Notes on Helen Frowe’s Defensive Killing 1. Background Assumptions ........................................................................................................... 1 2. Some Basic Concepts for Individual Self-Defense ..................................................................... 2 2.1 Threats .................................................................................................................................. 2 2.2 On-lookers, Bystanders, Direct Threats, Indirect Threats, Causes of Threats ...................... 3 2.3 Justice and Permissibility...................................................................................................... 5 2.4 Liability and Immunity ......................................................................................................... 5 2.5 Necessity and Liability ......................................................................................................... 7 2.6 Proportionality and Liability................................................................................................. 7 2.7 Agent Responsibility and Moral Responsibility ................................................................... 8 2.8 Exploitative and Eliminative Harms ..................................................................................... 8 3. Substantive Claims about Individual Self-Defense .................................................................... 9 3.1 Moral Responsibility............................................................................................................. 9 3.2 Liability and Moral Responsibility ..................................................................................... 10 3.3 Liability and Necessity ....................................................................................................... 11 3.4 Liability and Proportionality............................................................................................... 11 3.5 Liability and Defense of Honor .......................................................................................... 14 3.6 Liability and Defensive Action without Defensive Harm .................................................. 14 3.7 Liability: Other Claims ....................................................................................................... 15 3.9 Permissibility and Wrongdoing .......................................................................................... 16 3.9.1 General ......................................................................................................................... 16 3.9.2 Direct Threats ............................................................................................................... 16 3.9.3 Indirect Threats ............................................................................................................ 16 3.9.4 Bystanders .................................................................................................................... 17 3.10 Permissibility and Necessity (for Lesser-Evil Justification)............................................. 17 3.11 Permissibility, Exploitation, and Elimination ................................................................... 17 3.12 Permissibility and Duties to Bear Costs ........................................................................... 18 3.13 Permissibility and Reasonable Prospect of Success ......................................................... 18 4. Basic Concepts for the Morality of War ................................................................................... 18 5. Substantive Claims about the Morality of War......................................................................... 19 5.1 Claims about Liability of Non-Combatants ........................................................................ 19 5.2 Claims about Immunity of Non-Combatants ...................................................................... 19 5.3 Other Claims ....................................................................................................................... 20 1. Background Assumptions Methodology: - HF does not attempt to identify a full moral theory. She focuses on some main moral principles. (p. 3). - As you will see, she has a large number (e.g., more than 20) of basic moral principles. She is skeptical (fn. ? p. ?) that all relevant moral issues can be captured by small number of basic moral principles. Some, such as myself, hold that theoretical parsimony is an important general (but not infallible) guide to truth, and are thus skeptical of approaches that have a large number of basic principles. Of course, there is an important issue about how one counts basic principles (given that P1 and P2 can be combined to P1&P2). - Many of here principles have the form of being necessary, or sufficient, for permissibility, or for liability. She means to be conclusive principles, and not merely pro tanto (which can be overridden by other considerations). Lethal Threats: HF focuses on defense against lethal threats, but she intends her theory to generalize to non-lethal threats. 2. Some Basic Concepts for Individual Self-Defense Note: Most of the material clarifies the terms as HF uses them. In some places, however, I identify my preferred usage when different. I flag this with a PV. 2.1 Threats Rights-intrusion (PV): the crossing of a boundary protected by rights: (1) non-autonomous (neither permissible nor impermissible, neither rightful nor wrongful), (2) rightful (=just) = autonomous but does not wrong the right-holder (e.g., because she is liable to such intrusions in virtue of wrongdoing ) (3) wrongful (= unjust) = autonomous and wrongs the right-holder (e.g., because the rightholder is not liable to such intrusions) Intrusion-harm (PV): harm from a rights-intrusion. Not all harms are intrusion-harms (e.g., the harm I suffer when I lose a valued watch). PV Comments: Note that on my account of intrusion (above) whether something is an intrusion depends on what rights people have (even when subject to proportionality and necessity). Nonetheless, whether something is an intrusion does not depend on whether it is unjust, just, permissible, or impermissible. So, it’s not moralized in the strong sense of the term, which HF seem to use. Important: HF focuses on empirical threats (which are just or unjust), whereas the approach I favor focuses on (rights-based) intrusion-harms (which are non-autonomous, just, or unjust). For HF, the crucial notion is whether one is made worse off in certain empirical ways. For me, the crucial notion is whether one is made worse off by having one’s rights intruded upon. Threat (HF; a purely empirical notion) = an action, bodily movement, or presence, that makes the victim worse off than she would be in the threatener’s absence. Example: HF holds (p. 41) that, if each of two shipwrecked people will survive if and only if she is the only person clinging to a piece of driftwood, neither has a claim-right that the other not cling to it, and they simultaneously cling to it, then each is a threat to the other, even though neither intrudes upon the rights of the other. HF (e-mail) allows that the notion of harm may be person-relative: For example, opening a bag of peanuts bay be a threat to a person with a peanut-allergy, but not to others. 