1. Robert B. Pippin, Nietzsche, Psychology, & First Philosophy, The University of Chicago Press, 2010, ISBN, pp. 139. 2. Summary Pippin sets out to understand what Nietzsche means by 'psychology': why is it the path to the fundamental problems and what is its relationship with traditional philosophy? If we understand the phrasing of Psychology as ' the Queen of the Sciences' - the title of the first chapter - traditionally, this would implicate that psychology must be understood as a fundamental doctrine that is to encompass everything. (4) At first sight, the doctrine of will to power, which has clearly psychological implications, seems to be the most valuable option for such an understanding. However, this approach turns will to power into a metaphysical imperative; everything in the organic world is driven by a basic overpowering drive. (6) Contrary to this metaphysical (Heideggerian) claim, Pippin proposes the French moralists model to understand Nietzsche’s meaning of ‘psychology’: "how we should understand what happens when people appeal to normative considerations, or try to live well, how those norms come to matter people, how even they could or could not come to matter". (8) The moralists are psychologists who don't rely on a deeper philosophical theory of human nature, allowing them to write honestly - cf. Pascal's l'homme honnète. Psychology replaces a first philosophy, "because of the primacy of the 'psychological' question of some basic, always presupposed 'stance toward life' […]." (12) This stance or orientation, exemplified by Montaigne's cheerful writing - his Heiterkeit -, can not be reached by argument, revelation or systematic philosophy. (11-12) Support for this can be found in the beginning passages of Thus spoke Zarathustra (Z), On the Genealogy of Morals (GM), and Beyond Good and Evil (JGB). Pivotal in these passages is the Nietzschean description of philosophy in erotic terms, for example, in the image of philosophers as clumsy lovers striving for knowledge. This erotic striving or attachment to life implies the priority of psychology, because it helps us to understand our attachments as conditions of life. We can not be argued or demonstrated into desiring an ideal, such as the philosophical attachment to the ideal of truth, because what matters most is what "inspires some great erotic striving". (14) The conventional approach of Nietzsche's imagery between truth as a woman and philosophers as male clumsy lovers is, therefore, incomplete. It is not merely a rhetorical device, but returns to Plato's characterization of philosophy as a kind of love. What distinguishes philosophers is not their method, but their distinct eros: "what provokes or inspires their desire, what grips them". (16) By identifying Diotoma's assumption in Plato's Symposium - that nothing can find satisfaction in any finite delight -, as a negative evaluation of life, Nietzsche accuses Plato of diverting eros away from what can be enjoyed. (17-18) Original erotic attachment is, then, an expression of perspective, and not the natural situation of man. If we want to understand Nietzsche we need to address what Pippin identifies as the Montaigne-problem. It concerns living by the ideal, which Nietzsche struggled to attain, but failed to reach, of affirmative reconciliation of oneself with the weak and corrupt human condition. (11, 23) This Montaigne-problem, however, is not the key to Nietzsche's philosophy and goes back to a more general psychological issue, which Pippin refers to as the primordiality problem. The primordiality problem has, above all, to do with value, since it is concerned with understanding the source of our practical commitments to some accepted, governing standard. (23-26) The authority of constraints and requirements I impose on myself aren't just naturally imposed physical (im)possibilities, but are expressions of my intentions, and, as such, are promises. "These sorts of commitments are thus basic or constitutive for the very possibility of thought, belief, action, all intentionality." (25) A commitment is an erotic attachment and always corporal. When something grips us passionately, we commit and 1 identify with a desired end. (29) Nietzsche's use of 'depth' in 'depth psychology' could then be understood as an attempt to grasp a passionate identification with a commitment. Psychology is primary, because of the primordiality of orienting, normative, depth commitments. (32) Nietzsche understands the psychological conditions of value as the possibility of an actionguiding depth commitment. Beliefs about commitments to norms, however, vary over generations. Nietzsche, therefore, insists on the necessity of a historical dimension to the psyche, something that clearly distinguishes him from French and Greek psychology. (2, 31) Depth commitments aren't transcendent, but have taken root in us. This historical dimension makes that Nietzsche's approach to the question of knowledge is not to be understood in the traditional sense of Socrates or Kant. Contrary to those philosophers’ return to metaphysics to solve the fact that humans can only attain a limited amount of the truth, Nietzsche focuses on how much knowledge we can embody or incorporate (das Wissen sich einzuverleiben). (38-39) Einverleibung involves the enterprise of making oneself an experiment of life. The process of incorporating knowledge into the body brings about a tension between our intellectual conscience and our passionate desire. This tension can be translated in the question of ‘what is fair or fit to want?’