Public Law of Europe_Final

advertisement
1
THE PUBLIC LAW OF EUROPE
Reflections on a French 18th century Debate
Published in: Helena Lindemann et al. Erzählungen vom Konstitutionalismus
(Baden-Baden, Nomos 2012), 43-73.
Martti Koskenniemi
The Max Planck Institute in Heidelberg brought out recently a massive fourvolume work on the Ius publicum europaeum, containing comparative essays on
the history and situation of public law in the various European countries.1 The
expression “Ius publicum europaeum” – the “Public law of Europe” – is also
familiar, at least to international lawyers, from the title of Carl Schmitt’s
polemical analysis of the territorial order that was centred on Europe between
the 16th and 19th centuries.2 But as both a product and a critique of that order,
the expression originates in France where its first widely published appearance
took place in the title of a collection of treaties between European nations from
the Peace of Westphalia to the mid-18th century, namely Abbé Gabriel Bonnot de
Mably’s Droit public de l’Europe (1746).3 Mably published the treaties together
with commentaries on the context of their conclusion and their objectives and
later supplemented this work with a long essay in which he sketched a “science
of negotiations” the mastery of which would enable European monarchs and
diplomats to pursue their fundamental interests in peace and war rationally, in
accordance with their relative power, and so to avoid the calamities that their
ambition, greed and fear had caused in the past.4
Armin von Bogdandy, Pedro Cruz Villalón & Peter M. Huber, Handbuch Ius Publicum Europaeum
(4 vols., Heidelberg, Müller 2008).
2 Carl Schmitt, Der Nomos der Erde im Völkerrecht des Jus Publicum Europaeum (Berlin, Duncker &
Humblot, 1988 [1950]).
3 Gabriel Bonnot de Mably, Le droit public de l’Europe. Fondé sur les traitez conclus jusqu’en
l’année 1740 (2 vols, The Hague, Duren 1746). The work had many subsequent editions. One
with Mably’s last version of the famous introductory essay came out as Le droit public de l’Europe.
Fondé sur les traitsés. Précédés de Principes des négociations pour servir d’introduction. Nouvelle
édition (Amsterdam & Leipzig, Arkstée et Merkus 1773).
4 Modern edition: Gabriel Bonnot de Mably, Principes de négociations pour servir d’introduction au
droit public de l’Europe.(Intr. & notes par Marc Bélissa, Paris, Kimé 2001), 45. It is to this edition
that references below will be made.
1
2
The present essay is a brief reflection of the context in which Mably published
his three-volume treatise with its lengthy introduction. I am especially
concerned to show that the topos of Droit public de l’Europe in 18th century
France differed significantly from the way the tradition of natural law and the
law of nations as we know it from Hobbes, Grotius and Pufendorf developed
elsewhere on the continent or in Britain. Mably’s “science of public law”
employed a vocabulary of naturalism but focused on the enlightened interests of
monarchs and their states, suggesting that “Europe” might be best conceived
analogously to a market where everyone’s regard for their own security and
welfare would bring out the greatest good of all. The demise in Germany of the
natural law tradition at this time led, among other things, to a conception of
positive treaty-based European international order. In Britain, it led to Adam
Smith and the rise of political economy. In France, however, Droit public de
l’Europe became a mixed bag of traditional raison d’état and modern economic
providentialism that finally crystallised in a doctrine of Jacobine virtue that
ended up eating proverbially its own children. By 1815, the Public law of Europe
had become another name for the system of restoration enshrined in the Vienna
treaties as reported and analysed especially by German academics.5
1. The Time of Absolutism
French jurists played a central role in the development of constitutional law and
political theory during the wars of religion. That “[t]he state rapidly
disintegrated into a composite of local seigneuries, city-states and factions which
warred with royalty itself”6 prompted anxious theorization on the powers of the
king vis-à-vis the nobility and the estates and on the role of provincial
parlements. On all sides of the controversy – Catholic, Protestant and politique –
jurists put forward historically informed constitutional theses in support of their
respective positions. The most famous product of the debates was Jean Bodin’s
(1530-1596) Six livres de la république (1576) that laid out the theory of
See my ‘Into Positivism: Georg Friedrich von Martens (1756-1821) and Modern International
Law’ in 15 Constellations. An International Journal of Critical and Democratic Theory (2008), 189207
6 Frank W Church, Constitutional Thought in Sixteenth Century France. A Study in the Evolution of
Ideas (Boston 1941), 74.
5
3
sovereignty as the “absolute and perpetual power over the commonwealth”.7
This theory – by no means invented by Bodin – articulated in legal terms the
need of a strong central power that could put an end to the internal chaos by
uniting the country around a strong monarchy. It was used to full effect by
Cardinal Richelieu whose long reign (1616-1642) contributed to the silencing of
further debate on public law and the constitutional limits of supreme power.
Bodin had regarded sovereignty compatible with a robust set of fundamental
laws, natural law and the law of nations.8 Half a century later Cardin Le Bret
(1558-1655) had in his De la souveraineté du Roi (1632) removed French
sovereignty from being subordinated to any secular standards – “sa première
marque est de ne dépendre que de Dieu seul”.9 There was no international
normative order, indeed no secular normativity at all. The power to wage war, to
conclude or to break treaties came from the inside of the divine sovereignty of
the “Most Christian King”.
In the 17th century, the place of jurists as articulators of the political reality was
taken by intellectuals and courtiers writing in a raison d’état mode such as the
Duke of Rohan (1579-1638), focusing on techniques whereby the ruler could
solidify or enlarge his realm. A new political category of the “interest” developed
as a guide to government and policy, “the tyrant of tyrants”.10 Ever since
Giovanni Botero’s (1544-1617) first venture in this genre, it became axiomatic to
think that this interest would differ from state to state and between monarchs so
that an in-depth discussion of it would require a separate treatment of different
types of state – great powers, small powers, maritime and land powers and so
on. The “reason of state” would not be expressed in general rules but directives
that would be specific to the situation of every state or a dynasty.11 This
Jean Bodin, On Sovereignty. Four Chapters from the Six Books of the Commonwealth (J. Franklin
ed., Cambridge University Press1992 [1576]), Bk I Ch 8 (1).
8 See e.g. Jean-Fabien Spitz, Bodin et la souverainété (Paris, PUF 1998), 11-30.
9 Cardin Le Bret ‘De la souverainété’. In Les Œuvres de Messire C Le Bret (Paris, Du Bray 1643), I.II
(5).
10 Bocciali as quoted in Etienne Thuau, Raison d’état et la penseé politique a l’époque ei Richelieu
(Paris, Albin Michel 2000), 313.
11 See further Thuau, Raison d’état and the excellent Christian Lazzeri, ‘Introduction’ to Henri de
Rohan, De l’intérêt des princes et des Etats de la chrétienté (Paris, PUF 1995), 1-152. I have dealt
with this matter also in ‘International Law and raison d’état: Rethinking the Prehistory of
7
4
undermined theorization over public law or the law of nations. Grotius, Hobbes
and Pufendorf had written their naturalist tracts as scientific pieces, intended for
universal application. By contrast, the reference in French public law was always
France itself.12 If something was said of other countries, this was only by way of
comparison and invariably to France’s advantage. De Bret lavishly congratulated
the French for the excellence of the monarchy and the glories of France’s history.
Under divine kingship even the just war tradition tended to coalesce with what
the (French) King wanted.
Moreover, natural law had begun to appear largely as a preserve of
Protestantism, used by the Huguenots to attack Louis’ alleged efforts at
“universal monarchy”. 13 There was something to this of course. The search for
La gloire remained predominant as a war motive even as the actual operations
turned from conquest to protecting the security of the realm.14 By the end of the
century, however, France was exhausted by its endless wars. The countryside
had been abandoned and bad harvests in 1693-94 contributed to widespread
famine in rural areas. Wanton destruction in the course of the war effort had
created an anti-French coalition in Europe further contributing to dissatisfaction
at home for which there was no open channel of expression.
Even a privileged observer, Archbishop Fénelon (1651-1715), the preceptor of
the royal princes at Versailles, had to summarise the early criticisms in terms of
the malevolence of Louis’ courtiers, indifference towards the suffering of the
population, the uses of glory and vengeance as motives of war: “une guerre
injuste n’en est pas moins injuste pour être heureuse”.15 What Fénelon suggested
International Law’, in Benedict Kingsbury & Benjamin Straumann, The Roman Foundations of the
Law of Nations. Alberico Gentili and the Justice of Empire (Oxford University Press 2010), 305-320.
12 On the intense connection between the (knowledge of) public law and absolutism in 17 th
century France, see also Michel Foucault, Il faut defender la société. Cours au College de France
1976 (Paris, Gallimard/Seuil 1997), 109-112, 156-158.
13 See e.g. Samuel Pufendorf, Of the Nature and Qualification of Religion in Reference to Civil
Society (1687) (Indianapolis, Liberty Fund 2002), 11-12, § 5-6 (17-18); Gottfried W. Leibniz,
‘Mars Christianissimus’, (1683) in Political Writings (P Riley ed., Cambridge University Press
1972), 121-145.
14 On the predominant role of “glory” in Louis’ wars, see John A. Lynn, The Wars of Louis XIV 16671714 (London, Longmans, 1999), 27-43.
15 Francois de Salignac de la Mothe-Fénelon, ‘Lettre à Louis XIV’, in Lettre à Louis XIV et autres
écrits politiques (Paris, Bartillat 2011), 49.
