Andrew Zimmerman George Washington University The Shifting Temporalities of Communism: From the Stages of History to the “war of the enslaved against their enslavers” For “Reframing Latin America’s Nineteenth Century,” Yale University, February 27-28, 2015 Karl Marx had two distinct understandings of the place of communism in history: on the one hand, communism represented a distant vanishing point of history. Communism, as he wrote in the “Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts” of 1844, was “the riddle of history solved.” Yet communism was also, simultaneously, the ongoing historical process through which revolutionaries worked toward this end of history. “Communism is the real [wirkliche -- i.e. actual] movement,” Marx wrote the next year in the German Ideology, “that abolishes the present [jetzigen] state of things.” Throughout his intellectual career and through his political engagements, Marx searched for a temporality that would bridge the space between these two communisms -- the real movement against the present and the future vanishing point that solves the riddle of history. The stage theory that Marx and Engels proposed in their early work fell apart in the failure of the 1848 revolutions, while the American Civil War prompted them to reconsider a self-emancipatory temporality of revolutionary war. The American Civil War of 1861-65 played a role for Marx similar to that which the Haitian Revolution of 1791-1804, as Susan Buck-Morss has shown, played for Hegel. When Marx and Engels formulated a stagist temporality in the manifesto that they composed for the Communist League in late 1847, they displaced an earlier program by the tailor-intellectual Wilhelm Weitling. In an 1843 pamphlet, Weitling had demanded an immediate abolition of money, a community of goods, and a reorganization of society that would end poverty and, just as importantly, the subjugation of the poor, as workers, to the whims of the rich. This could occur at any point through armed insurrection.i In their manifesto, Marx and Engels rejected this immediatism, claiming it only helped a feudal elite and prevented the full development of capitalism as a necessary stage on the road to socialism. When revolution broke out in Europe in 1848, Cologne communists condemned this stagist temporality for asking workers to “precipitat[e] ourselves voluntarily into the purgatory of decrepit capitalist rule in order to arrive at the cloudy heaven of your Communist Credo.”ii The bourgeoisie across Europe proved to be an implacable enemy of workers, prompting Marx and Engels to abandon the mechanistic, stage theory of the Communist Manifesto. (Their 1 Zimmerman, 2 stages of economic growth -- minus the final stage of communism -- would be taken up more than a century later by W.W. Rostow in his “Non-Communist Manifesto”iii) The “Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Napoleon,” published in 1852 in New York City for the thousands of German communists émigrés in the US, registered Marx’s post-1848 crisis of communist temporality. In the “18th Brumaire,” the bourgeois progress that Marx and Engels had praised in the Manifesto now seemed little more than repetitions of the past. Marx imagined a temporality that breaks with the linear chronology of conventional history: “The social revolution of the nineteenth century cannot take its poetry from the past but only from the future.” The American Civil War would help Marx and Engels establish a new kind of temporality, a self-making temporality of revolutionary warfare. The two followed closely the progress of the war, in which thousands of German communists and other revolutionaries not only participated and often worked closely with insurrectionary slaves, developing new forms of anti-slavery politics that exceeded, underwrote, and were finally squashed by, official Union military policy. It was through the nineteenth-century revolt of the enslaved in the Americas that Marx finally imagined a communist temporality. The enslaved were, in the nineteenth century, a kind of absolute proletariat with “nothing to lose but your chains” against whom the journeymen who made up the rank-and-file Communists of the nineteenth century measured their own decline. The First International in 1864 and the first volume of Capital of 1867 each situated themselves explicitly in relation to the defeat of slavery in the United States. Despite the failure of Reconstruction to weaken other despotic forms of private property, Marx held on to the self-generating temporality of revolutionary warfare. In his analysis of the Paris Commune of 1871, an event that moved him as only the US Civil War had, Marx described the attack of the Third Republic on the Commune as a “slaveholders’ rebellion.” Yet, where the bourgeois state and party system in the United States had subverted much of the revolutionary potential of the war, the Commune, though defeated, offered a model politics for future revolutions. The Commune, for Marx, was an episode in the same struggle as the American Civil War, “the war of the enslaved against their enslavers, the only justifiable war in history.” Revolutionary politics had become, for Marx and Engels, an innovative and experimental form. The mechanistic stages of the manifesto gave way to a surreal temporality of poetry from the future and opened a place for revolution as war, as the violent moment of political creativity analyzed by Hannah Arendt, Walter Benjamin and others. Zimmerman, 3 i Wilhelm Weitling, Die Menschheit, wie sie ist und wie sie sein sollte, 2nd ed. (1838/39; Jenni, Sohn, 1845). Gottschalk, Freiheit, Arbeit, February 25, 1849, quoted in Hans Stein, Der Kölner Arbeiterverein (1848-1849): ein Beitrag zur Frühgeschichte des rheinischen Sozialismus (Köln: Gilsbach, 1921), 96. Translated and quoted in David McLellan, Karl Marx: His Life and Thought (New York: Harper & Row, 1974), 217. iii W. W Rostow, The Stages of Economic Growth, a Non-Communist Manifesto (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1960). ii