ORGANIZATIONAL LEADERSHIP By: Ronald F. White, Ph.D. Professor of Philosophy College of Mount St. Joseph INTRODUCTION Although human beings and other primates are individual biological organisms, they have the capacity to organize collectively in pursuit of common goals. What we all call “organizations” are actually sociopolitical systems that involve the interaction of “leaders” and “followers” in the pursuit of these goals. This lecture will explore some of the philosophical and ethical issues that arise in the context of organizational leadership. ORGANIZATIONAL INQUIRY Human inquiry is about asking questions and proposing answers. One of the stumble blocks inherent to organizational inquiry is the fact that various the various questioning disciplines that constitute human inquiry (philosophy, economics, political science, psychology, sociology etc.) have developed their own distinctive conceptual frameworks and vocabulary. As we explore what these various disciplines have to say about organizations, we invariably encounter a wide assortment of synonymous, overlapping and contradictory terms, such as: organizations, social groups, social systems, communities, associations, and institutions. Unfortunately, nuanced meanings make it difficult to navigate across disciplines. It is also important to acknowledge that human beings spawn many different types of organizations in pursuit of the vast array of human interests, including: political organizations, business organizations, professional organizations, religious organizations, medical organizations, athletic organizations, news organizations etc. Despite this variability, the literature on leadership tends to focus on political and business organizations. Inquiry into the nature of organizations and organizational behavior can be very general and ask timeless and/or universal questions about all organizations or it can be time-specific and/or particular kinds of organizations, such as political, business, or religious organizations. Therefore, inquiry into organizational behavior raises a morass of questions, some of which are longstanding in the history of inquiry, while others emerge and dissolve at a specific time and place. There are two traditional lines of human inquiry relevant to the study of organizations: descriptive inquiry and prescriptive inquiry. But keep in mind that, as is often the case, the distinction itself is subject human inquiry and not as clearcut as we would like. Descriptive inquiry into the nature of organizations generally entails the empirical analysis of the “real world” of organized human behavior; that is, the attributes of leaders and followers and the social relationships that exist within and between organizations. So the long-term goal of descriptive inquiry, therefore, is to discover the objective universal laws of nature, which in turn, enable scientists to explain, predict, and ultimately control organizational behavior. Hence, descriptive analysis is committed to the discernment of Truth and Falsity, with questions such as: How do human leaders and followers compare with leaders and followers from other species, especially other primates? Who are the leaders and followers of an organization? What are their respective psychological and/or character traits? How are leaders and followers identified? Are leaders born (e.g. charismatic leaders) or can leadership be transmitted via teaching and learning? What are the organizational ends that leaders pursue? By what means do leaders aspire to attain those ends, and, how efficiently are those ends attained? How do leaders go about maintaining the status quo or instituting changes in the ends or the means? Who bears the costs and who enjoys the benefits of these organizational decisions? To what degree do followers compete and/or cooperate with leaders and/or each other? To what degree do these organizations compete and/or cooperate with other organizations in their environment? Traditionally, descriptive inquiry relies on empirical methodology employed by social scientists; usually psychologists, sociologists, political scientists, economists, and/or historians. In recent years, evolutionary biologists have also begun to contribute to that body of theoretical knowledge. One of the most basic questions raised by descriptive inquiry into the nature of organizations is whether there exists a single, overarching set of natural laws that govern the behavior of all organizational leaders and followers? Or, are the laws of nature contingent upon the pursued end? In short, are the laws of nature generically and/or contextually variable? For example, are the laws governing political organizations commensurable or incommensurable with business organizations? We might also question whether historical knowledge of leadership within a particular organization at a specific time and place elucidates the present situation for that organization, or whether that knowledge transfers over to other organizations or not. Does the history of political organizations elucidate knowledge business past or present business organizations? What do you think? Are the laws of nature that govern political organizations and business organizations commensurable or incommensurable? Traditionally, descriptive inquiry is conducted by biologists social scientists that study human nature, and prescriptive inquiry is conducted by theologians, and philosophers; however, today social scientists and biologists now contribute more to organizational ethics. PRESCRIPTIVE ORGANIZATIONAL INQUIRY Prescriptive inquiry into organizational leadership deals with questions of value; or, the discernment of Good from Bad organizations, leaders, or followers. In contrast to descriptive analysis, which seeks to discover the immutable “laws of nature,” prescriptive analysis involves questions of value and usually (but not always) entail identifying the moral rules, character traits (virtues), etc. that shape normative organizational behavior. Here one of the most puzzling problems is that all organizations utilize a variety of rules intended to govern the moral relationships between organizational leaders, followers, and other organizations in their social and physical environment. Most organizational rules are pragmatic rules that are intended to serve