2 PV Comments: So, the same action and physical consequences can be a threat when done to A (worse off) but not to B because B is indifferent or likes the impact? In e-mail, HF says that being worse off need not (and probably is not) understood in terms of the agent’s preferences. It might be understood objectively worse off in some sense. Question: Does this mean that Smith is a (just) threat to me because the woman I am courting will leave me for him? Or that the new business is a (just) threat to my business? HF declined to answer, but she typically focuses worsening survival chances. Two sufficient, but not necessary, tests for establishing that someone is a threat (and not a bystander or on-looker), p. 45: - If Victim were not permitted or not able to harm X, X’s presence would reduce the value of the most valuable courses of defensive action that are morally permissible (and feasible) for Victim. o Note that, if Victim has another equally most valuable defensive action, then there is no reduction in value. P. 35 o PV’s reconstruction to avoid counterfactuals: The value of Victim’s most valuable course of defensive action that does not involve harming (using?) X is less than her most valuable course of defensive action that does involve harming (using?) X. - X could be morally responsible for his position with respect (= posing a danger) to Victim. o PV: It’s not clear what cases this covers that are not covered by the first condition. Threats are either rightful (just) or wrongful (unjust). Pp. 41, 43. - Non-autonomous threats against non-liable people are deemed unjust. E-mail. o PV: This seems to me to be a mistake. Rocks do not wrong people. Nor do infants or windblown people. Thus, the threats they pose are not unjust (nor just)— although, of course, they are unfair in some sense. Non-autonomous threats should be treated separately from wrongful autonomous threats (even if they are equally liable). o PV: By “unjust treatment” HF means something different than I do: she means “not liable to the treatment” 2.2 On-lookers, Bystanders, Direct Threats, Indirect Threats, Causes of Threats On-looker for Victim: (1) Her actions, movements, and presence do not contribute, and have not contributed, to a threat to Victim, and (2) neither intentional harming of her, nor harming her as a side-effect, would avert/mitigate the threat to Victim. P. 31 - On-lookers are not threats, nor means of averting a threat. Bystander for Victim: (1) Her actions, movements, and presence do not contribute, and have not contributed, to a threat to Victim, but (2) suitable (intentional) harming of her would avert/mitigate a threat to Victim (using her as a shield) - Bystanders are not causally involved in the threat to victim at all, but their presence offers additional opportunities for averting a threat, compared with their absence. p. 22, 45. 3 Direct threat: an action or bodily movement that threatens without any intervening agency by others. - This includes non-autonomous threats. Pp. 32, 63-64. o Friend, whose paralyzed body is used by Villain to beat Victim to death. P. 32 o Innocent person in a falling trolley that will crush kill Victim. P. 38. o Innocent person whose body will crush and kill Victim. P. 38. o Innocent person tied to front of trolley, combined physical mass of which will crush and kill Victim. P. 39 Indirect threat: an action, bodily movement, or presence, that contributes, via the agency of another, or via an act of nature?, to a threat. P. 2, 22, 32 - Question: Does nature count as an intermediary (e.g., in Trolley case with freak act of nature setting off the threat)? Suppose that agent voluntarily goes to sleep by one of the tracks (if relevant, you can assume that she knows that there is a possibility that Nature will act as follows). Nature then starts an empty trolley down the track towards the five. Is the single agent an indirect threat to the others? (Here there is no intermediate agency of people, just Nature.) HF tentatively says yes (e-mail). - Enablers (PV’s term): help to bring about a threat (e.g., driving the car from which shot will be fired). - Obstructers ([my reformulation of HF, p. 22 to avoid problematic subjunctive conditionals]: pose no direct threat, but they contribute to a threat (via the agency of another, or of Nature? [as in Runaway Trolley, p. 33]) because their presence reduces the value to Victim of the most valuable [= least costly] defensive actions available to her without harming them. Example 1, p. 34: Passerby—who will be startled and thereby reveal presence of Victim—is an obstructer, since her presence reduces the value of the most valuable defensive actions (i.e., just hiding quietly) available to Victim without harming Passerby. Example 2: Innocent person lying next to tracks of runaway trolley that will kill Victim, p. 38. - Indirect cause of a threat: Her current actions, movements, and presence do not pose a threat (direct or indirect) but her past actions, movements, and presence causally contributed to a direct threat by another agent to Victim. P. 36. o Example: Mafia bosses who hires Hitman to kill Victim and can no longer influence Hitman. P. 36 Cause of a threat = direct threat or indirect cause of a threat. P. 36. Question: P. 79, bottom, seems to suggest that one can be a direct threat without being a cause of that threat. Is this because one is a cause of a threat (direct or indirect) only when one is agentresponsible for bringing it about (as opposed to allowing) the threat (which seems implausible)? There is also some reference to intentionality, but I’m not sure how it’s relevant. Is it because one is a cause of a threat only if one intentionally brings it about? I’m a bit lost here. 4 2.3 Justice and Permissibility Just (PV strict sense) = wrongs no one. Just (common sense, PV loose sense) = does not wrong the intrudee under consideration (e.g., the person attacked), even though it might wrong someone else (e.g., because it involves using someone else’s gun without her consent). - It’s better, I think, to call such intrusions rightful, where this leaves open whether someone else is wronged. Just (HF) = does not harm anyone who is not liable to that harm - Note: Non-autonomous harms can be unjust in this sense. Permissible (PV, and HF?) = (1) not impersonally wrong, and (2) wrongs no one without overriding (= lesser evil) justification. Overriding (lesser evil) justifications: This is a kind of consequentialist appeal (but with special moral theory of the good) that can override rights considerations. It allows that an action can be permissible even though it wrongs someone, when the expected value of the impersonal moral goodness of its consequence is sufficiently greater than that of the best consequences obtainable without wronging anyone. - Note that in this case wronging is necessary to achieve the expected benefits. - Some versions allow such overriding justifications only when there is a conflict of rights. Others allow them even when there is no conflict of rights. - This typically requires that the benefit be significantly greater than the wrongful harm imposed (or, according to HF, harm she has a duty to bear). o Where a person is liable (or has a duty to bear) to 5 units of harm, it can be permissible, on the basis of overriding justification, to impose 6 units of harm, for 5 units of benefit, since this is really 1 unit of excess harm for 5 units of benefit. pp. 10, 84-85 o HF (pp. 9, 69) writes of “discounting” liable harm, but she means (confirmed by e-mail) “ignoring” that harm. By “morally weighted harm”, she means “non-liable (and no duty to bear) harm”. She doesn’t mean to invoke weights. 