The Judgment of Beauty To judge that something is beautiful is, on the basis of one’s b-enjoyment, to judge that others will enjoy the item in that way, other things being equal. We restate the account of b-enjoyment for convenience. One b-enjoys x’s appearing to have A only if φ is an experience of y’s looking to x to have the features in the array A, and, for some group G (1) x φ’s, and x's φing causes (2) – (5): (2) (a) x occurrently believes, of φ, under A, that it occurs; (b) and has the felt desire, of φ, under A, that it should occur for its own sake; (3) the belief/desire pair in (2) is a first-person reason under A for x to φ. (4) x occurrently believes that x directly values φ’s having A. (5) x occurrently believes that x G-universally values φ’s having A. One believes that one G-universally values x’s appearing to have A if and only if there is a sufficiently large group G of relevantly similar others, and collection C of relevant similar arrays of features such that, for any member y in G, there is some array A’ in C such that if x were to appear to y to have A’, then y would occurrently believe that y directly values x’s appearing to y to have A’. One can think this is not to commit to thinking that the G-similar others will b-enjoy x’s appearing to them in the relevant way. To judge that something is beautiful is to take this step. More fully, One judges x beautiful if and only if (1) one b-enjoys an item x as appearing to have an organized array A of features; [I had dropped the “organized” but put it back in here because of the discussion simples that begins on p. 13] 1 (2) one believes that those in the relevant similarity group will, other things being equal, b-enjoy the item’s appearing to have a sufficiently similar array A’; (3) one’s b-enjoyment is one’s reason for belief in (2). To motivate this account, imagine Carol is looking at Michelangelo’s David. She b-enjoys it for the way the sensuous harmony of the naked form expresses composure, confidence, and readiness for action; as part of her b-enjoyment, she occurrently believes that she G-universally values the statue’s appearing that way. When Carol, on the basis of her b-enjoyment, judges that appropriately believing others in the similarity group G will b-enjoy the David as having the same or a sufficiently similar array of features, she judges that their b-enjoyment will reveal to them the same or a very similar G-universal valuing. She judges that they will share with her the same vision of a contingency-transcending G-universally valuing. The judgment of beauty is the claim of a shared perception of transcendence: one’s subjective ascription of an array of features reveals through one’s enjoyment a valuing valid for all relevant others. A key difficulty this account faces is that there is an apparently compelling argument that one’s b-enjoyment cannot be a reason to think that appropriately believing members of the relevant similarity group will b-enjoy the item in question. Consider Carol’s judgment that the David is beautiful. She b-enjoys the David as having an array A of features, and, on that basis, judges that those in the relevant similarity group will, other things being equal, b-enjoy the item as having A, or a sufficiently similar array A’, provided they form the belief that x has A (or A’). The difficulty that one knows that one routinely encounters disagreement with one’s 2 judgments of beauty. Imagine, for example, that, in a discussion with his friend, Roger, William expresses his belief that the “naked and ashamed” verse in Son House’s rendition of John The Revelator is beautiful. William is confident Roger will agree; he knows from the discussion that they both have formed very similar beliefs about the verse, and he knows Roger belongs to the appropriate similarity group: they share a very similar understanding and appreciation of the blues; Roger understands and appreciates the references to Genesis, and he is very familiar with other renditions of John the Revelator. Roger does not, however, think the verse is beautiful. “I think it is very fine,” he says, “and I enjoy listening to it, but—beautiful? No, I draw the line there. Beautiful it is not.” Such disagreements are commonplace. Appropriately-believing others whom one, on excellent grounds, regards as relevantly similar nonetheless often reject one’s judgments of beauty. This happens even in cases like the David, cases in which there is widespread agreement that the thing is beautiful. Suppose Carol expresses her view that the David is beautiful to her companion, Mason. Mason, who does not b-enjoy the statue, replies, “Sadly, not for me.” Carol first assumes that he simply fails to perceive the sensuous harmony expressive of composure, confidence, and readiness for action, but she is quickly corrected. Mason, an art historian, offers a description of the David that elaborates on the sensuous harmony theme in ways that Carol finds illuminating and that deepens her b-enjoyment; in offering the description, Mason is not merely reporting the views of other experts; he sees what he is describing with his own eyes and is articulating his own belief. Carol is now even more puzzled. She cannot understand how Mason can see the statue as he 3 does and not find it beautiful. She suggests to him that a homophobia-induced inability to enjoy looking at a naked male body prevents him from b-enjoying the statue and on that basis finding it beautiful. Mason, who is gay, responds that he is certain that homophobia is not the problem. He nonetheless does not b-enjoy the David, and never has; he does not know why. Mason acknowledges that many others agree with Carol, and he is more than willing on that basis to agree that the David is beautiful, but this agreement does not express his own non-derivative judgment that the statue is beautiful. He makes no such judgment; his agreement merely acknowledges the view of the majority of others. The solitary b-enjoyer who declares, “My b-enjoyment is sufficient reason to attribute a like enjoyment to all relevant others,” would appear to be clinging to slender reed of support, one quickly crushed the obvious fact of widespread disagreement. So how can it be at all plausible to represent someone who judges an item beautiful as predicting, on the basis of his or her b-enjoyment, that all members of a group who form an appropriate belief will b-enjoy the item? We know that our b-enjoyments are not generally a reliable guide in this regard. Our answer is that the person who judges something beautiful entertains as a working hypothesis that those in the relevant similarity group will, other things being equal, b-enjoy provided they form the belief. When Carol judges the David beautiful, she knows it is highly likely that she will encounter those who, like Mason, fail to b-enjoy the David even though they belong to the appropriate similarity group and form an appropriate belief. She nonetheless predicts their benjoyment as a working hypothesis. Like a full-fledged belief, the hypothesis guides her thought and action. She uses it to identify similarities and dissimilarities 4 between the David and other items she and others judge beautiful; and, to elicit their reaction, she asserts to others that the David is beautiful. She proceeds in this way because she wants to know who directly values relevant experiences of the David in the way she does. She wants to know this because, as we noted earlier, one has compelling reason to discover a like-minded community with which one shares a vision of G-universal valuing. Responding to others disagreements can lead to revisions of the working hypothesis that yield a more accurate definition of the relevant community. There are three ways in which Carol can respond to Mason’s failure to b-enjoy the David. 