1. Shapiro, on Hart's way out 1. First Argument a. Inclusive legal positivism won't work because having rules of recognition (RoR) that include morality as part of the law means that the rules/laws validated by them won't make a practical difference. b. Put differently: If you accept a RoR that says something like 'morality is law' then the laws that are validated by it, which are moral rules, don't make a practical difference. i. Green: BUT Shapiro's argument proves too much, for the above example: 1. Imagine an RoR - what congress says is law 2. By virtue of accepting the RoR, you've accepted the infinite number of possible laws that's Identified in it (Securities & Exchange act, an Act like the SEA but with slightly different content, etc) 3. So according to this, you don't really need laws. You've accepted the RoR, and everything that is law is identified in the RoR, so you only need facts that trigger RoR, th laws themselves don’t make a practical difference. a. Facts (semantically) can be as simple as person x did action y or congress has said that z is law. 4. From this it follows that either a. you don't need laws at all except for the RoR, or b. there's something wrong with his argument 2. Second Argument a. This is directed at the form of inclusive legal positivism of in which Morality is a necessary, not sufficient, condition for law. b. Put differently: Legal rules are valid UNLESS they violate a moral principle (moral principles is necessary condition). i. Shapiro's problem - in order to think about whether the law is valid, you have to refer to the same reasons for action that the law is meant to displace. 1. E.g. Congress's statutes on employees' pay are valid law UNLESS they are grossly unfair (moral principle) 2. But gross unfairness is one of the reasons for action the law was meant to displace ii. Green’s question: 1. Why not say that Congress is preempting certain reasons for action but not gross unfairness? Why assume that gross unfairness is one of the reasons for action the law was meant to displace? 2. Shapiro’s response: the problem is that the validity of the law, its very existence as law, depends upon its not being grossly unfair. There is no problem with a valid law that does not displace the reason for action of gross unfairness. But such a law does not have its validity depend upon its not being grossly unfair. 3. In saying that the law is not valid if it is grossly unfair, it is suggested that the law preempts all reasons for action including gross unfairness . iii. But if that’s true, then in requiring one to consider gross unfairness, one is required to consider the same reasons for action the law is meant to displace For the exclusive legal positivist in contrast, the constitutional provision that says that congress’s statutes on employees’ pay are valid unless they are grossly unfair must be reinterpreted 1. Not being grossly unfair is not a condition for valid law. Instead, congress’s statutes are valid but do not preempt the reason for action of gross unfairness 2. The equal protection clause would be another example. Although this looks like a condition for the validity of law, for the exclusive legal positivist it must be reinterpreted. In effect the EPC is limiting the preemptive scope of every law that Congress passes. It's not a necessary condition for valid law, it's simply a limitation on the preemptive force of valid laws. a. So the law can be valid even though it violates equal protection, but it can't preempt the reasons for action tied to equal protection. b. To say otherwise is to argue that the law is meant to preempt all other reasons of action, including other law/morals. That's incoherent bc it requires you to take into account the things that the law is supposed to preempt. 3. Doctor example a. "Take the blue pill." That order preempts all of your medical reasons for action. That's a valid medical directive, even if it doesn't preempt ALL reasons for action (e.g. gun to head, religious objections, etc). i. Exclusive legal positivist - the directive is valid, but it's only partially preemptive of your reasons for action b. Imagine that a Dr. said instead “ ‘Take the Blue Pill’ – this directive is valid if isn’t overridden by nonmedical (e.g. religious) considerations i. This doesn't work because you have to consider those non-medical reasons for action to determine the validity of directive. Although the doctor appeared to have condition the validity of his directive upon its not violating non-medical reasons for action, what he really did was issued a valid medical directive that preempted only medical and not nonmedical reasons for action. c. Reality - it's a valid medical directive right now, to the extent that it displaces medical reasons. But it's not dependent on or preemptive of things that a medical directive doesn't displace (e.g. gun to head, religion). 4. In the same way, law must be valid without morality . But the function of provisions that refer to morality like the equal protection clause is that they limit the preemptive scope of the law to not include those relevant moral considerations a. In our legal system the isolation of the preemptive scope of the law is probably only with respect and judges . If Congress passes a statute that preempts many reasons for action that the judge might consider otherwise. But because of the equal protection clause equal protection is a moral reason for action that is not preempt i. The judge can (indeed must) consider that reason for action in determining whether he should strike down the law. 3. Sum up: the inclusive & exlclusive legal positivist agree on whether judges look to morality to decide legal questions, but they disagree as to which part of the law is LAW and which part is only morality. 2. Brink, Legal theory 1. Theory of hard cases among positivists - gap in the law that a judge has to fill in (acting like a legislator) a. Created by the semantic properties of the words in the legal rules i. e.g. no vehicles in the park - include stroller? b. Meaning of a word is exhausted by the criteria for using the word that people accept at a particular moment i. Water 1. Then: liquid, transparent, potable; 2. Now: H2O 3. Intentionalists with these positions are talking past each other c. Extensionalists argue that the meaning of the term is not the same as the criteria people use in connection with the term . Although people thought water in the past was a transparent tasteless potable liquid, they were wrong about the meaning of their own word i. Water meant H2O d. Under an Extensionalists theory Fidelity to the meaning of the constitution does not necessarily = fidelity to what was in the minds of the founders i. The meaning of the term can outstrip what's in the minds of the people who use the term at the time they use it ii. e.g. gold standard - heavy yellow metal v. atomic AU gold; toxic - what's actually toxic, not what ppl thought was toxic at the time e. Natural kind v. Moral terms i. To say that someone is incorrect when they argue that, for example, slavery is just, is to imply that people share a concept of justice, it even though they might have different criteria for using the concept ii. Scalia - ppl who wrote constitution wouldn't have called execution cruel & unusual 1. Specific v. general intent to refer to a given criteria (e.g. specific - water=H2O v. general - water = whatever I'm pointing to at this moment) 2. Presumption in favor of specific intent would constrain judges in their discretion, but has other negative consequences too