2.4 Liability and Immunity Liability to harm: Individual lacks a right against having the harm inflicted, because he has forfeited his usual rights against such harm as a result of behaving in a particular way (e.g., not because of onset of dementia). He is not wronged by such harm. - HF adds: Ordinarily, he may not defend himself against such harms. P. 3, 4, 72, 96. Note that p. 85 (after Apparent Murder) treats the second condition as always holding for liability. - PV Comment: I wouldn’t invoke rights of defense in this definition. I think, for example, that non-autonomous threats are liable to defensive harm (e.g., not owed compensation) but they have rights of self-defense. 5 Question about Dignitary example, pp. 83-84: You say that Dignitary is not liable to defensive attack, because she hasn’t forfeited her right not to be so attacked (because Dignitary’s defensive attack is just, despite the false belief). Agreed. - You then say that she lacks a right not to be suitably attacked, because she has a duty to bear to bear certain costs in virtue of the threat she imposes. I say: If she has this duty, and she is not complying with it, does she not forfeit her right not to be suitably attacked? o PV: I think that HF reserves liability to attack to cases where the individual has lost her rights against attack in virtue of being a threat for which she is responsible. So, there will be lots of cases where a person is not wronged by the attack even though she is not liable. - Of course, even if you grant this, you may also hold something stronger: By posing the threat to Victim, she immediately (prior to any opportunity to bear some of the costs and thus prior to any failure to meet her duty) loses her right not to be suitably attacked. But I don’t understand why this isn’t a case of forfeiting rights in virtue of posing a threat. Can you explain why not? Liability to defensive harm: liability to harm that serves a defensive purpose (e.g., reduces unjust harm). P. 100 Liability to non-defensive harm from defensive action: liability to harm that the defending agents believes serves a defensive purpose but in fact serves no defensive purpose - Example: In Apparent Murder, p. 85, Enemy is morally responsible for making Victim falsely believe that Enemy poses an unjust lethal threat. HF says that he is liable to being killed, even though this is not defensive harm. HF does not distinguish between formal and effective liability (my terms), but I believe that the distinction is sometime relevant for her discussions. Formal liability to a certain intrusion (PV; McMahan calls this potential liability): The intrusion is compatible with absolute proportionality (which is an upper limit, based solely on the consequences of the attacker’s past and present and possible future actions in the absence of any defensive action). - Facts about the consequences of defensive attack (how effective the defense is, whether it is necessary, the harms suffered by various people, etc.) are not relevant. Effective liability to a certain intrusion (PV): The intrusion does not wrong the individual, given the full circumstances and the consequences of defensive action. - Pure proportionality externalists [PV’s term] (e.g., purely past-regarding externalists) about liability hold the formal liability is all there is to (full) effective liability. - HF’s proportionate means externalism holds that facts about whether the defense has reasonable prospects of success (e.g., is a means) are relevant. - Internalists hold that necessity is also required. Immunity from harm: not permissible to harm (even if liable). - PV: This terminology is somewhat confusing. On a Hohfeldian analysis of rights, an immunity to X is simply the lack of a liability to X. Better to say: impermissible to harm. 6 2.5 Necessity and Liability Necessity condition for liability (roughly): the least costly means to harmed person of achieving a relevant goal (e.g., reduction in harm from non-rightful threats) without imposing costs on nonliable others. Internalists (such as McMahan and PV) hold that that liability involves a necessity condition, but externalists (such as HF) deny that it does. 2.6 Proportionality and Liability Proportionality - Narrow: This is a condition on liability to harm. o It is typically held that the harms to which a person is liable must not be too great relative to the achieved reduction in the non-rightful harms (e.g., killing someone to stop him from stealing your chocolate bar is narrowly disproportionate). – Normally, however, they may be significantly greater than the benefits obtained (e.g., kill a wrongful attacker to stop him from cutting off your legs). - Wide: This is a condition for overriding (i.e., lesser evil) justifications for permissibility. o The harms to non-liable parties must not be too great relative to the achieved benefit from the reduction in the non-rightful harms. Normally, these harms (in excess of any harm to which the bearers are liable) must be significantly less than the benefits obtained (e.g., one may kill one innocent person to save a million, but not to save one). Important: HF (fn. 38, p. 155; e-mail) uses “proportionality” to mean something like the kind of standards usually used for “narrow proportionality”, but she applies those standards both to cases where the individual is potentially liable and to cases where the individual is not potentially liable. She says that wide proportionality is simply part (along with necessity and reasonable prospective of success) of a lesser-evil justification for wronging some people. I’m not sure, however, that she is consistent. The following are some distinctions that I would make, that HF does not make. Absolute proportionality (PV): the upper limit of harm that can be effectively proportionate, based solely on the consequences of the attacker’s past and present and possible future actions in the absence of any defensive action). - Facts about the consequences of defensive attack (how effective the defense is, whether it is necessary, the harms suffered by various people, etc.) are not relevant. Full proportionality (PV): proportionality in a given circumstances given the facts about the attacker’s past, present, and possible future actions, and given the facts about options the defender has and their consequences. For example, if a defensive action imposes a massive, but absolutely proportionate, harm on an attacker with only a trivial reduction in the intrusion-harms 7 imposed by attacker, then the defensive action may not be fully proportionate, even though it is absolutely proportionate. 