1. Refusing to revise She can leave her judgment unrevised. A judgment of beauty is an “other things being equal” judgment, and, Carol could take the position that other things are not equal. Something unknown in Mason’s character or history might inhibit his b-enjoyment; the statue might, for example, remind him of his first love, a memory that enlivens pain still fresh despite the passage of time. In such a case, Mason is excluded from a community to which Carol belongs. The community consists of all those attribute the same (or a very closely similar) array of features as Carol does, and who b-enjoy the statue as having that array. Members of this community see their b-enjoyment has having revealed the same contingency-transcending Guniversal valuing. Mason does not share this vision of transcendence. Where one has sufficient reason to suspect that other things are not equal, the failure of someone to b-enjoy does not provide any reason to abandon one’s other things being equal judgment that they would so enjoy. 5 Many disagreements over beauty are plausibly disagreements over whether “other things” are “equal.” Suppose Sally b-enjoys Carl Orff’s Carmina Burana and for that reason judges it beautiful; Sam disagrees, calling Orff’s compositions childish compared to Brahms. Despite his condemnation of the composition as childish, Sam still directly values his listening experience. (One can directly value what one regards as childish.) But Sam does not b-enjoy listening to Carmina Burana since his perception of the music as childish prevents him from thinking, with regard to any group G, that his valuing is G-universal. One believes that one G-universally values x’s appearing to have A if and only if there is a sufficiently large group G of relevantly similar others, and collection C of relevant similar arrays of features such that, for any member y in G, there is some array A’ in C such that if x were to appear to y to have A’, then y would occurrently believe that y directly values x’s appearing to y to have A’. Sam does not believe that there is any group of people relevantly similar to him that satisfies the above condition. Sally regards Sam’s accusation of childishness as simply one more manifestation of his obsessive need to appear superior to anyone with whom he engages in conversation, and she is convinced that, if Sam were freed from his obsession, he would b-enjoy listening to the music. Sam, who is well aware of Sally’s view of him, thinks Sally lacks a sophisticated musical ear. The claim that other things are not equal is not a plausible defense if a sufficient number of those who form the appropriate belief fail to b-enjoy the item. It is, of course, possible for “other things” not to be “equal” in such a case; evil space aliens may have distorted the responses of almost everyone. Such eventualities are extremely unlikely, however. So what are Carol’s options if a 6 significant number of people disagree with her judgment that the David is beautiful? 2. Revising the belief One option is to decide that she has not identified the relevant array of features with sufficient precision and detail. Perhaps she could count on agreement from those who form the belief that the David has a different, perhaps richer and more complex, array of features. It is helpful to switch examples. Suppose Carol finds the opening lines of the poem in Nabokov’s Pale Fire beautiful: I was the shadow of the waxwing slain By the false azure in the window pane; I was the smudge of ashen fluff—and I Lived on, flew on, in that reflected sky. Carol believes that the lines capture the situation of a self-consciousness that identifies itself only with its own self-consciousness, not with any contingent circumstance in which that self-consciousness happens to be embodied. Mason forms the same belief, but he thinks any sufficiently mature adult should regard the lines as the adolescent and indefensible refusal to accept that the self is embodied in a particular contingent setting, and, far from regarding the lines as beautiful, he finds their adolescent indulgence unpleasant. Grant, for the sake of argument, that the vast majority of readers agree with Mason. Carol could respond by attempting to reformulate her first-personauthoritative assessment of the lines in a way that side-stepped the charge of adolescent indulgence. To respond this way is to concede the non-existence of the community of b-enjoyers to which one thought one belonged and to seek to a 7 differently defined community. Carol might, for example, set the lines in the context of the rest of the poem and see the lines, not as the endorsement of a selfconsciousness refusing to identify with anything beyond its own self-consciousness, but as introducing the plight of such a self-consciousness and laying the foundation for considering ways to escape its isolation (the first line, after all, reads “I was” not “I am”). Debates over beauty often exhibit just this sort of criticism and redefinition. In taking this line we do not wish to decide whether there is some specific set of concepts (as invoked by our critical vocabulary) which are the exact beauty-making features of the thing, or whether, as argued in an influential paper of Isenberg’s, there is some kind of non-conceptual perceptual content which our critical vocabulary gestures at rather than explicitly identifying. Whether the features in question relate most primordially to a way of experiencing or to a way of conceptualizing, or whether there is even a coherently expressible difference between the two, is not at issue. The point is just that whatever the specific array of features in question is, and however we indicate it, it is an open possibility for the lonely lover of beauty to try to work harder to make others see or understand, and for the lonely holdout to believe that there something he or she is simply missing, in either case no matter how much intelligent scrutiny has come before. 