity has a special value and is deserving of respect. It is clear that being a person is different and more complex than just being human. A human being is part of 8 the species homo-sapien. It has genetic and biological characteristics that make one a human being. Simultaneously though, a person has a set of metaphysical and psychological properties that go beyond being a human being and confer moral status (Newson 277). It is because many feel that persons are more than just bodies, that they are also made special because of other properties, that many theorists have come up with criteria that are required to be a person. Many philosophers have even offered species neutral descriptions of personhood. These views hold that a person is a rational and selfconscious agent aware of his or her past and future, regardless of what species it is. Hence, intelligent apes would also count as persons (Newson 280). Religious perspectives also have had an immense influence on theories of personhood (Newson 278). A core position has been to adopt a vitalist view of moral status and personhood, which emphasizes the wrongness of intentionally taking innocent human life. This position is all-inclusive in that it includes all human life regardless of their age or development, for they satisfy the criteria for personhood in virtue of being human (Newson 278). Moral status is present from fertilization because even though zygotes do not presently have self-awareness or cognitive abilities, they will. Zygotes should be recognized as actual people because they have an actual potential that should be treated as an already functional capability (279). Many philosophers have a problem with potentiality because they feel there is a strong distinction between being and becoming. They point to the fact that “ . . . a caterpillar is not a butterfly, and a foetus is not a human being, only a human becoming” (279). Furthermore, some argue that potential is 9 unfounded because not every fertilized egg will give rise to a new individual; many pregnancies are spontaneously lost” (Newson 279). Currently in modern ethics approaches to personhood have attempted to define an attribute or set of attributes, which are collectively constitutive of personhood (Newson 279). Many approach the question by asking what a person must have for moral status. This is why many argue that what is needed is a concept of self as a continuing subject of experiences and as a continuing entity. The problem with this approach though, is that fetuses already developed and viable, as well as infants and some who are cognitively impaired do not qualify for moral status (279). Since these beings lack sentience and desires, there is no future to frustrate and thus no harm being done to them (Newson 279). As Margaret Little notes, it is not so much that these theorists believe that one has moral standing only when sentient, but that beings that have never been sentient cannot be harmed. This is because in order to be harmed there must be a setback of interests and no interests develop until the being is sentient (“Abortion and personhood” 337). Some theorists hold a simple criterion for determining which lives are valuable. A being’s life will have value as long as it is capable for valuing its own interests. A zygote cannot be aware of itself, therefore it cannot value its life and this is why it cannot be a person with a right to life. This would make personhood a threshold instead of it coming in degrees. Those that are pushing for personhood also see personhood as a threshold; once fertilized the embryo is a person until death. Some, including myself, think that personhood is problematic as an all or nothing concept. If personhood is a matter of degree it will be possible to accord moral consideration to some beings that are not yet persons. The moral consideration of such 10 beings will steadily increase as it gets closer to full personhood (Little, “Abortion and Personhood” 332). Some recognize that mental capacities do not develop all at once (Little, “Abortion and Personhood” 281). A gradual approach is more biologically accurate, reflexive of America’s reality and ambivalence, intuitive and more responsive to the realities of pregnancy. I will use Margaret Little to illustrate this. First though, I will present the anti-abortionists argument for personhood at conception. 1.2 Argument for Fetal Personhood There are two arguments offered for fetal personhood by anti-abortionists. The main argument is that the embryo is an innocent life recognized and valued by God. Abortion therefore, is murder. However, since America is a democracy and there is a separation between church and state, proponents of personhood also claim secular justification for a right to life. The claim that the zygote is a person comes from the belief that a human and unique individual exists at the moment of fertilization and develops gradually until death. Personhood USA states on its website, “A person, simply put, is a human being. This fact should be enough. The intrinsic humanity of unborn children, by definition, makes them persons and should, therefore, guarantee their protection under the law” (n. pag.). It continues, “When the term ‘person’ is applied to a particular class of human beings, it is an affirmation of their individual rights. In other words, to be a person is to be protected by a series of God-given rights and constitutional guarantees such as life, liberty, and the 11 pursuit of happiness” (n. pag.). Thus, according to Personhood USA unborn fetuses should possess the right to life because they are human. Those that are pro-life are using the biological claim that life begins at conception. This new life is human and distinct from the woman with its own genetic code. This is not a potential human life, but an actual human being in the early stage of development. Now that there is a human being, they go on to argue that it is a person with the right to life (PersonhoodUSA.com). As abort73.com, an anti-abortion website asserted, “Something is a person if, by nature, it has the capacity to think rationally, express emotion, make decisions, etc. This capacity is something that a person has as soon as he begins to exist, since it is part of his nature . . . So it is impossible for a fetus to not be a person” (n. pag.). Anti-abortionists assert that age, size and IQ are differences in degree, but not in kind. These different levels of cognitive abilities and development all are equally human and qualified to life. Thus, a person is a human being and the differences between a person before and a person after birth do not matter. Because from the moment of conception there is a person, a member of the human community, it is required to give it moral status. Whoever is a valuable person now was also a valuable human person at every moment in its past, including when that person was in the womb (abort73.com). Although fetuses and zygotes are not actual rational agents, they still have some of the moral properties of a rational agent because of what kind of beings they are. Conferring upon them moral status would make sense since newborns and those that are cognitively disabled are given moral status although they may not be self-aware or cannot be moral agents. Abort73.com points out that even though zygotes and early fetuses do not look 12 like humans, they quickly develop characteristics that are similar to persons (n. pag.). Anti-abortionists point to the rapid growth of the fetus “ . . . in order to better understand why it is such a fallacy to argue that abortion is the mere removal of cell tissue . . . ” (abort73.com). They believe it is a misconception that most abortion occurs before the embryo or fetus is recognizably human. They state, “Day after day, thousands of aborting women wrongly believe that they’re simply eliminating some undifferentiated human cell tissue. . . . Abortion is not the mere removal [of] cell tissue; it is the death of living, growing human beings” (abort73.com). Moral status is present from fertilization because even though they do not presently have self-awareness or cognitive abilities, they will. To not give them moral consideration because they do not have the degree of cognitive abilities they feel is discriminatory; Abort73.com calls these “inconsequential differences” (n. pag.). In light of the fact that embryos are genetically human beings a woman cannot have the right to an abortion. Those that are pro-life claim that there can be no choice for abortion because it is a criminal choice. “The law generally leaves people the legal freedom to make bad choices, but the law must do all it can to prohibit criminal choices” (abort73.com). They see abortion as act of violence that must be precluded by law. 1.3 Are the Anti-abortionists’ arguments Accurate? Anti-abortionists hold that zygotes, embryos, and fetuses even in their first trimester have the same moral status as a person. That the obligations owed a newborn are also owed to zygotes. Anti-abortionists hold this because the zygote and the person it 13 will become are the same; there are no significant differences between them. A person starts as a zygote and continues until death. As Armstrong and Hsieh note, the first half of the personhood argument is purely biological discussing human life, the second part is concerned with the politics of being a “person” (25). They state, “To slide between these two distinct concepts using the term ‘human being’—as ‘personhood’ advocates consistently do—is to commit the fallacy of equivocation” (25). They point out that, the political concept of person cannot be given by science, for that is a question for philosophy. Proponents of abortion assert that the differences between zygotes and persons are insignificant. If their criterion for being a person is merely being human, then they are right and zygotes are identical with persons, but as discussed earlier many theorists believe that a person is more than genetics; it has metaphysical and physiological qualities that give value. Intuitively, fetuses are not rational agents that think and are selfconscious. Proponents assert that fetuses’ potentiality makes them numerically identical (exactly alike) to persons, but biology does not support that. A zygote and early fetuses are not even conscious until about twenty-two weeks (Armstrong & Hsieh 26). It means they have no desires, feel no pain and are absolutely unaware that they are alive or of what awaits them. While persons are conscious, zygotes and fetuses have never been. Unlike a born infant a zygote is invisible to the naked eye. It has absolutely no organs, not even a human form. Without a brain it lacks the capacity for awareness, emotions or pain. It is more akin to skin cells than an infant. It is not even living its own life; it is partaking in the life of the woman. The zygote cannot even become a baby on its own. It must first implant in the lining of the uterus, if it cannot do this then it will be flushed 14 from her body without anyone knowing it existed (Armstrong &Hsieh 26). Although fetuses are becoming persons, they are not yet persons. Numerical identity between the fetus and the person it will become seems debatable, but it could be that zygotes are continuous with the persons they later become and thus, can qualify for its protections. Personhood proponents’ arguments are basically that with one egg and one sperm you get one zygote and then one child. This zygote is supposed to be numerically continuous with the human entity that will eventually develop. However this is impossible if the zygote splits after formation. Identical twins come from a zygote that splits into two. This means that from one zygote you get two individuals. This is why, “[t]he concept of numerical continuity is too narrow as initially defined to allow for any variations during or subsequent fertilisation” (Dawson 176). According to Dawson there is an overemphasis on genetics in directing the course of events after fertilization (176). There is no evidence that fertilization is the beginning of a human being; 78 percent of human fertilizations end up lost and do not progress to the next developmental stage (178 Dawson). Proponents of personhood hold that morals against killing can be applied to zygotes because the individual human being exists with a distinct genetic constitution; however, the genetic constitution of an individual is not necessarily formed at fertilization. Not only can many changes still occur; identical twinning may occur twelve days after fertilization and in this process the original zygote ceases to exist (Dawson 176). This is why Dawson goes on to state that arguments used by those who are for personhood, “ . . . provide an inadequate basis for policy formation or legislation regulation reproductive technology as they hold only little relevance to actual biology” (177). Proponents of personhood assert that zygotes are exactly alike the persons they 15 become, but this is not necessarily what occurs biologically speaking with zygotes either splitting or ceasing to exist. While proponents of personhood assert that having the potential in one’s nature confers full moral status, Little states, “Having the potential for moral status is not itself immediately prescriptive; one may wonder why the whole is granted a status by virtue of its peak achievement. This view comes from the conviction that inviolability is an essential rather than accidental feature” (“Abortion and Personhood” 334). Persons have metaphysical and psychological properties that go beyond being a human being and thus give value and confer moral status—not from having a