2.7 Agent Responsibility and Moral Responsibility Agent-responsibility (often confusingly called “moral responsibility”, but not by HF): whether a person’s presence or movements, and the associated results “belongs” to an agent, or “flows from” her agency (e.g., not the movement of an insane or windblown person.). P. 74 Moral responsibility (PV) = some positive degree of (moral) culpability = agent-responsibility for acting wrongly (impermissibly) [e.g., based on degree of psychologically autonomous choice, strength of the evidence that action was wrong, and resistibility of choice] Moral Innocence (PV): no agent-responsibility for acting wrongly (impermissibly) [even if acting wrongly] Moral responsibility for an unjust threat (HF): agent-responsibility for acting unjustly (or perhaps for acting wrongly) On the other hand, she seems to distinguish two cases based on motives. - Minimally responsible: only slight degree of moral responsibility? - Culpable: high degree of moral responsibility? But she writes: o agent acts unjustly from bad motives (e.g., greed, jealously, or malice; p. 1; Deliberate Trolley, p. 34). [Are bad motives really needed if one freely and knowingly acts wrongly (but perhaps indifferently)?] o Why do motives matter for culpability? Why isn’t it enough that one freely and knowingly acts wrongly (but perhaps with good motives)? Aren’t I culpable when I wrongly take your wallet, in order to help some starving children? Here we assume that the ends do not justify the means. - Moderate responsibility (a possibility confirmed by e-mail): something in between (for example, someone under minor duress knowingly acts wrongly) Morally innocent (HF): not morally responsible for acting wrongly (or unjustly) - agentially innocent: not agent-responsible for any threat that is unjust (or impermissible?). P. 74 o non-threats o threats who are not agent-responsible for the threat: (e.g., fetuses, schizophrenics, falling people; p. 8, 10, 21, 22, 25) - agentially responsible for threat that is unjust (impermissible?) but not morally responsible (e.g., because there was inadequate evidence that her action was impermissible or inadequate opportunity to avoid performing it). 2.8 Exploitative and Eliminative Harms Note that the following are defined in terms of the agent’s aims (intentions). Related definitions could be given in terms of (1) the agent’s beliefs, (2) evidentially supported propositions, and (3) the objective facts. 8 Eliminative harming: harming that aims at mitigating/eliminating a threat that she currently poses (and thus not deriving any benefit from her current presence). P. 8 [e.g., killing the falling person who will otherwise crush one] Exploitative (sometimes called opportunistic) harming: harming that aims at making use of Victim to mitigate/eliminate a threat to which she does not currently contribute and (added by email) for which she is not causally responsible in virtue of past actions (movements or presence) (and thus deriving a benefit from Victim’s current presence and from her overall presence). (p. 8) [e.g., pulling a bystander in front of one to block Aggressor’s bullet that would otherwise kill one] Merely (or barely) opportunistic harming (killing) [e-mail: a third, non-overlapping category]: harming in a way that uses [ignore references to “aims to use”] the victim to avert a threat for which she (or her body) is causally responsible in virtue of past actions (movements or presence), but to which she (her actions, movements, or presence) does not currently contribute (and thus deriving a benefit from Victim’s current presence but not from her overall presence) [e.g., killing the person who threw the knife to ringleader, where ringleader now is attempting to kill one with it, so that the rest of the mob will be scared away]. P. 163. To use a person= To use solely as a means [sometimes abbreviated to: to use a means] = To use their person (in the more generic sense) exploitatively p. 46. - E-mail: Eliminative use is not using as a means, but merely opportunistic use is. 3. Substantive Claims about Individual Self-Defense All views are HF’s, unless otherwise noted. 3.1 Moral Responsibility An agent is morally responsible (for an unjust threat) if and only if (confirmed in e-mail) Agent intentionally fails to avail herself of a reasonable opportunity to avoid imposing the unjust threat. p. 10, 73 An agent intentionally fails to avail herself of a reasonable opportunity to avoid unjust threat, if and only if (confirmed in e-mail) [my reformulation] (1) she believes, or reasonably believes, that she has a feasible action that (a) is not too costly to her or other innocent people and (b) will not pose the unjust threat, and (2) she chooses an action that she correctly believes will lead to an unjust threat. p. 11 - Unlike McMahan, HF denies that (e.g., in Careful Motorist) mere knowledge that one imposes a very small risk of imposing unjust harm is sufficient to make one morally responsible for that harm, if it eventuates. Risks that are sufficiently low (relative to the risked harms) are deemed irrelevant (because one can reasonably believe that one won’t impose the harm). 9 - - - If, however, one knows that one is contributing to a project that aims at (intends) unjust intrusion-harm (e.g., Driver in Drive-By), then one may be morally responsible for intrusionharm, even if the risk is very small. P. 82 The threshold for a reasonable belief that the threat one poses is just is very high. P. 184. o Those who knowingly contribute to a threat are morally responsible for their contribution unless (1) they have very strong evidence that the threat they contribute is just, or (2) they have a reasonable belief that they lack a reasonable opportunity to avoid posing the threat. P. 184. The standards for reasonable belief above are sensitive to the same factors below for being too costly. Whether an action is too costly depends on: (1) the cost to the agent, and other innocents, of avoiding posing the unjust threat, (2) the unjust harm, if any, to the victim of posing the unjust threat, and (3) the kind of threat (direct threat, indirect threat, indirect cause of a threat), if any, that the agent poses, and (4) whether the agent will be allowing herself to threaten, or causing (bringing about) herself to threaten (if she threatens at all). - The limit on costs depends on the circumstances. o Lowest limit on cost: for indirect threats who allow themselves to threaten. o Highest limit on cost: for direct threats who cause themselves to threaten. o High, but lower, limit on cost: for indirect cause of threat. P. 74 - An action is not unreasonably costly for an agent if it does not exceed the cost that she is morally required to bear for Victim’s sake. P. 86 3.2 Liability and Moral Responsibility Narrow View of Liability (HF’s and McMahan’s [original?] view): A person can be liable to be defensively harmed only to avert a threat for which she is morally responsible. P. 17, 188 Broad View of Liability (Hurka’s and PV’s view): A person can be liable to be defensively harmed