3. Relativization Another way to defend one’s judgment of beauty against disagreement is to revise one’s description of the similarity group. By way of illustration, suppose Vicki reads Wallace Steven’s Sunday Morning, a poem offering Stevens’ reflections, from a distinctly non-Christian perspective, on the Christian story of the crucifixion of 8 Christ, the sacrament of communion, and the Christian promise of immortality. She forms the belief that the poem has a certain array of features (concerning the elegance of the language, the power of the metaphors to capture aspects of the Christian themes of communion, suffering, salvation, and immortality); she benjoys the poem as having that array, and, on that basis, judges it beautiful. That is, she thinks that appropriately-believing others in the relevant similarity group will, other things being equal, b-enjoy the item. In her enthusiasm for the poem, she takes the relevant similarity group to include anyone with sufficient knowledge of Christianity. A few days later, she encounters Guanglei, a Buddhist, who is a counter-intelligence analyst for the Chinese government. He has thoroughly studied Christianity and Christian culture, and, when he reads Sunday Morning, he easily forms a belief which is not at all dissimilar to the one Vicki forms, but he does not b-enjoy his reading of the poem as having the array of features he attributes to it. He does not in fact enjoy reading the poem in any way at all, but, even if he did, his enjoyment would not amount to b-enjoyment. Even if he were to directly value his reading the poem, he would not, value his reading of it G-universally. He would not recognize any group of relevantly G-similar others. The poem offers him a vision of an alien world, a world he understands, but with which he does not identify or sympathize. In response to Guanglei’s reaction, Vicki revises her judgment of beauty; she now restricts her prediction of b-enjoyment to those who are not only sufficiently familiar with Christianity but who also have an affective attachment to it similar to her own. Vicki could have tried to avoid this revision by claiming that other things are not equal in Guanglei’s case. The boundaries of “other things are not equal” claims are hardly clear, but we interpret such claims as 9 asserting interferences with processes and attitudes that would otherwise yield a particular result, and we do not think it is plausible to posit such interference in cases like Guanglei’s. Some debates about beauty are plausibly regarded as debates about the proper relativization of a judgment of beauty. Consider Vladimir Nabokov’s novel, Pale Fire, for example. The novel contains a long poem by the—fictional—famous poet, John Shade; the poem is preceded by an introduction by Shade’s friend, Charles Kinbote; Kinbote’s commentary, correlated with the poem’s numbered lines, follows the poem. The poem and Kinbote’s observations comprise a highly allusive and self-referential narrative in which Shade and Kinbote are the characters. The novel makes considerable demands on the readers intellectual abilities, sophistication, and literary knowledge (the title, “Pale Fire,” for example, is from Act IV, scene 3 of Shakespeare's Timon of Athens: "The moon's an arrant thief, / And her pale fire she snatches from the sun", a line traditionally interpreted as a metaphor for creativity and inspiration). Carol and Mason both attribute more or less similar arrays of features to the novel; each b-enjoys it as having the relevant array, and each judges it beautiful on that basis. They restrict their respective judgments to different similarity groups, however. Carol excludes from her group traditionalists about the novel who regard Pale Fire as “self-referential trash”; Mason includes them on the theory that they would abandon their “selfreferential trash” assessment if they were ever to form a belief about the novel similar to Mason’s own. Mason is convinced that if they could see the novel through his eyes, they would indeed b-enjoy it and judge it beautiful. Carol is convinced 10 they would not. Mason attributes greater power to the novel to generate benjoyment than Carol does. The extent of an item’s power to generate b-enjoyment matters. Compare the community that b-enjoys Pale Fire as having arrays of features similar to those Carol and Mason attribute to it to the community that b-enjoys the Taj. Members of each group are convinced their b-enjoyments reveal a contingency-transcending G-universal valuing; however, the contingency transcending vision of the Pale Fire group is available to the relatively few capable of understanding the novel; the vision of the Taj group, however, is accessible to many. One cares about both. The b-enjoyments accessible only to “specialist” groups may offer profound insights, but few would forego membership is wide reaching communities such as those who b-enjoy the Taj. B. Knowledge? If one successfully defends/revises one’s judgment of beauty in one or more of the above ways, does one thereby qualify as knowing, or at least having good reason to believe, that appropriately-believing others in the relevant similarity group will b-enjoy the item? One may plausibly offer the David as an example. Carol b-enjoys the statue for the way the sensuous harmony of the naked form expresses composure, confidence, and readiness for action, and judges that those who form the same or similar belief will, other things being equal, b-enjoy the David as having the same or similar array of features. The group that has made the same or more or less similar judgment is quite large, and has endured as a sizable group from the creation of the statute in 1504 to the present. One might 11 plausibly regard Mason-like failures to b-enjoy (failures of appropriately believing members of the relevant similarity group) as cases in which other things are not equal, and hence regard Carol as knowing that relevant others will b-enjoy the statue. The background of agreement, moreover, need not be agreement about the particular item one judges beautiful. Imagine Carol sees a man on the street during a trip to Beijing; she b-enjoys his face and judges it beautiful. She will never see the man again, nor ever meet anyone who has, but the face is similar to those that people have for centuries judged beautiful. Compare a case of “unique beauty.” Suppose Carol is the first to see a new painting by an aspiring artist. The painting is as innovative as impressionist painting was when it first appeared. She thinks the painting is beautiful, but there is no David-like history she can rely on to support her claim that others will b-enjoy the painting; indeed, apart from her and the artist, there is no history of others judging, or refusing to judge, the painting beautiful. Of course, Carol—and others—can develop a relevant history by determining whether others agree with her judgment of beauty, and, if there is sufficient agreement, she will at some point know that others will b-enjoy. We want, however, to deemphasize the importance of knowledge in this