5
in his instructions to his royal student was adherence to “common rules of
justice and humanity”, faithfulness and modesty in public and private life and the
prohibition of morally dangerous trade of “luxuries”.16 This was also a key theme
in Fénelon’s most famous book, The Adventures of Telemachus, Son of Ulysses
(1699). Here Fénelon celebrated ancient virtues as the proper directions to
govern France, consisting above all of moral adroitness, modesty, love of truth
and justice, keeping one’s word even to one’s enemies and following the laws of
war and humanity.17 As Telemachus arrived on the Island of Crete, admired by
visitors and famous for its prosperous villages, he found out that the only reason
for unhappiness on the island emerged from the desire for superfluities. Hence,
Minos, the wisest of lawmakers, had decreed that children should be educated in
the simple life, to compete in the excellence of virtue. “Courage” was associated
not only with fearlessness in war but trampling excess riches underfoot. “Ici on
punit trois vices qui sont impunies chez les autres peoples: l’ingratitude, la
dissimulation et l’avarice”.18
Fénelon rejected the separation of private and public morality that had
accompanied the doctrine of arcana imperii promoted by Richelieu and the
raison d’état publicists.19 In his view, what was lacking was moral leadership
under the king that would educate the country in peacefulness and virtue;
economic resources, for example, ought to be oriented towards flourishing
agriculture and not wasted in superfluities.20 A State that would grow
prosperous by relying on domestic resources, he argued, would also be stronger
in its foreign policy and have no need for demonstrations of militarism.21 In the
upcoming intellectual battle between the “ancients” and the “moderns”, Fénelon
Francois de Salignac de la Mothe-Fénelon, ‘Examen de conscience sur les devoirs de royauté.
Mémoire pour le duc de Bourgogne’ (c. 1708-9) , in Lettre à Louis XIV, 75, 80-85.
17 Id. 101.
18 Francois de Salignac de la Mothe-Fénelon, ‘Les aventures de Télémaque, fils d’Ulysses,’ in
Ouvres de Fénelon, Archevêque de Cambrai, (Tome 3, Paris, Lefevre, 1835 [1699]), 26.
19 See further Martti Koskenniemi, ‘International law and Raison d’État. Rethinking the
Prehistory of International Law’, in Benedict Kingsbury & Benjamin Strumann (eds), The Roman
Foundations of the Law of Nations. Alberico Gentili and the Justice of Empire (Oxford University
Press 2011), 308-310.
20 Istvan Hont, Jealousy of Trade. International Competition and the Nation-State in Historical
Perspective (Harvard University Press 2006), 25-27.
21 For a comment, see Michael Sonenscher, Before the Deluge. Public Debt, Inequality, and the
Intellectual Origins of the French Revolution (Princeton University Press 2007), 110.
16
6
would epitomise those looking to examples of antique virtue against the
supporters of commercial modernity. This put him on the minority in
eighteenth-century French debates. The language of virtuous rule would reemerge towards the end of the century, but then in a wholly different context.
2. The Peace of Utrecht
The death of Charles II of Spain in 1700 created the danger of the union of
French and Spanish crowns. The war that followed opposed the “Grand
Coalition” of Austria, Britain and the Netherlands (later joined by Savoy and
Portugal) against France. In this context, Féneleon composed a series of
memoranda for friends in the court to speak against the war.22 He also lamented
the slowness of the peace talks and proposed to include in the delegations men
of “substantive reputation” who would be alien to the kinds of scheming that he
assumed would take place in regular peace talks.23 It was not to be so. The
French minister Colbert de Torcy (1665-1746) used seasoned courtiers whom
he could trust to outmanoeuvre their counterparts in the best tradition of ancien
regime diplomacy. The negotiations lasted for many years and involved precisely
the kind of secret bargaining, sometimes directly between the ministers, that
Fénelon wished to exorcise from virtuous policymaking.24
The expression “droit public européen” appeared in the Franco-Dutch Peace
treaty, one of the many instruments forming the Peace of Utrecht (1713) to
recognize the types of derivative title in international law that had been familiar
already to Grotius.25 But the notion was also linked to the principle of the
balance of power that underlay the whole effort of treaty-making at Utrecht,
For the Memoranda, see Oevres de Fénelon, Achevêque de Cambrai. (Tôme 3, Paris, Lefevre,
1835), 410-441.
23 See Lucien Bély, L’art de la paix en Europe. Naissance de la diplomatie moderne XVIe – XVIII
siècle (Paris, PUF 2007), 433, 452.
24 Bély, L’art de la paix, 503-524. A good account of the conduct of the peace talks from the French
perspective is in Dale Miquelon, ‘Envisioning the French Empire: Utrecht 1711-1713’, 24 French
Historical Studies (2991), 653-677.
25 Wilhelm Grewe, Epochs of International Law (Berlin, De Gruyter 2000), 395.
22
7
marking a shared desire to work against “universal monarchy”.26 Already
Fénelon had advocated the need for European powers to ally against the
inevitably hegemonic designs of the strongest among them. Such leagues, he
wrote, would serve the role that laws and magistrates served in domestic
contexts. To seek equilibrium was to work “à la liberté, à la tranquillité, et salut
public”. It was to operate a kind of “loi naturelle de la sûreté de…nations”.27 As
Emer de Vattel put it half a century later, had the powers allowed the union of
the two crowns, they would have delivered “Europe to servitude, or at least to
the most critical and precarious situation”. Vattel concluded that Europe now
formed a “political system” with closely connected interests that can be best
preserved by maintaining a “political equilibrium” and “forming confederacies in
order to oppose the more powerful potentate, and prevent him from giving law
to his neighbours”.28
Alongside the diplomatic organization of Europe the Utrecht treaties also
contained provision on the Anglo-French colonial settlement in North America as
well as other territorial issues (Britain received Gibraltar and France parts of the
Habsburg inheritance in Spanish Netherlands, Milan and Sardinia) and on the
fate of the asiento – the transfer of the monopoly of Atlantic slave trade to the
English South Sea Company.29 It was no utopian peace arrangement. But the
world around it was in full change. The “crisis of European conscience” that had
permeated intellectual life at the turn of the century was slowly passing.30 Early
Enlightenment intellectuals viewed many aspects of the ancien regime, including
its dynastic wars, with a critical eye. The peacemakers at Westphalia three
quarters of a century earlier had been content in consolidating the state system
as a response to the religious crisis. Eighteenth-century spirits aimed higher,
See also Marc Bélissa, Fraternité universelle et intérêt national (1713-1795). Les
cosmopolitiques du droit des gens (Paris, Kimé 1998), 85-86.
27 Francois de Salignac de la Mothe-Fénelon, ‘Sur la necessité des former des alliances, tanst
offensives que defensives contre une puissance étrangère qui aspire manifestement à la
monarchie universelle’, in Œuvres De Fénelon, 3, 360-363, 361a-b.
28 Emer de Vattel, The Law of Nations (Ed & intr by B .Kapossy and R. Whatmore, (Indianapolis,
Liberty Fund 2008 [1758]), Bk III Ch III § 44,47, 48 (493, 496-7).
29 The point about the centrality of the trade aspects of the treaty arrangements especially for
France is made in Dale Miquelon, ‘Envisioning the French Empire’, in 24 French Historical Studies
(2001), 654-655.
30 See Paul Hazard, Le crise de la conscience européenne 1680-1715 (Paris, Fayard 1961),
especially 225 et seq.
26
8
speculating on science, history and a universal law of nations, debating the
values of secularism and enlightened rule over European populations.31 The last
years of the Sun King’s rule had demonstrated the international extension of
domestic absolutism. Something had to be done to tackle it.
3. Abbé de Saint-Pierre: between Reason and Passion
One of the participants in this debate was Charles Irenée Castel, Abbé de SaintPierre (1658-1743). 32 In the context of the negotiations to the Treaty of Utrecht,
Saint-Pierre produced the most widely read proposal in the 18th century
concerning the establishment of an international institution designed to secure
peace in Europe, the Mémoire pour rendre la paix perpetuelle en Europe.33 This
“memorandum” was followed up by successive editions of the much larger 3volume Projet pour rendre la paix perpetuelle en Europe.34 It is not known
whether the author himself had been present in Utrecht. There is no mention of
him in the Acta diplomatica. But he was a friend and assistant to the Cardinal de
Polignac who was one of the French negotiators.35 There is no doubt that the
See especially Marc Bélissa, Fraternité universelle et intérêt national (1713-1795). Les
cosmopolitiques du droit des gens (Paris, Kimé 1998) 7-18, passim.
32 Saint-Pierre had been educated in Jesuit colleges but never joined the clergy. Instead he moved
to Paris where he received powerful mentors close to the court of Louis XIV. His early years were
devoted to science and he was appointed to the Académie française in 1695 from which, however,
he was later expelled owing to his attacks on the regime. He had been appalled by the clientelism
and inefficiency of the last years of the reign of the Sun King. In a number of articles and letters,
Saint-Pierre proposed fiscal reforms and the introduction of proportional taxation as remedies to
the crisis. See Merle J. Perkins, The Moral and Political Philosophy of the Abbé de Saint-Pierre
(Geneva, Droz 1959), 73-81. He believed that financial mismanagement had led to a situation
where the State could no longer receive credit at levels that would enable carrying out of even
normal administrative tasks. He advocated turning state administration into an impersonal
bureaucracy to prevent its use for the purposes of corruption. The rule of law was needed for
concerns of efficiency and for the preservation of the liberty of the citizens. See Thomas E. Kaiser,
‘The Abbé de Saint-Pierre, Public Opinion, and the Reconstitution of the French Monarchy’, 55
Journal of Modern History (1983), 618-643. Saint-Pierre was no enthusiast of the abstract and
unorganised debates on natural law. An effectual politics was to be based on “evidence” and
“esprit de raisonnement”; it would need to be of practical use in the administration of the state.
In order to teach political science methodologically he suggested the establishment of an
Académie politique that would teach a new science, namely a science de government.
33 Charles Castel de Saint-Pierre, Mémoire du projet pour rendre la paix perpetuelle (pour le
ministre M. de Torcy, 1 septembre, 1712).
34 Projet pour rendre la paix perpetuelle entre les Souverains Chretiens, (Utrecht, Schouten 1717).
The version usually referred to, and on which Rousseau, for example, based his “Extract” and
“Judgment”, is the shortened version, Abregé du projet de paix perpetuelle (Rotterdam, Beman
1729).
