Jordan Mobley The Second Amendment and the Myth of Neutral Self-Defense Jordan Mobley Although recent high profile shootings resulting in mass casualties have occurred with alarming frequency in the United States,1 there has been an eerie silence from the absence of any public conversation about the effects of gun control, or lack thereof, on the nation. In this Article, I argue that the lack of public debate is not simply due to the surge in advocacy for individual gun ownership rights over the last (three) decades, nor the strength of second amendment rights the gun lobby claims. Rather, I argue such silence is driven by a deeply rooted racialized fear of minority violence on the part of whites, which simultaneously neglects the fact that the groups most vulnerable to such policies that make guns freely available are people of color living in impoverished communities. Thus, the current state of second amendment law, and the progeny2 thereof is the product not of an impartial legal system, but implicit (or sometimes explicit) racial bias. Non-neutral policy preferences favoring individual gun ownership over the lives of (number of gun deaths each year) are manifested through Supreme Court decisions, the policies fervently promoted by the pro-gun lobby like the now infamous “stand your ground” laws, and the utter neglect of the impact of easily available guns on vulnerable communities. These same anti-control advocates, whether it be the Court in Heller and McDonald or political advocacy groups, rely on a farce that race is not a factor in these discussion—that the Second Amendment is colorblind. It is dangerous to neglect the prominence of race in the national discourse on gun control. Not only is it hypocritical, because, as discussed infra,3 race is used to the benefit of anti-control advocates by ginning up fears and thus creating a perception that individual gun ownership is a necessity for purposes of self-defense. But beyond that, anticontrol advocates rely on a notion that the Second Amendment and its progeny (i.e. stand your ground and other hyper-self-defense laws) are neutral. That the inherent rights of gun ownership and the color blind nature of our constitution do not implicate race. Yet, if race is not a factor considered when examining the prudence, legality, and morality behind individual gun ownership, the role of implicit and explicit racial bias, and non-automatic legal judgments are assumed to be absent. In this article I hope to show that the legal and moral bases for anti-control laws are based largely on value judgments influenced by a narrow, misunderstanding of the historical concept of self-defense and the tradition of individual gun ownership. Part II of this article provides a brief 1 As I was working on this article, the nation was rocked by the tragic shooting at Sandy Hook Elementary. While this article does not propose specific controls, or address anything closely related to the tragedy, I do hope it serves to break down some of the barriers to the National dialogue on much needed gun control. 2 By progeny, I include, without reference to chronology, much of the movement toward less regulated individual gun ownership. 3 See infra note 103 and accompanying text. 1 Jordan Mobley critical background of the colorblind constitution, explaining the error in believing constitutional text lends itself to neutral interpretations in light of a highly racialized society. Part III analyzes the Supreme Court’s decision in Heller though a lens critical of its purportedly neutral, and absolute textual interpretation. Part IV looks at historical and current notions of self-defense, focusing on the dissonance between the narrow “self-defense” touted by the proponents of individual gun ownership and the historical realities of self-defense. This section also examines the different ways that implicit racial bias precludes any sense of neutrality in self-defense, as commonly understood. Section V concludes and proposes that exposing the racial motivations underlying the voices against reform will open dramatic new avenues for substantial and necessary reform. II. A Critical Background There is a common understanding that the Constitution is colorblind. In this respect, it renders the special considerations of race irrelevant to the discussion of the Second Amendment.4 As long as there are no overt racial biases in the processes that the Constitution guarantees, any racial disparity in the results are irrelevant.5 The apparent neutrality of the Constitution, lends itself to the supposedly mandated textual interpretation of the Second Amendment at the heart of the decision in Heller. It enables the Court to apply its own policy judgments and historical presumptions to the text of the Constitution, and still claim neutrality. The notion of the colorblind constitution is a prudent one in a post-racial society—if race does not matter in society, then why should it matter in our application of laws? Yet, given the lingering racialization of society, the colorblind constitution is inapposite with current and historical reality.6 The Civil Rights Era brought a great many victories for racial equality in the United States. As a result, there is a commonly held misconception that those victories represented total victory. Thus, the total victory of the Civil Rights Era means that we now live in a post-racial society—one where de jure discrimination is ancient history, and the only racial prejudice lies with a few overtly bigoted outliers. This is simply not the case. Significant structural racial hierarchies still exists in most facets of society, and racial prejudice, unconscious or not, is not hard to find in the average American.7 Thus, because the colorblind constitution prevents any See generally Neil Gotanda, A Critique of “Our Constitution is Color-Blind,” 44 STAN. L. REV. 1. 5 Kimberlé Williams Crenshaw, Race, Reform, and Retrenchment: Transformation and Legitimation in Antidiscrimination Law, 101 HARV. L. REV. 1331, 1341–42 (1988) (explaining the “restrictive” vision of antidiscrimination law, which focuses only on equality of process, not of results). 6 “This belief in color-blindness and equal process, however, would make no sense at all in a society in which identifiable groups had actually been treated differently historically, and in which the effects of this difference in treatment continued into the present.” Id. at1345. 7 Id. at 1384. 