the realization of organizational goals. These rules can be judged solely in terms of efficiency. Thus, the most vexing problem facing organizational inquiry what to do when there is a conflict between efficiency (that is, ”getting it done”) and morality (how your affect persons). What happens when “getting the job done” seems to entail widely held moral rules or principles? Call it the “problem of dirty hands.” Indeed, one of the oldest distinctions in the history of prescriptive inquiry is Plato’s distinction between intrinsic goods (things that are “good for their own sake”) and extrinsic goods (things that are good for their pleasurable consequences). Much of the history of philosophy has been occupied offering alternative categorizations. In philosophy, there are several longstanding competing moral theories. Divine Command Theories hold that moral rules are justified based on the authoritative “Word of God,” Teleological Theories state that moral rules are justified based on their consequences (usually pleasurable); Deontological Theories (or rights-based theories) state that moral rules are justified based on universality; and Virtue-Based Theories state that moral rules are justified based on their proximity to standards of human excellence, such as courage, trust, etc. Most philosophers embrace the view that prescriptive morality must address universal questions that pertain to the good and bad treatment of persons. This entails not only inquiry into the nature of the moral theories, but also inquiry into human nature, and the composition of the moral universe. In ethics, the distinction between persons and non-persons is of central importance. Persons are entities that occupy the moral universe that can be reasonably assigned rights, duties, and/or obligations. . In the Western moral tradition, most personhood theories have been anthropocentric theories that say that the moral universe is exclusively composed of human beings. It was often argued that only human “persons” possess intrinsic value, and therefore humans are “good for their own sake.” “Non-persons” or non-human entities such as, such as non-living things, property, plants, and animals were thought to possess only extrinsic value via their relationship to human beings. However, since the 1970s a very robust philosophical tradition emerged out of the “animal rights movement” and “right to movement die” identifies moral personhood with the possession of certain descriptive attributes associated with brain function such as: consciousness, sentience, self-awareness, and/or intelligence. If descriptive inquiry seeks knowledge of the universal laws of nature, prescriptive inquiry seeks knowledge of moral rules. Traditionally, prescriptive organizational inquiry asks questions such as: Who ought to be rulers and who ought to be followers? What constitutes a good leader or a bad leader? What ends ought to be sought by good leaders and what means ought to be employed in attaining those goals? And, whose interests ought to be served by the organization? Today, there is also a lot of debate among scholars over the exact values that leaders and followers ought to embrace or exemplify. Some of them include: efficiency, integrity, honesty, courage, equality, liberty, justice, trust, reverence, temperance, happiness, and prudence. Another issue commonly encountered in applied ethics is the role of that “good” or “bad” intentions play in assessing moral responsibility of organizations, leaders and/or followers. Indeed, many leaders intend to do good things, but are actually ignorant of either what is good, or how to attain it. What can we say about well-meaning but inept leaders and/or followers, or well-meaning but inept organizations? In sum, organizational inquiry must address the larger philosophical question of the relationship between that descriptive “is” and the prescriptive “ought.” Are there universal moral rules that apply to governmental, business, and religious organizations? If so, can this moral structure be discovered and/or justified based on descriptive analysis (Science)? If there is a conflict between the descriptive and prescriptive organizational structure, how is that conflict to be resolved? Are organizations persons and if so, what are their moral rights and moral obligations within the larger moral universe? Ultimately, inquiry into organizational behavior must address the philosophically challenging relationship between the morality and legality. LEGALITY AND MORALITY Metaphorically speaking, the Laws of Nature are coercively enforced by “Mother Nature.” However, we must guard against our natural propensity to mix metaphors. There is no conceptual absurdity associated with human beings violating the “Laws of the State” or the “Laws of Morality.” Unfortunately we do it all the time. However, it is not clear what it means when we claim that human beings “violate the Laws of Nature.” Is it physically possible for human beings to violate the universal laws of gravity, thermodynamics, economics, or evolution? In the Judeo-Christian tradition, human beings can violate the laws of nature by virtue of their divine origination via the doctrine of special creation. In the Western Liberal, and even Western Scientific traditions, human beings act outside of Nature, via their possession of free will. But when we violate those laws of nature, so the argument goes, Mother Nature imposes “natural consequences” upon us. For ethical leadership, one of the most important aspects of Human Nature is that human beings organize themselves into groups based on leadership and followership. Indeed, other primates exhibit similar organizational patterns. Unlike the “Laws of Nature,” the “Laws of the State” and the “Rules of Morality” imply enforcement by human beings. The Laws of the State are enforced by the coercive power of government. Hence, if human beings violate these laws, government imposes legal sanctions, usually in the form of physical and/or economic penalties. The rules of morality are enforced by a public sanction, usually in the form of assessment of praise or blame. In totalitarian states, the Laws of Morality are often enforced by legal sanctions, while liberal states attempt to minimize the government’s ability to dictate morality via the criminal code. There