distinct set of chromosomes (“Abortion and Personhood” 334). Anti-abortionists espouse these secular arguments about genetics and being a human being in order to have a right to life, but even they do not believe that being human is enough to make someone morally considerable. One abortion website states, “It is not the raw genetic material which gives human beings significance, it is the unique attention given to us by our Creator” (abort73.com). They state, “Ultimately, human life matters because God matters, and God is the author of human life” (abort73.com). Really the secular arguments used by proponents of personhood are just to mask their religious view that life is valuable because of God. This is also why they state that rights are God given. This belief according to Armstrong and Hsieh is false though, rights are not God given, they are instead rooted in facts about human nature, and the conditions for survival and flourishing (25). They come from the conditions required by people’s nature for their proper survival (25). Proponents fallaciously believe that rights and genetics confer moral 16 status because God gives them; ethically however, moral personhood comes from not only being a person, but also through intrinsic value. It is understandable why anti-abortionists want to give fetuses the right to life. In his article “The Values of Life,” Govert den Hartogh notes that it is easy to see how a fetus can be said to benefit from the fulfillment of the duties correlating to its alleged right to life. In the sense that every living being benefits from everything which contributes to its flourishing (54). Nevertheless, the value of human beings cannot be answered solely by natural creative processes. This is because as den Hartogh notes, human beings can transcend mere genetics and remember their past and make plans for the future, they can integrate their memories and their plans into a more or less coherent whole (58). Consequently, human beings attribute personal value to their individual lives. Non-conscious entities, like fetuses, cannot value anything themselves at all, and when an individual specimen lacks consciousness, it seems to be worthy of protection only if it has special characteristics endowing it with value to other conscious beings. Thus, according to him, in the cases of zygotes and fetuses, they are not deriving value solely from natural investment, but from the relationship they have with the woman (58). The fetus’s value is relational in that its value is also coming from its connection to the woman. This relational value does not depend on the fetus being self-ware or conscious, as Newson notes, “A woman develops a relation to the being growing in her womb, at least as soon as she feels it moving, long before it has aims and memories and selfconsciousness, or even consciousness” (60). Den Hartogh notes that this relational value is a problem for conservatives since their position requires that being an individual member of the human species should be a reason to attribute intrinsic value. They do not 17 want to be committed to the intrinsic valuation of all the living organisms that are human species like placentas or living human cancer cells (58-59). The only way to keep them out in a principled way is to value a human life and require that beings that qualify are continuous or identical with human beings, which eventually will live a conscious human life. The problem is that the embryo will not qualify because before implantation it can still develop into two human beings or more—there is no numerical continuity between the embryo and the person. This relational value of fetuses is not completely independent of developmental characteristics either (den Hartogh 60). Den Hartogh states, “Otherwise the relation of the mother to the fetus or the newborn child would not be different from the relation between a child and its doll: it would be based on ascribing to it characteristics in fantasy which it doesn’t have in reality” (60). The state the woman is in during pregnancy is a state of anticipation, and no one can pinpoint when exactly this anticipated reciprocity turns into actual reciprocity (60). Den Hartogh compares the relationship to a loving relationship. When you love someone you do not love her irrespective of her properties, but it is not correct to say you love her because of her properties, because that would mean that you would be committed to loving everyone with the same properties to the same degree. He states, “Love is irreducibly particularistic you are relating to a token individual, not to a specimen of type” (61). As he points out, if you are just a blob of tissue no one can actually put their love upon you. To be loved you must be an individual (61). Many who want to bypass the metaphysical arguments of personhood simply point to the fact that abortion and ending embryonic life is the same as killing an innocent person and that is why it is wrong (Little, “Abortion and Personhood” 336). This is 18 because the way killing someone deprives it of its future, aborting an embryo also deprives it of its future. Future for persons is valuable and just like those who are alive, fetuses also have futures. As Little points out though, its logic holds that it is worse to end the life of a zygote than that of child or a teenager. Its logic would hold the loss of the zygote as more of a loss because it has more life to lose. Intuitively however, many would feel that the loss of a toddler or teenager would be worse than that of the zygote. Although it is true that what makes killing so reprehensible is that it robs someone of their life, the reason it is so horrible though, is that persons know what they are losing. Additionally, this argument is under the belief that the embryo would continue to become a person as long as the mother does not interfere. This view fails to take into consideration that the fetus has no trajectory independent of the woman. Abortion in some instances is more of a letting die, which is that it leaves the fetus no worse off than it would have been absent the woman’s help to begin with (Little, “Abortion and Personhood” 336). As Little states, “At least early in pregnancy, we might say, it is not clear that one should describe ending gestation as depriving the embryo of its future rather than continuing gestation as helping to provide it with one” (“Abortion and Personhood” 336). It is important to remember that anti-abortionists are using these arguments to change and influence actual policy that will affect people’s daily lives. Not only are these arguments unsound, but they also have devastating effects. 19 1.4 Personhood’s Consequences Personhood legislation would legally establish personhood at the moment of conception, granting full legal rights to a fertilized egg. This would require criminal investigation of any miscarriages deemed suspicious, it would ban common fertility treatments and would ban potentially life-saving embryonic stem-cell research. Doctors and women‘s health advocates have stated that the proposals would jeopardize women’s right and lives. Not only would they ban virtually all abortions, including those from rape and incest, they would also ban some birth control methods like IUDs and “morning after pills,” which prevent fertilized eggs from implanting in the uterus. They would also outlaw the destruction of embryos created in laboratories. Many women are fearful of the fact that doctors may hesitate out of fear of prosecution to save women who have life threatening pregnancies (Armstrong & Hsieh 1). Besides outlawing abortion these amendments would “adversely impact the lives of sexually active couples, couples seeking children, pregnant women and their partners, doctors and medical researchers” (Armstrong & Hsieh 1). Personhood legislation would mandate harsh legal penalties for harm done to zygotes and intentionally harming a zygote would be a crime of the same magnitude as harming a born infant. So if a zygote is a legal person from the moment of fertilization then any intentional act of preventing it from implanting, which is what happens when women take the morning-after pill, or aborting the embryo or fetus would be first-degree murder (9). Any actions that may endanger the well-being of the embryo or fetus could then be considered child abuse (9). 20 If a parent threatened to harm its child you could physically separate them, however you cannot separate a woman from the fetus. Women seeking to terminate their pregnancies may have to be physically restrained until the fetus is delivered. As Armstrong and Hsieh state, “Thus, the ultimate alternative to legal abortion is police officers strapping an uncooperative woman to her bed for weeks or months and forcing her to give birth—then throwing her in prison for attempted murder” (11). It would also outlaw the abortion of fetuses that are severely deformed with no hope of viability outside the womb. There are many couples that have given their stories on having children who are encephalic (missing most of the brain), or have a terrible illness or deformity. They discussed how horrible and painful it is to go through the delivery process and to then watch your child die (Armstrong & Hsieh14). It is important to remember that the intent of personhood language is to protect all life, regardless of the mental level of functioning, so it may require for some women to give birth no matter the cognitive or physical disability (14). As Armstrong and Hsieh point out, “ . . . painful family decisions would become political spectacles for anti-abortion activists under the false banner of ‘protecting life’” (15). Many critics have discussed the problem these abortion bans produce for ectopic pregnancies, which are the leading cause of pregnancy related death during the first trimester in the United States (Armstrong & Hsieh 13). These occur when a fertilized egg develops outside of the uterus. In 1992 about half of all ectopic pregnancies ended in hospitalization (13). Under personhood amendments the lives of women may be put at risk. As Armstrong and Hsieh ask, “ . . . how would prosecutors treat doctors who prescribe medical intervention as a ‘first resort’ in cases of ectopic pregnancy to better 21 protect the woman’s life and health?” (13). As one oncology nurse stated, “ . . . I was asked to give methotrexate for an ectopic pregnancy . . . I believed the pregnancy was tubal. Needless to say I refused because I was unsure of the morality of it” (Armstrong & Hsieh 13). As Armstrong and Hsieh note, these personhood laws my require doctors to conduct theological debates before providing emergency medical care or may be forced to use less dangerous methods of treatment (13). What about women who get cancer? Will they have to delay treatment to save the child? Under an enforced personhood law a woman might not be able to obtain an abortion even if she feared for her life, thereby usurping her rights to autonomy, bodily dominion and integrity. Personhood legislation would also ban in-vitro fertilization. About 12 percent of American women have used infertility treatments or services (Armstrong & Hsieh 17). Fertility treatments helped women deliver more than 50,000 infants in 2007. Using solely in vitro fertilization helps many women become pregnant (17). As Armstrong and Hsieh point out, without infertility treatments many women would not be mothers and their children would not exist today. This is why many people feel that personhood amendments are not really “pro-life” but are anti-life since they “ . . . would actively damage, prevent, or destroy the lives of so many actual people . . .” (19). 1.5 Does Personhood fulfill its Function? Proponents of personhood are after moral status for the fetus and they want it through redefining what a person is. Personhood is supposed to do all the moral work. Once the fetus becomes a person it becomes a member of the moral community. Once a 22 fetus is a person it is automatically immoral to abort the fetus at any stage, for any reason; however, as discussed earlier, personhood is a contentious concept with no clear characterization. In his article “The Failure of Theories of Personhood,” Tom Beauchamp points out that, “The concept of person is simply not orderly, precise, or systematic in a way that supports one general philosophical theory to the exclusion of another” (319). To assert that the fetus is a person at whenever is your preference and decide that its destruction is murder is inescapably a moral decision, for which we have to have moral reasons (Hare 205). “To say that a fetus is (or is not) a person gives by itself no moral reason for or against killing it; . . . the word “person” is doing no work here (other than that of bemusing us)” (Hare 206). Just like genetics, having the capacities of language, rationality and selfawareness lack an intrinsic connection to moral properties like moral agency and moral motivation (Beauchamp 312). Beauchamp believes that a creature is a moral person if it is capable of making moral judgments about the rightness or wrongness of its actions and if it has motives that can be judged morally. Moral personhood unlike metaphysical personhood is sufficient for moral standing. The moral protections afforded by this community may be extended to the weak and vulnerable who fail to qualify as a moral person, but moral standing for these individuals must rest on some basis other than moral personhood (315-316). It is not that fetuses and newborns, or brain-damaged patients do not deserve moral protection; it is just that as Beauchamp astutely points out, their protections do not come from moral personhood (316). It is not that fetuses need personhood to be morally considerable, what they need is only the capacity for pain and suffering. 