4 2 Jordan Mobley significant consideration of race, it makes it impossible to respond to the actual problems created by racial disparity, further structuralizing racism in today’s society.8 III. Heller and Its Progeny I am not going so far as to argue that the majority in DC v. Heller was operating under a racial bias—I cannot discern the hearts and minds of those five justices. I am, however, suggesting that the opinion could be read to reflect value judgments which in the aggregate may suggest a racial bias. Heller is perhaps one of the most thoroughly originalist decisions written by the Court. Despite its superficial mooring in the text of the Second Amendment itself, the majority goes well beyond the text to make value judgments, favoring one understanding of history over another. In Heller.9 Scalia relies on a quasi-textual, quasi-historical analysis of the Second Amendment to determine that the Second Amendment guarantees the right of individuals to freely possess firearms for self-defense. In McDonald, Alito applies a test examining whether the right to keep and bear arms is fundamental to our scheme of ordered liberty, or whether the right is “deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition.”10 Despite broad claims to the contrary by the NRA and other gun-right advocates, the right to keep and bear arms was historically understood as a collective, rather than individual right.11 Prior to Heller, the Court never acknowledged any individual right in the three instances the Court addressed the Second Amendment.12 In fact, many considered the collective right model to be the singular and uncontroversial approach to understanding the Second Amendment.13 It 8 Id. at District of Columbia v. Heller, 128 S. Ct. 2783 (2008). 10 McDonald v. City of Chicago, 130 S. Ct. 3020, 3035 (2010). 11 See Heller, 128 S. Ct. 2822 (Stevens, J. dissenting). 12 See Benforado Adam Benforado, Quick on the Draw: Implicit Bias and the Second Amendment, 89 OR. L. REV. 1, 12 (2010). Speaking of the Second Amendment, in 1943 the Third Circuit Court of Appeals made it clear that it believed there was no individual right embodied in the Second Amendment: “It is abundantly clear both from the discussions of this amendment contemporaneous with its proposal and adoption and those of learned writers since that this amendment, unlike those providing for protection of free speech and freedom of religion, was not adopted with individual rights in mind, but as a protection for the States in the maintenance of their militia organizations against possible encroachments by the federal power . . . . The almost uniform course of decision in this country, where provisions similar in language are found in many of the State Constitutions, bears out this concept of the constitutional guarantee.” United States v. Tot, 131 F.2d 261, 266 (3d Cir. 1942), rev’d on other grounds, 319 U.S. 463 (1943); see also Carl T. Bogus, The History and Politics of Second Amendment Scholarship: A Primer, 76 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 3, 4 n.7 (2000). 13 Bogus, supra note 12, at 4. 9 3 Jordan Mobley was not until the 1960s that the first article proposing an individual right model of the Second Amendment appeared.14 The crux of the majority opinion in Heller is the prefatory clause to the Second Amendment, which ostensibly qualifies the right contained there: “A well regulated Militia, being necessary to the security of a free State, the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed.”15 Justice Scalia, author of the opinion, wrote that the prefatory clause announces for the world why the amendment was being codified.16 It was codified to protect the presence of the militia, but the prefatory clause has no limitation on the inherent right of arms.17 The operative clause, “the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed,” is where Justice Scalia finds the inherent, individual right. Part of this discovery, is based on the interpretation of “the right of the people” as connoting individual, rather than collective rights.18 This interpretation is based on the appearance of the use of similar phrasing to connote individualism elsewhere in the Constitution, namely in the First, Fourth, and Ninth Amendments. Based on this collective interpretation of the operative clause, Justice Scalia argues then that the clearly not-individual use of “militia” in the prefatory clause, renders that clause incapable of limiting the operative clause.19 Before his analysis of the rest of the text, history and tradition behind the Second Amendment, Justice Scalia wrote, “we start therefore with a strong presumption that the Second Amendment right is exercised individually and belongs to all Americans.”20 With this presumption, Justice Scalia continues to “strongly read” the text—interpreting the phrase to “keep and bear Arms” to mean possess and carry, in any context, not just a military context, as the prefatory clause may suggest. Thus, the operative clause, which per Justice Scalia’s treatment of the prefatory clause is the singularly significant clause in the Second Amendment, guarantees “the individual right to possess and carry weapons in case of confrontation.”21 Having established the individual right from a narrow focus on the operative clause, Justice Scalia turns to the historical background of the Second Amendment to confirm his conclusion.22 According to Justice Scalia, the historical background is of utmost importance because the Second Amendment did not create the right, but merely “codified a pre-existing 14 Id. at 6. This article was a student article titled, The Right to Bear Arms, A Study in Judicial Misinterpretation. 15 U.S. Const. amend. II. 16 District of Columbia v. Heller, 128 S. Ct. 2783, 2788 (2008). 17 Id. at 2788. (explaining that the Second Amendment has “two parts: its prefatory clause and its operative clause. The former does not limit the latter grammatically, but rather announces a purpose.”). 18 Id. at 2790. 19 Id. at 2791. 20 Id. 21 Id. at 2797. 22 Heller, 128 S. Ct. at 2797. 4 Jordan Mobley right.”23 History leads Justice Scalia to believe that the purpose of the prefatory clause was to state a purpose for the right contained in the operative clause: to prevent the elimination of the militia.24 In contrast, Justice Stevens argues in dissent that the scope of the Second Amendment is limited to the right to maintain a well-regulated militia. [A] conclusion that the Second Amendment protects an individual right does not tell us anything about the scope of that right. . . . Guns are used to hunt, for self-defense, to commit crimes, for sporting activities, and to perform military duties. The Second Amendment plainly does not protect the right to use a gun to rob a bank; it is equally clear that it does encompass the right to use weapons for certain military purposes. Whether it also protects the right to possess and use guns for nonmilitary purposes like hunting and self-defense is the question presented in this case. The text of the Amendment, [and] its history . . . provide a clear answer to that question.25 Using ostensibly the same tools—text, history, and precedent—the dissent, representing four members of the Court, comes to a conclusion contrary to the majority’s. The dissent concludes that “when each word in the text is given full effect, the Amendment is most naturally read to secure to the people a right to use and possess arms in conjunction with service in a wellregulated militia.”26 Mirroring the majority’s approach, Justice Stevens’ dissent analyzes each of the distinctive clauses and phrases of the Amendment, and with each concludes something different than Justice Scalia. Without belaboring the specific differences, the point is that these phrases