is also a strong tradition in Western Liberalism that supports the view that Mother Nature enforces both the descriptive and prescriptive dimensions of human experience. Realist philosophers argue that organizational ethics is conditioned by Nature, and that idealistic prescriptions that violate human nature are invariably weeded out by Mother Nature herself, whether we like it or not. In other words, as Kant observed moral prescriptions must ultimately conform to the dictates of reality: “ought implies can.” Much of what is presented in leadership ethics runs against the grain of Human Nature, and therefore may violate the “ought implies can” proviso. Hence, we cannot do ethics without reliable empirical knowledge. ORGANIZATIONAL ENDS AND MEANS As teleological systems, all organizations aspire to fulfill certain desired ends, goals, or purposes. Teleological organizational behavior can generate enormous complexity. Some organizational goals are simple, and clearly identified (make money), while others are complex, not easily identified (save souls). Some ends are simple and relatively easy to attain while others are more complex difficult to attain, depending on efficiency of the means employed and the level of competition by other organizations in the environment. Some organizational ends are universally regarded as good while others are bad. Organizations often pursue multiple goals. And of course, not everything that an organization does is planned, and therefore wrought with “unintended consequences.” Sometimes unintended consequences are efficient or good and sometimes they are inefficient or bad. In general we tend to classify organizations based on their goals. It is widely believed that the primary goal of a business organization is to earn a profit and the primary goal of a religious organization is to worship God. Political organizations fulfill multiple purposes which often conflict. These goals include: providing protection from hostile nations in the environment, providing economic security for leaders and/or followers (citizens), and/or protecting private property. Theocratic regimes also worship God. However, it is important to acknowledge that governmental organizations are constrained by the natural laws of economics, and therefore governments can, at least in theory, “go out of business.” One of the universal descriptive features of organizational behavior is the degree of cooperation and competition between leaders and followers, and the distinction between voluntary and involuntary cooperation. Cooperation between leaders and followers involves compliance with rules and the degree of freedom to enter or exit the organization. All organizations employ varying degrees of coercive force (and threats of force) for both rule compliance and organizational entry and exit. Hence, some organizations are based on voluntary association, whereby individuals freely choose to be followers and voluntarily comply with organizational rules. All voluntary associations include embrace freedom of exit. Although, membership in the Roman Catholic Church is (more or less) voluntary in terms of entry and exit, your continued association with the church requires adherence to certain rules that govern your behavior. Failure to comply with its most fundamental rules can result in a variety of sanctions imposed by church leaders, including forced exit or excommunication. ORGANIZATIONAL PLANNING Are there objective universal laws of nature that govern the behavior of leaders and followers engaged in organizational behavior? In other words, is the behavior of political organizations, business organizations, and religious organizations determined by the same Laws of Nature? And if so, would human knowledge of these laws facilitate the explanation, prediction and control of all organizations? Unlike most other ethicists, I think that in the “real world,” all organizations are essentially political organizations, and therefore, the natural laws that govern, what I shall call “sociopolitical reality” are objective, universal, evolutionary, and explicable in biological terms. Human beings and other primates are distinctive in that they purposefully plan for the future, both individually and collectively. Power is inexorably teleological and therefore subject to analysis in terms of means and ends. The “Ends” of human endeavor are simply the objects of short-term and/or long-term planning (“Goods”) as pursued by individuals and organizations. Planning is central to the realization of both individual goals and organizational goals. Individual planning involves the pursuit of individual goals and collective planning is planning by organizations. Of course, self-interested individual planning often conflicts with collective planning, which raises serious moral issues concerning the nature and limits of an organization’s use of coercive power over individuals in the exercise of its collective planning. When there are conflicts between individual and organizations, communitarian regimes tend to maximize collective planning and liberal regimes tend to maximize individual planning. Planning usually involves rules, which form the basis of cooperation between leaders and followers. Individual and collective planning entail the formulation, replication, and enforcement of rules. Rules are the bulwark of planning and serve as the primary instruments for the exercise of power. Whoever makes and enforces the rules holds political power. So sovereignty is about who makes the rules, how those rules are enforced, and who follows those rules. Efficient rules embedded in organizational structure are well known, easily enforced. It is much easier to enforce organizational rules when both leaders and followers benefit from those rules. Inefficient rules that do not advance organizational goals and/or not benefit leaders and followers are more difficult to enforce and make cooperation difficult attain. There is a lot to be said about planning. Organizational planning entails purposive planning for the realization of organizational goals. Organizations are complex evolutionary systems that change over time, which means that organizational leaders and followers also change over time, as do organizational goals and organizational plans. But leaders and followers