23 Beauchamp states that there are two properties that qualify a being for moral standing: the capacity for pain and suffering, and properties of emotional deprivation. He states, “As Jeremy Bentham pointed out, the capacity to feel pain and undergo suffering is more relevant to moral standing for nonhuman animals than are cognitive properties” (316). Moral standing is to protect individuals because harm is bad in itself, not because it is bad for members of a certain species or type of individual, and not because the individual is or is not a moral person. As Hare pointed out, to say that a fetus is a person provides no moral reason against killing it. Not only does personhood not qualify the fetus for moral consideration, but it also does not do what we want it to do. It does not tell us whether abortion is ethically justified or not. I agree with personhood proponents that fetuses are morally considerable, but my point is that personhood is not what makes fetuses morally considerable, their capacity to suffer does. Most Americans rely on other information besides the status of the fetus, so the moral status of the fetus is not enough for ethical judgment. In America there is an enormous amount of ambivalence. Many take into consideration both the woman and the fetus. Not only does relying solely on personhood leave out a woman’s right to bodily dominion, but it also fails to realize that there are other variables in pregnancy that dictate for some the morality of abortion. This is why many Americans allow abortion when the woman has been raped, when the fetus will be cognitively or physically handicap, or if the woman is in poverty or other circumstances. For many Americans the moral status of the fetus—which is not conclusive—is not enough to judge the morality of abortion. 24 1.6 Ambivalence Jon Shields notes in his article “Almost Human: Ambivalence in the Pro-choice and Pro-life Movements,” that there is a sharp contrast between warring activists and the vast majority of ambivalent Americans. The national debate may reflect a high polarization, but as he states, “There is an especially broad consensus for this view in the case of abortion, since surveys routinely reveal that countless Americans remain torn between the interests of women and embryos” (496). Americans whether pro-life or prochoice, tend to care far more about embryos with anthropomorphic characteristics than those without them. According to Shields these sentiments moderate both movements and public policy. There is not much sympathy for weeks-old embryos, hence the allowance of in-vitro fertilization where regulation is scarce even in conservative states. He states that the most plausible explanation for these shared intuitions about early- and late- term embryos is that inherited psychological traits compel us to sympathize with beings with anthropomorphic characteristics as opposed to undifferentiated bundles of cells (Shields 496-497). People who are fervently pro-choice are very ambivalent and are at war with their own sentiments (Shields 497). Shields writes, “One study of a Denver hospital concluded that even ‘people who fought for the law suddenly [felt] uneasy when it actually came to the performance of an actual abortion’” (498). While psychologically nurses were better at tolerating first-trimester abortions, they found living fetuses much more troubling (499). Some employees and doctors suffered from nightmares and images (503). A New York City ethnography stated that, “ . . . all doctors and nurses were troubled by abortion 25 sometime between 10 and 20 weeks gestation” (499). An abortion clinic employee even stated that she hated abortion because of ‘[t]he destruction I can’t deny’ (501). Abortion workers were surprised at their moral uncertainty. As one woman stated, “I feel like I’m letting the whole movement down. If I’m not certain, what does that mean for women who will need abortions?” (Shields 504). Although there is this strong sympathy for the fetus it can be counteracted by the personal circumstances of pregnant women. The reasons for abortion also shaped the counselors’ emotional responses to it. Shields noted that at one extreme a twelve year-old who was pregnant by her uncle raised the morale because workers again felt their work in the service of humankind (504). Although the interests of the fetus matter, numerous Americans at the same time understand that abortion is necessary for women’s health, life and well-being. Those that are pro-life also suffer from ambivalence. Many pro-lifers do not have problems with in-vitro fertilization or IUDs. The small bundles of cells do not command the same sacrifice or commitment more mature fetuses do (Shields 507). While the national debate just highlights two sides, most Americans fall somewhere in-between depending on the circumstances. Sometimes abortion is justifiable and sometimes it is not. Countless Americans try to balance both the interests of the woman and the interests of the fetus, trying to moderate their intuitions. This broad consensus for abortion and the strong visceral reactions that arise from Americans on both sides of the debate show that common ground can be found (Shields 506). Obstetricians and gynecologists cited the most important factor for deciding whether or not to perform an abortion was the age of the fetus (505). This is why personhood proponents use pictures to promote their cause. The pictures show suffering 26 and thus for many, they inspire horror (508-511). While there is little middle ground, he notes that both sides agree that one should not defend the rights of organisms based on their likeness to persons (511). Both sides are trying to be rational and place their sympathy and intuitions for the fetus aside, for most people emotion is driving moderately and not extremely (Shields 512). It is for these reasons and more that moral consideration for the fetus should be gradual. 1.7 Gradual Moral Status For many Americans it is just as extreme to confer personhood status at fertilization, as it is to confer it until cognitive abilities arrive. Gradual moral status allows us to take into consideration the health of the fetus, the prospects of its survival and the health and circumstances of the woman. These variables affect how the woman views her pregnancy. Furthermore, as discussed earlier, the value of the fetus is not entirely intrinsic, but relational, and this relational value is not independent of developmental characteristics. Not only are there these variables that immensely affect the status of the fetus, but the fact that the fetus is inside the woman and uses her body also means that her outlook on the pregnancy does matter morally (Little, “Abortion and Personhood” 332). For many Americans early abortion is not much of a problem, but late abortion is. This is because many have a graduated view where developing human life has an important value worthy of respect. As it grows, its status grows until at late in pregnancy 27 where the fetus is deserving of the very strong moral protection due newborns (Little, “Abortion and Personhood”332). According to Margaret Little in her article “Abortion and the Margins of Personhood,” gradual moral status would allow for the moral status of the fetus to grow as the fetus grows in the womb (343). In the first trimester the moral status of the fetus is modest since the fetus has no trajectory independent of the woman’s assistance. Viability is important in this case because in some instances aborting can instead of killing, be more akin to letting die. In order for aborting to function like letting die, it depends on whether the fetus has a hopeful trajectory independent of gestation. As Little puts it, “When the fetus has no opportunities that the act of aborting would forestall, abortion is properly viewed less as interference and more akin to a letting die, to a removing of lifesustaining assistance” (“Abortion and Personhood” 343). Abortion done in the first trimester is not so much ending the pregnancy as it is refusing to continue it. In the second trimester the fetal status continues to grow and become more personlike. This means that it takes greater justification to decently abort (Little, “Abortion and Personhood” 343). There may be justified reasons however; there are considerations that may lead one to abort. As Little notes, if the moral status of the fetus evolves so too can the woman’s circumstances. The pregnancy may become physically taxing, a marriage may end, a job may be lost, she may be sent to jail or the mental health of the mother has worsened. Or maybe news of a horrible ailment or disability is found out. Little states, What we might say about the care of premature infants born with such conditions, the finding of profound abnormality in the middle of 28 pregnancy brings its own issues, both because the fetus’s status, while substantial is not yet equivalent to a newborn, and because of what it means to have one’s body carrying, attached to, and sustaining a fetus with a profound impairment. (“Abortion and Personhood” 345) These circumstances may lead a woman to justifiably abort. In the third trimester the fetus is almost mature and the viability solidifies. It is more conscious and it can apparently feel and respond to pain (Warren, “Status of Abortion” n. pag.). The fetus now has viability and opportunities independent of the gestating woman; however, even though the child has full moral status, the fetus is still in the woman and their physiologies are intertwined, implicating the woman’s health, life and bodily integrity. Little points out that “ . . . getting the fetus out implicates the same” (345). According to Little in the third trimester women do not need to be granted a right to elective abortion independent of considerations of their health and life, “ . . . but details of medical need or method may not be ones best demarcated by legislative bodies” (347). This is not because there is a feeling of unequal status between a newborn and a fetus in the third trimester, but because regulating the body is different from regulating custody; with so many variations in pregnancy it hard for legislation to take them all into account. For Little, moral consideration of the fetus depends on fetal viability—the point at which others can reasonably and meaningfully sustain the fetus’s life if only it could be delivered from the pregnant woman. Little goes on to state that, “‘Viability’ of course, is a bright-line idea making a continuum of probabilities and complexities—how good the chances of survival, how brutal the interventions, how sober the risks of catastrophic impairment, how enormous the resources to assist to relative independence” (“Abortion 29 and Personhood” 343). While I agree that in some instances viability does matter to the morality of abortion, I do not want its moral consideration to rest solely on viability because viability can be dependent on technological possibilities (Warren, “Moral Difference” 51). Technology may make it possible for first trimester fetuses to become viable and therefore usurp a woman’s right to an abortion. I do not think it is so much its viability in the second in the third trimesters that bestow moral consideration, as it is that there is a life that is not only becoming more formidable, but also as Beauchamp points out, a life that we do not want to suffer. 1.8 Why Gradual Moral Status? Biology clarifies that the fetus is continuously growing and pictures give us proof. Bundles of cells in the first trimester go on to become a fetus with hands, feet, a heart and many other characteristics. The fetus becomes increasingly like a child while in the womb. As Dworkin notes, the later the abortion the more like a child a fetus has already become—the worse it is (90-91). There is a natural investment that would be wasted since an abortion grows steadily larger and more significant (92). According to Mary Ann Warren in her article “On the Moral And Legal Status of Abortion,” we should take seriously that as a human being develops continuously its rights develop in the same way (n. pag.). She states, “It does seem reasonable to suggest that the more like a person, in the relevant respects, a being is, the stronger the case for regarding it as having a right to life, and indeed the stronger its right to life is” (n. pag.). She states that although a seventh or eight-month fetus has features that make persons want to protect them, they 30 are not significantly more personlike than an embryo. She asserts that in the relevant respects, a fetus, even a fully developed one, is considerably less personlike than is the average mature mammal and because of this if the right to life of a fetus is to be based upon its resemblances to a person, then it cannot be said to have any more right to life than a woman (n.pag.). Thus, along with Armstrong and Hsieh, she concludes that a fetus’s right to life could never override a woman’s right to obtain an abortion, at any stage of her pregnancy. Mary Ann Warren asserts fetuses should not be given personhood status because she points out, “It is impossible to treat fetuses in utero as if they were persons without treating women as if they were something less than persons” (“Moral Difference” 59). Extending personhood would violate women’s rights to autonomy and physical security (59). Already hospital or physicians have court ordered women to undergo Caesarean sections against their will. “[F]orced Caesareans threaten to reduce women to the status