are not as clear as either Justice pretends. The greatly disparate interpretations of the same words indicate that there is no single interpretation mandated by the text. Constitutional text is incapable of, on its own, guaranteeing any absolute rights. With this understanding, Heller and its progeny can be understood as a choice, not a mandate. There are competing Constitutional interests at play. They must be resolved through careful balancing, not pretextual application of rote textual formulae. Having established that there was no absolute basis for the “originalist” decision, it becomes clearer that the majority27 in both important cases was expressing policy preferences – especially considering the stated, and acknowledged, legitimate government purpose behind the laws that were struck down. Tradition and history supposedly gave us the contours of the Second Amendment right. But there is a problem with relying on such a feeble tool, for such important decisions. At some point, history is not going to give us a credible answer once we get to nuanced questions. At the end of the day the court will have to balance, because history is simply unable to handle those questions of policy preference. The majorities of Heller and 23 Id. Id. at 2801. 25 Heller, 128 S. Ct. at 2822 (Stevens, J. dissenting.). 26 Id. at 2831. 27 McDonald garnered a plurality of justices. 24 5 Jordan Mobley McDonald chose property rights over human rights.28 The danger here is the same danger with current notions of discrimination – the majority hides behind a supposedly neutral application of the law, disguising the value-laden decisions on which these cases were actually based. When the Heller and MacDonald decisions are taken from the security of the colorblind constitution and confronted with a highly complex, racialized society, the authoritative bases with which those decisions were announced quickly erode. The impact of anti-control laws visà-vis the prevalence of weapons available in communities of color, namely shockingly high rates of gun violence, cannot simply be viewed as an unfortunate effect of the absolute, unambiguous wishes of our framers.29 Instead, these decisions reflect value judgments made by the Court, placing a higher value on a rigid interpretation of history which includes an inherent right to selfdefense over the actual effects of guns on the United States. The actual impact is staggering. Census data for 2009 shows that there were 11,031 firearm related murders in the United States.30 The same data shows that firearm related murders accounted for over 80% of the total murders for that year.31 In Chicago, the murder rate in 2012 surpassed the 2011 total, in August.32 As an international comparison, the U.S. has several thousand more gun homicides than the rest of the G-12 member nations combined.33 This is a problem that is not going away. IV. Self-Defense, the White Privilege A. The History and Myth of Self-Defense If Heller and McDonald guarantee an individual right to own a gun for the purpose of self-defense, what does that mean in the context of a highly racialized society? Self-defense has historically been a white privilege, for years encountering no question that American Indian tribes34 or African-Americans35 enjoyed the same right. The myth of self-defense has become a 28 See infra text at note 102. Having shown the impact of guns on impoverished communities, I think there is no doubt that gun violence in the United States is a human rights issue, after all, it affects what should be our most protected right – the right to life. 29 District of Columbia v. Heller, 554 U.S. 570, 634–35 (2008). 30 LAW ENFORCEMENT, COURTS & PRISONS: CRIMES AND CRIME RATES, THE UNITED STATES CENSUS BUREAU, Murder victims—circumstances and weapons used or cause of death tbl.310 (2012), available at http://www.census.gov/compendia/statab/2012/tables/12s0310.pdf (showing that in 2009 there were a total of 9,203 murders by firearm where the firearm type was known, and another 1,828 murders by firearm where the type of firearm was unknown). 31 Id. 32 http://chicagoist.com/2012/08/21/saturday_murders_in_chicago_tie_201.php 33 http://www.gunpolicy.org/firearms/compare/194/number_of_gun_homicides/10,11,18,31,280,6 6,69,88,91,125,172,177,178,192. 34 Ann E. Tweedy, “[H]ostile Indian Tribes . . . Outlaws, Wolves . . . Bears . . . Grizzilies and Things Like That?” How the Second Amendment and Supreme Court Precedent Target Tribal Self-Defense, 4 THE CRIT: CRITICAL STUD. J. 1, 4 (2011). 35 Id. at 2–5. 6 Jordan Mobley means of covering the exceptionally biased nature of historical gun ownership, while simultaneously romanticizing it. Myths are stories drawn from a society’s history that have acquired through persistent usage the power of symbolizing that society’s ideology and of dramatizing its moral consequences-with all the complexities and contradictions that consciousness may contain. Over time . . . the original mythic story is increasingly conventionalized and abstracted until it is reduced to a deeply encoded and resonant set of symbols, “icons,” “keywords,” or historical clichés. In this form, myth becomes a basic constituent of linguistic meaning and of the processes of both personal and social “remembering.”36 In this context, the myth of self-defense is not used in any way to convey fiction, but instead as Tweedy used it, as a means of conveying the historical and cultural complexity of selfdefense.37 Comparing the myth of self-defense to historical realities of early America reveals the dissonance between the two. Despite these disparities, however, the myth of self-defense remains pervasive throughout the conversation on individual gun rights today. “From Plymouth Colony to the sandy plains of Kuwait, firearms in the hands of free Americans have purchased, maintained and preserved our freedom, liberty and unique way of life.”38 The first sentence in an article promoting the opening of a then new firearms museum, accompanies a picture of early, well-armed settlers arriving to the shores of the “new” world. In another article in American Rifleman, the author paints a romanticized picture of the relationship between a particular early settler and his firearm. “Those hearty souls who left England in 1620 in search of a fresh beginning in the New World did so knowing that just the act of surviving could be their greatest accomplishment. . . . Like most of the able-bodied men in the new colony . . . [John Alden] carried his own musket.”39 These articles begin to convey part of the myth of self-defense, involving an adventurous pioneer seeking freedom, and relying on his firearm to defend himself and his family from the “savages” of the “new” world.40 The prevalence of the “savage” as a motivator for gun ownership was evident even in the Supreme Court’s questioning during Heller. Justice Kennedy rhetorically asked whether there was no concern embodied in the Second Amendment “of the remote settler to defend himself and 36 RICHARD SLOTKIN, GUNFIGHTER NATION: THE MYTH OF THE FRONTIER IN TWENTIETHCENTURY AMERICA 5 (1992). 