. "The 'tension' formulations certainly indicate that the growth of our intellectual conscience means that our deepest (or 'depth') commitments are not immune to the claims of reflection and justification, as if one could be simply strong enough to legislate in defiance of the claims of reflection." (36) Nietzsche's answer to this tension, in the spirit of Montaigne's cheerfulness (Heiterkeit), is a gay science addressed in chapter two What is a Gay Science?. In chapter 3, titled Modernity as a Psychological problem, Pippin further elaborates what is meant by "tension" in Nietzsche's writings. This tension is concerned with the way the soul can pull against itself and matters self-consciousness itself. It is often depicted by the image of the bow, as in Z 9 or JGB preface 4 and is to illustrate the self's negative relation to itself. (37, 56) "Tension", or self-dissatisfaction, which is, also always a historical possibility, allows for the possibility of some distance from oneself. "Nietzsche's account of this tension or self-dissatisfaction is essentially historical. The psyche amounts to a historically achieved and quite variable way of holding ourselves and others to account. […] This historical narrative does, though, make a very minimal assumption about the 'nature' out of which such historical development proceeds." (59,60) The human being is primarily understood by its distinctive activity of esteeming, valuing, schätzen (cf. Z 43), allowing for an implicit, but hugely important, distinction between human action and ordinary event. Although Nietzsche assumes little about human nature, it is clear that consciousness is a reactive phenomenon that is more than a kind of second-order neutral self-monitoring. The self-relation is a tension, because it is always evaluative and involves self-dissatisfaction. "This tension, while it is perfectly consistent with a naturalism and presumes no dualism, is hardly a matter of basic drives just being in conflict or tension." (59) Similarly, the issue of nihilism can not be one of the presence or absence of urges, because we are not committed to them. Nihilism is an erotic problem, concerned with the failure of desire. Modern bourgeois Europeans have lost the capacity to feel self-contempt for their animal status. (62) In chapter 4, named "The Deed Is Everything [Das Tun ist alles]", Pippin further explains why Nietzsche's conception of the agent - and its self-consciousness - leaves Christian ontological dualism behind. Because of the primordiality of psychology normative considerations are understood as a condition for the intelligibility of our assertions; amounting 2 to the primordiality of esteeming (i.e. the ability to make and keep promises). However, these normative considerations are themselves embedded in depth-commitments, which refer to a "basic orientation of life in terms of eros and erotic attachment, prereflective and prevolitional". (69) In GM Nietzsche aims at providing a historical and genealogical narrative about the 'subject' and identifies the slave rebellion as the momentum of creation of ‘a subject behind the deed’. (70-71) The slave achieves the accomplishment of performing a voluntary deed by choosing to do it, or not, and, as such, the slave rebellion managed for the conception of an unbiased subject with freedom of choice to become successful. When Nietzsche opposes this view of the subject, by denying the possibility of an agent being individually responsible for its actions, he immediately faces the problem of the disappearance of the subject's intention. (68,72) How can a Nietzschean understanding of the subject solve the commonsense psychological view that an agent can stand "both 'behind' and 'before' some activity in order for the event to be distinguishes as a deed at all, as something done by someone"? (72) The answer can be found in Nietzsche's distinction between an activity and the mechanistic senselessness of the ordinary modern scientific worldview (GM II 12). Nietzsche is not denying that there is a subject of the deed, he is just asserting that it is not separate from the activity itself - is in the Christian dualistic understanding. The subject is 'in' the deed. (75) Nietzsche's account of the subject, therefore, relies on the notion of expression of power and not intentional causality. It is only when a subject can recognize itself in the deed, that the deed can be said to "express" the subject. "This means that the act description cannot be separated from this mutable intention, since, as the intention comes into a kind of focus, what it is I take myself to be doing can also alter." (78) Only the deed can show who an agent is or what he is committed to. Pippin's expressivist approach to Nietzsche, furthermore, consists out of an inseperability thesis, in which the determinate meaning of an intention can not be isolated - especially from social and historical factors -, and a nonisolability thesis, where the recognition of an agent's intention as justifying an action depends on the agent's character, life-history and the community or tradition wherein he lives. (77-78) The subject is continually translated in the actuality of the deed and is conversely translated back into the