context. Responses to other’s disagreement may lead to knowledge, but, on the way, they may also define communities of like b-enjoyers. The process may lead one to join with others in forming the same or similar beliefs that an item has a certain array of features, and to b-enjoy the painting as having that array. One may care as much or more about the formation of such communities as one does about whether one ultimately achieves knowledge. Of course, none of this may happen. The innovative artist may abandon painting to go to law school, and burn 12 his paintings, leaving Carol the only one who has seen them. In this case, Carol may never know whether others would have b-enjoyed them. IV. False Positives, False Negatives False positives and false negatives would show that our account of the judgment of beauty was incorrect. False positives are cases in which the definition is fulfilled but in which one withholds any judgment of beauty; false negatives, cases in which one makes a judgment of beauty when the definition is not fulfilled. We consider a number of false negatives and false positives. Our goal is not merely to dispose of objections, but to illustrate the explanatory power of the account. A. False negatives 1. Simples On our account, a completely uniform shade of blue cannot be judged beautiful; only items which one regards as having an organized array of features can be so judged. This may seem questionable. After all, people do say, “That is a beautiful shade of blue,” and, in any case, to avoid the charge of arbitrariness, the requirement of an organized array needs a justification. To begin with, one should set aside examples which do not really involve a uniform shade and which are not disallowed by our account. A shade of blue can be the dominant feature in a b-enjoyed organized array of features (in an abstract painting, for example) where that b-enjoyment serves as the reason for a judgment of beauty; further, a “color connoisseur” (an artist, for example) might attribute to a shade of blue an organized array of relations to other shades of that color, benjoy the shade as having that array, and, on that basis, judge it beautiful. What 13 follows from our account is that one cannot b-enjoy a shade of blue as merely having the feature being that shade of blue. Since we require that b-enjoyment be the reason for one’s judgment of beauty, it follows that one cannot judge the shade beautiful. To justify this result, suppose one did claim to b-enjoy looking at the shade of blue merely as being that shade. That is, one claims that, for some similarity group G, (1) one looks, and one 's looking causes (2) – (5): (2) (a) one occurrently believes, of his looking, under the feature blue, that it occurs; (b) and has the felt desire, of his looking, under the feature blue, that it should occur for its own sake; (3) the belief/desire pair in (2) is a first-person reason under blue for one to look; (4) one occurrently believes that one directly values looking at the blue color; (5) one occurrently believes that one G-universally values looking at the blue color. (5) is the problem. Can one coherently G-universally value looking at the particular shade of blue? To G-universally value is to directly value [direct valuing is not required as the definition is currently stated, but should be]. One directly values an x’s having an array of features A if and only if one regards x’s having A as, in and of itself, a third-person reason to act in ways that contribute to its being the case that x has A. Our argument appeals to general limitations on what one can coherently regard as a reason for action. One cannot, for example, coherently regard the belief that there will be a full moon as a reason to seek a new proof that no positive integers a, b, and c satisfy the equation an + bn = cn, for n greater than 14 2 (Fermat’s Last Theorem). We first explain why this is so, and then return to the shade of blue issue. Limitations on what one can regard as a reason for action arise because one cannot coherently claim that a belief is a reason for action without being able, in principle, to offer others an explanation of why the belief provides as least some justification for performing the action. The others may reject the explanation, but what one offers must qualify—at least in one’s own eyes—as a possible explanation, and it will do so only if one believes things that one regards as weighing in favor of performing the action. One may object that one can indeed meet this requirement with regard to offering the belief that the moon is full as a reason to seek a new proof of Fermat’s Last Theorem; one could easily meet the requirement if one lived in a community of astrologers who believed in appropriate connections among astronomical events and mathematical discoveries. But no one, or almost no one, lives in such a community, and absent some such convictions, there is nothing one believes that one regards as weighing in favor of thinking that the moon’s being full provides some degree of justification for seeking a new proof. To avoid misunderstanding, we should emphasize that we are not embracing a “community relativism” about reasons; we do not think that a belief qualifies as a reason only relative to this or that community. We are just emphasizing two facts: first, to claim that a belief is a reason is to commit oneself to being able in principle to offer others an explanation of the justificatory force of the belief; second, one’s beliefs impose limits on what one can offer as an explanation. This is consistent with an anti-relativism that recognizes principles for assessing, criticizing, and revising 15 views about what counts as an explanation that are valid independent of the views of any particular community. Now let us return to the question of whether one can G-universally value looking at the blue color. One who claims to do so is committed to offering a candidate explanation to others of why the color’s appearing in the way it does provides a third-person reason to look at it. The task is demanding. One could meet this demands if, for example, one believed that by enjoying the shade one would be granted a vision of the ultimate spiritual reality and that one’s life would thereby be transformed for the better. We do not, however, think that the vast majority of people have beliefs that would support any explanation at all. One issue remains: remarks like, “That is a beautiful shade of blue.” These can be understood as claiming the blue is particularly pleasing, suitable, or whatever. 2. Beauty without G-universal valuing It appears that one can judge that something is beautiful without a relevant G-universal valuing. If history had been different, impressionist painting would have been a putative example. Impressionism was not well received when it first appeared (critics included Henry James, who lamented the retreat from the “good old rules that decree that beauty is beauty and ugliness, ugliness”1). Imagine a world in which impressionism never catches on; painters eventually stop painting in that style until only a single impressionist painter remains. Imagine him looking at 1 Henry James, “Parisian Festivity,” New York Tribune, 13 May 1876. 