37 See Tweedy, supra note 34, at 2 n.3. 38 Philip Schreier, Freedom’s Guns, American Rifleman 32, May 1998, available at http://www.nramuseum.org/media/940537/freedoms%20guns.pdf. 39 Philip Schreier, From the Old World to the New, American Rifleman 43 March 2001, available at http://www.nramuseum.org/media/940597/new%20guns%20old%20world.pdf 40 See Tweedy, supra note 34, at 9 (“[T]ribes have historically been constructed as a caricatured other that European colonists and then white American citizens need to defend against.”). 7 Jordan Mobley his family against hostile Indian tribes and outlaws, wolves and bears and grizzlies . . . .”41 There is wide agreement that the Second Amendment “grew directly out of Americans’ colonial experiences of defending themselves through militias.”42 As tensions between the colonies and colonial powers heightened, the myth of selfdefense began to include more political notions of freedom, namely freedom from oppression. The ability to participate in a militia and defend one’s country, or political freedom generally became one of the primary facets of the myth of self-defense. The myth thus conveys a dual understanding of the gun owner as “both the guardian of the free state and the defender of home and hearth.”43 The myth was an enabling one. It allowed individuals to create a safety for themselves that they would not have had otherwise. It allowed settlers to live off the land through hunting, and to defend themselves from hostiles, whether they are wild animals, Native Americans, or other settlers. The romanticism that flows from the “tradition” of gun ownership is largely due to this ability for the gun and self-defense to enable an individual to take advantage of new land, new opportunities. In this sense, the myth of self-defense is intricately tied to the American Dream, perhaps explaining its stronghold in the American psyche. The myth of the Second Amendment is just that—a myth. Self-defense, in this context, is not the clean, innocent (read: neutral, unbiased) concept that we tend to think of—it is not justified killing. Instead, it functions as a means of justifying campaigns of racial and ethnic oppression and extermination. Far from self-defense, the gun was a means of preserving white European values in the “new” world—“the gun culture originated in the concerns of white citizens to control those of other races, especially blacks and Native Americans. ”44 The myth of self-defense, and much of American history portrays Native Americans as the aggressors, justifying the appropriateness of the centuries of self-defense resulting in total displacement, and almost complete eradication of Native American populations. From the point of view of colonists and early Americans, there was no bridging the “ineluctable political and social differences” between the natives and the newcomers—the only basis for coexistence was subjugation.45 In Heller, Justice Scalia is so willing to practically excise the prefatory clause of the Second Amendment because of the seemingly inherent nature of the right to bear arms for the purpose of self-defense—certainly, the reasoning goes, such a recognized right cannot be so 41 Tweedy, supra note 34, at 11 (citing Transcript of Oral Argument at 8, Heller, 554 U.S. 570, (Mar. 18, 2008) (No. 07-290)). 42 Id. at 12. 43 Maxine Burkett, Much Ado About . . . Something Else: D.C. v. Heller, the Racialized Mythology of the Second Amendment, and Gun Policy Reform, 12 J. GENDER RACE & JUST. 57, 76 (2008). 44 David C. Williams, Constitutional Tales of Violence: Populists, Outgroups, and the Multicultural Landscape of the Second Amendment, 74 TUL. L. REV. 387, 406 (1999). 45 Tweedy, supra note 34, at 12–13 (quoting RICHARD SLOTKIN, GUNFIGHTER NATION: THE MYTH OF THE FRONTIER IN TWENTIETH-CENTURY AMERICA 5 (1992)). 8 Jordan Mobley couched as the prefatory clause would suggest.46 Justice Scalia looks to English common-law as one of the authorities for the substance of the Second Amendment—looking to how this right was viewed in the context of not simply a specific right granted by a legal document, but a “natural” right that all free men enjoy.47 Yet, the dark history of the United States shows that the right to self-defense was a “white” right, one specifically kept from African-Americans48 and Native Americans.49 The gun was a symbol not of equalizing opportunity,50 but of gaining an advantage—the technology allowed white plantation owners to control greater numbers of slaves without fear of revolt;51 it allowed small groups of early settlers to exert a tactical advantage over the native populations.52 Far from equalizing, “the gun [permitted] its holder to transcend his perceived position of inferiority and to gain superiority over, rather than equality with, his adversaries.”53 The so-claimed inherent right to bear arms for self-defense recognized so easily by Heller is eroded by the selective nature through which we have historically viewed self-defense. It was not an inherent right available to anyone. Instead, it is a tool, by which subjugation is enabled and justified. Historically, self-defense has been a white privilege, not an inherent right. The moral authority that the myth of self-defense provides to Heller and other notions of individual gun rights is thus stripped of significance when understood as a pretext for subjugation and extermination—no individual has a right to this kind of self-defense. B. Racialized Self-defense Today Why does the myth of self-defense54 matter? Because the same dynamics are still at play—self-defense is not anymore neutral today than it was three hundred years ago. It is no “[T]he Second Amendment was not intended to lay down a ‘novel principle’ but rather a right ‘inherited from our English ancestors.’” Heller, 554 U.S. at 599 (quoting Robertson v. Baldwin, 165 U.S. 275, 281 (1897)). 47 Id. at 615. 48 Burkett, supra note 43, at 78. 49 Tweedy, supra note 34, at 41–51 (detailing the specific prohibitions against Native Americans possessing weapons, thus having the right to defend themselves despite recurrent violence against these populations). 50 Gun ownership is often thought of as the great equalizer. This is embodied in the “Cowboy Corollary” to the Declaration of Independence, which essentially says that God made men, but the gun made them equal. See Burkett, supra note 43, at 77–78. 51 This scenario is what Samuel Colt, inventor of the Colt Revolver, claimed was his inspiration for his invention. See e.g., Burkett, supra note 43, at 78. 52 See Tweedy, supra note 34, at 41–51. 53 Burkett, supra note 43, at 77. 