35 Perkins, Moral and Political Philosophy, note 32 supra, at 51.
31
9
reference in the peace plan to “the present peace” – which Saint-Pierre says
cannot be believed to be lasting – was precisely to the treaties made at Utrecht in
1713.36 As a literary achievement, the Projet was unimpressive. It consisted of
three volumes of poorly organised, repetitive arguments in defence of a
permanent organisation in Europe to guarantee the peace and security among
European sovereigns and for resolving any disputes through arbitration. Perhaps
for this reason, Saint-Pierre produced an Abregé of the plan in 1729 that then
remained the focus of debate on the nature and possibility of peace in Europe
throughout the 18th century.
Saint-Pierre did not believe in a universal peace system. In the first version of the
project he included both Turkey and Russia, but later on dropped Turkey and
even came to advocate joint European war against it. Adopting the plan, SaintPierre wrote, Europe’s monarchies could guarantee their safety and external and
internal dangers – in fact the plan was more concerned with domestic rebellion
than interstate war. The plan would also enable peaceful growth of trade and
industry, and thus also contribute to the prosperity of the ruling dynasties.37
Mutual promises among sovereigns, truces, commercial treaties, guarantees and
alliances, he wrote, were fragile and easily overridden. They, like the balance of
power, were dependent on the whims of princes and changes of national fortune:
“Il est impossble de que le Système de l’Équilibre rende la paix durable en
Europe; qu’ainsi les malheurs de la Guerre se renouvelleront incessamant
& dureront tant qu’il n’y aura pas entre les Souverainetez Chrétiennes une
Société permanente qui leur donne sûreté suffisante de l’execution des
promesses fairtes dans les Traitez…”38
Saint-Pierre thus proposed the establishment of a permanent institution, a Union
européenne with 18 or 24 sovereign members (the number varied in different
Abbé de Saint-Pierre, Abregé du projet de paix perpetuelle (Rotterdam, Beman 1729). As a
literary achievement, the Projet was unimpressive. It consisted of three volumes of poorly
organised, repetitive arguments in defense of a permanent organisation in Europe to guarantee
the peace and security among European sovereigns and for resolving any disputes through
arbitration. Perhaps for this reason, the Abbé produced an Abregé of the plan in 1729 that then
remained the focus of much debate of the nature and possibility of peace in Europe throughout
the 18th century.
37 Saint-Pierre, Mémoire, Troisième discours, 153.
38 Saint-Pierre, Mémoire, Deuxième disocurs, 73.
36
10
parts of the plan) all of which would be Christian, European States.39 The draft
Treaty on the European Union contained 12 “fundamental” and 8 “important”
articles that included five principal elements. 40
First, the members of the union would agree to preserve the existing territorial
and dynastic status quo in Europe. The Union was not to intervene in the affairs
of its members for any other reason than for implementing the guarantees,
including the suppression of any domestic dissent (“à soumettre les esprits
rebelles”).41 The plan included an engagement – taken in view of the problem of
Spanish succession – that no sovereign could rule over two or more States.
Peaceful changes were allowed, and territorial or succession disputes were to be
resolved through arbitration. Second, the permanent institution of the European
Union was to be set up in which the sovereigns would be represented in a Senate,
each of them having one vote.42 The fundamental articles could be amended only
by unanimous vote while the “important” ones required a three quarters’
majority. Thirdly, the Senate was to organise European commerce on the basis
of a general most-favoured nation treatment. It would also set up a Chamber of
Commerce in each major town that would have alternate jurisdiction to
adjudicate trade disputes. The members of the union would see to the
enforcement of any judgment thus made. Fourthly, the Senate would also
arbitrate between sovereigns. A member taking arms or refusing to execute a
judgment would be declared the enemy of all. 43 Fifthly, there would be a joint
military force to protect the Union from external dangers – particularly against
the Turks – as well as internal dangers, rebellion and civil war. All costs would be
In making his proposal, Saint-Pierre wrote that he was following the examples of the
constitution of the German-Roman Empire and the famous plan of the foreign minister of Henry
IV, the Duke of Sully. Both claims were dubious. Saint Pierre believed – wrongly – that the
German estates had entered the empire as sovereigns and that Sully’s specific had not really been
to direct the plan against Austria. In Fact, the German estates had never been sovereign and the
hegemonic purposes of Sully’s design were well-known. See Patrick Riley, ‘The Abbé de St. Pierre
and Voltaire on Perpetual Peace in Europe’, 137 World Affairs (1974), 187-189.
40 Saint-Pierre, Mémoire, Quatrième discours, 271-366.
41 Saint-Pierre, Mémoire, Quatrième discours, 273. Article 2 provided that the union could take
action to see to it that the monarchic or republican form is maintained but also that the internal
electoral laws and capitulations are honoured (276-277) and article 3 that during periods of
regency or othereise weakness in ruling house, nothing threatens its security (279-281).
42 Article 1, Saint-Pierre, Mémoire, Quatrième discours, 271.
43 Saint-Pierre, Mémoire, Quatrième discours, 308.
39
11
collected as contributions from members, allocated in accordance with their
relative wealth at the conclusion of the treaty.
Despite his reputation as idealist and a pacifist, Saint-Pierre was actually neither
one nor the other. His proposals were not written in the form of utopias in the
manner of a More or a Campanella. Unlike Fénelon, he had a bleak view of human
nature. We are slaves of our passions, he held, and when carried away by them,
the only thing that can restrain us is
“…la crainte d’un mal plus fâcheux et plus terrible que le bien qu’il desire
de ne peut paraître desirable”. 44
Like many contemporaries, Saint-Pierre felt that the bonds of virtue were
loosening and that moral education or the example of the ancients would not halt
this. His experience as the Chaplain of the Duchess of Orléans from 1692 had
convinced him of the decisive role of passions in public life. They could not be
tamed by mere appeals to reason, the standards of Christian piety or natural law.
The proposal was therefore not to get rid of passions but to turn them for
virtuous purposes. 45 As suggested by Spinoza (1632-1677): “An affect cannot be
restrained or taken away except by an affect opposite to, and stronger than, the
affect to be restrained”.46
Saint-Pierre’s plan was based on a realist, even a Hobbesian view of human
nature and European politics. It relied on utilitarian, self-interested calculations
of the sovereigns themselves. “Mon dessein est de montrer avec évidence que
tous les Souverains ont plus d’intérêt de signer la Traité fondamentale, que de
réfuser de signer”.47 Saint-Pierre even made his own the famous saying of the
proto-realist Duke of Rohan – “princes command peoples, but interest
commands princes”.48 He did not try to reform princes but to convince them that
Abbé de Saint-Pierre, as cited in Merle L. Perkins, ‘Civil Theology in the Writings of the Abbé de
Saint-Pierre’, 18 Journal of the History of Ideas (1957), 245.
45 This is the classic point in Albert Hirschmann, The Passions and the Interests. Political
Arguments for Capitalism before its Triumph (Princeton University Press 1997[1977]).
46 Benedict de Spinoza, Ethics (trans E Curley, intr. S Hampshire, Harmondsworth, Penguin 1996
[1677]) II/215 (120).
47 Saint-Pierre, Abregé, 42.
48 Saint-Pierre, Projet, 66-71.
44
12
they had a genuine interest in peace, that peace, rather than war, was the best
way for European monarchs to preserve their security and well-being. They
could, of course, continue to wage wars and sign peace treaties. But in so doing
they could never be certain that their neighbours might not immediately breach
their promises once they felt they had developed the capacity for victory.
Moreover, even if princes could guarantee peace for themselves, they could not
guarantee it to their dynasties in the future.49
As long as sovereigns could breach their promises with impunity, nothing could
make them feel safe. As with humans in general, the only way to durable peace
was to set up a formidable authority that could launch revenge immediately
when unjust passions take over. This, of course, is what Hobbes had been saying
in the context of the English civil war half a century earlier. Saint-Pierre was
careful not to refer to Hobbes but what he was saying about international peace
amounted to the same.50 The only way to restrain monarchs was to provide for a
supranational authority that can take action against them in case they violate the
peace. But this introduced a tension in the proposal: if they really were
passionate runners after instant gratification – why would they suddenly become
rational interest-maximisers?
4. Rousseau: the politics of irony
The Projet was widely circulated among French elites who generally regarded
them as hopelessly inadequate and contradictory. As Voltaire saw it, it was as
likely that peace could be maintained among European sovereigns “as the peace
between elephants and rhinoceros, wolves and dogs. Carnivorous animals will
Saint-Pierre, Abregé, 12-13.
He was, as Celine Spector has put it, “’hobbesien’ à l’intérieur mais utopiste a l’extérieur” –
while Rousseau, for his part, was “utopian” from the inside but “realist” from the outside, ‘Le
projet de paix perpetuelle: De Saint-Pierre à Rousseau’, in Jean-Jacques Rousseau. Principes du
droit de la guerre. Ecrits sur la paix perpetuelle (B Bachofen & C Spector (dir), B Bernardi & G
Silvestrini (eds), Paris, Vrin 2008), 275-276. On Saint-Pierre’s Hobbesianism, see Perkins, The
Moral and Political Philosophy of the Abbé de Saint-Pierre, 52-62. See also Thomas Kaiser, ‘The
Abbé de saint-Pierre, Public Opinion and the Reconstruction of the French Monarchy’, 55 Journal
of Modern History (1983), 626-627.