person he is. But how is the sorrow about an action one did to be understood? By denying the subject a separate status from its deeds Nietzsche finds himself in a similar position to Spinoza. Guilt is replaced by sadness at what was expressed in the deed; that I was not who I thought I was. (83) In Chapter 5, titled The Psychological Problem of Self-Deception, Pippin uncovers, through his expressivist approach, the inherent weaknesses of contemporary naturalist interpretations of Nietzsche's writings. Typically, the psychologist reductionist view understands human conduct to be explained by "reference to basic human drives that determined behavior independent of conscious assessments and motives, which were always ex post facto rationalizations." (87) Contrary, Pippin claims, the expenditure of drives is never a pure unconscious expression. A drive doesn't go unnoticed or is beyond conscious control, but is always hidden. The agent hides the real motives. (87-89) Consequently, beside an esteemer the subject can be characterized as a denier (Entsager); who is not just an ascetic, but also an affirmer (Bejahender) (FW 27). Self-deceit, therefore, becomes Nietzsche’s greatest point of interest in his mature works. Slavish behavior, for example, cannot be understood as an outer expression of an inner unconscious drive, enabling the appearance of slavish types or slavish conduct. At the heart of the slave revolt lays self-deceit, because in their morality of sympathy and pity the slaves can hide the cruelty of their rebellion. "The slavish also became divided against themselves; that is, they revolted, something both slavish and not slavish, a double consciousness." (92) Nietzsche tries to approach these phenomena of self-deceit from the perspective of intellectual honesty (Redlichkeit). Thusly, he tries to shame the ones who are deceiving themselves, allowing for a transvaluation to occur. Interpretation, in the 3 psychologist case, is not just finding what lies hidden, as if looking for a cause or symptom, but is about paying attention to how something is hidden. "It matters that the conscious selfunderstanding is an attempted evasion of another and truer self-understanding, just as it matters that the latter is being hidden." (93) To understand the subject’s 'hiding activity' better, Pippin introduces Freud's notion of the unconscious, that understands actions not merely as natural events or sufferings, but as psychologically motivated deeds that I am trying to accomplish, as a second approach to Nietzsche's psychology. "[S]elf-knowledge is not observational but interpretive and, let us say, always promissory, futural, as complexly interpretive as the interpretive question of just what it is that is being done; action explanation is not causal, and motives cannot be understood as fixed, datable mental items." (101) The Nietzschean ideal of self-knowledge is not about being true to your own nature, but lies in the practical fulfillment in your deeds; to become who you are (Du sollst der werden, der Du bist) (FW 270). In Chapter 6, named How to Overcome Oneself: On the Nietzschean Ideal, Pippin asserts that Nietzsche’s impetus to overcome ourselves does not mean that one is really to overcome himself, rather it is an encouragement to endure a fate in a certain way. The psychological self-relation is, therefore, constitutive of the problem of freedom. (108) Understanding freedom as a value or an aspiration to be attained shows Nietzsche, again, as upholding a psychological model in the sense of the French moralists. The self-relation, or self-mastery, consists out of sustaining a wholehearted commitment to an ideal. (113) The conditions for such a self-relation, however, are partly social and historical, going often beyond what an individual can achieve. (116, 120) "The conditions for the attainment of freedom - the proper relation of attachment and detachment - seem, as they have several times before, largely prevoluntary and extend in scope beyond what individuals can do." (116) To be capable of self-overcoming or genuine freedom one must not only be able to bear the personal burden of self-overcoming, but also be able to affirm it under its historical and social conditions. This affirmation of one’s fate causes a state of tension, making the problem of freedom a psychological problem. "That is, Nietzsche clearly considers freedom to consist in some sort of affirmative psychological relation to one's own deeds, a relation of identification, finding oneself in one's deeds, experiencing them as genuinely one's own. He also considers this state of being an achievement rather than the exercise of an inherent capacity. The achieved state in question requires an unusual intentional self-relation, in particular an intentional relation to one's own commitments." (119) Nietzsche's understanding of freedom does not call to a simple strength of will, but for selfovercoming, and since self-overcoming is life or will to power, the realization of will to power lies in self-overcoming. (117,120) 3. Characterization The first four chapters were presentations held in October and November of 2004 at the Collège de France in Paris and were published in book form under the title Nietzsche, moraliste français: La conception nietzschéen d'une psychologie philosophique (2006). The first versions of those chapters/lectures were formed at the Wissenschaftskolleg zu Berlin, where the author stayed on a research leave. Chapters five and six also originated in the form of lectures and were published as articles. As a whole the book is dedicated to the memory of Bernard Williams. 