54 In this section, I will be only addressing the individual aspect of self-defense—the defense hearth and home, rather than homeland. This is the case for two reasons. First, practical constraints of this paper. Second, it seems clear that in light of technological advances in weaponry, i.e. heavy automatic weapons, unmanned drones, and other technology, the Second Amendment protects political self-defense in name only. Heller fully acknowledged that limits, 46 9 Jordan Mobley great mystery that the obscene gun violence in places like Chicago is the result of weak gun regulation. I don’t think any reasonable person would argue that making guns harder to get will result in less violence. So then why is it that we do not respond to these patent truths? Because a substantial and loud segment of the population cling to this mythical notion of self-defense. We rubber stamp laws, like the now infamous “stand your ground,” and fail to respond to overwhelming gun violence, while hiding behind the shield of the inherent right to self-defense. But if we understand the ugly side of self-defense, perhaps it is no longer sufficient to support an anti-control movement that defies logic and reality. 1. Implicit Racial Bias It is with some hesitance that I approach this subject. There is a great deal of connotation associated with saying something has racial implications. It is precisely the point of the theory of implicit racial bias, however, that there is not necessarily racial animus or bigotry involved in these decisions. There is something of a misnomer concerning bias when it comes to current conceptions of discrimination. Bias is generally understood to have conscious motivations, as reflected in the structure of anti-discrimination law, which “constructs intergroup bias as something that occurs when a ‘discriminatory purpose’ motivates a decision.”55 However, much discrimination, and racial bias generally, occurs without a discriminatory purpose or intent, but instead “when an individual’s group status subtly, even unconsciously, affects a decision makers’ subjective perception of relevant traits, on which ostensibly non-discriminatory decisions are subsequently based.”56 Thus, the line between intentional discrimination and implicit racial bias lies with cognizance of that bias and the response to it.57 However, in some cases, even intentional discrimination does not involve actual animus, merely capitalizing on the predictive nature of racial stereotypes.58 Whether or not our law reflects a the common notion that racial bias is only present where there is conscious purpose, or whether our common notion reflects it because our law says it is so, it is hardly arguable that it is the case. The colorblind approach to the law is insufficient such as prohibiting civilian use of automatic weapons, are constitutionally appropriate restrictions. Thus, despite the militia focused language of the Second Amendment, modern Second Amendment jurisprudence prohibits an average citizen from coming close to matching the armament used by militaries around the world. This effectively renders the political selfdefense aspect of the Second Amendment useless. See e.g., John Zulkey, The Obsolete Second Amendment: How Advances in Arms Technology Have Made the Prefatory Clause Incompatible with Public Policy, 2010 U. ILL. J.L. TECH. & POL’Y 213 (2010). 55 Linda Hamilton Krieger, Civil Rights Perestroika: Intergroup Relations After Affirmative Action, 86 CAL. L. REV. 1251, 1278–79 (1998). 56 Id. at 1279. 57 “Insofar as cognitive sources of bias are concerned, the difference between people who discriminate and those who do not is that members of the latter group notice the influences of stereotypes on their thinking and counteract those influences by consciously adjusting responses in a nonprejudiced direction.” Id. at 1285. 58 See infra, note 77 and accompanying text. 10 Jordan Mobley because it fails to consider the effects of a “society in which history, ideology, law, and patterns of social, economic, and political distribution have made race, sex, and ethnicity salient.”59 The colorblind approach to law also overestimates an individual’s ability to consciously engage with every decision she makes throughout her lifetime.60 Given the complexity of society, and the subtlety of biases, it is necessary to look beyond shallow notions of racial bias, to rely on factors more complex than animus and intent. With so many things to worry about on a daily basis from rising gas prices to terrorist attacks, our brains need to make short cuts. Significant studies have shown that individuals are unable to consciously deal with the constant bombardment of information that we are exposed to on a daily basis.61 To compensate we reflexively make associations between subconscious beliefs about various group attributes and the best way to respond to particular groups so that we can “quickly make sense of the people we meet.”62 Without these associations, the information that an individual perceives is meaningless—that is, without meaning.63 In other words, our observations remain generic and neutral instead of value laden and ultimately useful perceptions, unless the individual has a “preexisting knowledge structure” with which to process the observation.64 These structures are referred to as “trait constructs.”65 These trait constructs allow individuals to quickly assess a situation and know how to respond by applying the stereotypes of the trait construct to the ambiguous information being received.66 There is nothing inherently wrong with this. It is merely a way for an individual’s brain to process information more efficiently, especially in a society where information abounds. 59 Krieger, supra note 55, at 1277. See Benforado, supra note 12. 61 See Krieger, supra note 55 at 1284 n.120 (citing several studies of automatic mental processes). See also Benforado supra note 12 at 37–38. “Since 1998, more than 4.5 million [Implicit Association Tests] have been taken, and the results show pervasive implicit racial bias: indeed, about seventy percent of those who have taken the race-bias version of the test were found to exhibit ‘an unconscious, or implicit, preference for white people compared to blacks.’” Id. at 39. 60 The Implicit Association Test [IAT] is the method most frequently employed by researchers to measure implicit bias. “The IAT works by measuring response latencies as individuals attempt to categorize concepts on a computer—concepts that are strongly associated are quickly sorted, and those that are not strongly associated take subjects more time. In a typical IAT, a participant in a study is provided with exemplars of two social categories (for example, whites or blacks, homosexuals or heterosexuals, old people or young people), which they must then associate with certain abstract evaluative concepts (often words that have positive or negative valences, like ‘joy,’ ‘love,’ ‘happiness,’ ‘agony,’ ‘pain,’ and ‘evil’).” Id. at 38–39. 62 Benforado, supra note 12 at 38. 63 See Krieger, supra note 55 at 1280. 64 Id. 65 Id. 66 Benforado, supra note 12, at 38. 