49
50
13
tear each other apart at the first occasion”.51 When the project was
communicated to the Cardinal Fleury, the effective ruler of France during the
period of the Regency, the latter read it sympathetically, responding only: “Vous
avez oubliez un article essentiel, celui d’envoyer des missionaries pour toucher
les coeurs des princes et les persuader d’entrer dans vos vues”. 52 The selfdefeating character of the proposal seemed obvious to many. It was based on the
assumption that Europe would be ruled by monarchical absolutists who were
now suggested to give up a part of their absolute powers for an international
Union. The most famous comments were those by Jean-Jacques Rousseau,
written respectively as Extract of the Plan for Perpetual Peace in 1756 and
published five years later and the Judgment on Perpetual Peace, written in that
same year but published only in 1782. The former was a popularization of the
plan, the latter a statement of Rousseau’s own view on it.53
Rousseau used much ink to express his admiration of Saint-Pierre – so much so
in fact that the reader is left some doubt about whether the praise was intended
seriously. He began his critique by noting that “[i]f ever moral truth were
demonstrated, I should say that it is the utility, national no less than
international of this project”.54 But how he actually viewed the Abbé’s plan and
what his own suggested resolution was has been the object of endless
commentary. Two aspects of this critique are noteworthy.
On the one hand, Rousseau attacked the view that the plan could operate with
the present system of European government. Neither the monarchs nor their
states represented what was “reasonable”: of this the books of “savants and
jurisconsults” knew nothing.55. The natural lawyers – Hobbes, Grotius and
Pufendorf – had suggested that sovereigns were needed as a rational response to
Quoted in Jean-Pierre Bois, L’Europe à l’époque moderne: origines, utopies et réalités de l’idée
d’Europe (Paris, Colin 1999), 211.
52 Quoted in Frank L. Schuman, ‘The Ethics and Politics of International Peace’, 42 International
Journal of Ethics (1932), 149.
53 Both now published and commented in Rousseau. Principes du droit de la guerre.
54 Jean-Jacques Rousseau, ‘Jugement de paix perpetuelle’, in Principes du droit de la guerre, 116
55 Rousseau, ‘Principes du droit de la guerre’, in Principes du droit de la guerre, 69-81.
51
14
the violence in the state of nature.56 Even Grotius, though acknowledging natural
sociability, thought sovereigns necessary to maintain civil peace and that citizens
therefore had only the most limited right of resistance. All this was perversion.
Humans were not naturally warlike; even as egoists, they did not seek to destroy
each other. In producing a justification for state power, the tradition actually
created the situation from which it claimed to produce an exit. “All ran towards
their chains believing that they were securing their liberty”.57 War did not end
with the establishment of States, but began with it. The law of nations was
powerless in this respect: it was followed only when that seemed useful.58 The
ambitions of states and sovereigns (unlike that of humans) were unlimited and
their incessant suspicion of each other rendered all quarrels dangerous,
compelling a circle of mutual destruction.59
But Rousseau’s proposal to correct this state of things was anything but straightforward. Monarchs will never sign into a federation, not even a confederation
that went beyond momentary interests. But a revolution would not repair this
state of things, either. The sovereignty of the people being inalienable and
indivisible, it was unthinkable that the peoples could conclude a world
federation among themselves. True, small republics might form confederations
to find safety against great powers. But this arrangement would operate under
the old system of treaties and still be based on the interests of the parties and not
in any general interest of humanity or even of “Europe”. So Rousseau came to the
melancholy conclusion that the proposal for perpetual peace in Europe remained
“the illusions of a truly human heart”, admirable but unworkable and not capable
of being resuscitated in a reviewed form. Rousseau thus took leave from any
In Du contrat social (1762) Rousseau attacked Grotius’ “characteristic method of reasoning
[which] is always to offer fact as proof of right. It is possible to imagine a more logical method,
but not one more favourable to tyrants”. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract (M. Cranston
transl. & intr. Harmondsworth, Penguin 1958), 51 The target here was the weight Grotius
attached to customs and treaty practices as evidence of the content of the law – his famous “a
posteriori” method.
57 Jean-Jacques Rousseau, A Discourse on Inequality (M. Cranston transl. & intr., Harmondworth,
penguin 1984), Part II (122).
58 Rousseau, ‘Principes du droit de la guerre’, in Principes du droit de la guerre, 70.
59 Jean-Jacques Rousseau, ‘Principes du droit de la guerre’, in Principes du droit de la guerre, 7778.
56
15
project of perpetual peace. Under the present conditions, it was realisable only
by violence.
“Enfin les préjugés sont tellement contraires à toute espèce de
changement qu’à moins d’avoir la force en main il faut être aussi simple
que l’Abbé de Saint-Pierre pour proposer la moindre innovation dans
quelque gouvernement que se soit”. 60
For Rousseau, the price of internal peace attained through the social contract is
the externalisation of aggression – that is endemic, structurally determined
warfare between nations.61 In the longest part of his judgment of Saint-Pierre’s
proposal, Rousseau produced a mini-history of European politics from Charles V
onwards. This proved that the public interest was never anyone’s particular
interest. Even the peace plan attributed to Henry IV was in fact an effort to make
France Europe’s greatest power. The best moments have been those when an
equilibrium has existed, and for this, there had often been reason to thank the
Holy German Empire. 62
5. The Encyclopaedists
Like Rousseau, the philosophes were generally critical of the natural law
tradition.63 The thick works on ius naturae et gentium produced at German
universities were usually commented no further than to note the flagrant
contradiction between their heavy and repetitive style and the stylistic ideals of
the salon. Voltaire’s attitude is typical, and expressed with characteristic
sharpness. Instead of reading Grotius and Pufendorf, people should take up the
ancient writers on the topic of natural law and the law of nations:
“Croyez-moi, lisez les Offices de Cicéron. Rien ne contribuera peut-être plus à
rendre un esprit faux, obscure, confus, incertain, que de lecture de Grotius &
Puffendorf, & de Presque tous les commentaires sur le Droit public”.64
Jean-Jacques Rousseau, ‘Fragment sur le projet de paix perpetuelle’, in Principes du droit de la
guerre, 127.
61 Rousseau, A Discourse on Inequality, 122-123..
62 Rousseau, ‘Jugement sur la paix perpetuelle’, 122-125.
63 See generally Marc Bélissa, Fraternité, 69-84.
64 Voltaire, Dictionnaire philosophique (nouvelle edition, tome III, Amsterdam, Rey, 1789), 513.
60
16
But Voltaire himself could not avoid making frequent reference to natural law, as
indeed did all of his colleagues. This is understandable. What could have become
of the Déclaration de droits de l’homme et du citoyen without a literary culture
that habitually received all good things from “nature” and its laws? The
philosphes had no choice but to resuscitate ancient notions of law and morality.65
But these references appeared predominantly as rhetorical devices, appealing to
the readers’ recognition of the self-evident truth of what was being said, clearing
the way for the work of reform they were interested in.66 If a more elaborate
grounding was needed, they utilised the analytical method that suggested that
society, like nature, ought to be dissolved into its composite parts in order to
examine its operation – that it was to be analysed by interpreting individual
behaviour empirically by reference to the “passions” that they assumed guided
human motivation.67
In the Preliminary Discourse to his and Diderot’s Encyclopaedia (1751), for
example, d’Alembert recounted practically the whole of cultural progress in
terms of utilitarian need-fulfilment. The development of arts and sciences
emerged from “[t]he necessity of protecting our own bodies from pain and
destruction”, especially from the effort of the body to provide for “its endlessly
multiplying needs”.68 The historical progress of arts would begin from the more
immediately necessary (such as agriculture and medicine) and develop into
increasingly more abstract forms – physics, geometry and so on. Through this
process we also discover “that natural law which we find within us, the source of
the first laws which men must of necessity have created”. Its origin he attributed,
as a good empiricist, to the universal experience of oppression suffered by the
Carl Becker, The Heavenly City of the Eighteenth-Century Philosophers (2nd edn., Yale University
Press 2003 [1932]), 33-70.
66 See Peter Gay, ‘Voltaire and Natural Law’, in Voltaire’s politics. The Poet as Realist (Princeton
University Press 1959), 343-346 and The Party of Humanity. Essays in the French Enlightenment
(New York, Norton 1959), 60-62, and (an express response to Becker), 198-202 and further Marc
Bélissa, Fraternité, 69-70.
67 For this method, see e.g. Ernst Cassirer, The Philosophy of the Enlightenment (Princeton
University Press, 1979 [1951]), 18-27, 234-248, 254-256.
68 Jean Le Rond d’Alembert, Preliminary Discourse to the Encyclopedia of Diderot (R Schwab
transl. & intr., Chicago University Press 1995), 11, 14.
65
17
weak in the hands of the strong.69 Among aspects of d’Alembert’s vision of
general cultural progress was also a universal system of morality. Its origin
would no longer be looked for with God, however, but with the experience of
injustice whose expression natural law was.70
The encyclopaedists were not a homogeneous group. Nevertheless, their
analytical-compositive method invariably made them return to individual human
nature, to the urge to avoid pain and to find pleasure, from which they would
proceed to a long-term, “enlightened” sense of self-preservation that would
encompass concern for humans not only at home but everywhere.71 In their
recurrent recourse to the vocabulary of natural law and natural rights, usually
without express acknowledgment of the tradition itself, the encyclopaedists
found the simplest way to defend their programme of reform.72 The public
lawyers had sought the principles of government from the histories about Franks
and Gauls, thereby supporting the role of the nobility. By contrast 18th century
intellectuals discarded history and derived their principles from their notion of
the “natural” human being they assumed to exist as a rational egoist.73 The most
radical of the group, Baron d’Holbach (1723-1789), for example, produced a fully
naturalist structure of universal morality in which all rights and duties were
determined in view of the search for happiness, understood as continuous
pleasure.
“…nous fonderons la science des moeurs sur notre sensibilité physique,
sur les désirs dont nous sommes constamment animés, sur l’amour
continuel que chacun de nous a pour lui-même, sur nos vrais intérêts”.74
The task of law was to lead humans from the pursuit of blind passions to seeing
“the necessity to be useful for those whose assistance is needed for our own
d’Alembert, Preliminary Discourse, 14-15. For the Encyclopedia as a part of a process of
creating a single, hierarchical system of knowledges, see Foucault, Il faut défendre la société, 161162.