of inanimate objects—containers which may be opened at the will of others in order to get at their contents” (qtd. in Warren, “Moral Difference” 59). Although I agree with Warren that it is impossible to treat women as persons while simultaneously giving personhood status to embryos, their gradual development and increasing consciousness does make them morally considerable. As discussed earlier, the capacity for pain and suffering makes one morally significant. For a woman to be able to abort at any time during her pregnancy is extreme. The fetus is alive and although value is relational the capacities that make fetuses valuable to other human beings are maturing. A life is being destroyed—it is a loss and should be taken seriously. As Shields noted, “Among workers who strongly supported abortion rights, 77 percent described it 31 as a ‘destructive act’ and 18 percent actually said it was ‘murder’ (501). One clinic worker stated, ‘I think part of the problem is that we don’t talk about [the sadness caused by second-trimester abortion] . . . because there’s always that fear that somebody will hear it. . . . And an anti will get hold of it’ (Shields 501). Furthermore, as the fetus continues to grow abortion becomes less of letting die and more of an intentional killing when the fetus has become viable and can live independently. Gradual moral status allows many Americans to confront their ambivalence and balance their worries for the fetus and the woman. Gradual moral status is preferable because not only does it allow the fetus moral consideration, but it also considers the woman and acknowledges that the woman helps the fetus become a person. Pregnancy implicates every aspect of a woman’s life and although the fetus is of value, it is also a responsibility unlike any other. To become pregnant is not only a burden, but also deeply intimate. As Little states, “ . . . its costs, judged both as burden and intimacies, can be substantial, and deeply context dependent, grounded in what the pregnancy means in the narrative context of the woman’s life” (“Abortion and Personhood” 344). As Little points out, what continued pregnancy asks prospectively of the woman is more than is required by any other citizen. Little states, “A constitutionally-protected right of access to abortion, then, is a core protection for women’s status as citizens; and early abortion, while regretful, can be regarded as a decent and, indeed, a potentially honorable action” (“Abortion and Personhood” 344). Gradual moral status not only speaks to many Americans’ ambivalence on abortion, it can account for reality. Many Americans do not consider fetuses persons, while they do allow for gradual moral status. This is why in-vitro fertilization and IUDs 32 are allowed, but why Americans have such austere reactions when a fetus is aborted during the second or third trimesters. It can account for why some women abort fetuses that will be cognitively or physically disabled. It can also make sense of den Hartogh’s theory of relational value. As the fetus continues to develop, it develops characteristics that make it more valuable to us; hence why we have such instinctive reactions to late term abortions, but not early ones. Unlike personhood at fertilization, gradual moral status takes seriously what the pregnancy would mean for the woman—at any stage (Little, “Abortion and Personhood” 344). Gradual moral status allows for women to be the other fundamental variable in assessing the moral and legal status of abortion. Little states, “Whatever the status of early human life, it does not develop on its own. . . . Put bluntly, it takes a great deal of work to turn early human life into something of full moral status” (“Abortion and Personhood” 344). 1.9 Conclusion The personhood movement although having secular arguments, is still fundamentally religious. One can see this through its logical leap from human biology to personhood (Armstrong & Hsieh 31). The right to life is inalienable and has intrinsic value because it originates with God. This is why fighting abortion is “God’s work” (PersonhoodUSA.com). This is why they do not even believe their inconclusive secular arguments. Their assertions are based on dogma instead of reality. There is no indisputable view on the moral status of embryos or fetuses that a pregnant woman is intellectually compelled to accept (McCullough & Chervenak 37). 33 Not only does personhood fail to tell us whether abortion is ethical or not, the intrinsic status required of the embryo is not possible. Its value is also relational. Personhood proponents and their belief that life originates with God renders women invisible and adds to the inadequacy and extremeness of the framework. Although she is the link between the zygote and human being, the work required of her to turn the embryo into something of full moral status is ignored. Personhood alone does not tell us whether abortion is immoral or not, there are other variables and sometimes abortion is not so much killing as it refusing to provide assistance in the first trimester. My point is that the moral judgment that abortion is never permissible is not substantiated because there is no conclusive evidence that fetuses are persons. Neither is it irrefutable that they have intrinsic value. Many Americans are ambivalent; they take into consideration both the fetus and the mother and rely on more information than just the moral status of the fetus to decide its permissibility. Due to the fact that the permissibility of abortion varies and since it is necessary to know more than just the status of the fetus in order to make that judgment, the anti-abortionist moral theory that solely depends on personhood is inadequate. This I will discuss more fully in the next chapter. 34 Chapter 2 Ethical Decision-making Moral norms are usually used in making judgments about particular actions. These norms are also used to inform public policy. According to Ronald Lindsay, there is this common morality and it is supplemented with widely accepted factual beliefs along with an understanding of our background social conditions (35). Sometimes these moral norms are justified seeking a reflective equilibrium. Reflective equilibrium is an approach that does not take certain norms or judgments as given, but that are instead revisable. It tests initial moral judgments by detailing and examining the consequences of adhering to these judgments. These principles are themselves tested against our background beliefs and theories, both moral and nonmoral. Judgments and principles that cannot be rendered consistent with each other and our background beliefs and theories may need to be modified or discarded (Lindsay 37). I would like to use this approach to judge whether anti-abortionist moral theory is justified. In the first chapter I discussed the consequences and theories of personhood. Now I would like to give some descriptive and background information about abortion in order to highlight what numerous Americans take into consideration when judging abortion. Proponents of personhood use a moral principle to judge the morality of abortion. It is always immoral to intentionally kill an innocent person and therefore, their moral framework is much more rigid and exceptionless. This is why they focus solely on the fetus. For many Americans however, the morality of abortion takes into account more than just the fetus. Many Americans, like those who are pro-choice, sometimes feel that abortion can be an ethical decision depending on the circumstances. New information and reflection can change our moral judgments, they are not necessarily absolute. 35 In this chapter I would like to discuss why women abort and how pregnancy affects their lives in order to highlight why unlike anti-abortionists, pro-choice Americans do take into consideration the mother and her circumstances when judging abortion. Then I will discuss why the personhood movement’s moral theory is inadequate to the task of judging abortion. 2.1 Exceptionless Moral Principles To share the view of gradual moral status for the fetus, or the view that in some cases abortion is justified, is to not be in-line with anti-abortionist morality. This is because their argument rests on one principle: that it is unequivocally immoral to kill an innocent human being. This argument is highly deontological. Deontology holds that individuals have strong duties to respect what follows from the inherent dignity and value of rational beings (Panza & Potthast 293). For John Finnis, an anti-abortionist philosopher, and other anti-abortionists, to not murder is a moral principle that cannot be overridden by other considerations (Boyle 77). No one should intentionally kill an innocent human. This is why the banning of in vitro fertilization, or contraception, or having women bear children because of rape does not discourage proponents—they insist that critics were and are missing and avoiding the central moral problem (Eckholm n.pag.). Personhood proponents see the abortion of the fetus as the sole moral problem in abortion and they feel any other focus unjustified. Furthermore, some anti-abortionists as well as those who are pro-choice hold other assumptions about women who electively 36 abort, which prevents them from having sympathy for the woman in some cases. There are assumptions about women who have elective abortions. These women are irresponsible, selfish, rash, and they are aborting because it is convenient. There is the belief that if she would only stop to think about her actions she would change her mind. This is why most people believe that most, if not all, women who abort are not good mothers. Nevertheless, statistics show that these assumptions are not entirely accurate. When women discuss their decisions to abort they usually have more than one reason for their abortion. Additionally, more than 62 percent of women who abort are already mothers (Guttmacher.org). Whereas the mother is looking past the pregnancy towards the life after it emerges out of the womb, anti-abortionists simply worry about making it out of the womb. 2.2 Why Women Abort The responsibilities for existing children are increasingly significant for women seeking abortions (Jones, Frohwirth & Moore, 88). Women not only want to provide material things for their children, but also abstract things like life enrichment, attention and nurturing. Women have certain ideals they want to uphold when it comes to having children. Before having children women want to have a home, a stable income, an education. They want to be in a stable relationship with a man they deem responsible, and they want to be able to be able to give all of themselves to their children. Jones, Frohwirth and Moore’s article “I Would Want to Give My Child, Like, Everything in the World,” provides research that shows that issues of responsibility and care for existing 37 and future children influence women’s decisions to terminate their pregnancies. Women are very aware of the responsibilities that being a mother entail and so want to be able to properly fulfill these duties. One case given in Jones, Frohwirth and Moore’s research was of a woman who was having an abortion in order to be reunited with her children. Her former partner was abusive and had left with two of her children and would not allow her to speak to them in an attempt to convince her to live with him again. Since then, she began to live with another man and ended up pregnant and she knew that she could not return to her partner in that condition. She stated: I have two kids, and I want to go back with my other two kids . . . I think a lot of times that it’s a baby that I’m killing. I love kids. I love my kids and I love babies. But I got nothing else to do . . . If I get pregnant again but with my ex-husband, I would have it because it’s a baby, and I love babies, and I would have it. (89) The abortion in this case was so this woman could reconnect with her family. The next case is of a woman who did not feel equipped to have another child at the time. She stated: Now, I have three beautiful children. I love them. That is a reason . . . It’s so difficult because I live for my children. And I love them so much . . . And it’s not like, “Oh, children! I can’t have another one.” It’s just the fact that everything that comes along with it . . . But, it’s not because, you know, I just don’t want to be a mother, or I just don’t want another kid, or, oh! (89) 38 It is perpetuated not only by anti-abortionists, but also by other women, that women who procure abortions do not know what they are doing, that they do not know what they are giving up, that they are selfish, but this shows the contrary. These women are not thinking foremost about themselves, but of their families, their children and the responsibilities they entail. This demonstrates how much responsibility and hard work goes into having another child or as the woman above describes it, “It’s just the fact that everything that comes along with it . . .” that prevents these women from taking on another child (Jones, Frohwirth & Moore, 89). Women who had abortions and had no children discussed that there were certain conditions that had to be met before they could be parents. One respondent stated: I have a feeling, like, if I would have had the baby, I wouldn’t have been able to give the baby everything I would have wanted to . . . I can’t have a new-born baby and not be able to take care of it, and I would want to give my child, like, everything in the world . . . I really do want a baby someday. I want to be able to support my child and give it everything it needs, and I don’t want to depend on anyone else for it . . . I want my kid to be healthy and stable, physically, financially taken care of. And I didn’t see any of ‘em happening [right now]. (91) Other respondents who did not have children said that they felt they were not mentally ready or mature enough to have a child. Some women do not want their children to grow up in less than ideal situations or in situations they themselves have been through and 39 find undesirable. In some cases respondents felt that it would be selfish to have the child instead of aborting it because they would be recreating the same negative circumstances for their future children (Jones, Frohwirth & Moore, 93). There are also instances where women wanted children, but then had to abort because of changing circumstances. Boonstra et al. point out that 1.3 million women procured abortions although they had planned for a child (8). This was due to changing circumstances where their marriage or finances became unstable or they or the fetus became diagnosed with a medical condition. This shows that not all abortions stem from irresponsibility or promiscuous behavior—sometimes even married or stable couples abort because of changing circumstances or because they cannot support a child. 