1 Sophia Conference Salzburg, September 2, 2015 Sentences as Predicates of Attitudinal and Modal Objects Friederike Moltmann CNRS-IHPST and NYU 1. The standard view and the new view of attitude reports and modal sentences 1.1. The Relational Analysis of attitude reports (1) a. John thinks that Mary is happy. b. think(John, [that Mary is happy]) The roles of propositions: - primary bearers of truth values - the meanings of sentences / embedded sentences - the contents or ‘objects’ of propositional attitudes Properties of propositions - have truth conditions essentially - are mind- and language-independent abstract objects Problems for propositions - How can abstract propositions act as the content of mental attitudes? - How can abstract propositions bear truth values and, as structured propositions, have the particular truth conditions they are supposed to have (the problem of the unity of the proposition)? Linguistic problems for the Relational Analysis The Substitution Problem (Moltmann 2003a) (2) John fears / thought that S. John fears / thought the proposition that S. The interpretation of nominal constructions (3) a. John’s thought that S / the thought that S b. John’s thought was that S. 2 that S a complement, an apposition? 1.2. The Quantificational Analysis of modals Modals represent quantifiers ranging over (accessible) possible worlds (whose range and ordering may be contextually given) (4) a. John may leave. a’. w (w f(wo) & [John leave]w = true) b. John must leave. b. w(w f(wo) [John leave]w = true) 1.3. The new logical form of attitude reports and modal sentences (5) a. John thinks that Mary is happy. b. John has the thought that Mary is happy. c. e(think(e, John) & [that Mary is happy](product(e)))] (6) a. John needs to leave. b. John has the need to leave. c. d(need(d) & [John to leave](d)) ---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- 2. Attitudinal objects and cognitive products 2.1. Aims [1] Avoid the conceptual problems for abstract propositions by making use of attitudinal objects (roughly playing the role of propositions). [2] Make use of the ontology overtly reflected in particular types of terms and constructions in natural language for the semantic analysis of attitude reports and modal sentences. General observation (due to Bolzano) Natural languages hardly display terms for propositions, but rather a wealth of terms for cognitive products and more generally attitudinal and modal objects. 2.2. Attitudinal objects Attitudinal objects include cognitive products, illocutionary products and mental states. Attitudinal objects are described by non-gerundive nominalizations of attitude verbs. 3 Cognitive products thought, judgment, realization, decision, conclusion Illocutionary products claim, promise, request, command, answer, question ‘Mental states’ intention, desire, belief, fear, hope 2.2. The action-product distinction (Twardowski 1911) thinking – thought, judging – judgment, deciding – decision, concluding - conclusion claiming – claim, promising, promise, requesting – request, answering – answer Products but not actions carry truth or satisfaction conditions and enter similarity relations based on a shared content. Products, roughly, play the role of propositions but as cognitive particulars. Products are best understood as the abstract (nonenduring) artifacts (Thomasson 1999) produced by the action (Moltmann 2014, to appear). By contrast: recent approach to propositions as types of acts (Soames 2010, Hanks 2015). 2.3. Mental states John’s belief that S, John’s intention to do V share the relevant characteristics of cognitive and illocutionary products, but should better not be viewed as products of actions. Searle (1983) Intentional states are prior to (intentional) actions Intentional states come with intrinsic satisfaction conditions and a force (mind-world or world-mind direction of fit) 2.4. Properties of attitudinal objects (Moltmann 2013, 2014, to appear) [1] Having truth or satisfaction conditions (7) a. John’s belief / claim that that S is true / false. b. John’s desire was satisfied. c. John’s request was fulfilled. d. John’s decision was implemented. e. John’s command was executed. (8) a. John followed Mary’s advice. b. John complied with the instruction. 4 (9) a. John ignored the command. b. John broke his promise. c. John took up the the offer. General observation: Predicates of satisfaction can be predicated neither of propositions nor of actions or events (Ulrich 1979,Twardowski 1911). [2] Involving a force and a form (mode of (physical) manifestation) (10) a. ??? John’s hope was his decision (namely to leave the country). b. ??? John’s thought was his remark (namely that it will rain). c. ??? John’s claim was his suggestion (namely that it might rain). [3] Having truthmakers or satisfiers The by-locution: (11) John followed Mary’s advice by taking the class. Different types of attitudinal objects may have different types of satisfiers (Searle 1983): Truth-directed attitudinal objects, desires, hopes, fears situations and actions Intentions, decisions, plans, directive illocutionary products (requests, demands) actions ‘by way of fulfilling the intention, decision, request…’ (Searle 1983) Questions answers as illocutionary products (questions as speech acts) or cognitive products (questions as products of inquiry) Attitudinal objects without satisfaction conditions / satisfiers - imaginations, entertainings, assumptions - factive emotive states and illocutionary acts: regrets, delights apologies [4] Agent-dependence, concreteness (12) a. ??? John’s thought is Mary’s thought. b. ??? John’s remark was Mary’s remark. (13) a. John heard Mary’s remark. b. The thought occurred to John this morning. c. The request was made yesterday. 