70 See d’Alembert, Preliminary Discourse, 12-13, 44.
71 See further, Marc Bélissa, Fraternité, 23-49.
72 Joseph Schumpeter, Histoire de l’analyse économique. I – L’age des fondateurs (Paris, Gallimard
1983 [1953]), 196-197.
73 See further, Foucault, Il faut défendre la société, 186-187.
74 Baron D’Holbach, Système social ou principes naturels de la morale et de la politique. Tome I
(Paris, Niogret, 1822), 77.
69
18
felicity”.75 The social contract and the binding force of legislation were likewise
received from calculations of long-term utility.76 There was in d’Holbach no
normative difference between natural and positive law at all; the legislator
merely declared what natural law said. Only scientific and technical questions
remain about how to reach general happiness, interpreted as always also
compatible with enlightened individual interests.77 This was the basis of the law
of nations, too:
“Une nation est obligée, pour son propre intérêt, de partager les mêmes
vertus que tout homme doit montrer à son semblable, fût-il étranger ou
inconnu”. 78
All nations had a duty of humanity towards each other, none may do to others
anything that is not within the boundaries of the equitable: “Tels sont les
principes du droit des gens, qui n’est au fond que la morale des peoples”.79
Sovereigns did not exist in a state of war with each other; all humans were joined
as members of their nations in a moral community where war was only an
expression of the vain search for glory, the avarice of tyrants. But history showed
that conquests were rarely useful, that large military forces were economically
destructive and wars always created injustice.80
D’Holbach may have been extreme as materialist but the logical consequences he
drew from his naturalism were widely shared among the encyclopaedists. There
was a general problem at the heart of that sentiment, however. On the one hand,
d’Holbach and others rejected the universal truth of Christianity. Morality and
law differed by time and place; each community had its own history and its own
values that were reflected in the “spirit” of its laws and customs. On the other
D’Holbach, Système social tome I 92
D’Holbach, Système social tome I 308.
77 D’Holbach, Système social tome I 310-311.
78 Baron D’Holbach, La morale universelle, ou les devoirs de l’homme, fondés sur la nature. Tome
second (Paris, Masson 1820), tome II, 2. This was obviously very close to Montesquieu’s
formulation, namely that “different nations ought in time of peace to do one another all the good
they can, and in time of war as little injury as possible, without prejudicing their interests”, The
Spirit of Laws (T Nugent transl. New York, Halpern 1949), 5.
79 D’Holbach, Morale universelle II, 4.
80 D’Holbach, Morale universelle II, 2-21. On this point among the philosophes generally, see
Bélissa, Fraternité, 79-84.
75
76
19
hand, they also persisted in arguing about a shared human nature on the basis of
which it would be possible erect a structure of universal rights and duties. This
famous ambivalence also extended to an uncertainty in all of this literature about
the nature of treaties and the positive practices of the law of nations. The first
intuition was to follow Pufendorf and Barbeyrac and to deny any validity to
them; they were after all the products of ancient regime diplomacy. On the other
hand, what else than formal treaties concluded between sovereign nations could
found the egalitarian European order they were advocating?81
Perhaps it was this problem that led the jurist Antoine-Gaspard Boucher d’Argis
(1708-1791) to write the essays on “natural law” and the “law of nations” in the
Encyclopaedia as wholly conventional accounts of ius naturae and ius gentium
from the Digest to Grotius and other modern writers. This was a restatement of
many of the positions the philosophes had been vehemently attacking.82 Probably
for this reason Diderot inserted an essay on Droit naturel by himself in the
Encyclopaedia in the form of a brief philosophical discourse. If the law of nature
was universal, and could be found by reasoning, what was it? A person who
reasons, Diderot claimed, will find it as the same as the “general will” of
humankind: “elle serait toujours relative à la volonté générale & au désir
commun de l’espèce entire”. “Of the whole species” – this meant that the
“general will” was not “voluntary”, but a scientific statement of what might be
useful for the human race. In this form, it was also compatible with d’Alembert’s
preliminary discourse. Diderot expressly rejected pure voluntarism. “Les
volontés particulières sont suspectes; elles peuvent être bonnes ou méchantes,
mais la volonté générale est toujours bonne”.83 The “general will” was not a real,
psychological will but a scientific proposition about the needs of the species,
See also Bélissa, Fraternité, 27-32.
Boucher d’Argis, ‘Droit des Gens’ and ‘Droit de la Nature ou Droit naturel, Diderot &
d’Alembert, Encyclopédie, ou dictionnaire raisonné des arts et des métiers etc., University of
Chicago ARTFL Encyclopedia Project (Robert Morissey ed.: http://encyclopedie.unchicago.edu),
5: 126 and 131. In particular, Boucher d’Argis rehearsed the themes about the relative overlap
between natural law and the law of nations since their confusing definitions in the Digest. His
own position was that natural law was a law of reason, universally valid among humans, and that
the law of nations was divided into “primary” and “secondary”, the former dealing with rules of
public and private law valid everywhere, the latter containing those conventional rules that
nations have agreed or followed in practice. Most of the entries were written as overviews of the
doctrines of Pufendorf and Burlamaqui.
83 Diderot, Droit naturel, in Encyclopédie 5: 115-116.
81
82
20
what was useful for humankind a whole. 84 All this seemed true and appealing –
but exorbitantly general. What would it mean to speak of the good of humanity if
humanity seemed to be completely divided on this?
6. Into Economic Naturalism
This view became eventually the heart of a new naturalism that integrated the
law of nations within a series of assumptions about the operation of the
economic system. In early 18th century, “Colbertism” had been finally
undermined by the financial chaos of the last years of the Sun King’s reign, and
new types of policy advice began to emerge from French intellectuals. This was
the context, also, of the rise in France of the quarrel between the “ancients” and
the “moderns” one aspect of which focused on the role of “luxury” in political
community. Was the development of a “commercial society” of the kind that was
emerging in England a beneficial or a corrupting influence? The “moderns”
embraced Montesquieu’s doux commerce thesis according to which “[p]eace is
the natural effect of trade”.85 This meant, among other things, that commerce
was “always necessarily connected to the affairs of the public”.86
Many Frenchmen were impressed by England’s commercial spirit which they
saw as an essential part of the nation’s power. Economic wealth came to be seen
as part of the calculation of the balance of power. But this did not mean that
trade necessarily operated as a zero-sum game. Free trade might actually benefit
everyone – at least within certain limits.87 In a hugely successful work on the
politics of commerce the jurist and political commentator Jean-Francois Melon
(1675-1738) emphasized both the dangers of economic dependency that might
be created by the intensification of commerce – especially commerce on
“necessities” – but also the advantages that would follow for all nations from
For Diderot’s (and d’Alembert’s) utilitarianism see Catherine Larrière, L’invention de
l’économie au XVIIIe siècle (Paris, PUF 1992), 51-57, 67-75; Cassirer, Philosophy of Enlightenment,
246-248.
85 Montesquieu, Spirit, 316.
86 Montesquieu, Spirit, 318.
87 The leading work today on this is Istvan Hont, Jealousy of Trade. International Competition and
the Nation-State in Historical Perspective (Harvard University Press 2006).
84
21
their specialization in particular trades. Trade policy, he suggested, was an
absolutely central aspect of a nation’s foreign relations and “[t]he greatest of all
Maxims, and the best understood, is, that Commerce requireth only Liberty, and
Protection”. 88 As long as the nation could take care of its subsistence, it would
have no reason to fear trading with others. Moreover, “The Spirit of Conquest
and the Spirit of Commerce, mutually exclude each other, in a Nation”. 89
Through active commerce, especially trade of “superfluities”, nations could
benefit much more efficiently and with less cost than through warfare.
Like Melon, a new generation of political thinkers such as Pierre le Pesant, Sieur
de Boisguilbert (1646-1714) and Richard Cantillon (c. 1680-1743) stressed the
importance of combining efficient domestic agriculture with free trade on
“luxuries” (i.e. on non-necessities) as the best way for national strength. They
were followed by the Physiocrats whose leading lights, Marquis de Mirabeau
(1715-1789) and Francois Quesnay (1694-1774) borrowed extensively from the
natural law tradition, arguing that the economy possessed its own intrinsic laws
distinct from the rules of political government. The economy would work best if
left to its own devices, while it was the task of legislation to see to it that no
obstacles were introduced to the use of property rights.90
One of the most outspoken members of the group was Paul-Pierre Le Mercier de
la Rivière (1719-1801) who sought to lay out the “natural order” of political
societies in which he integrated the economic system through the unfortunately
labelled doctrine of ”legal despotism”. There was, he wrote in Natural and
Essential order of Political Societies (1767), a “natural order” for societies. “Cet
ordre n’est qu’une branche de l’ordre physique”.91 By grasping this humans
could realise the two objects of all their actions: enjoyment of pleasure and
Jean-Francois Melon, Political Essay upon Commerce (D Bindon transl. Dublin, Crampton,
1738), 42-43.
89 Melon, Political Essay, 136.
90 For the natural law basis of the Physiocrat theory, see especially David McNally, Political
Economy and the Rise of Capitalism. A Reinterpretation (University of California Press 1990), 85151 and Catherine Larrère, L’invention de l’économie au XVIII siècle (Paris, PUF 1992), passim.
91 Le Mercier, L’ordre naturel, 37.
88
22
avoidance of pain.92 The first right of all was the right of self-preservation. This
right was absolute, as was its concomitant, the right to acquire for oneself
whatever was useful. For every right, there was a duty, and society could be
articulated in terms of the absolute rights and duties of individuals towards each
other.93
Societies were based on the search of happiness, and greatest happiness was
abundance:
“…le plus grand bonheur possible consiste pour nous dans la plus grande
abondance possible d’objets propres à nos jouissances…”.94
To achieve this, production had to increase. This, again, was possible only in a
regime of liberty – through the free use of our forces and our properties.95 In this
way, social order was part of the physical world. Awareness of its laws provided
knowledge of absolute justice and absolute injustice in the same way that the laws
of nature operated in an absolute way. 96 Everything either pointed to increased
abundance or it did not; that is, everything was either called upon or prohibited.