11 Jordan Mobley The problem arises because a person readily characterizes information into a trait construct when that construct is readily available in the memory at the time of the behavior.67 Thus, in a society where stereotypes are prevalent, they are likely to be unconsciously adopted for these purposes, whether or not they are consciously believed: Any activity, conscious or unconscious, that “primes” a particular trait construct will tend to increase its accessibility and the corresponding likelihood that ambiguous information will be assimilated or encoded in a manner consistent with that trait. . . . Once activated, stereotypes serve to “prime” the trait constructs with which they are associated. Incoming behavioral information, especially if capable of various interpretations, is accordingly assimilated into those traits associated with the stereotype.68 The interplay between trait constructs and negative racial stereotypes creates an untenable situation where an individual’s daily processing of information is done unconsciously through a racially biased lens. The prevalence of negative stereotypes only serves to ensure the accessibility of those stereotypes to be assimilated through automatic mental processes, which in turn lead to behavior based on those stereotypes, enforcing the viability of those stereotypes for others. It is a perpetual cycle. The negative influence of implicit racial bias is not only prevalent, but also difficult to detect and overcome. The suggestions for how to counteract these processes that can lead to discrimination illustrate how much of a problem implicit racial bias can be. Four conditions have been proposed, which if satisfied will mitigate these mental processes: First, one must become aware of the nature of the particular mental process which threatens to bias one’s judgment. Second, one must be motivated to correct its unwanted influence once it has been recognized. Third, one must be able to discern the direction and magnitude of the bias, lest it be “overcorrected” and judgment skewed in the opposite direction. And finally, one must have sufficient control over his or her mental processes to correct the effect of the unwanted influences.69 67 See Krieger, supra note 55 at 1280. Id. 69 Id. 1286 (citing Timothy D. Wilson & Nancy Brekke, Mental Contamination and Mental Correction: Unwanted Influences on Judgments and Evaluations, 116 PSYCHOLOGICAL BULL. 117, 119–20 (1994)). 68 12 Jordan Mobley The burden of overcoming the negative influence of these automatic mental processes hints at a reason why racial stereotypes still exists in a post-Civil Rights Era.70 Arguably, there are few who still argue that race makes an employee more or less qualified or a person on the street more or less dangerous, yet many still act this way. An easy example is the way that code words or topics, like welfare or public housing are often used as ways to talk about race, without explicitly invoking the taboo.71 Indeed, one of the most common racially stereotyped associations links crime to being black.72 The stereotype of Black Americans as violent and criminal has been documented by social psychologists for almost 60 years. Researchers have highlighted the robustness and frequency of this stereotypic association by demonstrating its effects on numerous outcome variables, including people’s memory for who was holding a deadly razor in a subway scene, people’s evaluations of ambiguously aggressive behavior, people’s decision to categorize nonweapons as weapons, the speed at which people decide to shoot someone holding a weapon, and the probability that they will shoot at all. Not only is the association between Blacks and crime strong (i.e. consistent and frequent), it also appears to be automatic.73 It is important to recognize that implicit racial bias is not just relevant to in-the-moment decision making, but much more broadly, because it effects our information processing generally. As it relates to anti-control, the real danger is in believing that control policies are neutral, that they have no racial implications. If this is the case, then anti-control advocates, gun owners, and the public in general think that race is only relevant when individuals are explicitly thinking about it. While explicit uses of race are relevant to this discussion74 the greater danger 70 See Cynthia Kwei Yung Lee, Race and Self-Defense: Toward a Normative Conception of Reasonableness, 81 MINN. L. REV. 367, 402–05 (1996) (“Over time, as society has publicly denounced racism, overt racial prejudice appears to have declined. Negative stereotypes of African Americans, however, still persist. One of the stereotypes most often applied to African American males is that they are more dangerous, more prone to violence, and more likely to be criminals or gang members than other members of society.”). 71 Dorothy E. Roberts, Welfare and the Problem of Black Citizenship, 105 YALE L.J. 1563 (1996) (“[I]t is common place to observe that ‘welfare’ has become a code word for race.”). 72 See Benforado supra note 12, at 40. (citing Jennifer L. Eberhardt et at., Seeing Black: Race, Crime, and Visual Processing, 87 J. Personality & Soc. Psychol. 876, 877 (2004)). 73 Jennifer L. Eberhardt et at., Seeing Black: Race, Crime, and Visual Processing, 87 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 876 (2004) (internal citations omitted). See also Cynthia Kwei Yung Lee, Race and Self-Defense: Toward a Normative Conception of Reasonableness, 81 MINN. L. REV. 367, 402–05 (1996); L. Song Richardson & Phillip Atiba Goff, Self-Defense and the Suspicion Heuristic, 98 IOWA L. REV. 293, 298–307 (2012). 74 See infra notes 81–102 and accompanying text. 13 Jordan Mobley is the rhetoric which takes advantage of the spongy nature of heuristics75—creating stereotype after stereotype about race, violence, and self-defense which in turn engender profound racial biases. 2. Explicit Bias One of the primary motivating factors for explicit bias is economics. Despite arguments to the contrary,76 an understanding of explicit bias can be a great asset for economic motives. For this discussion, however, the notion of economics can be expanded to include political economics. Economist Ian Ayres conducted an experiment which revealed the use of implicit bias in retail car sales.77 The experiment revealed that dealerships purposely considered the race of a potential car buyer and paired that customer with a sales person of a race and gender thought to be most likely to make the sale in light of the race and gender of the customer. More specifically, dealers targeted buyers of a specific race and gender who were most likely to pay a high-markup price.78 Not only were the race and gender boundaries of these interactions optimized, but the information exchanged within these relationships differed based on the race/gender pairings.79 There was no animus involved, but the import of the experiment is that manipulating racial biases and the flow of information through those biases, whether implicit or explicit, can engender support for a particular position. In this example, favorable race/gender pairings made customers more amenable to making a car purchase. The same is arguably true of political economy. In the same way that the dealerships capitalize on racial biases to manipulate relationships between the buyer and seller to “generate revenue-based disparate treatment,”80 so too advocacy organizations can capitalize on racial biases to manipulate the relationship between the advocate, the message, and the public. This is precisely why the NRA embraces racial bias, it allows the organization to turn racially motivated fear into support. In a recent op-ed piece by NRA Executive Vice President, 75 Accessibility of stereotypes increases the amount they are used, which in turn increases accessibility—thus, acting like a self-perpetuating process. See Krieger, supra note 55 at 1284. 