5 [5] Similarity relations based on sharing content Is the same as: exact similarity (14) a. John’s thought is the same as Mary’s thought. a’. ? John’s thinking is the same Mary’s thinking. b. John’s request is the same as Mary’s request. b’. ? John’s speech act is the same as Mary’s speech act. [6] Part structure driven by partial content (15) a. part of John’s decision – part of John’s deciding b. part of John’s claim – part of John’s claiming Parts of attitudinal objects are partial contents, not the temporal parts of actions. [7] Properties of understanding and evaluation based on content (16) a. John’s answer is incomprehensible. b. John’s answering is incomprehensible. 2.4. Kinds of attitudinal objects Terms for kinds of attitudinal objects: the belief that S, the claim that S… (17) a. The belief that S is widespread. b. John and Mary share the belief that S. Kinds inherit relevant properties from instances, e.g. truth conditions. 2.5. The logical form of attitude reports based on the notion of an attitudinal object Attitude verbs express relations between (Davidsonian) events and agents. Clausal complements are predicates of the product of the (Davidsonian) event argument. (18) a. John thought that S b. e(think(e, John) & [that S](product(e)))] c. syntactic relation: event-product-pred(that S, thought) believe etc: event argument is the mental state, product-function maps mental state onto itself Nominal constructions: (19) a. John’s thought that S b. d[thought(d, John) & [that S](d)] c. the thought that S 6 d. d[thought(d) & [that S](d)] e. syntactic relation: mod(that S, thought) Alternation with complex predicate constructions light verb – product nominalization (20) have the thought – think, make a request – request, give avice - advise Complex predicates only (21) have the impression that, German die Absicht haben ‘have the intention’, French avoir peur ‘fear’, avoir besoin ‘need’ The semantics of ‘special’ or ‘nominalizing’ quantifiers (Moltmann 2003a, b, 2013) (22) a. John thought something nice. b. ed(think(e, John) & nice(d) & d = product(e)) (24) a. John thought what Mary thought. b. ede’(think(e, John) & d = product-kind(e) & think(e’, Mary) & d = productkind(e’)) ---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- 3. The semantics of attitude reports Independent sentences: express the property of being a product composed of smaller products corresponding to the compositional semantics of the sentence. Embedded sentences: may express a range of derivative meanings (properties of products) The most coarse-grained meaning: property of being a product that has certain satisfiers and perhaps violators (25) a. John thinks that Mary is happy. b. [that Mary is happy] = d[d consists of a referential product involving the use of ‘Mary’ and a predicational product involving the use of the concept ‘happy’] c. e(think(e, John) & [that Mary is happy](product(e))) (26) a. John (implicitly) believes that Mary is happy. b. Satisfaction-based derived sentence meaning (first version) sat([that S]) = d[i(I ╟ d i ╠ S)] ╟ : exact truthmaking, ╠ : inexact truthmaking c. e(believe(e, John) & sat([that Mary is happy])(product(e))) Underspecification of attitudes by clausal complements 7 (27) Fiona wants to PRO catch a fish. (Fara Graff 2013) Products are causally relevant and carry full satisfaction / truth conditions. Clausal complements may underspecify products with respect to their content. -------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- 4. Modals 4.1. Modal predicates Must, may, should, ought to, need to, is obliged to, is necessary, is possible The approach Clausal complement, clausal subject subject or prejacant have the same function in modal sentences as in attitude reports: they are predicates of the modal objects and characterize the modal object in terms of its satisfiers/truthmakers (and perhaps violators/falsifiers) Deontic modals: take modal products as implicit argument whose satisfiers are actions Epistemic modals: take modal products as implicit arguments whose satisfiers are situations 4.2. Modal objects Modal products artifacts produced by illocutionary acts of request, permission, invitation, offer Modal objects that are not modal products: abilities, logical necessities and possibilities Modal products described by nominalizations of modal predicates The need for John to improve, John obligation to help, the permission to leave, the offer to stay, the invitation to come to the party Modal products not described by nominalizations: laws, rules, duties Properties of modal products - have satisfaction conditions (28) a. John fulfilled the need to improve by taking classes b. Mary took up the offer to take a vacation by hiking in the montains for a week - have a temporary existence Modal products are established and go out of existence at some point in time, but unlike cognitive and illocutionary products they may endure past the act that establishes them. Evidence 1: predicates specifying the endurance of a modal product (29) a. John’s promised yesterday to help. Today, John is still under the obligation to to help. b. Yesterday, John invited Mary to stay. Today, the offer to stay still holds. 