2.3 Reproduction & Women’s Autonomy As pregnancies occur in women’s bodies and because not all women are in control of their reproductive systems there always exists the possibility for an unwanted pregnancy (Boonstra 6). It is because of how pregnancy affects women’s independence and their bodies that feminists (that are pro-abortion) and those that are pro-choice hold that women should have the choice to abort. Employed single women who become pregnant face not only the interruption of their jobs and careers, but a decrease in their earning ability rendering them unable to raise a child on their own. Even worse for women who already have children, pregnancy can bring them below the poverty line (Guttmacher.org). 40 Many Americans agree with the Supreme Court that women should have autonomy over the decision to abort. In the Supreme Court case Roe v. Wade, the right to choose an abortion was based on a woman’s private decision. As Eugenie Robinson points out, privacy rights affirm the importance of a respect for autonomy and un-coerced decision making in ethical life, thus protecting personal choices from arbitrary interference and state intervention (77). Those that are pro-choice believe that this right to an abortion should be protected regardless of whether some object to it as immoral (Dworkin 61). As Thomas Hill points out, “To respect someone as an autonomous person . . . is to acknowledge that certain decisions are up to him or her and thus to refrain from efforts to control those decisions” (48). He continues that when we say that someone is autonomous it is not a description; it is to grant that a person has a right to control certain matters for himself or herself. Self-determination and control over one’s body is a fundamental part of being an agent with needs and rights (48). Denying women the rights to control their bodies would exempt them from these values. There is a great fear among feminists and others that women become secondary to their roles as mothers and are seen just as vessels for baby making (Copeland n.pag.). Many feminists are of the view that taking away women’s rights to an abortion is in essence declaring them unfit to make decisions for themselves. Anti-abortionists must remember that choices must exist in order for human beings to participate in morality. I must choose to do something in order to be held accountable for it (Young 43). Although anti-abortionists view women who abort as morally deficient and selfish, many women know that it is morally grave to abort, however there are concrete realities and responsibilities that push them to do it (Scott 320). As Thomas Hill states, “Ideally 41 autonomous, or self-governing, moral agents would respond to the real facts of the situation they face, not to a perception distorted by morally irrelevant needs and prejudices” (51). Pregnancy can be extremely risky for some women and has several severe physical effects (Robinson 47). Not to mention that there are medical anomalies and that some women are mentally unstable and serious dangers to themselves (Copeland n. pag.). Furthermore, those that are feminists and those that are pro-choice realize that women sometimes abort out of their responsibilities to children they are currently raising. As Robinson states, “If she has responsibilities to herself and to other that the care of the fetus will force her to neglect, she is being forced into a position in which she cannot but act irresponsibly” (48). Women realize that children can dampen their prospects and can exacerbate their already unequal and undermined social and economic statuses. Pregnancy involves immense sacrifices that range from physical, economic and emotional; this is why those that are pro-choice feel women are justified when they abort for their careers or well-being (Copeland n.pag.). For those that are pro-choice there is nothing inconsistent between holding abortion immoral and still allowing people the choice. This is because they are aware of the moral complexity and the various dimensions of the issue (Scott 325). Support for abortion may come from a higher-order belief in tolerance and civil liberties rather than reflecting a specific judgment on abortion itself (Scott 320). Anti-abortionists must realize that in reality it is hard to live up to the ideal of motherhood and that with children being such immense responsibilities and in wanting to provide them the best lives, women are forced to take into account their circumstances. 42 With children needing many material things besides love and affection some people consider it wise and responsible to consider one’s circumstances. As Ayn Rand stated, The capacity to procreate is merely a potential which man is not obligated to actualize. The choice to have children or not is morally optional. Nature endows man with a variety of potentials—and it is his mind that must decide which capacities he chooses to exercise, according to his own hierarchy or rational goals and values. . . . To an animal, the rearing of its young is a matter of cycles, for man is it is a life-long responsibility that must not be undertaken causelessly, thoughtlessly, or accidentally. (qtd. in Armstrong & Hsieh 29) This is why to simply have a child due to an accident is as Armstrong and Hsieh state, “self-destructive” (29). Bringing another human into the world is a morally serious consideration that supersedes any absolute duty to remain pregnant (Porter 80). It is also important to remember that, “[t]he woman who gets the abortion and the woman who gives birth are the same woman at different stages of their life” (qtd. in Jones, Frohwirth & Moore, 80). Some women who abort already are mothers or will go on to be mothers. Although some women are irresponsible and may abort for callous reasons, not all women who obtain abortions are necessarily selfish or morally incompetent. They are not all making these decisions on whims; some of these decisions are well informed—even compassionate. I bring up these assumptions and stereotypes about women who electively abort because these assumptions occasionally make it hard to take away the taboo and stigma of abortion. These stereotypes demean the real necessity of abortion and hinder us from 43 realizing that many Americans find elective abortion just as justified as abortion in an emergency. More importantly, these stereotypes do not allow many Americans to realize that mothers and women who abort are in many cases are the same woman. These assumptions sometimes further the view that it is the woman against her fetus, and makes it harder for us to see the relationship that exists between a woman and the fetus, which I will discuss further in chapter 3. 2.4 Conflicting Responsibilities It must be acknowledged that in reality women do not think of the decision to abort as one where their rights are being exercised, but it is one of care and responsibility in relationships. It is not about conflicting rights, but of conflicting responsibilities (Porter 80). As Porter states, “Difficult decision making involves multiples negotiations between social structures, ideologies, immediate social contexts, and particular desires, rationales shift according to changing needs” (85). She points out that women “ . . . deliberate, weigh options, reflect, equivocate and eventually decide” (85). This is not a simple decision and if we want an ethics of abortion that is realistic and reflective of that then it must take women’s circumstances into consideration. As stated earlier, women usually have more than one reason to abort. Do we really want to criminalize women when they are aborting to reunite their families, to give their already limited resources to their living children, or because they were raped? This is why with an issue so complex like abortion, we must be wary of absolutes. It must be taken earnestly that abortion is contextual and unique to each pregnancy, not something universal that applies to any 44 woman and any fetus (Sherwin, 238). In some situations abortion will be morally permissible and in some it will not, however we need to look at each instance individually because every woman experiences pregnancy differently. While personhood proponents focus on just one moral problem, those that are pro-choice or that take these other factors into consideration perceive even more ethical concerns if the woman were forced to gestate. Those that take in both the woman and the fetus are trying to find a balance and are trying to make the choice that involves less harm. A legislator, Albert Blumenthal, who wanted to repeal antiabortion laws completely before Roe v. Wade asked, ‘Isn’t that the ultimate morality? Could we have saved 367 young women from dying if we had not imposed on them our own sense of morality and condemned them . . . to the butchery of the side streets of Harlem or Riverside Drive in my district?’ (Boonstra12). Many Americans realize that abortion will continue even if made illegal, endangering the lives of not only women, but their children as well. As stated in the beginning by Ronald Lindsay, common morality is supplemented with widely accepted factual beliefs along with an understanding of our background social conditions. When creating new policy or legislation there is a need to be systematic and coherent with other theories, facts and background social conditions. Proponents of personhood want to use their morality to create policy, but their secular arguments and assumptions are not entirely accurate or irrefutable; a fertilized egg is not continuous with the person it later becomes and an abortion in the first trimester is more of letting die than killing for the fetus has no trajectory without the woman. Their focus on solely the fetus disregards facts and background social conditions that show abortion is necessary for 45 women’s well-being in American society, and that varying circumstances sometimes make abortion the more ethical choice to make. Personhood proponents just focus on the status of the fetus, while some Americans are ambivalent and take into consideration both the fetus and the woman. This is why personhood legislation does not cohere with how numerous Americans view the abortion issue and fails to reflect and speak to reality since many of things it would criminalize, like IUDs and in-vitro fertilization, many Americans are proponents of. 2.5 Personhood Proponents’ Moral Theory Proponents of personhood are using a deontological theory of ethics. This theory has to do with what is morally required, forbidden, or permitted. Deontologists hold that some choices cannot be justified by their effects (Daniels n.pag.). According to this theory what makes a choice right is its conformity with a moral norm or principle. Personhood’s moral argument rests on one principle: that it is absolutely immoral to kill an innocent human being. It is considered exceptionless by John Finnis and other antiabortionists because “ . . . an act of intentionally killing an innocent human being . . . is wrong in such a way that anything further one might discover about the action will not change its moral valence from impermissible to permissible” (Boyle 79). It is simply morally out of the question to ever intentionally abort a child. This evil should not be done no matter how great the outcome will be (Boyle 79-80). Goods are not only to be protected, but also promoted. There are no instances where you can ignore one’s inherent dignity (Finnis 294). This theory therefore, forbids you from ever taking an innocent life 46 and at the same time, requires that you promote life. Finnis and personhood proponents always hold life as something valuable—a gift (from God). It is a good that needs to be protected and promoted because of its value and inviolability. Finnis and personhood proponents believe fetuses have intrinsic value and a dignity that should not be destroyed and base their argument for moral impermissibility on this. There just can be no justification for taking an innocent human life. I argued in Chapter 1 however, that unconscious persons do not have intrinsic value due to their inability to value anything for itself; they therefore have a relational value that is developmentally dependent. Personhood proponents hold that naturally human beings are valuable, Den Hartogh points out though that persons are not naturally valuable, they are valuable because they can attribute value to their lives and