to avert any proportionate threat (even ones for which she is not morally responsible; e.g., threats from others). Moral responsibility for an unjust (direct or indirect) threat renders a person liable to defensive force/harm. P. 10, 27, 72, 80. - Driver who, under threat of death from Terrorist, drives car for a drive-by killing is liable to being defensively killed. A person can be liable to being defensively harmed only to avert an unjust (direct or indirect) threat for which she is morally responsible (but it can be permissible, a lesser evil justification) to harm a non-liable person. pp. 4, 37, 73, 75, 83 - Harming a person to avert a threat for which she is not responsible makes exploitative use of her, and therefore wrongs her (because no one is liable to such use), even if she is liable to defensive harm (to reduce unjust harms for which she is responsible). P. 188 So, non-autonomous threats and reasonably ignorant unjust threats are not liable to defensive attack, are wronged if so attacked, and are owed compensation if so attacked? I would reject this. 10 HF (e-mail) says that that they have certain duties to avoid harming and are not wronged if they fail to perform those duties. She also says that they are not owed compensation when defensively attacked. Seems a bit confusing. Thus, a person can be liable to being defensively harmed if and only if the harm helps averts an unjust threat for which she is morally responsible. 3.3 Liability and Necessity Internalism about liability (e.g., McMahan, PV): (Effective) Liability requires necessity Externalism about liability (Quong and Firth, HF): Liability does not require necessity. - Purely backward-looking externalism about liability (Quong and Firth?): Liability is based solely on what the agent has done in the past (and not what the options and consequences are for defending against her). o There is no requirement that the harm be necessary or a means (instrumental) to advancing the relevant goal (e.g., reduction in unjust harm). - Pure proportionality externalism (PV): Liability is based solely on proportionality (which can be sensitive to what the agent is currently doing and may do in the future). o There is no condition how effective, or necessary, the defensive action is. o In e-mail, HF acknowledges that this may be a better description of the Quong and Firth position. There is no reason to limit the relevant facts to past behavior. - Proportionate means externalism about liability (HF): An agent is liable to a given harm only if it is a proportionate means of averting a threat. This requires both proportionality based on the past and some positive effect on averting the threat (a means). P. 12-13 In middle of last paragraph of p. 105, HF adds: “attacker must be morally responsible for an unjust threat”. This is part of her account of proportionality, but it seems best not to build it into the content of proportionate means externalism (so that it is a more general doctrine). Harms that had some prospect of averting a threat but failed to do so fail the necessity test. P. 152 PV: This seems quite wrong. The various tests should be based on the objective facts at the time of action. If the objective facts are probabilistic, the relevant tests (necessity, proportionality) should be based on the objectively expected value at the time of action. How things happen to turn out is irrelevant. (Defensive action that is 99.99% likely to succeed but doesn’t can still be a means and can be necessary and proportionate.) 3.4 Liability and Proportionality Proportionality is judged by the magnitude of the harm to which one contributes, not by the magnitude of one’s contribution to that harm (pp. 76-78), nor by the cost of taking a reasonable opportunity to avoid the harm). - HF’s argument on p. 78 for the first point on assumes that those who jointly (via joint plans) impose a threat are liable for only their contribution to the threat (with contributions 11 summing to 100%), but I think that in such cases, each individual can be fully liable for the threat (summing to more than 100%). Joint intentions change things morally, I think. Proportionality of defensive harms is determined by whether, if fully successful, the harm to the attacker is proportionate to the reduction in harm to defender (and perhaps others). P. 150-51 PV’s view: Absolute proportionality is (in agreement with HF) not based on the probability of successful defense. It is merely the most harm that can be imposed in light of the threat imposed. Full proportionality (in a given choice situation, given the facts about the consequences of various choices) is based on the (objectively) expected values: of the harm imposed on the attacker and on the level of non-rightful harm imposed on the defender. I disagree with HF that (full) proportionality is based on the appropriate balance, if the defense if fully successful. Imposing 10 units of intrusion-harm to prevent, with certainty, an unjust imposition of 10 units of intrusion-harm may not wrong an innocent attacker, but imposing the same harm may wrong her if it has only a 1% chance of success. Foreseen harms (e.g., to others) that are mediated by other agents are heavily discounted in a defender’s proportionality calculation (e.g., a victim preventing her attack even though it will lead attacker to attack two additional women). PV: For (narrow) proportionality, the question is the limits of harm to an intruder that will not wrong her. A natural thought is that the intruder must not suffer harms that are too great relative to the protection to defender of the defense. Shooting a rapist in the leg to stop a rape is narrowly proportionate in this sense, even if it has the result that the rapist will rape two additional women (whom he would not otherwise have raped). It does not, it seems to me, wrong the rapist (even though it may be wrong) to shoot him in the leg where this stops the rape. HF seems to assume that the effects on everyone must be determined to determine narrow proportionality, and that makes it seem in places (e.g., p. 129) that she is invoking wide proportionality. She isn’t, but she is, I claim, invoking an implausible criterion for narrow proportionality It’s enough, I say, for the intrusion-harm to the attacker not to be too great relative to the protection to just the defending agent (independently of the effects on others, although those effects may be relevant to the permissibility of so defending). PV: More generally, my view is that narrow proportionality is satisfied as long as there is some group of individuals (including the defending agent or not) who have authorized, or at least not denied authorization, relative to whom the defense is proportionate. That’s enough to establish that the attacker is not wronged (where necessary for the achieved reduction in non-rightful intrusion-harms). That leaves open whether the defense is permissible (and the effects on everyone are relevant for that). [We now return to HF’s views] At some point [if it defends enough innocent victims], it’s going to become proportionate to start inflicting even lethal collateral harm as part of a bid to prevent the unjust, forcible imposition of this regime. End of first full paragraph, p. 141. 