16 one of his paintings. As he does so, he fulfills the following conditions for the appropriate φ and A: (1) x φ’s, and x's φing causes (2) – (5): (2) (a) x occurrently believes, of φ, under A, that it occurs; (b) and has the felt desire, of φ, under A, that it should occur for its own sake; (3) the belief/desire pair in (2) is a first-person reason under A for x to φ. (4) x occurrently believes that x directly values φ’s having A. The above conditions are almost the conditions for b-enjoyment. All that is missing is (5): x occurrently believes that x G-universally values φ’s having A The objection is that the painter may judge the painting beautiful on the basis of the enjoyment characterized by (1) – (4) and hence that b-enjoyment is not required as the reason for a judgment of beauty. To make his plausible, suppose that, over the years since the disappearance of impressionism, the painter has encountered many who have looked at the painting and formed beliefs very similar to the painters; however, not a single one of them has G-universally valued the paintings. They understood the painting, they just didn’t like it. The negative responses have worn the painter down to the point at which, when he looks at the painting, he no longer expects anyone else to G-universally value looking at the painting. Our answer is that when the painter fulfills (1) – (4), there is a similarity group G such that he G-universally values looking at the painting. The group consists of anyone who shares his attitudes and reactions to impressionism. That group currently consists, as far as the painter knows, only of himself; however, even when, at a certain time, a similarity group consists just of oneself, one may 17 still judge a painting beautiful on the basis of the related b-enjoyment. We offer the following considerations in defense of this claim. We begin with the observation that groups of people making the same judgment of beauty can be categorized along two dimensions. The first is the size of the group that b-enjoys the item as having more or less the same array of features. The “more or less” allows variation in enjoyed arrays; they must just be more alike than they are different. The second dimension is temporal duration, the length of time the group exists. Michelangelo’s David illustrates both ideas. Recall Carol’s judgment that the David is beautiful. She b-enjoys the statue for the way the sensuous harmony of the naked form expresses composure, confidence, and readiness for action, and judges that those who form the same or similar belief will, other things being equal, b-enjoy the David as having the same or similar array of features. The group that has made the same or more or less similar judgment is quite large, and has endured as a sizable group from the creation of the statute in 1504 to the present. Similar remarks hold for the Taj, the Parthenon, and selections from Shakespeare, Goethe, and Keats, to take just a few examples. Contrast the judgment that 1960 pop song Teen Angel is beautiful. In the song, the teen-aged narrator’s car stalls on a railroad track; he helps his girlfriend to safety, but she runs back to the car and is killed when the train strikes; they find the narrator’s high school ring in her hand. The group that judges the song beautiful is small (if it exists), and it most likely reached its maximum size around February 1960 when Teen Angel ranked number one on the U. S. Billboard Hot 100. Innumerable examples fall between extremes represented by the Taj and Teen Angel, including Sunday Morning and Pale Fire. The former, like the David, has a 18 large group that judges it beautiful on the basis of b-enjoying it as exhibiting arrays of features that are more or less similar, and the group has remained sizable since the first publication of the poem in 1915; however, unlike the David, which has cross-cultural appeal, the group that judges Sunday Morning beautiful is almost certainly restricted to those with sufficient emotional and intellectual attachment to Christianity and Christian culture. The group that judges Pale Fire beautiful is even more restricted, given the demands the work makes on its readers; nonetheless, a sizeable group has endured since the book’s 1952 publication. We concede that, when one expresses a judgment of beauty, others most naturally understand the judgment as follows: one judges that others who experience in the relevantly similar waywill, other things being equal, b-enjoy the item as having a specific organized array of features, where, at the time of the judgment, the relevant similarity group is, or under appropriate circumstances would be, a reasonably sizable group that is a successor to similar groups extending significantly back into time (more or less like the groups that, for example, judge the Taj, Sunday Morning, and Pale Fire beautiful). The “or under appropriate circumstances would be” qualification allows one to judge something beautiful in this way even if few, if any, others have encountered it. The rationale for this attitude lies in a point we emphasized earlier: to regard a reason as G-universal is to regard it as transcending the contingencies of one’s particular situation—in the sense that others in other situations with other attitudes and interests also acknowledge the reason. The larger and more diverse the similarity group, the less one’s recognition depends on idiosyncratic attitudes and interest, and the more it depends only on widely shared attitudes and interests. Given one’s compelling 19 reason to discover such contingency-transcending reasons, our interest in judgments of beauty involving sizeable similarity groups is understandable. This does not, however, mean that, when the similarity group consists just of oneself, one cannot judge something beautiful on the basis of the related b-enjoyment. It just means that others may not be much interested in the judgment. 