4 4. Critical Points Pippin's Nietzsche, Psychology and First Philosophy argues for the primacy of psychology in Nietzsche's mature works – Also Sprach Zarathustra (Z), Jenseits von Gut und Böse (JGB), Zur Genealogie der Moral (GM) – in an enticing and innovative way. His gained insights into what Nietzsche meant by 'psychology' urges us to reinterpret the psychological question of nihilism as an erotic problem, wherein modern man succumbed to a failure of desire, and to reformulate Nietzsche's naturalism into, what Pippin calls, an expressivism that primarily understands the human being as an esteemer – as formulated in Z 43 and GM II 8. Humans are fore and foremost orienting, esteeming or valuing creatures (schätzen) that have, what Pippin calls, 'attachments' – or 'depth commitments' – as conditions of life. Psychology is of central concern, because it helps to understand the subjects’ passionate identification with a commitment or erotic attachment. (12, 14, 25, 32) "[P]sychology will be a sort of replacement for first philosophy because of the primacy of the 'psychological' question of some basic, always presupposed 'stance toward life' […]." (12) The gain of Pippin's approach is the intriguing insight that Nietzsche's characterization of the philosopher is similar to Plato's: the philosopher is driven by a distinct eros. The philosopher's love for philosophy is a perfect illustration that a human's original erotic attachment is an expression of perspective; of one's attachment to an ideal. The classical reading of the preface of JGB, where philosophers are portrayed as clumsy lovers, is, therefore, incomplete. The image of male philosophers chasing truth as a woman is not a mere rhetorical illustration of the natural situation of the active masculine being that overpowers passive women. The image is explicitly concerned with the philosopher's erotic striving or depth commitment as condition of life. Pippin asserts that this particular approach to psychology makes Nietzsche one "of the great 'French moralists'." (9) The French moralists considered a reliance on a deeper philosophical theory of human nature a limitation to write honestly – cf. Pascal's homme honnête. The goal of Nietzsche's appraisal of psychology over philosophy as "the path to the fundamental problems" (JGB 23) is to provide insight into "how we should understand what happens when people appeal to normative considerations, or try to live well, how those norms come to matter people, how even they could or could not come to matter." (8) In considering these commitments to norms to vary over generations, Nietzsche improves and extends the French moralists model with a necessary historical dimension to the psyche. (3, 31) The best illustration of this primordiality of psychology is GM where Nietzsche offers a historical and genealogical narrative about the 'subject'. (70) To grasp how the 'subject' is to be comprehended in Nietzsche's complex understanding of 'psychology', Pippin proposes a second model: the Freudian notion of the unconscious. A subject's actions are not merely natural events or sufferings, but are psychologically motivated deeds it is trying to accomplish. From this Freudian perspective Pippin brings about the greatest contribution of the book to recent Nietzsche studies: his expressivist reading of the subject-deed relation. His fundamental claim is that human conduct cannot be completely understood by a mere "reference to basic human drives that determined behavior independent of conscious 5 assessments and motives, which were always ex post facto rationalizations." (87) Nietzsche's psychology, understanding the subject as an esteemer or valuator, who upholds a certain (hidden) attitude towards life, comprehends that our drives are not just physical expenditures beyond our conscious control, but are hidden, because we hide them in our continuous interpreting activities. Pippin's expressivism shows that in Nietzsche's philosophy the recursiveness of the deed is pivotal. The deed is an expression of who I am, while it constitutes me at the same time; a relation between subject and deed famously captured in Nietzsche's phrasing of "the deed is everything" in GM I 13. By means of this rejection of a subject behind the deed Nietzsche is, nevertheless, "not denying that there is a subject of the deed. He is just asserting that it is not separate, distinct from the activity itself; it is 'in' the deed." (75) A subject's determinate meaning of its intention cannot be isolated from social and historical factors, and the recognition of a subject's intention as justifying its action depends on the agent's character, life-history and the community or tradition wherein it lives. (77-78) Pippin's expressivist view shows that the will to power, although agreeable with a form of naturalism, casts a serious doubt on all kinds of one-sided readings – those in line with Heidegger, and those reducing Nietzsche to a strictly biological paradigm. (7, 87) Despite our positive considerations, Pippin's expressivist account poses some troublesome problems. Firstly, it is unclear how this new approach is to be aligned with will to power. Pippin's