12 It can be proportionate to risk collateral damage to innocent people in the course of averting harm to the lesser interests of sufficiently many people. (p. 14). Whereas one ought to bear lethal costs rather than (intentionally?) cause oneself to nondefensively kill an innocent person, one need not bear lethal costs rather than (intentionally?) allowing oneself to non-defensively kill an innocent person. Nonetheless, one must bear significant costs (e.g., paralysis rather than death) in the latter case, since one is morally responsible for being a threat (since the opportunity to avoid being a threat is reasonable and one intentionally chooses not to take it). Indeed, one is liable to having such costs imposed. P. 79. A person who is morally responsible for indirect lethal threats (e.g., intentionally obstructing escape route) is liable to defensive force, including being killed. P. 10 PV: General note on killing: I think, rather controversially, that full proportionality for nonrightful killing is based on the actual setback to interests the killing imposes on the victim and on the actual setback to interests that defensive action will impose on the attacker. If the killer will in any case die in five minutes (or have a comparably low quality longer life), she may be liable to being killed to protect your little finger. If you will die in five minutes (or have a comparably low quality longer life), a non-autonomous killer (for example) with a normal life may be not be liable to being killed to stop her from killing you. HF seems to assume that all innocent lives are equally valuable for proportionality calculations. A note on PV’s views on proportionality in case they are relevant to discussion: I distinguish (in the concepts section) between absolute formal proportionality (given only the facts about the attacker’s past and possible future actions) and full proportionality (given the full facts, including the defender’s feasible options and their consequences). Full proportionality, I claim, requires aggregative proportionality in its consequences (comparing the benefits and costs for feasible actions to defender and attacker). This requires that the attacker not suffer more intrusion-harm than under the most intrusion-harm he experience by an absolutely proportionate (for everyone) defensive action that minimizes the total (for defender and all intruders) excess intrusion-harm. Excess intrusion-harm for an individual is the intrusion-harm to her in excess of the level of intrusion-harm for which she would be agent-responsible for imposing on defender (and which is in fact non-rightful) in the absence of defensive action (adjusted upward, if culpable). - For example (with just one intruder), suppose that imposing intrusion-harm of 10 on nonautonomous intruder is absolutely proportionate to avoid intrusion-harm of 10 to defender (e.g., it doesn’t wrong intruder when the only alternative is for defender to bear a harm of 10 herself). The intruder is thus formally liable to having 10 units of harm imposed. Nonetheless, he may not be effectively liable to this, because it may be aggregatively disproportionate. Suppose that the defender has one additional option, which imposes 2 units of intrusion-harm on intruder and reduces her intrusion-harm to 1 (from 10). That option minimizes total excess intrusion-harm (2+1 =3, vs. 10) and intruder only suffers 2 units of intrusion-harm. Thus imposing 10 units on intruder imposes more harm on intruder that the excess intrusion-harm minimizing action. It is fully (but not absolutely) disproportionate because it is not aggregatively proportionate. 13 3.5 Liability and Defense of Honor A person’s honor (PV’s reconstruction) is the public recognition of her being an entity with certain rights (who thus can be wronged). The more rights (in the superset sense) that are publically recognized, the greater her honor. Her honor is reduced when she is wronged, but less so when she, or others, forcibly resist such wronging, and (I would add) less so, when such wronging is publically recognized, condemned, and/or rectified. HF (e-mail) suggests that she should have used the term moral standing (and perhaps would not invoke any of the public recognition stuff I suggested above). Unjust threats to the victim’s honor are liable to defensive attack to protect that honor (even if the defense does not reduce the physical threat). Pp. 13, 90, 101. Fn. 32, p. 179 Question: Why not simply allow that harms need not be physical harms? Surely psychological harms are relevant. Do you think that, even if the victim’s interests/wellbeing is in no way affected, that her honor still can be affected (e.g., because it’s a matter of public recognition and that matters, even the victim doesn’t care about it)? Question: Are physically harmless wrongings threats to the victim’s honor? HF (e-mail) says that spitting and pulling hair are threats to honor, although I say that these are not harmless. Question: Is it only (or primarily?) culpable primary threats that threaten one’s honor (and not unjust threats based on mistaken belief that that was permissible?). p. 110. Fn. 23 suggests this. Yes, HF confirms. Question: I wonder whether even innocent autonomous unjust threats do not threaten one’s honor, if they are not be publically recognized as mistakes. Although proportionality in defense of one’s honor is sensitive to the seriousness of the primary threat, it is not (pace Statman) proportionate to impose a harm equal to the primary harm merely to defend one’s honor, when this has no effect on the primary harm one suffers. It is, for example, proportionate to break a wrist or arm to defend one’s honor against rape but not to impose blindness, paralysis, or death. Pp. 112-13, Fn. 32, p. 179 3.6 Liability and Defensive Action without Defensive Harm Threats can be liable to harms imposed by defensive action (even if it does not reduce the risk of harmful threat), even if they are not liable defensive harms P. 100, 154 - Example: In Apparent Murderer, p. 86, Enemy is morally responsible for the Victim’s false belief that his (ineffective) attack was needed to defend against an unjust attack by Enemy. Enemy is liable to be killed by Victim. o Note: Liability is, I believe, attacker-relative. Enemy may be liable to be killed by Victim in this case, but he is not liable to being killed by a third-part who knows that Enemy poses no threat to Victim. - Other examples? 