Private vices turn into public virtues:
“dans la système de la nature chaque homme tend perpétuellement vers
son meilleur état possible, & qu’en cela même il travaille & concourt
nécessairement à former le meilleur état possible de corps entier de la
société”.97
The repetition over again of the italicized expression “absolute” by Le Mercier
was intended to highlight the necessary character of this order of relationships
he discussed and to justify the despotism of the laws that were expected to
express society’s natural order in a vocabulary of natural rights and duties.
This led le Mercier into an authoritarian government under laws that had the
absoluteness of physical laws. Quesnay had already written that “[t]he natural
“…la nature…a voulu que [les hommes] ne connussent que deux mobiles, l’appétit des plaisirs
& l’aversion de la douleur”, Le Mercier de la Rivière, L’ordre naturel et essentiel des sociétés
politiques (Nourse, Londres 1767), 33.
93 Le Mercier, L’ordre naturel, 11-17.
94 Le Mercier L’ordre naturel, 27 (emphasis in original).
95 Le Mercier, L’ordre naturel, 33.
96 Le Mercier, L’ordre naturel, 11.
97 Le Mercier, L’ordre naturel, 35.
92
23
laws of the social order are themselves the physical laws of perpetual
reproduction of those goods necessary to the subsistence, the conservation, and
the convenience of men”.98 From this, Quesnay had developed a very rigorous
notion of the rule of law. His “legal despotism” was not monarchic absolutism,
however. The “laws” that would govern society were the intrinsic laws of the
social order. Their “absoluteness” meant that they “had already been written” by
nature itself. The only task was to discover them and to “dictate” them to society
at large.99 Thus there was no basis to distinguish between legislative and
executive power, either: one was merely the extension of the other. “Partager
l’autorité, c’est l’annuller”.100 A multitude of opinions would create chaos, while
the power and correctness of legislation would be guaranteed by the proof of the
laws of the social order (“la force intuitive et déterminante d’évidence”).101 Such
evidence also operated against misuse of authority: arbitrary despotism would
always fail in the long run.102
Exactly the same principles were operative at the international level. In the first
place, the natural society that preceded the establishment of particular societies
was not destroyed by the latter. When visiting distant peoples in peaceful
conditions, the same hospitality was found as at home. The expansion of
commercial relations relied on a wholly unthinking respect for rights and duties
all over the world. Different political societies were not fundamentally different
but best seen as branches of the same tree, parts of the universal human
society.103 A federation of Europe was no chimera. In fact, it was already in
existence.
“…on doit la supposer toujours faite, ou plutôt toujours existente sans
l’entremise d’aucunes conventions expresses à cet égard, & par la seule
force de nécessité don’t elle est la sureté politique de chaque Nation en
particulier”.104
Quesnay, ‘Despotisme de la Chine’, quoted in McNally, Political Economy, 123.
Le Mercier, L’ordre naturel, 75-78., 105, 113.
100 Le Mercier, L’ordre naturel, 129.
101 Le Mercier, L’ordre naturel, 100, 101-104, 130. On the Physiocrat doctrine of legal despotism,
see further McNally, Political Economy, 121-129.
102 Le Mercier, L’ordre naturel, 163-165, 170-178.
103 Le Mercier, L’ordre naturel, 318-320.
104 Le Mercier, L’ordre naturel, 323.
98
99
24
Short-sighted passions had driven nations to war in the past. But nature
compelled them to regard each other as brothers, possessing the same rights and
duties as individuals possessed at home. The prosperity of nations lay in the way
they followed the “essential order of societies” that called upon respecting the
rights of each other. 105
In the hands of les économistes natural law developed into increasingly technical
propositions about how society ought to be organised so that the productive
cycle would create optimal wealth; free trade was an essential aspect of this,
especially once domestic self-sufficiency in “necessities” had been guaranteed.
After that point, free trade with the surplus agricultural product and especially
with “luxuries” (i.e. non-necessities) would unite the participating nations in an
increasingly peaceful world of commerce.
7. Droit public as analysis and critique: Mably
Not everyone was convinced of the desirability of such a world. The Mandevillian
hypothesis about private vice and public benefit flew in the face of ideas about
republican virtue and community and tended to reduce the state into a passive
instrument of private interests. Concentrating on commercial benefit and the
search of “luxury” was also widely seen as leading to corruption and the slow
decline of the nation in relation to more vigorous neighbours. For example,
popular speculation about the causes of the fall of the Roman and Spanish
empires pointed precisely to the corrupting influence of riches on the ruling
elites and society at large.
In the debates about the governmental reform that commenced at the end of the
reign of Louis XIV Saint-Pierre, as we have seen, represented the thèse
monarchique. He insisted that the monarchy ought to be rationalized and
brought within legal rules, projecting this view at the international level by
105
Le Mercier, L’ordre naturel, 331-333.
25
arguing that a peaceful “union” would actually be in the educated self-interest of
European monarchs. A different perspective on European peace was taken by
another abbé, namely Gabriel Bonnot de Mably (1709-1785) whose Droit public
de l’Europe (1746) became an immediate commercial success; it was published
in several editions, translated into German and Italian and used in England as a
university text.106 It also solidified the name of the European political order since
the Treaty of Westphalia. The work was essentially a compilation of treaties,
with commentaries on the context and purpose of each treaty in view of the
fundamental interests of the parties. It was supplemented in 1757 with a long
preface, entitled “Principes de négocations pour servir d’introduction au droit
public de l’Europe” that provided both a critique of the short-sighted egoism of
monarchic diplomacy and a theoretical articulation of “European public law” in
terms of the search for their fundamental (in contrast to arbitrary) interests of
European rulers.
Mably came from a relatively modest family of provincial noblesse de robe. Like
his brother the philosopher Etienne Bonnot de Condillac, he had been taken into
the protection of Madame de Tencin in whose salon he was introduced to
Parisian elites. Through this means he also achieved in 1742 a position as
Secretary to Cardinal Tencin who served as Minister of State in Fleury’s
government. Until his sudden break with Tencin five years later, Mably had
followed and participated in the diplomacy of the day, reflecting on his
experiences in the Droit public de l’Europe and especially its extended theoretical
introduction.107 The book was not the first of its kind – large compilations of
treaty-texts had existed since mid-17th century. But it was distinguished by its
relative conciseness, its rational organization and above all by the commentaries
through which Mably introduced the treaties as parts of a European foreign
policy system. Although the commentaries pretended to neutrality, they included
criticisms of the policy of Louis XIV that prevented the publication of the work in
France until the intervention of the Marquis d’Argenson who had just left his
Johnson Kent Wright, A Classical Republican in Eighteenth-Century France. The Political
Thought of Mably (Stanford University Press, 1997), 36-37.
107 See Wright, A Classical Republican, 35-38; Marc Bélissa, ‘Introduction’, in Gabriel Bonnot de
Mably, Principes de négiciations. Pour servir d’Introduction au Droit public de l’Europe (Paris,
Kimé 2001), 8-10.
106
26
post as France’s foreign minister.108 The principal importance of the work lay,
however, in the introduction that was appended to the editions after 1757 and in
which Mably could freely launch hic critiques of the short-sightedness and
irrationality of the diplomacy of ancien régime Europe.109
Like Saint-Pierre, Mably had commenced his career as a royalist. By the time of
the publication of the Principes de négociations, however, he had made a sharp
turn and now preached republican values. His publications from this time
onwards have preserved his name in French intellectual history alongside JeanJacques Rousseau among the most vocal critics of the “parti des modernes”,
including the économistes and other advocates of commercial society. Mably
resented a society based on the search for “luxuries”. He was especially critical of
the inequality among citizens that it brought along, and lamented the associated
demise of patriotic virtue. Like Rousseau, too, he was critical of modern natural
law that was founded on self-preservation. Instead of following Hobbes, Grotius
and Pufendorf, Mably drew on the Ciceronian heritage for which humans were
naturally endowed by reason and virtue, and argued that the best way to learn
them was to examine the events of Roman and Greek antiquity. 110 Mably would
ground his critique of inequality and private property on neo-Stoic themes that
would be later integrated in the Jacobin doctrine of virtue. Although he has
received the reputation of belonging with the early utopian socialists, he was
dubious of the realism of any project to return communal property, describing it
as no more than an “agreeable dream”.111
Mably’s Principes de négociations was an attempt to provide the basis for a
rational science of diplomacy – a “science morale” – that would focus on the
fundamental interests of all European States. Like Saint-Pierre, Mably was
frustrated by the lack of organization of the rational study of politics in France.
In Germany, such study had been organised under the topic of natural law and
the law of nations at the universities, and in Britain a flourishing natural law
Bélissa, ‘Introduction’, 14.
Wright, Classical Republican, 54.
110 On Mably’s “about face” in the course of 1747-50 from the “Parti des Modernes” to the “Parti
des Anciens”, see Wright, Classical Republican, 39-65.