extensive analysis of GM II 12 in the third chapter, where Nietzsche opposes 'activity' to the 'mechanistic senselessness' of modern sciences, is considered to furnish proof that the 'subject is in the deed'. Pippin's argumentation for this is quite adequate, but incomplete since it is plain that Nietzsche is not only concerned with an agent's activity of esteeming, but the activity of will to power. This indistinctness seems to suggest that a treatise of Nietzsche's psychology must address what Nietzsche exactly means by a "physiopsychology" as "morphology and the doctrine of the development of the will to power" (JGB 23). How can the activity of the will to power be explained in a naturalistic vocabulary without falling into a reductionism? We think Pippin's expressivist account forms a decent and well thought-out first step towards a substantial understanding of this biologism, however, in its present form it is too incomplete to accomplish anything like this. The hesitation to specify will to power in Nietzsche's psychology, secondly, makes Pippin's reading of 'will to power' as 'self-overcoming' unwillingly one-dimensional. 'Selfovercoming', being an achievement of some sort of affirmative psychological relation to one's own deeds, is understood as the true expression of will to power. "[T]he true realization of the will to power, genuine freedom, has rather to do with self-overcoming." (120) This hypothetical identification of freedom, as a psychological self-relation (108) or one's affirmative psychological relation to one's deeds, with the summum bonum of will to power seems to be somewhat at odds with the earlier rejection of the doctrine of will to power as a model for psychology in Nietzsche's works. (4) The exact function of will to power to Nietzschean psychology and its understanding of the subject-deed relation remains enigmatic, presenting a third problem: how are we to take hold of the role of 'fate' in Nietzsche's psychology. While we can say that 'fate is expressed in the subject's deeds' (cf. WS 61) – to recuperate Pippin's phrasing – Pippin refrains from framing the subject-deed relation in Nietzsche's understanding of fate. Pippin hints at amor fati at the end of the first chapter and 6 again near the end of the final chapter in considerations about freedom and necessity (116), but never gives a systematic discussion of how his expressivism relates to Nietzsche's understanding of fate. Notwithstanding the difficulties these three issues bring about, we do not consider them to point to an inherent flaw of Pippin's expressivist approach. We think they can rather be ascribed to the book's over-all unsystematic character. This book is still too much a group of lectures, rather than a systematically written exposé and is still in need to homogenize its fundamental claims. The book's unsystematic nature, however, cannot account for the problematic tension between both Pippin's major claims of expressivism and his model of the mind that assumes selfdeceit. His expressivist thesis shows that consciousness cannot be a second-order neutral selfmonitoring of interactions between urges, but is an interpreting activity, assuming very little about human nature. Consciousness, however, is not only understood as an interpretive dynamic, but as self-dissatisfaction. "The self-relation in question is everywhere interpretive and evaluative, involves a self-dissatisfaction (…). (…) Such second-order awareness is originally reactive and negative." (59, 60) Pippin founds his reading on the ground of the depiction of consciousness as a bow under tension. In Z 9 and JGB preface 4 this image illustrates how the soul pulls against itself. (37, 56) We can certainly agree with a discussion of consciousness as tensional; understanding the self-relation primarily as an interpretive dynamic. Therefore, in our sense, Pippin is correct in his assertion that Nietzsche is primarily interested in phenomena of self-deceit. (90) Understanding consciousness as a tensional dynamic whereby a subject's deeper drives or commitments are hidden from himself, is, however, not a controversial or novel claim in Nietzsche receptions. Patton (2008, 472-3) already showed – in reply to the (Deleuze 1977a, 95) – that the notion of ‘feeling of power’ does not only involve the will and how it affects (human) behavior, but also the interpretation and comprehension of (voluntative) agency. Identifying consciousness with self-dissatisfaction is, conversely, a general claim of a certain model of the mind exterior to Nietzsche's philosophy and is a claim we found to be too unsubstantiated to accept. First of all Pippin's account of consciousness in Nietzsche's philosophy is far too incomplete to justify it as reactive. Pippin pays, for example, no attention to Nietzsche's changing view on the impact of consciousness on the human organism. Whereas Nietzsche took an overall positive stance towards consciousness until the middle of the 1880s and even attributed the increasing, critical awareness of the inaccuracy of consciousness to the effectiveness of consciousness itself (FW 11), he disposes of consciousness in the fall of 1886 as a danger or an illness (FW 354). Secondly, although accepting that this tension of consciousness requires a historical explanation –"Nietzsche's account of this tension or self-dissatisfaction is essentially historical." (59) – the