8 Choice of tense in specificational sentences: (30) a. John’s promise (yesterday) was that he would help. b. ?? John’s promise is that he would help. c. John’s obligation is that he will help. (31) a. John’s request (yesterday) was that Mary leave the country. b. ?? John’s request is that Mary leave the country. c. Mary’s obligation is to leave the country. Modal products are on a par with laws (as products of acts of passing / declaring them): laws may generally endure past the act of establishing them. 4.3. Modals of necessity and of possibility (32) a. John must help. b. John may help. Difference between deontic may and must must: modal product (obligation) has both satisfiers and ‘violators’ satisfiers: actions of John’s helping by way of fulfilling the obligation violators: actions incompatible with John’s helping may: modal product has only ‘satisfiers’ Other cases promises: have satisfiers and violators, offers: have only satisfiers, requests: have satisfiers and violators, invitations: have only satisfiers Epistemic modals (roughly) Epistemic must: verifiers: situations verifying the evidence, falsifiers: situations incompatible with the evidence Epistemic might: verifiers: situations compatible with the evidence 4.4. The logical form of modal sentences and sentences involving modal products (33) Satisfaction-based (Derived) Sentence Meanings (second version Sat([S]) = d[s(s ╟ d s ╠ S ) & s(s ╢ d s ╣ S)] (34) a. John must help. 9 b. e(must(e) & sat([John help])(e)) (35) a. John may leave. b. e(may(e) & sat([John leave])(e)) (36) a. John asked Mary to come. b. John invited Mary to come. (37) a. e(ask(e, John, Mary) & sat([Mary come])(product(e))) b. e(invite(e, John, Mary) & sat([Mary come])(product(e))) c. [Mary come] = d[s(s ╟ d s╠ Mary come & s(s ╢ d s ╣ Mary come))] (38) a. e(ask(e, John, Mary) & sat([Mary come])(modal-product(e))) b. e(invite(e, John, Mary) & sat([Mary come])(modal-product(e))) ------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------ 5. Performative uses of modals in embedded sentences ‘Modal concord or ‘harmonic’ modals (39) a. John requested Bill to leave. b. John requested that Bill should leave. (40) a. John offered to help. b. John offered that he could help. The analysis Performative use of independent sentence (41) a. I promise that I will help. b. e(promise(e, cspeaker) & sat([that I will help])(product(e))] Performative uses of modals (42) a. You must leave! b. d[must(d) & sat([you leave])(d)] By uttering the sentence the speaker intends to produce a modal product as characterized by the meaning of the sentence. ‘Harmonic modals’ as performative uses of modals in embedded sentences (43) a. d[should(d) & sat([Bill leave])(d)] b. e(request(e, John) & sat([that Bill should leave])(-modal-product(e)))] (44) a. d[could(d) & sat([John help])(d)] 10 b. e(offer(e, John) & sat([John help])(modal-product(e))) -------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- References Graff Fara, D. (2013): ‘Specifying Desire’. Noûs 47(2), 250--272. Fine, K. (2014): ‘Truth-Maker Semantics for Intuitionistic Logic’. Journal of Philosophical Logic 43, 2-3, pp 549-577 ---------- (to appear): Survey of Truthmaker Semantics. Blackwell Philosophy of Language Handbook. Hanks, P. W. (2015): Propositional Content. Oxford UP. Moltmann, F. (2003a): 'Propositional Attitudes without Propositions'. Synthese 135, ,pp. 70118. ---------------- (2003b): 'Nominalizing Quantifiers'. Journal of Philosophical Logic 35.5., pp. 445-481. ---------------- (2013): Abstract Objects and the Semantics of Natural Language. Oxford UP, Oxford, Chapter 4. ----------------- (2014): ‘Propositions, Attitudinal Objects, and the Distinction between Actions and Products’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, supplementary volume on propositions, ed. By G. Rattan and D. Hunter, 43.5-6, pp. 679-701. ---------------------- (to appear): ‘Cognitive Products and the Semantics of Attitude Reports and Deontic Modals’. In Moltmann / Textor (to appear). Moltmann, F. / M. Textor (eds.) (to appear): Act-Based Conceptions of Propositions: Contemporary and Historical Contributions. Oxford UP, Oxford, to appear in 2016. Searle, J. R. (1983): Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind, Cambridge UP, Cambridge. Soames, S. (2010): What is Meaning?. Princeton UP, Princeton. Thomasson, A. (1999): Fiction and Metaphysics. Cambridge UP, Cambridge. Twardowski, K. (1911): ‘Actions and Products. Some Remarks on the Borderline of Psychology, Grammar, and Logic’. In J. Brandl/J. Wolenski (eds.): Kazimierz Twardowski. On Actions, Products, and Other Topics in the Philosophy. Rodopi, Amsterdam and Atlanta, 1999, 103-132. Ulrich, W. (1976): ‘An Alleged Ambiguity in the Nominalizations of Illocutionary Verbs’. Philosophica 18.2., pp. 113-127.