existence. When a member of an un-endangered species lacks consciousness it is worthy of protection only if it has special characteristics endowing it with value to other conscious beings (58). It is a value marked by context-dependency and gradualist character (61). Furthermore, I argued that moral considerability for fetuses does not even come from being a person or from belonging to a certain species, but from the capacity to feel pain and suffer. This moral theory also requires for life to always be promoted, realistically though, life is not always a gift. For some people whose lives are full of suffering or pain, there is more of a preference for death than for life. Having information about the kind of life the fetus will have outside of the womb matters ethically. If the fetus will be born without a brain, or with a severe disease that keeps it from flourishing or from a quality life, it may push the parents to abort out of morally compassionate reasons. If the woman is having severe health problems it may also be more ethical to end the life of the fetus, 47 than to continue it. Even if the child may not have a disease or something severe, a mother may decide that the having of an abusive household, a household with drug addicts, or a poor household may not only cause suffering (maybe the child will be taken away and put in foster care), but may also impede the flourishing of the child, pushing the woman to abort. As I mentioned in the beginning of the chapter, those that push for personhood assert that there is no information that could change the morality of abortion, but in reality some Americans realize there can be. Life is a good and the principle of not killing the innocent helps answer this tough moral question of abortion, but it is to only focus on one part of the problem of abortion (Boyle 80). I highlighted women’s reasons to abort and how pregnancy affects women’s lives to show that they also matter morally in the abortion debate. This deontological moral theory should not be used because of its inconsistent foundations, but also because of its exclusion of information, its ruthlessness and its sole focus on the fetus that ignores the moral complexities and Catch-22s that women experience. This moral theory fails to respect women. In Chapter 1 when I discussed ambivalence I highlighted that not only are many Americans worried about the fetus, they are also worried about the woman. I discussed that even people who were pro-choice undeniably felt that they were destroying life, incredibly however, when they helped women who were in dire circumstances they could at the same time be certain that in that instance what they were doing was justified. As the woman stated, she felt she was “helping humankind” (Shields 504). In America there are two sides to this issue—not one—and a moral theory for abortion, especially one that will be used for legislation, should reflect that. This moral theory fails to realize that there are conflicts between 48 duties and rights (Daniels n.pag.). Mothers are in deep conflict, I highlighted this in the testimonials earlier in this chapter. Women equivocate and think about what they are doing. This is a deeply complex issue and while principles can be great starting points, there needs to be ethical reflection. It must be taken into account where our moral theories lead us, what their consequences are. This is why even people who are pro-life are voting down these personhood initiatives. One woman stated that the proposal “yanked” her ‘ . . . in one direction and the other’ (Eckholm n.pag.). She felt a lot of compassion for teenagers and said that she had a lot of praying to do before she voted. This theory is paradoxical in that following this moral principle leads to actions that are perceived to be even less unethical. It ignores the nuances found in abortion. It cannot account for all the other circumstances some Americans take into consideration. Since fetuses are not persons, this theory irrationally requires us and permits us to make the world morally worse (Daniels n.pag.). What this morality would do to the living at the expense of those who are not is unjust given that fetuses do not have the same moral status as persons. This is why although abortion is ethically problematic critics of personhood amendments claim it is even worse to further victimize already hard-hit families (Grabiner n.pag.). As Gene Grabiner states, “Apart from the increased Hispanic/Latino teen-age birthrate (2005 data), the greatest overall increase in the American birthrate, consequent to outlawing choice, is likely to occur among poor and working people, many of whom are already unemployed/underemployed” (n.pag.). He goes on to ask, “But, if they are poor families forced by anti-abortion laws to become multi-child families what may be expected of the quality of life for those children?” (n.pag.) Children are not able to fulfill their potential due to inadequate social, economic 49 and educational conditions and this is also morally problematic. Although many that are pro-life insist that nothing is more sacred than human life, one pastor commented, ‘It matters whether a new life . . . might threaten to undermine the theologically understood fulfillment of already existing human beings’ (qtd. in Dworkin 46). This theory should not be taken seriously until it seriously takes into consideration the life that continues after birth. 2.6 Conclusion What I have tried to show in this chapter is that personhood’s moral theory is too rigid for many Americans and cannot speak to abortion’s realities. It does not show an acknowledgment of women’s background social conditions. For some information can change the morality of abortion—it is not as absolute as the proponents of personhood make it out to be. Finding out the fetus will be deformed, finding out the woman will suffer greatly along with the child, finding out that the pregnancy will greatly undermine the trajectory of the woman’s life, if you find out she was raped, that she cannot afford the children she already has—does change the morality of abortion. The statistics on what pregnancy does to women’s lives, the fact that women have a right to their bodies, the fact that inequalities against women are exacerbated when they become pregnant adds to the issue’s complexity and creates ambivalence. Testimonials of women who have procured abortions show us that abortion is about conflicting responsibilities and varying circumstances, that it is more complex than just the status of the fetus. As stated before, having a child is an immense responsibility 50 that supersedes any duty to remain pregnant. Anti-abortionist morality refuses to take this into consideration because of its principle. Furthermore, this morality turns the woman into a passive container. Biology shows that she is the link between fertilization and moral status. She is providing it life; it is extremely dependent on her. In the first trimester she is not killing as much as letting die. This morality grossly usurps rights to bodily autonomy and reduces her moral status using arguments that are faulty and disputed. It is undeniable that for many Americans this moral theory is shortsighted and inadequate. The fact is that personhood is contested, and this theory has severe consequences that cannot be justified. So why use this moral theory and why let it usurp a woman’s right to abortion? It is not that I do not agree with personhood’s principle, it is just that fetuses are not persons and while I agree that they deserve moral consideration, their moral status does not equal that of those who are living. I concede that abortion is always morally problematic and that it gets worse as the fetus continues to grow. There may not be a person, but there is a life and it is a loss. This belief that fetuses have intrinsic status and are inviolable is fundamentally religious. Its genetics is cited because a new life is something given by God. As one proponent of the initiative stated, ‘Personhood is bigger than just shutting abortion clinics; it’s an opportunity for people to say that we’re made in the image of God’ (Eckholm n.pag.). It is fine that proponents or personhood believe this, but they cannot require others to also believe them. Concomitantly, it must be acknowledged that this morality holds women to ideal standards instead of realistic ones. It is an imposition of values. This morality tells women with whom, when and under what conditions to have children (Hewson ii10). 51 Lastly, it is naïve to believe that personhood policy will get rid of abortion. It needs to be kept in mind that abortion is precipitated by unintended pregnancy. Thus, if we want to reduce the number of abortions we should start there. We can greatly reduce the numbers of abortion by increasing levels of contraceptive use. Additionally, we can reduce the need for abortions by helping women control their reproductive lives. Boonstra et al. point out that when women can control their reproductive lives it also benefits the nation, their children, their partners and themselves (5). If as a nation America is riled up on this issue, then why not aggressively do something about it that does not include restricting it? Unintended pregnancy should be a focus not only because it leads to abortion, but also so that as a nation Americans can realize that they are also responsible. Lack of contraceptives, lack of family planning and lack of sexual education has a cost. It is not just the fault of these women, as a nation the seriousness of sex and child rearing should be acknowledged by teaching young adults to be sexually responsible. Currently there is a war by conservatives against Planned Parenthood, a government institution that deals with family planning and abortion services. It is not fair to take away contraceptives from women, to take away their reproductive freedoms and then once they are pregnant to then force them to gestate and take on an immense responsibility. Conservatives cannot have it both ways. The reality is that abortion has to do with a fetus and a woman. Their relationship consistently fails to be acknowledged by both sides of the abortion debate. It is necessary to have a framework that takes seriously what Little calls “fetal geography” (“Abortion and Intimacy” (1). 52 Chapter 3 Margaret Little’s Relationship Framework Given that the personhood moral framework is inadequate, I propose Margaret Little’s relationship framework. I would like to show that her framework is better suited to assess the morality of abortion because not only does it take into account the fetus, the woman and their relationship, but also because it can speak to and make sense of abortion’s realities. 3.1 A Limited Right to Life Margaret Little’s article “Abortion, Intimacy, and the Duty to Gestate” discusses how America’s public debate on abortion is inadequate and points out that this issue is especially difficult because even when one tries to morally evaluate abortion carefully with the usual tools, the issue still seems beyond our grasp. She highlights that America’s laws view a person as an individual, physically separate from others. Little highlights how both sides of the abortion debate would view abortion as a violation of a right to life if the fetus turned out to be a person. This would circumscribe the woman’s right to an abortion because now the fetus would have the rights that she has. This sounds like an unlimited right for the fetus, but Little perceptively points out that this right is actually highly circumscribed—even for persons. She shows that although persons have a right to life the right does not include the right to a life preserver from a stranger, or the right not to be shot if it is done in self-defense. She asserts that along with a person’s right to life come questions about what contours the right to life has given varies circumstances. To 53 be inside a womb as Little notes, is to be in an extraordinary environment and enmeshment (1). Given its incredible circumstances and physical dependency it could be asked then, whether the fetus’s right to life includes the continuation of this relationship (“Abortion and Intimacy” 1). When women are pregnant there is a physical intertwinement that legally cannot be accounted for since law deals with individuals and not with fetuses. Even in our moral frameworks, there is never a focus on the relationship between the mother and the fetus. This intertwinement is not taken into account or acknowledged. Consequently, Little states, “The central figures in the abortion drama—fetus, gestating woman, and their relationship—are left out of the conceptual paradigm” (“Abortion and Intimacy” 1). Our theories do not let us fully appreciate the relationship arising from gestation. Little points out that literature on the relationship between mother and child is recurrently shown as a relationship “ . . . between strangers or with the woman dubbed a ready-made mother who is blithely assigned responsibilities of a kind and feel unmatched by any other citizen” (1). Hence, according to Little, those in the debate face the morality and politics of intertwinement and enmeshment with a conceptual framework that is ill suited to the task. Little highlights that not only is the intimacy neglected, but also that neither side takes pivotal that gestation occurs inside of someone’s body (1). 