14 Question: How are the conditions for liability to non-defensive harm different from those for liability to defensive harm? What are the general conditions for liability to harm, or to nondefensive harm? - HF replies: That’s something I need to think more about. My thought in the book was that one needn’t be responsible for an unjust threat to be liable to non-defensive harm, but only morally responsible for Victim’s belief that one poses an unjust threat. But Kim Ferzan has pointed out that, if liability is instrumental, Enemy can’t be liable in these cases, since harming him averts no threat. So I need to revise my treatment of these cases. Defensive attacks in response to unjust attack are unjust, if they have no prospect of success (and hence the harms imposed are not defensive harms). Proportionality is irrelevant. Such attacks are not means to defense and thus neither proportionate nor disproportionate. P. 151. - They also fail the necessity (last resort) requirement for permissibility. Question: Why are there no standards of proportionality, even if they are different? For example, suppose in Apparent Murder the merely apparent threat is a slight bruise instead of death. Is Enemy still liable to be killed (non-defensively)? HF: Yes, this (and the next question) is part of what needs re-thinking Question: I thought that one could be liable to defensive attack even if it serves no defensive purpose (e.g., where one is responsible for the attacker’s belief that she is being unjustly attacked by you). HF: I need to rethink this. 3.7 Liability: Other Claims It wrongs a person to be used solely as a means (i.e., exploitatively). Agents are liable to have defensive harm inflicted on them, when they have a duty to bear such harm. Victor Tadros also makes the stronger, and much more controversial, claim that agents are liable to have defensive harm inflicted on them, when they would have a duty to bear such harm, if they were able to. I am deeply suspicious of this appeal to a counterfactual duty. Various things may need to change for the person to be able, and that might fundamentally alter the situation. I think it better to simply specify the relevant actual conditions that make people liable. HF doesn’t endorse the counterfactual duty. 3.8 Liability and Rectification In general, HF gives little attention to rights of rectification for past wrongings (e.g., recognition, apology, compensation). I believe that failure to fulfill the rectification duties imposes an intrusion-harm and that this provides the basis for using harmful force (subject to the same conditions as all defensive force). There is a current threat in my sense: the threat of infringing these rectification rights. 15 3.9 Permissibility and Wrongdoing 3.9.1 General Lethal defense of lesser interests can be permissible (on the basis of an overriding justification) when enough people are protected (i.e., with aggregation). P. 14 To wrongly risk harm to a person is a wrong independent of whether the harm is realized. P. 156. It is impermissible to inflict collateral harms on innocents in defense of honor. Fn. 32, p. 179 It is impermissible to inflict harm on someone (even if liable to it), if that harm serves no moral purpose (e.g., for reducing primary unjust harm or for reducing threat to one’s honor). P. 117, Agents who pose (directly or indirectly) an unjust (e.g., lethal) threat, but who are not morally responsible for the threat (e.g., because their evidence supports the view that there is no reasonable opportunity to avoid so acting) have a duty to avoid [to the extent possible, I would add] imposing the unjust (e.g., lethal) harm (e.g., even if the costs are lethal)—even though they are not liable to defensive harm (e-mail). P. 9, 67 3.9.2 Direct Threats It is permissible to kill one innocent direct threat to save one innocent person. P. 40 Question: How is this possible? If they are innocent, they are not morally responsible. If they are not morally responsible, they are not liable. If they are not liable, then it is not permissible to kill them to save one innocent life. HF: They have a duty to bear significant harm to avoid killing an innocent person. This means that inflicting that much harm upon them does not wrong them (they’re not liable but they nonetheless lack rights against suffering the harm). PV: What if they are unable to avoid killing the innocent person? They have no duty in this case. I guess she means something like: Those who have a duty, when possible, to bear a significant harm are not wronged (or at least: it’s not wrong) when that harm is imposed on them. 3.9.3 Indirect Threats An indirect threat is liable defensive force only if she is morally responsible for her contribution to that threat. Pp. 47, 72. [In the text, HF writes: It is permissible to use defensive force against an indirect threat only if she is morally responsible for her contribution to that threat, but she retracted this by e-mail. It can be permissible on the basis of an overriding justification.] It is nearly always impermissible to kill innocent indirect threats merely to save a single life. P. 10 - It is impermissible to kill one innocent lying at the side of the tracks” [i.e., an innocent obstructer] top of P. 40. - It can be permissible, however, to kill one innocent person to save millions of lives. 16 - It is permissible to divert the trolley from where it will likely kill ten to where it will likely kill one, but it is impermissible to divert a trolley from where it will likely kill two to where it will likely kill one. (Moreover: The standard is set even higher in cases where one intentionally (rather than merely foreseeably) harms an innocent person.) P. 154 3.9.4 Bystanders There is a “prohibition on killing innocent bystander in the course of saving [only] one’s own life”. p. 6. The constraints on harming innocent indirect threats and innocent bystanders are sufficiently stringent that they can be overridden only by harms that meet both a proportionality standard (since they can be liable) and a lesser-evil standard. It’s proportionate to kill an innocent indirect threat or bystander to save just two innocent people, but the lesser-evil standard requires more. It requires, for example, that there is a reasonable prospect of achieving a proportionate good that significantly outweighs the harm inflicted on the non-liable persons. Revised Defense Account of mediated harms (endorsed by HF, p. 14): - Foreseen but unintended mediated (by other agents) harms are relevant to the permissibility of defensive action, but they are heavily discounted for the proportionality requirement. - The duty of agents to bear costs, rather than trigger merely foreseen mediated harms to others, is limited to her (general) duty to rescue others from (unjust?) harm. 3.10 Permissibility and Necessity (for Lesser-Evil Justification) A defensive harm, against a given person, counts as necessary (e.g., for permissibility) if it averts [added by e-mail: in a least costly manner] a the threat that she poses, even if other people will then go on to impose the harm averted. P. 208 Because harms to innocent people who are not potentially beneficiaries of the action are morally weighted moral heavily than harms to innocent people who are potentially beneficiaries of the action, where the harms are the same for the two groups, necessity (for permissibility) requires, when possible, harming the potential beneficiaries is required by the necessity condition (since only it minimizes moralized harm). (Thus, a state may be required to impose such harm on its own innocent non-combatants rather on innocent non-combatants in the aggressor state.) P. 146. PV: Note that here HF appeals to a moralized notion of necessity, with moral weights for costs and benefits. 