3. Beauty without enjoyment There are some examples that suggest b-enjoyment—indeed, enjoyment in general—is not required for a judgment of beauty. Goya’s Third of May is an example. It is arguably a case of what one might call “horrific beauty.” The center of the painting is occupied by a white-shirted guerilla with arms outstretched about to be shot by faceless firing line of blue-uniformed French soldiers, who are executing the lined up guerillas with mechanical precision. The following seems extremely plausible: only an extremely perverse person would enjoy contemplating the horrific scene; nonetheless, the painting, a masterpiece, has a beauty that makes it depiction of the horror all the more effective. There is a large and complex literature addressing “horrific beauty”; we offer the following reflections, not as a decisive treatment, but as an indication that our account of beauty has resources that may shed some light on such case. We agree of course that only the very perverse would enjoy the horror just for the horror, but this is consistent with b-enjoying the painting as having an array of features that concern its artistic merits—it masterful composition, use of color, and effective depiction of the contrast between the guerilla’s and the French army. One can b-enjoy the painting as having this array, and judge it beautiful on that 20 basis. The enjoyment aids one in looking at the horror, from which one might otherwise turn away. Our answer to the Goya example depends on the claim that one does not enjoy the horror. One may well object that many who watch horror films enjoy being horrified. Surely, there is no reason to deny that they can b-enjoy the horrific aspects of a particularly artfully executed film, but no one would claim the horror was beautiful. We do deny that the horrific aspects of the film are b-enjoyed. To b-enjoy the horror one must believe one G-universally values in the relevant way. That is, one must think that relevant others would also directly value the relevant experiences. For any relative large and diverse G, no one will believe this (or, if they do, they will soon be corrected). Not everyone enjoys horror films; many are repulsed. One may object that the objection gains power if we change the example from horror films. Consider Matthias Grünewald’s triptych of the crucified Christ, which depicts the horror of the crucifixion. It is fairly standard commentary on the painting that, in presenting the horror, Grünewald’s goal was not beauty but a sermon in pictures. Someone might b-enjoy the painting. Imagine that Perry, in despair over the troubles in his life, finds himself in front of the picture. As he contemplates the suffering Christ, he suddenly no longer feels lost and alone in his own suffering, which, in a sudden reversal of attitude, Perry now sees as a path to purification and salvation, and, as he looks the picture, he b-enjoys Christ’s purifying-path-to-salvation-suffering; in particular, he thinks anyone who sees the picture as he does would believe that there is a third person reason to looking the 21 picture finding in it Christ’s purifying-path-to-salvation-through-suffering. Isn’t Perry an example of b-enjoying something without judging it beautiful? We do not think so. We think that one who b-enjoys the painting in the way described will also judge it beautiful. Indeed, Perry might well describe his experience this way: “When I saw the beauty in Christ’s suffering, I realized my own suffering was the path to my salvation.” In general, the “horrific beauty” examples divide into two types: those in which the horror, which (virtually) no one would judge beautiful, is enjoyed but not b-enjoyed; and those in which the horror is b-enjoyed but judged beautiful. 4. Beauty without causation The account requires that one’s enjoyment causes the belief that one Guniversally values. The following example appears to show that this is not required. An elderly museum curator is looking at his favorite Gauguin. He fulfills the conditions for b-enjoyment with respect to an appropriate φ and A—except the causal conditions. Instead of causing the relevant beliefs and desires, the experience of the painting floods his consciousness with memories of his youth combined with an attention-consuming awareness of the comparative shortness of the rest of his life. He has the relevant beliefs and desires, but in spite of his experience, not because of it. Can the curator judge the painting beautiful on the basis of fulfilling (1) – (5) without the causal conditions? We see no reason to deny that he can. However, we take the robust enjoyment sustained by the feedback loop, not the curator’s pale refection thereof, to be the paradigm case of enjoying beauty. Indeed, if the curator had never b- 22 enjoyed the painting with the causal feedback loop in place, he would not, at least not without qualification, judge it beautiful. His attitude would be that something is missing, that it is not quite beautiful. B. False positives 1. Wine, chocolate, and chess Compare “Michelangelo’s David is beautiful” with “This Côtes du Rhône is beautiful.” Although wine connoisseurs sometimes describe wines as beautiful, wine is hardly the example one would produce if asked for a paradigm case of beauty, and—as we will argue shortly—for good reason. Our account of beauty, however, there is no relevant difference between judging the David beautiful and making the same judgment about the Côtes du Rhône. Imagine Robert, the goutridden wine critic, tastes a wine. He b-enjoys the wine. That is: (1) he forms a first-person authoritative belief ascribing array A of features to the wine; he finds in it an aroma of cherry and a touch of smoke combined with light taste of tannin and a soft taste of red fruit, spice, and earth). (2) This belief motivates and justifies his enjoyment of the wine for its own sake; that is, that belief is an underived active reason to enjoy of the wine has having that array. Further, as a deeply committed wine connoisseur, he thinks he should believe that the wine has that array, and that the belief should serve as an underived active reason. That is, he regards the proposition that the wine has A as an underived normative reason for him to enjoy the wine as having A. In addition, for a similarity group G of wine connoisseurs of similarity sophistication and discriminatory abilities, he thinks that if one of them forms the same or sufficiently similar belief, he or she will also believe that he regards the proposition that the wine has A as an underived normative reason for 23 him to enjoy the wine as having A. That is, (3) he regards the proposition that the wine has the array as a G-universal normative reason for any member of G to enjoy the wine as having A. Finally, his enjoyment causes or causally sustains (3). On the basis of his b-enjoyment, Robert judges the wine is beautiful. Similar remarks hold for b-enjoying the complexities of chocolate, or any item one can experience with sensations of sufficient structure and complexity. We think the wine, chocolate, and the like can be beautiful; however, we also think there is an important difference between, for example, judging a wine beautiful and judging the David beautiful. Take the latter example first. Now, by way of contrast, suppose Barbara and Carol are looking at the David; unlike Carol, Barbara fails to b-enjoy it. When Barbara expresses her disappointment, her remarks reveal that, unlike Carol, she does not believe that statue to evince a sensuous harmony expressive composure, confidence, and readiness for action. Indeed, she fails to attribute any organized array of features to the statue; it is, for her, just a lifeless piece of marble. To aid Barbara in forming an appropriate belief, Carol calls Barbara’s attention to the way the left leg is bent, the bend and slight turn at the waist, and the way the head is turned directing the gaze to the left and exhibiting the muscles of the neck; and he could ask her to try to see all these as combining to express concentration and readiness for movement. The essential point is that Carol can aid Barbara by directing attention to publicly accessible features of the statue. This is possible in many—but we do not claim all—cases. One can often refer to publicly accessible features when trying to assist others to form an appropriate first-person authoritative belief. 