111 Wright, Classical Republican, 103.
108
109
27
debate followed on the writings of Locke, Pufendorf, and others. Nothing of the
kind existed in France. Law schools were devoted to the practical training of
magistrates and universities were so tightly controlled by the Church that
intellectuals wanted to have nothing to do with them. Any public reflection on
the principles of natural and the law of nations was excluded. One could talk
politics only in the court and with the king.112 There had been a short-lived
experiment by Louis’ foreign minister Colbert de Torcy (1665-1746) to set up a
diplomatic academy in the Louvre in 1711-1719 with the motive of regularising
the careers of younger attachés. The handful of students who had been admitted
to the school studied Grotius and Pufendorf under the school’s director, the
distinguished jurist Yves Saint-Prest (c. 1640-1720), with practical exercises in
diplomatic correspondence and periods of traineeship at embassies abroad. The
school was terminated during the Regency at Cardinal Dubos’ request, however,
and no similar institution was set up in the course of the 18th century.113
Informal suggestions to this effect had been made by men such as Saint-Pierre,
for example, and the Entresol club of which he had been one of the founders,
provided a forum in which a select group of men could in relative freedom
discuss the government of France’s internal and external policy. But even those
debates were too sensitive for the monarchy; they came to an end in 1731.114
For such reasons, the “moral science” of Droit public de l’Europe and especially in
the Principes de négociations in 1757 had such importance. Mably wove the
French tradition of raison d’état into a legal vocabulary with the objective of
developing rules of foreign policy that would be based on a meticulous
assessment of each country’s relative position on the political map. Mably based
his new science on an account of European history as the history of the greed of
its rulers. The great mistake in France, for example, had been to conceive ruling a
Johan Heilbron, The Rise of Social Theory, (trans Sheila Gogol, Univ. Minnesota Press, 1995) 68.
For a thorough study of the school, see Guy Thuilier, La première école d’administration.
L’Académie politique de Louis XIV (Genève, Droz 1996). Predominant reasons for the school’s
closure were the resistance of ambassadors to the inauguration of a practice whereby they could
no longer choose their younger assistants, as well as the lack of interest in regular study shown
by many of the students. In addition, an organized study of politics inside the administration was
regarded with suspicion by a part of the king’s entourage.
114 For the establishment, operation and closure of the club d’Entresol, see Nick Childs, A Political
Academy on paris 1724-1731. The Entresol and its Members (Oxford Voltaire Foundation 2000).
112
113
28
private matter, often dependent only on the ruler’s search for personal glory. 115
European politics had been determined by family feuds (Habsburg/Valois;
Habsburg/Bourbon). Secret diplomacy and breaking of treaties were used to
satisfy the rulers’ passions.116 To emerge from this miserable state of things, the
latter ought to learn to design and follow policies that were appropriate to
protecting and enhancing the relative position of their countries on the European
political map. Large armies and the search for luxury were all “follies” that
undermined concentration on what is important – namely designing a policy to
respect its real, long-term interests.117 In describing this, Mably moved freely
between the language of “princes”, “peoples” and “nations” without a theory
about their relationship. Yet it was clear that he thought in terms of a “Europe” of
free nations whose people would be represented by their ruler.
Mably’s proposals follow Saint-Pierre and the raison d’état writers: for the
determination of their fundamental interests nations were to be divided in four
classes: ruling power (now France), rival power (now England), and powers of
second and third rank. Each possessed a fundamental interest, based on its
relative position that it would ignore at its peril. By aiming higher than its forces
allowed, or by neglecting constant vigilance, a nation was bound to disaster.
Balance of power would never provide sufficient protection. In fact, it would
usually favour the rival power (which is why William III had promoted it) and
might even became a predatory mechanism allowing (as in the case of the
partitions of Poland) dramatic redrawing of the political map.118 For the powers
of the second and third order Mably recommended strategies alternating
between principled pacifism and playing the principal powers against each
other, defending – as he put it – the Machiavellian nature of his suggestions by
their usefulness.119 The chapters on alliance strategies, in particular, were full of
examples of both well planned and rash negotiations. The point was to adopt a
Mably, ‘Principes de négociations’, 52-53.
Mably, ‘Principes de négociations’, 39-47.
117 Mably, ‘Principes de négociations’, 57-62.
118 Mably, ‘Principes de négociations’ 75-76.
119 “Je rougirais des maxims machiavéliques que je viens d’exposer, s’il n’était pas possible d’en
tirer des consquences utiles aux hommes”, Mably, ‘Principes de négociations’, 85.
115
116
29
conduct that would be consistently based on one’s relative position, and then
persist in following it (“se faire une règle certaine dans ses négociations”).120
In this regard, Mably suggested, the powers had not taken sufficient notice of the
recent emerge of economic wealth as a political asset. Wealth instead of military
had now become the new focus of policy. Territorial expansion, for example,
would no longer have much point – what use would it be to conquer a village at
the cost of expanding misery in one’s own villages? The war just began by France
and England (the seven years’ war) manifested a complete disregard of this, and
was against the fundamental interests of both.121 From now on it was necessary
for nations to concentrate on developing their wealth as the basis of their power.
This was the lesson to be learned from England’s rise to the position of rival
power and the fall of Austria and Spain from their earlier exalted status
In Mably’s view only a well-functioning agriculture was the basis of a nation’s
real and lasting economic strength.122 Trade in luxuries, by contrast, was harmful
because it would inevitably lead into increased domestic inequality. Already in
his first book Mably had argued that luxury had been a predominant cause for
the decline of ancient Rome and Sparta.123 In his later work, including the
Principes de négociations, he became even more insistent of the role of virtue –
even Stoic virtue – in the government of the state. In a separate detour in the
Principes, he critiqued mercantilist ideas of warfare and the doctrine of
commercial society he associated with David Hume. Luxury might profit the
merchant, but not the society as a whole. It created inequality, increased prices
and in the long run undermined itself: “le luxe, loin d’être favorable au
commerce, est, au contraire une symptome de sa décadence prochaine”.124
Luxury both corrupts society and leads to economic decline by benefiting only a
small class of citizens. For the creation of long-term sustainable wealth it was
Mably, ‘Principes de négociations’, 107.
Mably, ‘Principes de négociations’, 79. Likewise, Mably, Droit public de l’Europe. Fondé sur les
traités (tome 2, Genève, Compagnie des Librairies 1768), Ch XII, 260-265.
122 Mably, ‘Principes de négociations’,146-152.
123 See Wright, A Classical Republican, 33-34.
124 Mably, ‘Principes de négociations’, 150.
120
121
30
important for the nation to concentrate on the development of agriculture and
domestic exchange.125
In other late writings Mably would take an even stronger position against
commercial society and in favour of virtuous republicanism in a cosmopolitan
context. In a dialogue published in 1763 Entretiens de Phocion Mably put in the
mouth of the Athenian military commander his (“ancient”) view that giving in to
their passion for glory and riches provided the cause for the destruction of
ancient polities. Against this he invoked the Ciceronian concept of right reason,
recta ratio – precisely the strategy that Saint-Pierre had rejected as a utopian. A
life of avarice, greed, voluptuousness would never lead to lasting happiness. It
was true that passions could not be eradicated but they could nevertheless be
tamed by virtue and devotion to work for the happiness of one’s country.126 And
the good of one’s country must be seen in the context of humanity itself. A nation
that used violence and betrayal against its neighbours would be trapped by the
fear that it provoked in others.127 In a long “footnote” Mably attacked the violent
and unjust behaviour of European nations. The law of nations was known, but
used perversely and in support of irrational ambition. Even lately, he wrote, it
had been falsely associated with passing treaties, neglecting its basis in reason
and nature.
“Pendant qu’on ignore la loi par laquelle la nature lie tous les hommes,
pendant qu’on ne cherche qu’à rétablir un droit des nations favorable à
l’ambition, à l’avarice et à la force, peut-on être disposé à penser avec
Socrate, Platon, Phocion et Cicéron, que l’amour de la patrie, subordonné
à l amour de l’humanité, doit se prendre pour son guide, ou on s’expose à
produire de grands malheurs?” 128
True patriotism avoided violent conquest and sought to make one’s country
admired not because it its power – subject to the vicissitudes of fortune – but its
The argument of the self-destructive nature of commercial society is also made (by reference
to the writings of Richard Cantillon), in Gabriel Bonnot de Mably, Entretiens de Phocion sur le
rapport du morale et la politique (Paris, Librairie de la Bibliothèque Nationale 1872), 125-131.
See further, Wright, A Classical Republican, 60-64.
126 Mably, Entretiens de Phocion, 47-48.
127 Mably, Entretiens de Phocion, 52.
128 Mably, Entretiens de Phocion, 104.
125
31
justice and humanity.129 The conquest by Pericles may have brought wonderful
riches to Athens. But while the prosperity of citizens grew, the republic became
poorer. As luxury brought in greed, everybody felt themselves deprived. In the
end, the corruption of the soul of the Athenians led to the collapse of their city.130
For Mably’s Phocion, the health of politics was based on virtue: “le Providence a
établi une telle liaison entre la morale et la politique que le bonheur des Etats est
attaché à la pratique des vertus”.131 Passions such as love of glory and honour,
firmness and heroism may sometimes be socially useful, just like some poisons
may be used as medicine. In the end, however, Phocion tells young Aristias, the
city can be saved only, if at all, by disciplining politics by reason, expressed in the
laws by a virtuous legislator.132
Mably’s most striking text, however, was the dialogue on the Droits et devoirs du
citoyen between a Frenchman and his English guest, Lord Stanhope, written a
year after the Droit public de l’Europe but published only posthumously at the
eve of the revolution in 1789. Here the Englishman commented on the midcentury constitutional crisis in France, advocating the convocation of the EstatesGeneral but also a political “revolution”.133 Stanhope coldly dismissed the
Frenchman’s proposal to accept the conditions of loss of liberty in France in view
of the “anarchy” that struggle against despotism would bring, rejecting the
submissiveness taught by Grotius, Pufendorf, Wolff and Hobbes. Humans were
born with natural rights and duties and it was the purpose of the State to protect
and strengthen them. The natural law tradition built “sophisms upon sophisms”
to suggest that without kings there would be no security, reminding his
interlocutor that Grotius had published his writings with the blessings of Louis
Mably, Entretiens de Phocion, 107-121.
Mably, Entretiens de Phocion, 122-133.
131 Mably, Entretiens de Phocion, 135.
132 Mably, Entretiens de Phocion, 141-142, 154-160. See also Wright, A Classical Republican, 8090.
133 Abbé de Mably, Des droits et des devoirs du citoyen (Paris, Lacombe 1789). For the context, see
Keith Michael Baker, ‘A Script for the French Revolution: The Political Consciousness of Mably’, in
Inventing the French Revolution. Essays on French Political Culture in the Eighteenth Century
(Cambridge University Press 1990), 88-91. Baker makes the useful point about Mably’s
specifically political insistence on the dependency of political and social change on contingent
will and struggle, not as a an automatic product of economic or social forces.