3.11 Permissibility, Exploitation, and Elimination Compared with eliminative killing of liable people, there is no higher burden of justification for merely opportunistic killing (=opportunistic killing for which they are morally responsible in virtue of past actions, but not in virtue of present actions, behavior, or presence) P. 179, 181, 193 17 Killing a person exploitatively (e.g., killing Roof Shooter, p. 189, to block the bullets from Better Shooter, when it is costly to avoid Roof Shooter’s bullets) wrongs her, but it is a much less serious wronging when she is liable to eliminative killing (as Roof Shooter is on an internalist account, in which there is no necessity condition) compared to when she is not. Thus, it is easier for such actions to be permissible on the basis on a lesser-evil justification. P. 193 3.12 Permissibility and Duties to Bear Costs It worse for a person to suffer a given physical harm as the result of a rights-violation (even if a non-autonomous?) than to suffer the same physical harm as the result of a natural cause. P. 136. Question: Is this also true of permissible rights infringements? HF: I need to think more about this. - Thus (?), in defense cases, Victim is required to bear roughly the same cost to prevent mediated harms to others as he would be to rescue others from comparable harms. P. 136. 3.13 Permissibility and Reasonable Prospect of Success The Subsuming Account of Reasonable Prospects (Hurka and McMahan; rejected by HF): The permissibility of defensive action (individual, or for jus ad bellum) does not have an independent requirement of reasonable prospects of success (in achieving reduction in wrongful intrusionharms). This is because, they claim, it is automatically covered by the requirement that the intrusion-harm imposed be narrowly proportionate (if the chance of success is too low, the expected benefits will not be high enough) - HF claims that narrow proportionality is not sensitive to probability success. Instead, it is based on the assumption that defensive action succeeds in preventing (completely?) nonrightful intrusion-harm. P. 15. Stated otherwise, I think: Proportionality is based solely on the risk of non-rightful intrusion-harm that the other agent risks imposing, and not on the success of any defensive action. (This is true of what I call formal proportionality, but not, on my view, of effective proportionality.) - HF claims that, if there is no prospect of success, then the intrusion-harm is unnecessary. (p. 14). Agreed. - HF claims that the reasonable prospect of success requirement (for individual selfdefense as well?) is a distinct requirement for lesser evil justifications and it requires that there be a reasonable prospect of success that the use of force will be a means (i.e. increase the chance) of achieving a proportionate end. P. 15. The requirement of a reasonable prospect of success is a lesser-evil constraint on the infliction of proportionate harms. It provides protection against collateral harm to innocents. P. 153. 4. Basic Concepts for the Morality of War Reductive individualism (endorsed by McMahan, HF, and PV): Moral rules of war are just the moral rules of everyday life. (p. 2). No special permissions and no special constraints. Non-Combatant Immunity (traditionally accepted, rejected by HF and PV): It is impermissible to intentionally target non-combatants in war. P. 164. 18 Vital interests are those interest that warrant lethal defense even to protect those interests of a single person (i.e., without aggregation). Lesser interests are those interests that do not warrant lethal defense to protect those interests of a single person. Conditional force: Aggression that will become violent only if resisted. P. 124 Purely political aggression: Aggression that, if not resisted, threatens only political interests (e.g., sovereignty or territorial integrity) and not any vital interests of individuals (life, physical harm, etc.). 5. Substantive Claims about the Morality of War 5.1 Claims about Liability of Non-Combatants Contributions to welfare goods (food, medicine) can make one liable just as much as contributions to military goods (weapons) can, when one is morally responsible for the contribution to an unjust threat. P. 204. - Those who knowingly finance (e.g., by paying taxes) unjust war can be liable to defensive attack. P. 212. Many/most non-combatants in Western democracies are morally responsible for their contribution to the war effort, and are thus liable to defensive attack, because (1) they knowingly contribute to the war effort (e.g. providing taxes, food, or military equipment), (2) they not have very strong evidence that the threat to which they contribute is just, and (3) they do not have a reasonable belief that they lack a reasonable opportunity to avoid posing the threat. Pp. 15-16, 184. In war, past contributions to macro-threats one’s state imposes (its war effort) count as current threats for the individual. Thus, individuals with such past contributions can be liable (when morally responsible for those contribution) for current defensive harm. P. 194-95. Red Cross medics can be liable to being defensively killed, if they are (as they often are) morally responsible for indirect unjust lethal threat (e.g., by saving the life of an unjust soldier who will return to battle). P. 202. - It is permissible for them to treat unjust soldiers who will return to battle only if the just combatants consent to this. P. 205. 5.2 Claims about Immunity of Non-Combatants It can be permissible (on the basis of a lesser evil justification) to kill non-liable non-combatants, even medical personnel. P. 17 19 The requirement of necessity, for permissible defensive force, provides only limited protection to non-combatants. P. 188 Given (1) the epistemic difficulty of identifying liable non-combatants, and especially (2) the difficulty of attacking liable non-combatants without causing impermissible collateral harms (e.g., to young children), there is in practice a strong presumption that attacking non-combatants is impermissible (but which can be overridden in specific cases). 188. 5.3 Other Claims Reasonable prospects of success is an independent jus ad bellum requirement of permissibility (not reducible to the narrow proportionality requirement): See above under individual selfdefense. Conditional Force Argument (rejected by HF): If the political interests of individuals are not vital, harmful forcible resistance to purely political aggression is (narrowly?) disproportionate. - This lends some support to non-reductive statism (e.g., because the sovereignty of the state is vital to the state). HF’s response to Conditional Force Argument: It can be proportionate to risk collateral damage to innocent people in the course of averting harm to the lesser interests of sufficiently many people. (p. 14). Defense against merely political aggression that is only conditionally violent can be permissible, because foreseen, but mediated (by other agents), harms are heavily discounted in a defenders proportionality calculation. P. 137. If there is a duty of care (as claimed by Rodin), it is owed to all people (equally?) and not merely (or primarily) to one’s co-citizens. P. 138. 20