76 There is much literature arguing that the free-market economy erases discrimination through competition. See e.g., GARY BECKER, THE ECONOMICS OF DISCRIMINATION 21–23 (2d ed. 1971). 77 See Ian Ayres, Fair Driving: Gender and Race Discrimination in Retail Car Negotiations, 104 HARV. L. REV. 817 (1991). 78 Id. at 855. 79 Id. at 827 (“the tests reveal that salespeople asked different types of questions and used different tactics in attempting to sell the cars.”). Ayres explained that the types of questions and sales tactics employed by the sales people depended on the race and gender of both the sales person and the customer. For example, “sellers asked black female testers more often about their occupation, about financing and whether they were married,” while “sellers asked black male testers less often if they would like to test drive the car, whether they had been to other dealerships, and whether they had offers from other dealers.” Id. at 834. 80 Id. at 856. 14 Jordan Mobley Wayne LaPierre, said it was prudent to be armed in these dangerous times. He warned “good Americans” that Latin American gangs have infiltrated every major city, and that the border “remains porous not only to people seeking jobs in the U.S., but to criminals whose jobs are murder, rape, robbery and kidnapping.”81 Quite explicitly, LaPierre preys on an already alarming prevalence of racism toward Latinos, so that later in the article he has good reason to ask for donations. In the context of this discussion, this understanding of explicit bias affirms the continual presence racism has in this national dialogue. It reminds us that race is not absent from daily life, but is, in fact, deeply embedded in our national psyche. 3. A Rational Shooter? Much scholarship demonstrates the impact of implicit bias on the in-the-moment decisions involved with self-defense situations. It all points to the same conclusion: there are practical concerns that self-defense is not a neutral concept in application. The notion of the “rational shooter,” upon which much of the Second Amendment rhetoric is based, is flawed. The idea of the “rational shooter” is pervasive. It is hard to imagine that regulation of gun ownership would be decreasing if there was general consensus that gun owners were irrational, biased, and excessively fearful individuals. Yet, is this what humans are? There is a crazy notion that once you put a gun in someone’s hand, rationality returns, enabling the shooter to make the right instinctive decision about when and who to shoot in a threatening situation. Implicit bias theory has turned the notion of the “rational shooter” on its head. In the last decade, the theory of implicit bias has been applied to assess the impact of race on “shoot/don’t-shoot” decisions.82 The research in this area shows that shooters with implicit associations between race and weapons or crime show bias in their shooting behavior.83 Specifically, this bias is manifested by quicker and more accurate shooting, or deciding not to shoot where the “suspect” is unarmed: “Participants are faster and more accurate when shooting an armed Black man rather than an armed White man, and faster and more accurate when responding “don’t shoot” to an unarmed White man rather than an unarmed Black man.”84 Even more significant, these studies revealed that implicit bias had a stronger impact on shooting decisions than did explicit, negative sentiments toward African Americans.85 Similar to other judgments, determining whether or not someone is dangerous is not easy. Thus, judgments of criminality are easily influenced by implicit bias—as a means of quickly 81 Wayne LaPierre, Stand and Fight, The Daily Caller Feb. 13, 2013, available at http://dailycaller.com/2013/02/13 /stand-and-fight. 82 Benforado, supra note 12, at 42. 83 Id. at 43–44. 84 Id. at 43 (citing Joshua Correll et al., Event-Related Potentials and the Decision to Shoot: The Role of Threat Perception and Cognitive Control, 42 J. EXPERIMENTAL SOC. PSYCHOL. 120, 126 (2006)). 85 Id. at 44. 15 Jordan Mobley determining a threat.86 Quick associations, heuristics, are used between race, gender and criminality to make these determinations.87 The impact of shooter bias is not a new discovery. Police officers and other armed law enforcement officials go through extensive training before they are allowed to carry weapons in their official capacity. This training is meant to “help officers avoid the snap judgments in shooting decisions that often reflect implicit racial bias.”88 While, implicit racial bias is not necessarily the primary purpose of this training, studies have shown that such training counteracts implicit racial bias.89 The same studies that measured the impact of training on police officers’ implicit racial bias in shoot/don’t-shoot decisions, also found that the same results occurred for college students.90 These students, who were novice shooters, showed reduced racial bias in their decision making after they received training.91 Law enforcement officials go through rigorous qualification training before allowed to carry weapons, the same is not required of the average citizen who wishes to carry a gun. Even more troubling is the proliferation of laws making it easier for citizens to carry guns,92 and laws reducing the accountability for using those guns in cases of self-defense.93 It is impossible to think that such training would be absolutely required of every gun owner, if the impact of racial bias on shooters was understood. Race has real and demonstrable negative impact on the decision-making of shooters, thus it is necessary to proactively consider the ways that race affects notions of self-defense. Self-defense, generally, eliminates the criminal liability for the use of deadly force where the non-aggressor has a reasonable belief of the imminent use of deadly force from another.94 This typical construct of self-defense exculpates deadly force for any reasonable belief—thus, 86 L. Song Richardson & Phillip Atiba Goff, Self-Defense and the Suspicion Heuristic, 98 IOWA L. REV. 293, 310 (2012)(“Faced with a potentially life-threatening situation, people are unlikely to take the time necessary for deductive reasoning. Rather, they will make their judgments of criminality quickly, based upon only small slices of behavior, under highly stressful circumstances.”). 87 Id. 88 Id. at 50. 89 Id. at 48. (“Officers, just like the community sample, held implicit bias, but their training allowed them to override the automatic associations.”). 90 Id. 91 Id. 92 Illinois was the last holdout among states enacting concealed carry laws. Ray Long, Illinois Concealed Carry Ban Tossed by Federal Appeals Court, Chicago Tribune Dec. 12, 2012, http://articles.chicagotribune.com/2012-12-12/news/ct-met-conceal-carry-ruling20121212_1_gun-control-gun-ordinance-todd-vandermyde (“Illinois’ days as the only state in the nation to forbid public possession of a firearm could be numbered . . . .”). 