24 Compare the wine example. Imagine that Barbara neither smells the cherry aroma and touch of smoke, nor tastes the tannins, red fruit, spice, and earth. To help her detect these features, Paul, a wine connoisseur, could have her taste other wines with similar but more easily detectable features; after sufficient practice with these wines, Barbara might be able to detect the features that initially eluded her. Paul does not, however, typically direct Barbara’s attention to publicly accessible features of the wine. He might call her attention to the wine’s color and viscosity, but this aid Barbara little, if any, in detecting the aromas and tastes that elude her. One may well object that aromas and tastes are “publicly accessible” features of wines. They are in the sense that there is remarkable agreement among wine experts—well-trained sommeliers, for example—on aromas and tastes. We have no wish to deny this. Our point is that such features are less accessible in the sense that reliably detecting them typically requires considerable specialized experience and training. It matters whether one can refer to generally publicly accessible features when trying to assist others to form an appropriate first-person authoritative belief. Iris Murdoch emphasizes similar point about art: The accessible existence of art, its ability to hang luminously in human minds at certain times, depends traditionally upon an external being, a fairly precise and fixed sensory notation or ‘body’, an authority to which the client intermittently submits himself. . . Art experience . . . is something we can self-evidently and identifiably have and enjoy, in various ways in various materials.2 We think a similar point holds for beauty: the “ability [of beauty] to hang luminously in human minds at certain times, depends [in a range of central and 2 Iris Murdoch, Metaphysics As A Guide To Morals (Allen Lane, The Penguin Press, 1993). 25 important—but not all—cases] upon an external being . . . an authority to which the client intermittently submits himself.” The publicly accessible features (accessible with out specialized experience and training) provide an “external authority,” shared external point of reference around which communities of like b-enjoyers may readily form. We do not, however, wish to overemphasize the role of publicly accessible features. By way of counterpoint, consider the conversion of M. Alphonse Ratisbonne, a Jew by birth and, for the first part of his life, an atheist by conviction. When Alphonse entered a chapel devoted to the Virgin Mary, he had a vision of the Virgin and was instantly converted to Catholicism. Alphonse described his state immediately after the conversion: I did not know where I was: I did not know whether I was Alphonse or another. I only felt myself changed and believed myself another me; I looked for myself in myself and did not find myself. In the bottom of my soul I felt an explosion of the most ardent joy; I could not speak; I had no wish to reveal what had happened . . . All that I can say is that in an instant the bandage had fallen from my eyes, and not one bandage only, but the whole manifold of bandages in which I had been brought up. One after another they rapidly disappeared, even as the mud and ice disappear under the rays of the burning sun. I came out as from a sepulchre, from an abyss of darkness; and I was living, perfectly living. But I wept, for at the bottom of that gulf I saw the extreme of misery from which I had been saved by an infinite mercy.3 One can readily imagine that, as part of the “explosion of the most ardent joy,” Alphonse b-enjoyed the vision of the Virgin and judged the vision beautiful. There are of course few publicly accessible features that one might indicate to help others b-enjoy a similar vision. There is the chapel and its adornments, but few who experience them experience visions. 2. The Oprah Sign 3 William James, Principles of Psychology 26 The following objection rests on two claims. First, there are attempts to judge something beautiful that misfire so badly that one should not regard them as genuine judgments of beauty. Second, on our account, such cases count as entirely non-defective judgments of beauty. We offer an example to illustrate and defend the first claim. If one finds the example unconvincing, it poses no threat to our account of the judgment of beauty. For those who are convinced, we contend that it follows from our account that the purported judgment of beauty does not really qualify as one. The example: outside Oprah’s studio in Chicago, there is a sign with a slanted “O” on top that reads “HARPO STUDIOS,” and below that, in smaller letters, “The Oprah Winfrey Show.” A group from a small town in Iowa gathers before the sign on Mother’s Day; having laid flowers before it, they contemplate it. Each forms the belief that the script-like slanted “O” complements the straight block letter “HARPO STUDIOS,” which is harmoniously offset by modest, “The Oprah Winfrey Show.” In their adoration of Oprah, the features combine in a way that fills them with awe, and, as a result, each fulfills—at least apparently fulfills—the remaining conditions of b-enjoyment for an appropriate φ and A : for some group G, (2) (a) each occurrently believes, of φ, under A, that it occurs; (b) and has the felt desire, of φ, under A, that it should occur for its own sake; (3) the belief/desire pair in (2) is a first-person reason under A to φ; (4) each occurrently believes that he or she directly values φ’s having A, and (5) each occurrently believes that he or she G-universally values φ’s having A. On the basis of this apparent b-enjoyment, each judges—or, at least appears to judge—that others will, other things being equal, b-enjoy the sign has having the array, 27 provided that they form the belief that it has the array. That is, each judges, or appears to judge, the sign is beautiful. Do they really judge that the sign is beautiful? Some will certainly think so, and with apparent good reason. Does one really want to deny that the beloved is beautiful in the eyes of the lover? On the other hand, it does seem wrong to concede that they really judge the sign beautiful. Imagine the fans extol the beauty of the sign as they show pictures of it