3.2 Fetal Geography Little draws attention to the fact that pro-life movements frame the issue on the fetus and grossly neglect the fact that pregnancies involve women. She notes that when 54 women’s interests are mentioned, they cannot counter the fetus’s claims. The view held by those that are pro-life neglects the fact that gestation happens inside of women’s bodies and the danger with this is that people then begin to think of fetuses as persons individuated and separate, that require rights identical to those human beings use in everyday life (“Abortion and Intimacy” 2). Little concedes that even if the view that abortion is not violating a right to life, there still may be ethical and legal reasons to restrict or prohibit it. She believes more interesting sources of concern would remain. These remaining concerns would arise from the belief that a woman who aborts is more than anything violating and reneging on positive responsibilities stemming from either beneficence or in virtue of a maternal relationship she has towards the fetus. Little claims that the question that needs to be acknowledged is whether, or when, one has a duty to continue gestating when one finds oneself pregnant. She also asks, what burden is imposed on women when they are forced to gestate (Little, “Abortion and Intimacy” 3) Little acknowledges that pregnancy does impose a heavy social cost, but that these concerns are incomplete because women’s stories about abortion are more about gestation and motherhood. She goes on to explain that to be pregnant is to be inhabited and occupied. She feels that it is important to realize that pregnancy involves a state of physical intimacy. To force a woman to gestate is to keep her in physical intertwinement against her consent. Many would argue that pregnancy and gestation are great and beautiful, an experience of love and enmeshment. Yet as Little points out, this is to miss the point because it neglects the fact that it was a willing gestation (“Abortion and Intimacy” 3). She claims that similarly to sex, which can be wonderful under consent yet 55 a violation without it, pregnancy too can be awesome with it or repulsive without it. Many hold the belief that all women want to be mothers and want to experience gestation, however this is as Little states, to point out the ideal. Regardless of what women are supposed and believed to want, it is what she actually wants that determines the status of the enmeshment. Little claims that forcing a woman to gestate is a liberty harm. It is about an invasion of self, not a thwarting of plans (“Abortion and Intimacy” 34). To gestate is to be in a relationship where the woman will most likely not just share her body, but also her heart. For many women this issue is not so much having the right to abort, but whether and when it is moral to exercise that right (Little, “Abortion and Intimacy” 4). Those that are pro-life believe that the woman should gestate out of beneficence, but gestating requires the sharing of one’s body, heart and soul. Thus, she claims that what is needed is a moral approach that does justice to the ethics of intimacy. She points out that abortion is problematic because of people’s beliefs of what mothers owe their children. Hence, we need an ethics of parenthood in order to understand what makes a person a parent in a normative sense and what responsibilities entail. Little goes on to argue that parenthood can have different layers where different moral responsibilities attach at each layer (4). 3.3 Parenting and Relationships Little points out that parenthood is a lived personal relationship, not just a legal status. Between parents and children is an emotional interconnection, a history of shared 56 experience, and immense affection. She explains that this is why parents’ self-sacrifice is often immediate. It is out of this intertwinement that the child has a legitimate expectation of sacrifice and why failure to provide assistance would be seen as problematic (“Abortion and Intimacy” 5). Most people have the intuition that in a case where a child had two fathers and needed a kidney, where one father is in a lived relationship with the child and the other was just a sperm donor (so only a biological connection), that the father with the lived experience with the child owes more than the father who has merely contributed his sperm. As relationships between parents and a child grow, the more sacrifice that is expected of them. She notes that this does not mean that all responsibilities of parenthood are functions of a relationship, but that responsibilities to share one’s body are (Little, “Abortion and Intimacy” 5). Little astutely points out that in ethics whether one ought to enter a relationship and when it is permissible to exit is rarely discussed (“Abortion and Intimacy” 5). She acknowledges that parenthood has many deontological obligations that exist regardless of the status of the relationship between the mother and the fetus, even the lack of one; however, she claims that some responsibilities do not arise from just social or legal statuses of parenthood, or just a biological connection, but out of the lived and personal relationships that accompany them. When discussing the ethics of relationships usually the discussion focuses on what morally flows from or governs relationships once they are entered, additionally though, Little adds one should also discuss whether one ought to enter and when it is permissible to exit (5). Little states that relationships require that one be open to the relationship and that some people have a claim to someone’s openness (“Abortion and Intimacy” 5). Little 57 holds that biology is morally salient in that it is a claim toward a further relationship. She explains that while she may legitimately decline to a stranger with no reason at all, if the person were her cousin, she would owe him an openness to that possibility. She notes that she does not have to pursue these relationships, and while there are a lot of reasons for declining she highlights that she needs better reasons to legitimately decline when it is her cousin and not a stranger. When it comes to people’s intuitions they usually feel that it is a sense of betrayal to decline a relationship when there is a biological connection for callous reasons. This is why there are moral claims about being open to entering such relationships. Little states, “My suspicion is that some of the passions about the morality of abortion stem from our tendency to confuse the two. We tend to conflate the claims one faces to enter a relationship with the claims one would face if one were within it” (“Abortion and Intimacy” 6). She continues, “One who declines to enter a relationship, even for bad reasons, does not owe what he would have owed if he had entered it” (“Abortion and Intimacy” 5-6). She asserts that responsibilities attach to the personal relationships themselves; women therefore, do not have a role based moral duty to gestate. She highlights that this matters directly to the responsibilities and abstentions of parenthood. She shrewdly points out that it is a form of abandonment to refuse openness to a child with someone who you have a biological connection with, and it is a form of abandonment to refuse a sacrifice that would in a lived relationship be reasonably expected, but that these are not the same abandonment. She states, “The sperm donor, or again the one-night stand, does not need the same sorts of reasons for declining to donate the kidney as does the father whose life is intertwined with the child’s” (Little, “Abortion and Intimacy” 6). Gestation is even more intimate than providing a kidney, since it 58 involves not only intertwinement, but also nine months of occupation. According to Little, this means: that a responsibility to gestate does not arise simply from being in a biological relationship with the fetus. Nevertheless, she admits that this does not mean that pregnancy is not a moral moment. Although the biological intertwinement grounds a legitimate claim to a further relationship one may have good reasons to decline, like issues of poverty (6). According to Little this framework of relationship ethics helps to make sense of the fact that intuitions regarding moral responsibility to gestate are varied, urgently felt and underdetermined (“Abortion and Intimacy” 6). Some women conceptualize their relationship as one between mother and child automatically, while for others it is slow and gradual. For other women the relationship is never one of motherhood, she is only in a biological relationship with a human organism. She perceptively points out that an objective perspective does not exist for what the fetus expects to help determine which woman’s conception is correct. She highlights that since the fetus is unconscious, there is not anything to help determine what the relationship is. There are no shared experiences to fill and define the relationship, consequently, there is little to the relationship, other than the woman’s experience and conception of it. Little acknowledges that constructing the decision as subjective seems as if too much power is being given to the woman. According to Little this is not the case because it is not so much that we are yielding to her point of view, it is that hers is the only one there is. If the moral duty to gestate arises depending on the personal relationship then the woman’s conception is the only thing besides biology to tell whether there is a personal relationship. She claims, “ . . . what you would need to do to leave open the possibility of developing a personal relationship is 59 precisely what you have no special responsibility to provide until you have entered the relationship: the use and occupation of your body” (“Abortion and Intimacy” 7). Little holds that although the fetus has a claim towards a stronger relationship, until that relationship exists, it has no strong claim to the intimacy involved in gestation. Little feels that with this relationship framework what seems puzzling can be explained. Many that are pro-life cannot understand or comprehend why women do not just put up their children for adoption, why the need for abortion? Little states, “What has seemed paradoxical (and indeed ethically confused) to many strikes me as perfectly sensible, and often wise, appreciation of the different moral contours involved with entering, existing in, and exiting relationships” (“Abortion and Intimacy” 7). It makes sense for women to decline entering a relationship when they know that once extant would not let them leave it (Little 7-8). 3.4 Appeal of the Relationship Framework The national debate fails to reflect many Americans’ ambivalence. Many Americans take into consideration the woman and the fetus. If there is to be a serious moral discussion on abortion my point is that I agree with Little, that a moral framework is needed, that not only takes into consideration the fetus and its moral status; the social, political and economic repercussions of having a child; but also fetal geography. This is the appeal of her framework: its comprehensiveness and acknowledgement of moral ambiguity, its coherence with other theories of moral status and the value of fetuses, its consideration of woman’s circumstances by allowing for gradual moral status, and its 60 insightfulness with respect to Americans’ ambivalence. What makes it really great is that it puts the relationship front and center, which makes sense since it is because of this relationship that the fetus is morally significant (Gibson 227). Gibson states, “It is the variety of relationships and roles that a human being participates in – their membership of a community- that gives them their value as persons” (227). It is also out of this relationship that responsibility to the fetus arises. Little perceptively points out that responsibility attaches to history and a lived relationship. Most parents deeply love their children and are willing to give up anything for them; however, they take for granted that they have been building this love and that they have a history with their child already. Little’s kidney example shows us that intuitively, layers of responsibility are possible when it comes to parenthood. The other vital part of the relationship framework is that it helps make sense of the 60 percent of women who abort and already have children and those who choose not to put the child up for adoption. It is not because they love the fetus less, but that they owe it less than what they owe their other children. It makes sense of why women abort instead of continuing the gestation. As time progresses for some women the bond strengthens because as Little points out, gestation is something intimate that forces the woman to share herself. When she has to give up her child later it leaves her with even more moral problems since she has no idea how the child’s life will turn out. She feels responsible and to spare herself the uncertainty she aborts. Anti-abortionist ideology naïvely asserts that nothing else is or should be considered besides the fetus’s right to life, while feminist ideology conveniently neglects the moral status of the fetus. This moral framework however, acknowledges that there is 61 something alive and growing and additionally, that its moral status is growing along with it (Little, “Abortion and Personhood” 333). She acknowledges that as the pregnancy continues and the status of the fetus continues to solidify it takes more justification to abort. At the same time though she believes women should have the unrestricted right to abort in the first trimester since they can best judge whether they can assume the position of mother. This seems to reflect intuitively how many people feel. It is a framework that takes a little from both sides of the debate to best acknowledge our moral intuitions. Little’s framework has the ambiguity that is necessary in an abortion framework. It is important to remember that not only do people’s views on abortion vary, but that their views also vary depending on the pregnancy and the circumstances. By being a relationship framework this is acknowledged because for each new relationship one must morally judge it anew. The decision or judgment must be re-given. It may change or stay the same, but the point is that there is a need to re-evaluate the situation. This helps keep us away from generalizations and simplifications. Each relationship is unique and each mother is in a different circumstance, which may or may not lead us to different judgments. If you notice Little’s framework, it does not have so much to do with rights, as it has to do with responsibility, care and moral intuition. For this debate to move forward and be responsive to both sides of the debate there is an immense need to go beyond the language of rights to a language of responsibility. Abortion’s complexity needs to be acknowledged and this is why I would like a more comprehensive moral framework. In order to have a better debate and have a more intuitive moral framework abortion must be seen as a complex moral construct. An ethic based on relationships and responsibility 62 would be better suited since realistically the decision is not based on rights, but on responsibility from the multiple relationships and social contexts that is really about minimizing hurt and maximizing compassion and care (Porter 80). Women need the right to abortion in order to be reproductively independent not only to vindicate a right to be left alone, but often also to strengthen their ties to others (Dworkin 65). 