93 Laws, such as the one central to the Trayvon Martin shooting, remove the duty to retreat and allow use of deadly force if in response to a reasonable fear of death or great bodily harm. See e.g., Florida Statutes Chapter 776. 94 See e.g., Richardson & Goff, supra note 86, at 314. 16 Jordan Mobley where “a person uses deadly force against an innocent victim, as long as the individual actually believed deadly force was necessary, and the mistake was reasonable,” the self-defense will still be available.95 The impact that implicit racial bias has on criminality judgments bear heavily on this notion of reasonableness.96 If, as has been demonstrated, race influences the level of threat felt by the non-aggressors, then this racialized notion of reasonableness dramatically expands the scope of justified killings—frequently covering deaths of innocent victims.97 In their piece on race and modern self-defense laws, Richardson and Goff use the tragic death of Yoshihiro Hattori as an example of this racialized reasonableness in action.98 Hattori, a sixteen-year-old Japanese exchange student, was on his way to a Halloween party with a member of his host family in Louisiana, when he was shot and killed by a man whose house Hattori mistakenly thought was the location of the party.99 Hattori was dressed as John Travolta, wearing a white tuxedo jacket . . . the two got lost and mistook the home of Rodney and Bonnie Peairs as the location of the party. They rang the doorbell, but when no one answered, the boys walked around the carport. At that moment, Mrs. Peairs opened the door. She saw Haymaker first, but when Hattori rounded the corner, she screamed, slammed the door shut, and yelled out to her husband to “[g]et the gun.” The boys began to walk away, still in search of the Halloween party. They were on the sidewalk, approximately ten yards away from the home, when Mr. Peairs ran outside with his laser-scoped .44 Smith & Wesson Magnum. Hattori, who spoke broken English, turned around and began to walk back towards Mr. Peairs, saying that they were there for the party. Mr. Peairs yelled “Freeze!” but Hattori did not understand what that word meant. When Hattori continued to approach, Mr. Peairs fired one shot, killing Hattori. The entire event, from the time Mr. Peairs opened his door, lasted about three seconds. A jury found Mr. Peairs’s belief that he was in imminent danger reasonable and acquitted him.100 While we do not know whether or not Mr. Peairs held any particular racial intentions, it would be completely normal for Hattori’s race to function as a substitute for suspicion.101 The narrative of Hattori’s death is echoed in the killing of Trayvon Martin. In that tragedy, similar to Hattori’s death, we do not know what mental processes led George Zimmerman to shoot and kill the unarmed teenager. What it does absolutely demonstrate is the potential for implicit racial 95 Id. “The suspicion heuristic demonstrates how easily honest—but mistaken—beliefs can occur when the person being judged fits a criminal stereotype.” Id. 97 Benforado, supra note 12, at 33–34. 98 Id. at 315. 99 Richardson & Goff, supra note 86, at 315. 100 Id. 101 Id. 96 17 Jordan Mobley bias to render objectively unreasonable shooting decisions, reasonable under current self-defense rubrics.102 4. Self-defense is not cheap The absolute allegiance to the inherent right to keep and bear arms for the purpose of self-defense is not without costs. As a result of the campaign to promote and further secure the traditions of gun ownership in our country, guns have become readily available. The real impact of the proliferation of individual gun ownership is not in widespread prevention of crime and harrowing instances of reasonable self-defense, as advocates of the individual right may suggest. Instead the real impact has been tragic, and disproportionately affecting impoverished communities of color.103 In Chicago, close to 90 percent of violent crimes occur in low-income areas, which are predominately black and Latino.104 Despite the fear that drives the perceived necessity of guns for self-defense, most gun violence is isolated. Gang violence, the most prevalent minority violence, is isolated—rarely touching the lives of the white middle class (as a result of systemic segregation, both economic and racial). For most, it is certainly something to be concerned about, but not something to be personally afraid of. In light of this understanding, the notion of self-defense yet again serves to mask the real racial impact of gun ownership, while promoting its non-racially relevant purposes—the narrow notion of actual, reasonable self-defense. V. Conclusion There are two purposes to emphasizing the racialized Second Amendment. First, it exposes the insufficiency of the fundamental rights arguments and the claimed moral high ground of gun advocates. And, second it allows Heller and its progeny to be seen as a choice, not a mandate. There are competing Constitutional interests at play. They must be resolved through careful balancing, not pretextual application of rote textual formulae. The Constitution does not make any absolute guarantees, “It fails [to do so] because the Constitution has to be read as a whole, and when it is, other values crop up in potential conflict with an unfettered right . . . the explicit terms of the Constitution, in other words, can create a conflict of approved values, and the explicit terms of the Constitution do not resolve that conflict when it arises. . . . A choice may have to be made, not because language is vague, but because the Constitution embodies the desire of the American people, like most people, to have things both ways. We 102 Patricia J. Williams, The Real Injustice at the Heart of the Trayvon Martin Case, The Nation (May 7, 2012), http://www.thenation.com/article/167455/real-injustice-heart-trayvon-martincase. 103 See Burkett, supra note 43, at 76. 104 Rebecca Leber, 34 People were Shot in Chicago on July 4, THINK PROGRESS (July 5, 2013), http://thinkprogress.org/justice/2013/07/05/2259541/chicago-gun-violence-july-4. 18 Jordan Mobley want order and security, and we want liberty. And we want not only liberty, but equality as well.”105 When we are able to see the interpretation of the Second Amendment as a choice, then we can look to smart regulation to curb the deleterious effects of gun ownership in the United States. I do not think that I have any great ideas about reform, certainly none that merit inclusion in this article, but there is plenty out there to point towards as reasonable steps to take. In any renewed discussion about gun ownership and self-defense, race must be a consideration. The deeply complex relationship between gun ownership and race cannot be ignored. Justice David Souter, Address at Harvard’s Commencement (May 27, 2010), available at http://news.harvard.edu/gazette/story/2010/05/text-of-justice-david-souters-speech/ 105 19