do not always cooperate. They often compete. Leaders compete with aspiring leaders as they jockey for positions in the organizational hierarchy. Leaders also compete with individual followers and groups of followers. And of course, organizations invariably compete for survival with other organizations in their environment. ORGANIZATIONAL IDEALISM AND REALISM In the ideal world, all organizations pursue praiseworthy short-term and long-term goals with maximum efficiency. Leaders and followers cooperate and sacrifice their individual self-interest without leaders having to resort to the threat of coercive force. In this other world, there is no competition between leaders, followers, or between various organizations. All organizations cooperate with one another in the execution of each other’s organizational planning. Everyone benefits and no one pays the cost. In the ideal world, all organizations survive forever and everyone is successful and happy. I call this organizational idealism. In contrast to the rosy dictates of idealism, organizational realism offers a very different scenario. As Machiavelli, Thomas Hobbes, and other realists have suggested, political organizations (or States) are subject to the natural laws that govern the exercise of power. These laws are objective, universal, and ultimately inviolable. Failure to comply with these natural laws invariably results in the natural dissolution of the State, or indeed any organization. Political power is simply the objective capacity of individuals and/or groups to pursue self-interest in a sociopolitical context. Therefore, I shall argue that organizational reality is invariably contingent upon relationships of power between individual leaders and followers engaged in organizational structures that serve various ends or purposes. In competitive environments, organizations that fail to take into account sociopolitical reality lose the struggle for survival. First of all, human beings are by nature individual self-interested biological entities programmed to pursue pleasure and avoid pain. Therefore, human beings are naturally attracted to pleasurable rewards and repelled by painful punishments. Human beings, however, are also social animals capable of organizing themselves in groups in order to advance those interests. The most puzzling aspect of the control of human behavior is how to “organize” selfinterested individuals into functionally cooperative organizations. As Machiavelli noted, in the “Real World” many followers are not really dedicated followers, but rather self-interested individuals that, if given the opportunity, will accept those rewards while surreptitiously violating the rules. And of course, not all leaders are, in fact, altruistically committed to organizational goals. Some leaders use their power as leaders to advance their own individual interests, often at the expense of the collective interests of their organizations. As noted earlier, other leaders are well-meaning and committed to organizational goals, but lack technical knowledge necessary to efficiently manage human and non-human organizational resources. And finally, some leaders are efficient leaders but pursue immoral goals and/or immoral means. Sometimes immoral leadership “pays off” in terms of organizational efficiency and sometimes it does not. Hence, the distinction between leaders and managers is often subject to debate. Organizations in the “Real World” and therefore must take into account the darker side of human nature. As Machiavelli noted, organizations that attempt to survive by offering rewards to leaders and followers in exchange for compliance with rules, eventually run out of resources, as leaders and followers naturally seek higher and higher levels of gratification. Conversely, organizations that rely exclusively on coercive threats also tend to be short-lived. That’s because the ability of leaders to threaten followers is limited by their finite ability to detect communicate the rules, force compliance with those rules, by the ability of followers to either avoid getting caught or by their ability to endure the painful sanctions imposed by leaders, and by the “followers” ability to exit the organization. If over the long run all of the leaders and followers choose to exit the organization, then organization must either reorganize via collective planning or suffer from extinction. Leaders can also exercise coercive power over followers through the strategic manipulation of information, by convincing followers that compliance with rules advances their self-interest, which, incidentally, may or may-not be true. Thus all organizations an ideology; that is they cultivate a body of descriptive and prescriptive beliefs that serve to justify their rules. The more collective planning the less room there is for individual planning and the less variation and novelty introduced into the organization. When the environment is stable and the organization is surviving on the basis of upholding tradition and by replicating the old effective rules, innovation or rule changes are destructive. (If it ain’t broke don’t fix it!) When the environment is unstable, and the organization begins to disorganize, innovation or new rules are essential to survival. Of course, inefficient rules can survive, at least temporarily, through the use of coercion. Over the long run, however, organizational rules, like organisms, survive on the basis of trial and error. But Mother Nature punishes biological and organizational inefficiency. Unfortunately, she often seems to be much more tolerant of immorality than inefficiency. THE ORGANIZATIONAL ETHICS INDUSTRY Finally, the most invisible fact of the study of organizational ethics is that it is also an industry. Companies develop and market products and services that offer insight and/or advice on how to form and maintain an ethical organizations. There are companies that produce books, videos, and websites. There are consultants that get paid to provide lectures, seminars, and other programs to promote ethical leadership and/or followership. Colleges and universities charge tuition to students that want to learn about ethical leadership and so do the professors that teach these courses. Believe it or not, I’m getting paid a nominal stipend to teach this course.