129
130
32
XIII.134 By reference to Locke’s Second Treatise, Stanhope then sketched a whole
plan for a “revolution ménageé” by the Estates-General. The executive and the
judiciary would be separated and the royalty’s position would be constitutionally
delimited. The conduct of foreign affairs would be dealt with conjointly by a
Royal Committee and the Estates-General, the latter possessing the power of
appointing ambassadors and receiving a report from the former for its criticism
or endorsement. With this, Mably has Stanhope say, “la nation aura bientôt un
droit des gens don’t les principes seront constans et uniformes”. 135
Mably’s views on natural law and the law of nations were part of an oeuvre that
was critical both of the institutions of the old regime and of the proposals to
transform France into a commercial society after the English example. They
expressed a republican emphasis on the active participation of virtuous citizens
in the ruling of the state, with solidarity to humanity in general and the equality
of all humans. He rejected both the practices of treaty-making and diplomacy of
the European states-system as well as the natural law tradition that he – like
Rousseau – saw as only offering a political legitimation to the latter. The way the
world was governed would have to be thought anew. Partial reforms would not
suffice. Revolution was necessary, and this was not to be hindered by temporary
disorders and confrontations.
8. Epilogue: Abbé Grégoire and the Draft declaration of the Rights and
Duties of Nations
Droit public de l’Europe was the name given in the 18th century to the system of
treaties between European potentates and their effort to maintain balance of
Mably, Droits et devoirs, 19-21.
But, Mably has Stanhope say, even after the establishment of the free republic, the dangers do
not end: Sparta and Rome were delivered to tyranny by internal divisions and neglect of
attention to the common good. Happiness and security also bring about negligence and lack of
attention for the strict enforcement of laws – the respect of laws and magistrates diminishes and
opportunities for tyranny grow. In war, too, danger is that the exceptional constitutional
measures taken will remain permanent. Or then, victory makes the people negligent and
lax.There has to be serious examination of governmental conditions to see to it, that the situation
does not remain permanent. Mably, Droits et devoirs, 336, 356-359.
134
135
33
power between their respective states and dynasties. In an oblique manner, it
also referred to the justifications sometimes given to this system from the
vocabulary of natural law and the law of nations. Grotius, Hobbes and Pufendorf
represented something that most mid-century enlighteners found unacceptably
conservative. But they still returned to natural law as the most readily available
platform over which to argue about liberty, equality and the rights of a universal
humanity.
In Droits et devoirs Mably put forward views that were strikingly prescient of
what the revolutionaries would be claiming in 1789. The critique of inequality
brought about by commerce and the defence of republican virtue touched on
themes that would be endlessly repeated in the National Assembly and the
Convention. But it was not clear what these ideas would entail for the conduct of
foreign affairs. The repudiation of the language of the ancien régime was not
accompanied by far-reaching calls for institutional change. This was also true of
the debates, in 1793 and 1795, when Abbé Henri Grégoire (1750-1831) tabled
his proposal for a declaration of the rights and duties of nations that had been
modelled after the Déclaration de droits de l’homme et du citoyen of 1789.
Grégoire was a provincial clergyman who had come to be known as a defender of
the Jews on the strength of a 1788 essay and an advocate of the abolition of
slavery in French colonies. A member and an occasional president of the
Assembly and the Convention, depicted in the foreground of David’s famous
Tennis Court Oath, Grégoire was a fervent Catholic but also a fighter in the
republican cause whose cosmopolitan activism was channelled towards a view
of France as the representative of oppressed nations everywhere. 136
See especially Bernard Plongeron, L’abbé Grégoire ou l’Arché de la Fraternité (Paris, Letouzey
& Ané 1989), 347-50. Grégoire was “Pantheonised” (i.e. his remains were transferred into the
Panthéon in Paris) in 1989 in which context several biographies were published of him. See e.g.
Georges Hourdin, L’abbé Grégoire. Évêque et démocrate (Paris Desclée de Brouwer, 1989);
Maurice Ezran, L’abbé Grégoire. Défenseur des juifs et des noirs (Paris l’Harmattan 1992). See
further Alyssa Goldstein Sepinwall, The Abbé Grégoire and the French Revolution (University of
California Press 2005). The biographies concentrate on Grégoire’s activities in favour of
tolerance, the reform of the Church and his many proposals for re-organising education and
fighting “vandalism” and deal with the draft declaration only in passing, if at all.
136
34
In the context of a debate on foreign affairs in the Constitution in the spring of
1793, Grégoire read to the Convention a proposal of 21 articles to be inserted in
the text that already contained the sentence according to which “le peuple
français est l’ami et l’allié naturel de tous les peuples libres”. According to the
proposal all peoples were “independent and sovereign” and connected to each
other by “universal morality” (Articles 1-2). From Montesquieu was derived the
rule that peoples ought to treat each other as they would wish themselves to be
treated and do in peace as much good and in war as little evil as they could
(Articles 3-4). Peoples were entitled to organise themselves as they wished; no
intervention in each other’s affairs was allowed. However, “no other government
[was] in conformity with the rights of peoples than ones that [were] based on
equality and liberty” (Article 8). Each people was master of its territory while
areas not subject to occupation (such as the seas) belonged to all (Articles 9-10).
Foreigners were to abide by the laws of the country where they stayed and a
people had the right to refuse entry to foreigners it considered dangerous to
their security (Articles 12-13) Any attack against the liberty of one people was
an attack on all of them. Offensive leagues were contrary to the “human family”
(Articles 15-16). Defensive wars were allowed but room was to be left for
negotiations (Articles 17-18). There were to be no ranks among the
representatives of peoples, and they were immune to the laws of their receiving
countries in respect of their mission (Articles 19-20). Finally, treaties among
nations were to be inviolable (Article 21).137
In view of the tense international situation in June 1793, however, the majority
of the deputies held it sufficient to state that France declared its friendship with
all peoples; there was reason to be “political” and not to express futile
philanthropic sentiments. Grégoire repeated his proposal in April 1795, after the
signature of the Peace of Basle, condemning in his introductory words old
diplomacy anew but also the kind of abstract cosmopolitanism that was only
“vagabondage physique ou moral”. “Real patriotism”, he affirmed, would include
For the articles, see Pierre Fauchon, L’abbé Grégoire. Le prêtre-citoyen (Paris, NouvelleRépublique, 1989), 87-88. The best discussion of the context and a full list of the 21 articles is
also in Marc Bélissa, ‘La déclaration du droit des gens de l’abbé Grégoire (join 1973, 4 floréal an
III)’, in http://revolution-francaise.net/2010/10/06/399-decrlaration-droit-des-gens-abbegregoire-juin-1793
137
35
love for humanity, too. Though Grégoire stated that natural law should rule over
politics, he condemned the traditions of natural law and diplomacy, including
Mably’s “Principes de négociations”. This time the reception from the audience
was cool, however, and the proposal was flatly rejected. The Convention not only
decreed on the different uniforms for ambassadors and ministers (going against
Grégoire’s Article 19) but also now opened the door for offensive war.
*****
Grégoire’s proposals became the target of the successive prefaces from 1796
onwards of his widely read Précis de droit international moderne de l’Europe by
the Göttingen professor, Hanover’s representative at Vienna in 1814-1815, Georg
Friedrich von Martens (1756-1821).138 Martens’ home university had
experienced Napoleon’s occupation and he saw in the declaration another
hypocritical instrument of French policy of conquest. Any declaration of
principles was meaningless without institutional or treaty-based guarantees.
Even if most people would agree to them in their abstract formulation, they
would not help when differences over their meaning arose. The world could not
be changed by abstract declarations, Martens wrote. Hence the turn to treaties
and to “positive” international law in the following decades. But if the tradition of
natural law and the law of nations was finished as part of diplomacy and public
law, it continued to flourish elsewhere.
As we have seen, despite their criticisms of the naturalist tradition, the French
intellectuals were unable to rid themselves of the language of natural law and
the law of nations. In a period that admired the achievements of the natural
sciences – Bacon and Newton particularly – that language pointed to the need of
a scientific policy of human society, too. This was accomplished by the
emergence in France of “social sciences” immediately before and during the
revolution.139 If “natural history” included a large view of human societies,
“political economy” suggested rules for their immediate government. With
138
139
See further my ‘Into Positivism’, 198-200.
See e.g. Heilbron, Rise of Social Theory, 119-147.
36
Physiocracy, the language of natural law helped to produce a view of economic
governance in which the old juridico-Machiavellian idea of an independent
political realm standing opposed to a civil society of autonomous individuals was
replaced, as Catherine Larrère has shown, with a view of individuality as part of
a total “system” of exchanges.140 “Private” activities (of buying or selling for
example) become part of the “public” operation of the state, and, through the
operation of free trade, of the realm, first, of a European-wide idea of law, then of
global law tout court. When everything operates in accordance with natural law
– this was Le Mercier’s “legal despotism”, a brilliant antecedent to today’s
globalization studies – then human “liberty” and “individuality” would be
conceived in terms of “rational” choices in a world of naturally self-regarding
individuals. Against this, the effort to resuscitate ancient virtues of republican
citizenship by Mably, Rousseau and others seemed even in the 18th century
quaint at best. When the tradition of law of nature and of nations learned what it
needed to become in order to provide scientific advice on how to rule, it realised
that it needed to become economics. At that point it was left for public law and
lawyers specialised in it to re-imagine the formal structures of statehood in
terms of a “rule of law” designed to make sure that the system of exchanges in
which individuality was produced and re-produced, could function with
measurable accuracy.
140
Larrère, L’invention de l’economie (Paris, Presses Universitaires de France, 1992), 309-314.
Download