3.5 Relationship Framework’s Shortfalls This framework uses reliable observations and draws on moral intuitions to promote a more ambiguous moral framework for abortion. It is a framework that morally considers both the fetus and the woman. I use facts and social background to try and justify some of my moral considerations. Some philosophers argue that these intuitions should not be trusted. Others also say that facts and logic should be the only things used to construct and justify moral theory. This framework and theory is also sympathetic and biased towards women. This framework presupposes most women who abort to be justified and gives women the unlimited freedom to decide whether to abort in the first trimester. This framework presents most women who abort as not selfish, or careerist or irresponsible. This is not because I do not think there are. I am sure some women do abort for trivial reasons; some do fail to give the fetus its due respect. Many women have more than one abortion (Cohen n. pag.). Nevertheless, I am convinced that for most women this does “ . . . not lead to unlimited, unprincipled abortion claims, but to an agonizing, morally acute dilemma that involves reflecting on the dialectical interplay 63 between rights and responsibilities, in view of personal life narratives . . . ” (Porter 86). This framework does not guarantee a responsible or even compassionate response from every mother, but it does put front and center the woman and the fetus and it allows the decision to be given by the one person that is responsible for it. I think these women are justified because sometimes to know what is ethical requires more than just the use of principles, but also information as to what are the intentions, consequences and contexts of our actions. Extreme cases of pregnancy and abortion force us to realize this. Varying information, gives us varying views on abortion. Furthermore, these varying views are justified by reality, theory and facts. If moral norms are going to be imposed on people, they should reflect some consensus and they should make the world better, not worse. The intuitions that tell us to both take into consideration the fetus and the woman can be justified and made sense by theories, facts and biology. Personhood moral theory fails because a fetus is not a person; this is why it is so extreme. Morality sometimes is not generalizable. Sometimes abortion is the better alternative. People weigh and equivocate, and try to do the least harm. Usually the most ethical thing to do is that which minimizes harmful consequences. Finnis and other abortionists argue that abortion is an evil and should not be done no matter how great the outcome will be (Boyle 80). Therefore, they view this framework as consequentialist (Finnis 126). Consequentialism is a moral theory that maximizes happiness. Thus, if to save fifty people you have to kill one, the morally right thing to do is kill the one person because saving fifty people creates more happiness than keeping alive one. Solely the consequences of the action are what matter. Many people like myself find this morally 64 repugnant. To abort though, is not to be a consequentialist because it is not about maximizing happiness, but about minimizing harm. Lastly, I realize that this thesis holds women and those that are dependent on them as the most vulnerable, while anti-abortionists see the pre-born to be, especially those that have cognitive or physical disabilities. Even though I agree that fetuses are alive and there is definitely life within them, I am giving greater moral status to the living. This is because the loss of a fetus is not as great as that of person who is living. Those that are living have people who love them, have more invested in their lives and most importantly, they know what you are depriving them of. Anti-abortionists place aborted fetuses on the same level as the death of Holocaust victims and this lowers the moral value of human consciousness (Porter 74). Many hold it morally worse when the person knows they are being killed. Even toddlers and those that have severe cognitive capabilities still represent more of a loss because even if they are not attributing value to their own lives, they have formed relationships with loved ones and their lives have more investment that would be lost. 3.6 Conclusion The point of this thesis is to show that personhood is a contested concept and it does not confer moral status like anti-abortionists think it does. Therefore, a moral theory that bases impermissibility on the personhood of the fetus is not justified. It is also to try and show that both sides of the abortion debate are justified, but that a fetus is not indisputably a person. Therefore, there is no foundation for authority to overrule the 65 decision to have an abortion. This is why the anti-abortionist moral theory that automatically judges abortion as impermissible is inadequate for judging the unpredictable morality of abortion. The relationship between mother and child, as well as the experience of the woman must be expressed without being distorted or worse— ignored (Porter 39). The relationship should not be ignored not only because it is through this relationship that the fetus becomes increasingly valuable, but also because it is disrespectful to women. Abortion is not only a right to bodily self-determination, but also the right to act as a moral agent (Gibson 232). Personhood proponents are right; Americans do need to re-think abortion. Let us have a debate and look at the facts and the realities without fear. Millions of women: sisters, daughters, mothers, cousins, aunts, procure abortions and many are still phenomenal mothers, so the stigma around abortion needs to be eliminated. Women can be justified in aborting and this needs to be acknowledged, women, even those who are pro-choice, should lose the fear of supporting abortion access. It is necessary for the wellbeing of all women, whether they need to abort or not. Not every woman’s pregnancy is the same so judgment should not be so quickly and harshly given. Americans must realize that personhood legislation will turn women and their partners who use contraceptives, in-vitro fertilization or who use stem-cell research into criminals. These consequences must be taken seriously. Reproduction affects all facets of a woman’s life, especially her well-being, which is why women should not have to fight for abortion rights every time politicians need help getting elected. It is important to bear in mind what you are imposing on a woman. To have a child is to have a responsibility unlike any other, a relationship that 66 will last a lifetime, an intertwinement, an occupation—all these things should be kept in mind when discussing abortion because if not you are not getting the full picture—fetuses do not exist alone, they are inside of women. Analogously, one must also realize the grave loss the fetus’s life is. That this human being was denied the gift of living and all the extraordinary things that come with it. Abortion is a difficult moral dilemma to unravel; it is not as easy as extremists on both sides of the abortion debate make it out to be. 67 Works Cited Abort73.com. “Medical Testimony.” 17 January 2009. Web. 6 Aug. 2012. Armstrong, Ari & Hsieh, Diana. “Personhood Movement is Anti-Life.” Seculargovernment.us. Web. 25 July 2012. Beauchamp, Tom L. “The Failure of Theories of Personhood.” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 9.4 (1999) : 309-324. Boonstra, Heather D., et al. “Abortion in Women’s Lives.” Guttmacher.org. Guttmacher Institute. (2006) : 1-45. Web. 26 June. 2012. Boyle, Joseph. “Exceptionless Rule Approaches.“ A Companion to Bioethics: Second Edition. Helga Kuhse and Peter Singer (ed.) Blackwell. 2009. GoogleScholar Web. July 2012. Cohen, Susan A. “Repeat Abortion, Repeat Unintended Pregnancy, Repeated and Misguided Government Policies.” Guttmacher Policy Review. 10.2 (2007) : n.pag. Guttmacher.org. Web. 6 Aug. 2012. Copeland, Libby. “The Suicidal Pregnant Woman and the Politics of Motherhood.” Slate. May 25, 2012. Web. 25 May 2012. Daniels, Norman. “Reflective Equilibrium.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 Edition). Edward N. Zalta (ed.) Web. 6 Aug. 2012. Dawson, Karen. “Fertilisation and moral status: a scientific perspective.” Journal of Medical Ethics. 13 (1987) : 173-178. PubMed. Web. 1 July 2012 Dworkin, Ronald. Life’s Dominion: An argument About Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom. First Vintage Book Edition. New York, 1993. Print. Eckholm, Erik. “Push for Personhood Amendment Represents New Tack in Abortion 68 Fight.” New York Times. October 25, 2011. Web. 1 July 2012. Finnis, John. “The Right and Wrongs of Abortion: A Reply to Judith Thomson.” Philosophy and Public Affairs. 2.2 (1973) : 1-12. JSTOR. Web. March 2012. Grabiner, Gene. “A Question of Choice.” Reproductive Health. 8:20 (2011). PubMed Web. 1 Aug. 2012. Guttmacher.org. Guttmacher Institute, 1996. Web. 23 Nov. 2011 Hare, Richard. “Abortion and the Golden Rule.” Philosophy & Public Affairs. 4.3 (1975) : 201-222. JSTOR. Web. 2 Aug. 2012. Hartogh, den Govert. “The Values of Life.” Bioethics. 11.1 (1997) : 43- 66. Google Scholar. Web. 1 Aug. 2012. Hewson, Barbara. “Reproductive Autonomy and the Ethics of Abortion.” Journal of Medical Ethics. 27. (2001) : ii10-ii14. Web. Nov. 2011. Hill, E. Thomas. Autonomy and Self-Respect. New York: Cambridge, 1991. Print. Jones, K. Rachel, Lori F. Frohwirth and Anne M. Moore. “I Would Want to Give My Child, Like, Everything in the World.” Journal of Family Issues. 29.1 (2008) : 7999. Web. Nov. 2011. Lindsay, A. Ronald. “Bioethics Policies and the Compass of Common Morality.” Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics. 30 (2009) : 31-43. PubMed. Web. 4 Aug. 2012. Little, Margaret O. “Abortion, Intimacy, and the Duty to Gestate.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. 2.3. (1999) : 295-312. Google Scholar. Web. Nov. 2012. ---. “Abortion & the Margins of Personhood.” Rutgers Law Journal, 39. (2008) : 331-348. Google Scholar. Web. Nov. 2012. 69 McCullough, Laurence B. and Frank A. Chervenak. “A Critical Analysis of the Concept and Discourse of ‘Unborn Child.’” American Journal of Bioethics. 8.7 (2008) : 34-39. PubMed. Web. 4 Aug. 2012. PersonhoodUSA.com. “What is Personhood?” PersonhoodUSA. 2011. Web. 6 Aug. 2012. Panza, Christopher and Adam Potthast. Ethics for Dummies. Wiley Publishing. Indiana, 2010. Print. Pollitt, Katha. “Fetal Right, Women’s Wrongs.” Eileen.undonet.com n.p. n.d. Web. 23 Nov. 2011 Elisabeth Porter. “Abortion ethics: Right and Responsibilities.” Hypatia. 9.3 (1994) : 6687. Google Scholar. Web. Nov. 2011. Robinson, G. Eugenie. “A Defense of Women’s Choice: Abortion and the Ethics of Care.” The Southern Journal of Philosophy. 30.3 (1992) : 39-66 GoogleScholar. Web. Nov. 2011. Saad, Lydia. “More Americans “Pro-Life” Than “Pro-Choice” for First Time.” Gallup.com May 15, 2009. Web. 7 Aug. 2012. Scott, Jacqueline. “Conflicting Beliefs About Abortion: Legal Approval and Moral Doubts.” Social Psychology Quarterly. 52.4 (1989) : 319-326. JSTOR. Web. Nov. 2012. Sherwin, Susan. “Abortion Through a Feminist Ethics Lens.” Ethical Issues: Perspectives for Canadians Third Edition. Ed. Eldon Soifer. Buffalo, NY: Broadview, 2009. 232-245. Web. Nov. 2011. Shields, Jon A. “Almost Human: Ambivalence in the Pro-choice and Pro-life 70 Movements.” Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society. 23.4 (2011) : 495-515. PubMed. Web. 5 Aug. 2012. Young, Robert. “The Value of Autonomy.” The Philosophical Quarterly. 32.126 (1982): 35-44. JSTOR. Web. Nov. 2012. Warren, Mary Anne. “On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion.” Biomedical Ethics. 4. T.A. Mappes and D. DeGrazia, Eds. New York:McGraw-Hill, Inc. 1996 pp. 434440. instruct.westvalley.edu/lafave/warren_article.html.n.pag. March 22, 2004. Web. 4 Aug. 2012. ---. “The Moral Significance of Birth.” Hypatia. 4.3 (1989) : 46-65. Google Scholar. Web.6 Aug. 2012. 71