nature of consciousness lies in its socially evolved structure between commander and servant and not in reactivity. "Assuming this observation is correct, I may go on to conjecture that […] at the outset, consciousness was necessary, was useful, only between persons (particularly between 7 those who commanded and those who obeyed); and that it has developed only in proportion to that usefulness." (FW 354) The incorporation of this originally social structure into the individual, shows, indeed as Pippin claims, that consciousness is "interpretive and evaluative" (59): “[T]hat consequently each of us, even with the best will in the world to understand ourselves as individually as possible, ‹to know ourselves›, will always bring to consciousness precisely that in ourselves which is ‹non-individual›, that which is ‹average›; that due to the nature of consciousness – to the ‹genius of the species› governing it – our thoughts themselves are continually as it were outvoted and translated back into the herd perspective.” FW 354 (See also GM II 16, Pippin (62)) Nietzsche accentuates that what is brought to a subject's consciousness is hidden and is hidden by the subject itself "due to the nature of consciousness". Because a subject consists out of socially, historically and organically formed structures, phenomena of self-deceit become rich zones of activity to a psychologist in the Nietzschean sense. Nietzsche, however, does not draw from this historical embeddedness of the subject and its self-relation the conclusion that the self's relation to itself is negative or dominated by self-dissatisfaction, as Pippin does. Pippin is correct in his refutation of Bittner's refusal to accept self-deceit as a viable issue in the domain of psychology, however, he underestimates how much of Bittner's objection might be attributed to Pippin's unfortunate choice of terminology, that distorts consciousness from a historically shaped interpretive dynamic into a negative and reactive phenomenon. On the more general point of Pippin's vocabulary, we are surprised, given his Hegelian background, that he did not take the chance to start a constructive discussion between Nietzsche's psychological project of philosophy and Merleau-Ponty's approach to phenomenology as "genetic phenomenology" (2009, 145) or "depth-history"; "remaking the path which has led from the natural world to this superstructure [of tradition]." (2002, 29) Also, we consider Merleau-Ponty's terminological approach to the body and consciousness a more suitable conceptual apparatus to grasp Nietzsche's philosophy, than Pippin's language of 'depth commitment’, 'erotic striving/attachment’, 'self-dissatisfaction', a.o. Even more provocative – but maybe more truthful to Nietzsche's biological phrasings – would be to try to accomplish this in the language of Dual Inheritance Theory, a recent Darwinian model that tries to understand humans as primarily cultural or psychological beings, not held on a leash by genes (Richerson & Boyd 2009). It is also quite puzzling why Pippin does not make use of Hadot's well established terminology of 'spiritual exercises' to account for the issue of a subject's stance toward life, or depth commitment. We do not claim Pippin should have gone about his research in the tradition of Hadot, however, an elaboration of how a depth commitment pertains to a spiritual exercise would be convenient. Finally, Pippin's appealing dissection of the issue of nihilism as a collective failing of desire rather than a simple physiologic degeneration that understands nihilism as an absence or presence of urges (69), does not require his account of self-consciousness as selfdissatisfaction. He successfully shows that the psychological question of nihilism is concerned with the identification of the human being's valuing activity. (52) Suffering, which 8 is unavoidable in this world, "provokes human beings into a complex response"; which is expressed in a reaction distinct for our species: "the burden of the question of the meaning of suffering". (60) Humans do not live their lives prudently avoiding suffering like animals, but need to consciously give account why a certain suffering befalls them. Individuality is, therefore, not just an "original state of being", as with Darwinism, but a "fragile, unstable, threatened, achievement". (61) Pippin stresses that humans, by their continuous valuating activities, are psychologically committed to their attachments toward life. The problem of nihilism is, therefore, not about knowledge or creativity, but about desire. (119) The meaning of suffering, interpreted by morality to be the subject's own sinfulness, changed our selfrelation by disfiguring the dynamic with our drives or erotic striving. How is life to be, correctly or healthily, valued in the face of the question of suffering? We are eager to follow Pippin's analysis of nihilism as a problem of commitment or erotic attachment, explained by his approach of expressivism. (54) However, the presumption about human nature as "a dissatisfaction with its own nature" (61) is, according to us, an unnecessary complication at this point. Discussing nihilism as an erotic problem is an important contribution to Nietzsche studies, despite the lack of proof for Pippin's understanding of nihilism in bourgeois Europe as the loss of the capacity to feel self-contempt at their animal status. (62) 9