to their friends. The astonished friends react with, “You’ve got to be kidding. You can’t really think that is beautiful. It’s just a sign!” Our account explains both reactions. We begin with the reasons to think the fans do not really judge the sign beautiful. One judges something beautiful only if one’s b-enjoyment is one’s reason for the judgment. To fulfill this requirement, the fans must think that, for some group G, they G-universally value the way the sign appears. . They cannot fulfill this condition. To see why, recall the point we emphasized when discussing the uniform shade of blue example. There are limitations on what one can regard as a reason for action: namely to claim that a belief is a reason is to commit oneself to being able in principle to offer others at least a candidate explanation of the justificatory force of the belief. The fans could meet this requirement if, for example, they believed that by enjoying the sign in the requisite way one would be granted a vision of the ultimate spiritual reality and that one’s life would thereby be transformed for the better. The fans, one may safely assume, do not have any such beliefs; indeed, one may safely assume that they do not have any beliefs that would support any candidate explanation at all. The fans adoration of Oprah dupes them into merely thinking that they think that they appropriately G-universally 28 value. Compare thinking, in one’s eagerness to impress one’s friends, that one understands why, in the theory of special relativity, the speed of light is constant in all frames or reference; when one tries to explain why to the friends, one discovers one only thought one understood. Since the fans cannot coherently regard themselves as G-universally valuing, they cannot b-enjoy the sign as having that array; consequently, they cannot make a judgment of beauty that requires that benjoyment as a reason. Having said this, can we still do justice to the truism that the beloved is beautiful in the eyes of the lover? We can offer this much: the fans almost judge the sign beautiful. The only problem is the requirement that they regard they Guniversally value. This is no small problem. It is by convincing one that one values in this way that the enjoyment of beauty convinces one that it has provided a contingency-transcending insight. Nonetheless, the fans think—mistakenly think, but still think—that their enjoyment of the sign provides them with such an insight. In their eyes, the eyes of the lover, they appear to themselves to judge the sign beautiful. 3. Michael Jackson’s Thriller The Oprah sign example reveals limits on what one can coherently judge beautiful. How far do those limits extend? Can one, for example, coherently judge Michael Jackson’s Thriller beautiful? On our account, one can b-enjoy Thriller and judge it beautiful on that basis. There is no “Oprah sign” problem of producing a candidate explanation of the existence of a reason that will support a claim of G-universal valuing. Thriller fans 29 will cite the elements of the music, lyrics, dance, and video, and, while one may not agree with the explanation, the features identified are certainly sufficient to constitute a candidate explanation. Many, perhaps most, will nonetheless think something has gone wrong if, when the visitors from outer space ask for examples of beauty, earth’s representatives offer, without further comment or qualification, the David and Thriller. We suggest the reason lies in a point we made earlier: when one expresses a judgment of beauty, others most naturally understand the judgment as predicting that others in a certain similarity group will b-enjoy the item, where the group is reasonably large and a successor to similar groups extending significantly back into time. Thus, imagine the space visitors return fifty years later; they again ask for examples of beauty and are again offered the David, but no one even mentions Thriller. When the aliens enquire about Thriller, earth’s representatives explain that Thriller is passé; it has been years since any significant number of people b-enjoyed it and judged it beautiful. It is currently viewed as in the same league as Teen Angel—a somewhat embarrassing moment in cultural history. This is not to deny that Thriller was once (on our story) b-enjoyed and judged beautiful. We are just pointing out that we recognize an important distinction between judgments of beauty which are associated with sizeable and enduring similarity groups, and judgments which are not. A distinction sufficiently important that we would not be likely to offer the aliens Thriller as an example of beauty even at the height of its fame—the court still being out on whether it should take its place alongside the David or Teen Angel. V. Beauty’s Power 30 We can now deliver on our promise to explain beauty’s power to compel our attention and appreciation, to unite us in shared visions, and to divide us with different ones. B-enjoyment is the source of these powers. It compels our attention and appreciation in three ways. When one b-enjoys x’s appearing to have the features in an array A, the associate belief/desire pair is an active reason, a reason that motivates and justifies continuing the experience. Second, the operation of the active reason is reinforced by the two beliefs about valuing: that one directly values and that one G-universally values. Third, the b-enjoyer is not only in the grip of a causal feedback loop, that loop typically enriches the conception of the relevant array of features and thereby renews the enjoyment in a more complex form. Judgments of beauty unite us in communities of like b-enjoyers, communities in which each member shares the belief that his or her b-enjoyment has revealed a particular normative reason that transcends life’s contingencies. Judgments of beauty, however, also divide us into distinct communities of b-enjoyers, communities from which, as a practical matter, many are simply forever barred from entry. Bobby Fischer played many beautiful chess games, but, since the vast majority of people lack the expertise to b-enjoy the complex chess relationships in which their beauty consists, the vast majority are forever barred from the community that b-enjoys them for those relationships. Similar examples abound, as the earlier discussion of Wallace Steven’s Sunday Morning illustrates. Guanglei will never become sufficiently immersed in Christian culture to join Vicki and others in the community that b-enjoys the poem for its portrayal of Christianity-rooted concerns over purification, suffering, forgiveness, communion, and immortality. 31 Vicki on the other hand will never join Guanglei in the community that enjoys classical Chinese landscape paintings. In each case, group members believe they G-universally value in ways that transcend life’s contingencies, but the two groups have profoundly different conceptions what that contingency-transcending valuing is. 32